whyte_agamben

download whyte_agamben

of 15

Transcript of whyte_agamben

  • 8/3/2019 whyte_agamben

    1/15

    Particular Rights and Absolute Wrongs: Giorgio

    Agamben on Life and Politics

    Jessica Whyte

    Published online: 28 March 2009 Springer Science+Business Media B.V. 2009

    Abstract Over the past decade, as human rights discourses have increasingly

    served to legitimize state militarism, a growing number of thinkers have sought to

    engage critically with the human rights project and its anthropological foundations.

    Amongst these thinkers, Giorgio Agambens account of rights is possibly the most

    damning: human rights declarations, he argues, are biopolitical mechanisms that

    serve to inscribe life within the order of the nation state, and provide an earthly

    foundation for a sovereign power that is taking on a form redolent of the concen-tration camp. In this paper, I will examine Agambens account of human rights

    declarations, which he sees as central to the modern collapse of the distinction

    between life and politics that had typified classical politics. I will then turn to the

    critique of Agamben offered by Jacques Ranciere, who suggests that Agambens

    rejection of rights discourses is consequent to his adoption of Hannah Arendts

    belief that, in order to establish a realm of freedom, the political realm must be

    premised on the expulsion of natural life. In contrast to Ranciere, I will argue that

    far from sharing the position of those thinkers, like Arendt, who seek to respond to

    the modern erosion of the borders between politics and life by resurrecting earlierforms of separation, Agamben sees the collapse of this border as the condition of

    possibility of a new, non-juridical politics.

    Keywords Agamben Aristotle Human rights Life Metaphysics

    Modernity Politics Ranciere Sovereignty

    There is no return from the camps to classical politics (Giorgio Agamben).

    J. Whyte (&)

    Centre for Comparative Literature and Cultural Studies, Monash University,

    Clayton, VIC 3800, Australia

    e-mail: [email protected]

    123

    Law Critique (2009) 20:147161

    DOI 10.1007/s10978-009-9045-2

  • 8/3/2019 whyte_agamben

    2/15

    In the final section of Homo Sacer, Giorgio Agamben paints brief portraits of a

    number of lives, which, on the surface, appear to have little in common: at one

    extreme, the series includes the Fuhrer of the Third Reich, a person who had the

    power to decide whether millions lived or died; at the other extreme, it includes the

    Muselmannthat figure of the concentration camps who had so lost the will to livethat he no longer belongs to the world of men in any way (Agamben 1998, p. 186).

    Alongside these starkly counter-posed lives from Second World War Europe, he

    discusses those of Wilson, a biochemist who, upon being diagnosed with

    leukemia, decided to turn his own body into an experimental laboratory, and of

    Karen Quinlan, whose life was sustained for years purely by artificial technologies

    and by virtue of a legal decision that ensured the machines would not be switched

    off. The choice of this brief series of lives may seem extreme, if not arbitrary,

    Agamben (1998, p. 187) writes. And yet each of them, he argues, exemplifies a

    collapse of the classical distinction between life and politicsa collapse whoseextreme manifestation was in the Nazi state, where biology was immediately

    political and the question of raceor equality of stock, as it was euphemistically

    referred tobecame the key political project. In Agambens view, however, the

    politicization of life extends far beyond the bounds of National Socialist Germany.

    The transformation of biological life into a political task, he argues, is the definitive

    event of modernity; the concentration camp is the new biopolitical nomos of the

    planet (Agamben 1998, p. 176).

    Given this claim, it is unsurprising that Agambens thought is often dismissed as

    overly pessimistic, especially as, in his view, the emancipatory resources of modernpolitics are, at best, impotent in challenging the growing indistinction of life and

    politics that he analyses. And yet, in a 2004 interview, Agamben responded to the

    charge of pessimism by quoting Karl Marx, who wrote in 1843, the desperate

    situation of the society in which I live fills me with hope. I share this vision,

    Agamben told his interviewers, hope is given to the hopeless. I dont see myself as

    pessimistic (Vacarme 2004, p. 123). In this paper, I will examine Agambens

    workin light of this phrase he borrows from Marxin order to elucidate the

    grounds for, and perhaps the limitations of, his hope. In doing so, I will argue that

    Agambens hope is intimately connected to his diagnosis of the desperate situation

    of contemporary biopolitics. To show this, I will focus on his understanding of

    human rights declarations, which he sees as simultaneously furthering the capture of

    life in the realm of sovereign power, andhelping to overcome the separation of life

    and politics, thus creating the possibility for a new, non-juridical politics.

    Agamben is only one of a number of thinkers to have engaged critically with the

    human rights project in the past decade (Balibar 2007; Brown 2004; Douzinas 2000;

    Ranciere 2004; Zizek 2004). In an essay entitled Who is the Subject of Human

    Rights?, Jacques Ranciere suggests contemporary critiques of human rights occur

    in the context of the failure of liberal capitalism to produce the irrepressible

    movement towards a post-historical world that had been proclaimed in the wake of

    the collapse of the Soviet Bloc (Ranciere 2004, p. 297). The reality, Ranciere

    suggests, did not live up to the humanitarian rhetoric; In the following years, he

    writes, the new landscape of humanity, freed from utopian totalitarianism, became

    the stage of new outbursts of ethnic conflicts and slaughters, religious

    148 J. Whyte

    123

  • 8/3/2019 whyte_agamben

    3/15

    fundamentalisms, or racial and xenophobic movements (Ranciere 2004, p. 297). In

    this context, human rights increasingly appeared as the rights of those who lived out

    their days in the dust of refugee camps, or of those who were forced to flee and

    found they had nowhere to go. Human rights, Ranciere suggests, began to appear as

    the rights of those who were unable to exercise rights of their own and thus neededsomeone else to exercise them on their behalf. In the subsequent legitimation of the

    discourse of humanitarian intervention, he sees the creation of nothing less than a

    right of invasion (Ranciere 2004, p. 297). This situation, Ranciere suggests, lead

    to a new suspicionthe suspicion that perhaps human rights were a mere

    abstraction, and the only meaningful rights were the rights attached to a national

    community (Ranciere 2004, p. 297).

    In Agambens work, this suspicion about the relation of human rights to the

    nation-state takes the form of a critical account of the ambiguous man/citizen link

    that underlies modern rights declarations. Rights, he argues, are attributed to man(or originate in him) solely to the extent that man is the immediately vanishing

    ground (who must never come to light as such) of the citizen (Agamben 1998,

    p. 297). While the nation-state is therefore founded on the fictional subsumption of

    man into the citizen, today we are witnessing the culmination of the separation of

    the rights of man from the rights of the citizen. The contemporary bearer of human

    rights par excellence is the Rwandan child, whose photograph is shown to obtain

    money but who is now becoming more difficult to find alive(Agamben 1998,

    p. 133). Human rights are the rights of those with no rights; of those Agamben refers

    to as bare life (Agamben 1998, p. 133). This initial similarity between Agambenswork and Rancieres is not incidental. Indeed a number of common concerns typify

    the work of these thinkers, both of whom are attempting to theorize the condition of

    politics today, while critically drawing on the resources of classical political

    thought. This initial commonality, however, should not serve to obscure the major

    differences between them, which, I believe, can best be approached through a

    consideration of their respective accounts of human rights. In what follows, I will

    suggest that both Agamben and Ranciere are responding, in different ways to

    Hannah Arendts critique of human rights, which relies on her reassertion of the

    Aristotelian distinction between zoe, or natural life, and bios, a qualified form of

    life. In order to grasp fully Agambens critique of human rights, and to understand

    his lack of pessimism, it will therefore be helpful to situate his work in the context

    of this Aristotelian legacy. While space constraints prevent a full engagement with

    Rancieres theorization of the political here, Agambens work can be brought into

    relief through comparing his response to this Aristotelian legacy to Rancieres on

    two points: firstly, their respective accounts of the distinction between life and

    politics; and secondly, their differing accounts of the political subject.

    In attempting to understand the situation of human rights today, both Agamben

    and Ranciere turn to Arendts influential essay from the Origins of Totalitarianism,

    The Decline of the Nation State and the End of the Rights of Man (Arendt 1976).

    Here, Arendt argues that the mass refugee flows following the First World War

    called into question the utility of human rights, by creating a section of humanity

    stripped of all political status; the conception of human rights based on the assumed

    existence of human being as such, she writes, broke down at the very moment that

    Particular Rights and Absolute Wrongs 149

    123

  • 8/3/2019 whyte_agamben

    4/15

    those who professed to believe in it were for the first time confronted with people

    who had indeed lost all other qualities and specific relationshipsexcept that they

    were still human (Arendt 1976, p. 299). From her examination of the situation of

    these refugees, Arendt, as Etienne Balibar points out, developed a radical critique of

    the supposed anthropological foundation of human rights (Balibar 2007, p. 728). Ifdestruction of civil rights also destroys human rights, Balibar explains, this is

    because the latter are based on the former, and not the reverse (Balibar 2007,

    p. 732). Thus, what Arendt refers to as the right to have rights cannot be derived

    from any essential quality of the human, any inalienable inherence of rights in the

    human person, but is premised upon the existence of a community of political actors

    who grant each other such rights. Abstracted from such a political community, the

    supposedly inalienable, universal human rights, Arendt concluded, are simply the

    rights of those who have no rights.

    As both Balibar and Ranciere highlight, Arendts dismissal of the efficacy ofhuman rights lead her to a paradoxical form of institutionalism (Balibar 2007;

    Ranciere 2004), which shares elements of Edmund Burkes conservative critique of

    natural rightsas expressed in his preference for his rights of an Englishman

    (Agamben 1998, p. 127). This preference for the rights of the citizen is premised on

    the rigid division of mans private life in the home (oikos) and his public life in the

    statea division, Arendt suggests, upon which all ancient political thought rested

    as self-evident and axiomatic (Arendt 1958, p. 28). That is, Arendts dismissal of

    human rights and her valorization of the rights that are granted through participation

    in the political sphere is premised on a narrow conception of the political, fromwhich social questions, including poverty, labour and reproduction are excluded in

    the name of freedom. Thus, as Ranciere highlights, Arendts critique of rights

    rested on the assumption that modern democracy had been wasted from the very

    beginning by the pity of the revolutionaries for the poor people (Ranciere 2004,

    p. 298). Indeed, it was this distinction between the political as the realm of freedom

    and the social as that of necessity that lead Arendt, in her book on the French and

    American revolutions, to suggest that it was the entry of the poor, with their social

    demands, into the French revolution that prevented it from establishing a realm

    of freedom, and that ultimately precipitated the terror (Arendt 1990). In the

    politicization of questions of poverty, labour, and reproductionand in the

    valorization of natural life at the foundation of rights declarationsArendt saw a

    blurring of the distinction between political and natural life, the impingement of

    necessity on freedom, and, ultimately, the eclipse of politics.

    In a similar diagnostic vein, Agamben argues that the decisive fact of modernity

    is the breakdown of the distinction between mere life (zen) and the good life (eu

    zen) that had defined politics for the Greeks. From Aristotle onwards, Agamben

    argues, the political realm has been predicated on a caesura that divides the human

    into a political and a natural life, and isolates what he refers to as bare life

    (Agamben 1998). The caesura Agamben identifies was predicated on a conception

    of the life lived in the polis as a particular form of life, from which the maintenance

    of natural life was decisively excluded. To understand this separation better, we

    should examine a passage from The Politics that takes on a decisive importance in

    Agambens work. Aristotle writes:

    150 J. Whyte

    123

  • 8/3/2019 whyte_agamben

    5/15

    The good life is indeed the chief end of the state both corporately and

    individually, but men form and continue to maintain this kind of association

    for the sake of life itself. Perhaps we may say that there is an element of value

    even in mere living, provided that life is not excessively beset by troubles.

    Certainly most men, in their desire to keep alive, are prepared to face a greatdeal of suffering, finding in life itself a certain comfort, and a feeling that it is

    good to be alive (Aristotle 1942, p. 114).

    Here, we see the clear distinction Aristotle developed between the pre-political

    fact of life itself, and the good life. While Aristotle suggests that men initially

    form states for the sake of mere life, this form of association is driven by biological

    necessity and, far from being specifically human, is shared by citizens, barbarians,

    slaves, women and animals. Once men become self-sufficient, however, enabling

    a certain number to free themselves from material concerns and live freely in the

    polis, what started as a means to secure life itselfis now in a position to secure

    the good life (Aristotle 1942, p. 28). In contrast to that simple fact of life that men

    share with all living beings, the good life is the specific end of man as the living

    being with logos. In Aristotles Politics, political life is not simply different from

    the life lived in the home by degrees, but is different in kind.1 In stark contrast to the

    latter, the life lived in the polis was a particular form of life, from which the mere

    maintenance of biological life was decisively excluded.

    This exclusion of biological life was necessary, Aristotle believed, to create a

    realm of freedom. While the free pursuit of the good life in the polis presupposed

    material self-sufficiency and the reproduction of the lives of citizens, thisreproduction was not considered political. As Arendt points out, revealing the

    Aristotelian foundations of her own account of politics, the good life was good

    to the extent that by having mastered the necessities of sheer life, by being freed

    from labour and work, and by overcoming the innate urge of all living creatures for

    their own survival, it was no longer bound to the biological life process (Arendt

    1958, p. 37). One consequence of this was that those whose lives were taken up with

    working to provide for material necessities were not considered fit to be citizens. In

    his Politics, Aristotle remarks that if a state existed merely to provide a living, it

    might be made up of slaves or animals, and that is impossible, because slaves andanimals are not free agents and do not participate in well-being (Aristotle 1942,

    p. 119). Slaves and animals (and women), in Aristotles view, were not able to

    participate in the good life, but were simply instruments for providing some with the

    sufficient quality of life it presupposes.

    Where Agamben differs from both Aristotle and Arendt is that, for him, zoe, or

    natural life, is not a pre-existing natural substrate but the product of a separation.

    Further, zoe, in his account, was not simply excluded from the polis, but was

    captured and politicized through this constitutive exclusion, and thus, has the

    1 Much of the first book of Aristotles Politics, which deals with the differences between the political

    sphere and the household, can be seen as a critique of Plato. This is implied in Aristotles comment, It is

    an error to suppose that the relationships between statesman and state, between king and subjects,

    between householder and household, between master and slaves, are all the same (Aristotle 1942, p. 25).

    It is because Aristotle separated political life from life in the home more emphatically than did Plato that

    Agamben often refers to the caesura between life and politics as stemming from Aristotle.

    Particular Rights and Absolute Wrongs 151

    123

  • 8/3/2019 whyte_agamben

    6/15

    peculiar privilege of being that whose exclusion founds the city of men (Agamben

    1998, p. 7). Agamben uses the term ban, borrowed from Jean-Luc Nancy, to

    signify the exposure through which life is at once excluded from the political

    community and captured in the realm of sovereign power. In his essay Abandoned

    Being, Nancy highlights the double meaning of the term banthe one who isbanned is both abandoned, or banished, and held in a ban (Nancy 1993). The one

    who is banned is therefore not simply set outside the law and made indifferent to it

    but is rather abandoned by it, that is, exposed and threatened on the threshold in

    which life and law, outside and inside become indistinguishable (Agamben 1998,

    p. 29). This ability to hold life in a ban by abandoning it is, for Agamben, the

    originary political relation. Agamben uses the term inclusive exclusion to define

    this limit relation, in which people are included in the political community purely by

    virtue of their exclusionan exclusion which leaves them utterly exposed to

    sovereign violence. The sovereign ban is the limit form of relation, but at this limit itremains a relation between the sovereign and that bare life that it includes only by

    excluding. Because zoe, in this account, is not merely excluded from the polis, but is

    captured within it, Agamben can argue that life is originarily included in the realm

    of a politics that is therefore biopolitics from the beginning. The life that is caught in

    the sovereign ban is, in Agambens terminology, bare lifea life that is

    politicized through the fact of its exclusion. This bare life is neither simply natural

    life nor political life but is the threshold of articulation that enables the passage from

    one to the other. Bare life, Agamben argues, is the sole referent of sovereign power.

    For the Sake of LifeBare Life in Modernity

    In stark contrast to this classical model, modern democracy, Agamben argues,

    presents itself from the beginning as a vindication and liberation ofzoe (Agamben

    1998, p. 9). This means politics ceases to be a specific activitythe pursuit of the

    good lifeand comes to be conceived as existing for the sake of life itself, for the

    protection of natural life. The decisive fact of modernity, in Agambens account, is

    therefore the breakdown of the distinction between life (zen) and the good life

    (eu zen), and between bios and zoe. In The Human Condition, Arendt suggests that,

    the disappearance of the gulf the ancients had to cross daily to transcend the narrow

    realm of the household and rise into the realm of politics is an essentially modern

    phenomenon (Arendt 1958, p. 33). In Agambens view, the disappearance of this

    gulf fundamentally transforms the status of all of those separations through which

    the ancients understood the specificity of political life. In modernity, Agamben

    writes, bare lifewhich had originally been situated in a relation of abandonment at

    the margins of the polisgradually begins to coincide with the political realm, and

    exclusion and inclusion, outside and inside, bios and zoe, right and fact, enter into a

    zone of irreducible indistinction (Agamben 1998, p. 9).

    This transition, through which bare life appears as the modern political subject,

    is, in Agambens view, a product of those declarations of rights, which, he argues,

    enabled the transition from divine to national sovereignty. The nation-state,

    Agamben argues, is founded on a unity of birth-territory-order, and human rights

    152 J. Whyte

    123

  • 8/3/2019 whyte_agamben

    7/15

    declarationswhich locate sovereignty in the natural life of a peopleare the

    originary figure for the inscription of natural life in the politicaljuridical order of

    the nation-state (Agamben 2000, p. 20). This location of sovereignty in the nation,

    Agamben argues, is only enabled by a fiction by which birth is automatically nation,

    and as such, becomes a political category. It is because rights declarations arepredicated on the creation of bare life, that is, because they politicize the fact of

    birth, that Agamben sees them as double edgedboth bearers of liberties and

    vehicles for the increasing inscription of life in the realm of a state that now finds its

    rationale in precisely that which the ancients had excluded as unpolitical: natural

    life, mans biological vulnerability. While Aristotle had seen natural life as outside

    the concern of politics, in modernity, the split between life and politics begins

    to heal, but only at the cost of tying life to the sovereignty of the state, and

    transforming politics into a means for the protection of biological lifea shift

    whose extreme manifestation we see in todays legitimation of state militarismthrough human rights discourses.

    An Ontological Trap? Ranciere on Agamben

    Up to this point, Agambens understanding of modernity sounds very much like

    Arendtsand indeed the equation of the two thinkers is central to Rancieres

    critique of Agamben. This critique has two key elements: firstly, Ranciere argues

    that Agambens account of human rights is predicated on the same separation of lifeand politics that underpinned Arendts suspicions about such rights; secondly, he

    argues that Agambens position leads to an ontological trap, in which every

    possibility for political contestation is foreclosed in advance (Ranciere 2004,

    p. 302). Following Ranciere, Slavoj Zizek frames this critique in the following

    terms: Agambens (and Foucaults) understanding of contemporary biopolitics

    as the culmination of Western thought ends up getting caught in a kind of

    ontological trap in which concentration camp appears as ontological destiny

    (Zizek 2004, p. 15). I would like to consider each of these arguments in turn, and

    suggest that it is because Ranciere misreads Agambens approach to the separation

    of life and politics, that he is unable to grasp fully why Agamben sees the need to

    situate contemporary political problems on the terrain of ontology.

    According to Ranciere, Agamben, like Arendt, situates those who have only

    human rights in a sphere of exceptiona sphere that can no longer be understood as

    a space of political dissensus, and which therefore exemplifies Agambens

    depoliticizing approach (Ranciere 2004, p. 298). What Ranciere terms dissensus

    (or at other points, dis-agreement) consists in an attempt to open rights declarations

    to a process of political contestation, to make the gap between their universal claims

    and particular application the space in which politics operates (Ranciere 1998).

    Ranciere has elsewhere referred to this strategy as verifying equality; Taking

    something which is usually dismissed as a groundless claim, he argues, it

    transforms it into its oppositeinto a grounds for a claim, into a sphere open for

    dispute (Ranciere 1994, p. 47). Rather than simply pointing to this gap in order to

    unveil the universal claims of human rights discourses, Ranciere sees formal

    Particular Rights and Absolute Wrongs 153

    123

  • 8/3/2019 whyte_agamben

    8/15

    equality as carrying a material weight that opens a space for substantive claims: if

    all are equal, then why not women too? If freedom from arbitrary imprisonment is

    an inalienable human right, why then should immigrants be detained? Following

    Ranciere, Zizek suggests that the properly cynical temptation of reducing it to a

    mere illusion that conceals a different actuality should be resisted (Zizek 2004,p. 22). Thus, in opposition to both Arendt, and to the Marxian characterization of a

    split between formal equality and substantive inequality, Ranciere challenges the

    view that human rights are simply the rights of those with no rights. Rather, he

    argues, the Rights of Man are the rights of those who have not the rights that they

    have and have the rights that they have not (Ranciere 2004, p. 302). By this, he

    means that those who are deprived of rightsthe immigrant, the woman, the

    workersimultaneously have these rights to the extent that they seize the rights that

    are inscribed as supposedly belonging to them, and use them as the basis for a

    political contestation (Ranciere 2004, p. 303).The subject of human rights that the title of Rancieres essay asks after is

    therefore not a pre-existing anthropological subject but the subject of a particular

    political dissensus. Relying on Aristotles description of the demos as those who

    had no part in anything (in Ranciere 1998, p. 9), Ranciere argues that the political

    subject in any situation is not a pre-existing collectivity or social group but a surplus

    name, a part of those who have no part that disrupts every attempt to order

    consensually the community (Ranciere 1998, p. 14). Political predicates, Ranciere

    argues, are always open predicates, in the sense that their use opens a dispute about

    what they entail, and whom they include. This means that political claims consistprecisely in subjecting the border of the political, the border that pertains to separate

    politics from life, to dispute (Ranciere 2004, p. 303). Politics, Ranciere argues, is the

    configuration of its proper place, a place that is never demarcated in advance

    (Ranciere 2004, p. 303). This means that political subjects, on Rancieres account,

    do more than contrast the supposed universality of rights to the reality of their

    particular application; they put together the world where those rights are valid and

    the world where they are not. They put together a relation of inclusion and a relation

    of exclusion (Ranciere 2004, p. 304).

    It is on the question of the political subject that Ranciere critiques Agamben who,

    he argues, collapses the space of politics into a pure power relation between

    sovereignty and bare life. Ranciere traces this depoliticizing gesture to Agambens

    relation to Arendt, writing:

    Agambens view of the camp as the nomos of modernity may seem very far

    from Arendts view of political action. Nevertheless, I would assume that the

    radical suspension of politics in the exception of bare life is the ultimate

    consequence of Arendts archipolitical position, of her attempt to preserve the

    political from the contamination of private, social, apolitical life. This attempt

    depopulates the political stage by sweeping aside its always-ambiguous actors(Ranciere 2004, p. 301).

    In Agambens state of exception, Ranciere argues, there is no space for contesting

    the borders of the political, and thus no politics at all. The will to preserve the realm

    of pure politics ultimately makes it vanish in the sheer relation of state power and

    154 J. Whyte

    123

  • 8/3/2019 whyte_agamben

    9/15

    individual life, he writes. Politics thus is equated with power, a power that is

    increasingly taken as an overwhelming historico-ontological destiny from which

    only a God is likely to save us (Ranciere 2004, p. 301302). Here, Ranciere is

    clearly evoking Martin Heidegger, in order implicitly to challenge Agambens desire

    to rethink politics in ontological terms. Before examining Agambens critique ofmetaphysics, however, I would like to spell out what I see as Rancieres misreading

    of Agamben on the relation of life and politics, which, Ranciere argues, relies on the

    Arendtian opposition of two lives (Ranciere 2004, p. 298).

    Throughout his essay, Ranciere consistently equates Agambens understanding

    of rights with Arendts institutionalist argumentan argument, Ranciere writes,

    that Agamben basically endorses (Ranciere 2004, p. 302). As we have seen, there

    are clear similarities between Agambens understanding of human rights, and

    modernity, and Arendts view of the relation that binds the Rights of Man to the

    modern nation state in such a way that the waning of the latter necessarily impliesthe obsolescence of the former (Agamben 2000, p. 19). And yet, while both

    thinkers share a diagnosis of modernity as typified by the blurring of life and politics

    and the increasing orientation of the state to the apolitical reproduction of life,

    Agambens response to this is directly counterposed to Arendts. In fact, Agambens

    belief that politics was originarily biopolitics means he could not be further from the

    Arendtian will to preserve the realm of pure politics of which Ranciere accuses

    him (Ranciere 2004, p. 302). The realm of pure politics, for Agamben, always

    presupposed the abandonment of bare life. Thus, in the modern collapse of the

    separation of life and politics that Arendt bemoans, he sees the condition ofpossibility of what he terms a completely new politics (Agamben 1998, p. 10).

    Agambens rejection of any project that aims to premise politics on its renewed

    separation from natural life could not be more explicit: I would not feel up to

    forgoing this indistinction of public and private, of biological body and political

    body, of zoe and bios, for any reason, he writes in Means Without Ends. It is here

    that I must find my space once againhere or nowhere else. Only a politics that

    starts from such an awareness can interest me (Agamben 2000, p. 139).

    So what is this politics? According to Ranciere, Agambens polarity of sovereign

    power and bare life collapses all dissensus and, as it were, all politics: That polarity

    appears as a sort of ontological destiny, Ranciere argues Any difference grows

    faint between democracy and totalitarianism and any political practice proves to be

    already ensnared in the biopolitical trap (Ranciere 2004, p. 301). Here it is worth

    noting that Agamben makes a similar point himself, in even more radical terms; In

    Homo Sacerhe writes:

    Until a completely new politicsthat is a politics no longer founded on the

    exceptio of bare lifeis at hand, every theory and every praxis will remain

    imprisoned and immobile, and the beautiful day of life will be given

    citizenship only either through blood and death or in the perfect senselessnessto which the society of the spectacle condemns it (Agamben 1998, p. 10).

    Thus, Ranciere is partly correct: Agamben does indeed see our time as one in

    which (what Ranciere understands as) dissensus would be already captured in the

    relation between sovereign power and bare life.

    Particular Rights and Absolute Wrongs 155

    123

  • 8/3/2019 whyte_agamben

    10/15

    In The Time that Remains, Agamben briefly considers Rancieres position that

    the people, or the political subject, is always the part of those with no part, the

    supernumerary part that is the bearer of a wrong, and thus disrupts every attempt to

    produce an orderly count of the political situation by opening this space to a dispute.

    Everything, Agamben suggests, depends on how we understand wrong anddispute. If democratic dispute is understood for what it truly is, that is, the

    possibility of stasis or of civil war, he writes, then the point is pertinent.

    If, however, following what Ranciere seems to think, the wrong for whom the

    people are a cipher is not absolute (as it still was in Marx) but, by definition,

    can be processed (Ranciere [1999, p. 39]) then the line between democracy

    and its consensual, or postdemocratic, counterfeit (which Ranciere goes so far

    as to overtly critique) tends to dissolve (Agamben 2005, p. 8).

    Here then, we have two claims, two accusations: on the one hand, Ranciereargues that Agambens dismissal of human rights is predicated on an elitist

    conception of pure politics which denies any possibility of political contestation,

    and leaves us trapped in an ontological destiny from which only a god can save us;

    on the other, Agamben suggests that Rancieres assertion of politics as the sphere of

    dispute over who and what is included in the political cannot be distinguished from

    the reign of a consensual ethics that both thinkers see as underlying the move

    towards a bloody militarism shrouded as humanitarian intervention. In the

    following section, I will turn to the terrain of ontology, in order to demonstrate why

    Agamben believes it is only here that we can break free of sovereign power, andavoid the complicity with the humanitarian state of which he implicitly accuses

    Ranciere.

    Being Alive

    In De Anima (On the Soul), Aristotle sets out to determine what it means to say that

    somethingwhether a plant, an animal or a humanis alive; For living beings, he

    writes, Being is life (in Agamben 1999a, p. 147). To this end, he establishes a

    series of divisions in the continuum of life, between what he terms nutritive,

    sensitive, appetitive, locomotive and intellectual life (Aristotle 1986, p. 210). While

    some of these are shared by only some living beings, and some only by the human,

    nutritive life, is present in others, and is primary, and is that most general power of

    the soul by which life is present in anything (Aristotle 1986, p. 54). In Aristotles

    isolation of nutritive life as the basic presupposition of all forms of life, Agamben

    sees the decisive moment in which, bare life as such was identified in the history

    of Western philosophy, a moment which he therefore identifies as the metaphysical

    foundation of modern biopolitics (Agamben 1999b, p. 230). Aristotles isolation of

    the general presupposition of nutritive life, Agamben suggests, served to mark

    divisions in the humanbetween vegetative and relational life, animal and

    humanwhich were then expressed in the political realm in the form of those

    distinctions between zoe and bios, and mere life (zen) and that good life (eu zen) that

    156 J. Whyte

    123

  • 8/3/2019 whyte_agamben

    11/15

    play a central role in Aristotles determination of the telos of politics and the work

    of man.

    It is this process of division that underlies Aristotles conception of the human as

    a living being with logos. Agambens account of metaphysics therefore consists in

    problematizing precisely this notion of human life, or logos, as an additionalcapacity, which he sees as implying a caesura thatbefore being expressed in the

    separation of oikos and polisruns through the human. Reflecting on Aristotles

    argument that the animal voice expresses only pleasure or pain, while human speech

    expresses the just and the unjust, Agamben locates this caesura in the human in the

    passage from the animal phone to human language. The living being has logos, he

    writes in Homo Sacer, by taking away and conserving its own voice in it, even as it

    dwells in the polis by letting its own bare life be excluded, as an exception, in it

    (Agamben 1998, p. 8). No longer the animal phone, which must be excluded to

    enable human language, but not yet language, what is captured in the passage tolanguage is a removed voice, or as Agamben terms it, a Voiceby which he refers

    to the taking place of language that occurs in a no mans land between sound and

    signification (Agamben 1991, p. 33). This metaphysical definition of the human is

    therefore achieved through the same ban structure that we have already identified:

    like political life, the fully human lifelife according to logosis achieved only

    through the separation and abandonment of bare life.

    This metaphysical definition of the human is intimately entwined with the

    question of politics. In isolating bare life, Agamben suggests, Aristotle is aiming to

    discover what is proper to man qua man, and whether man qua man has a work.From the isolation of a specific work of manwhich Aristotle sees as a particular

    form of life: life according to logosAristotle derives the end of politics. Politics,

    thus enables man to actualize the rational capacity Aristotle had isolated as

    definitive of human life, and to live according to what is proper to him; the polis is

    the place in which the metaphysical determination of man as a living being with

    logos is actualized. The political, as the work of man as man, Agamben argues, is

    drawn out of the living being through the exclusionas unpoliticalof a part of its

    vital activity (Agamben 2007, p. 6). Both politics and metaphysics, Agamben

    argues, are founded on the exclusion of that life that men share with other living

    beings. Thus, in contrast to humanismor what he refers to as the anthropological

    machine, which sees man as a conjunction of these elementsAgamben suggests

    that we should rather concern ourselves with their separation: It is more urgent to

    work on these divisions, to ask in what waywithin manhas man been separated

    from non-man, he writes, than it is to take positions on the so-called great issues,

    on human rights and values (Agamben 2004, p. 16). If, despite this suggestion,

    Agamben is indeed interested in the issue of human rights, his own position is

    informed by the view that any analysis of rights declarations must concern itself

    with precisely this mystery of separationwhich, in his view, is the basic

    presupposition of sovereignty and of every division and every articulation between

    life and politics (Agamben 2004, p. 16). Political power as we know it, he writes,

    always founds itselfin the last instanceon the separation of a sphere of naked

    life from the context of the forms of life (Agamben 2000, p. 4). And yet, while the

    contemporary indistinction of life and politics does indeed seem a desperate

    Particular Rights and Absolute Wrongs 157

    123

  • 8/3/2019 whyte_agamben

    12/15

    situation, if Agamben is filled with hope, this is because in the unity of politics and

    life expressed in human rights declarationsin a life that has no need to take on

    other values in order to become politicalhe sees the possibility of what he calls a

    form-of-lifea life that cannot be separated from its form, and for which what is at

    stake in the ways of living is living itself (Agamben 2000, p. 3).

    Remnant

    In explaining his lack of pessimism, Agamben argues that contemporary events are

    producing not only a new figure of domination but also a new figure of the subject,

    which arises out of the forms of desubjectivation most commonly associated with

    the collapse of the border of life and politics. Desubjectivation does not only have a

    dark side. It is not simply the destruction of all subjectivity. Agamben writes.There is also this other pole, more fecund and poetic, where the subject is only the

    subject of its own desubjectivation (Vacarme 2004, p. 124). This subject would be

    without substantive identity, and would therefore be unable to be represented by a

    state, claim juridical rights, or form the basis for an exclusive community (Agamben

    2005, p. 52). Agambens rejection of identity and his articulation of a non-juridical

    politics is premised on the view that any politics that presupposes a substantive

    subject leads to bloody forms of exclusion and to that capture of natural life that, he

    argues, is the originary act of sovereign power. In contrast, a subject that was only

    the subject of its own desubjectivation would be a life that would utterly escape thehold of sovereignty. Rather than having a natural life lived in the home and a

    political life lived in the state, this life would be an inseparable unity of life and

    politicswhat Agamben terms a form-of-lifein which life was exhausted in its

    ways of living. If todays desperate situation fills him with hope, this is because

    just as Marx saw the ravages of capitalism as producing the circumstances which

    made communism possibleAgamben sees todays indistinction of life and politics

    as creating the possibility, for the first time in history, of a new non-juridical

    politics, and of the inauguration of a form-of-life, or, as he puts it more simply

    elsewhere, a happy life (Agamben 2000, p. 3).

    In The Time that Remains, Agamben suggests his conception of the subject as the

    subject of its own desubjectivation permits more than one analogy with the

    Marxian proletariat (Agamben 2005, p. 31). In contrast to the working class as a

    sociological category, Agamben sees the proletariat as a non-substantive subject

    that must negate itself (as proletariat) in order to liberate itself and all of humanity.

    In a discussion of messianism and revolution, Agamben argues that the

    revolutionary vocation of the proletariat is not a new factical vocation but the

    nullification, or hollowing out, of every vocation. The proletariat thus lays bare

    the contingency of every factical vocationthe split between the private individual

    and her social positionwhile enabling the un-working of this separation. Thus, in

    Agambens view, the fact that the proletariat ends up over time being identified

    with a determinate social classthe working class that claims prerogatives and

    rights for itselfis the worst misunderstanding of Marxian thought (Agamben

    2005, p. 31). Like Agamben, Ranciere challenges every conception of politics

    158 J. Whyte

    123

  • 8/3/2019 whyte_agamben

    13/15

    predicated on the social being of a pre-constituted social group. What Agamben

    refers to as the remnant, however, is not simply the part with no part that opens the

    community to dispute, but that which can never coincide with itself, and which

    reveals the arbitrary nature of every social position (Agamben 2005, p. 57). The

    remnant is therefore not the object of liberation but its instrument. The remnant cannever be liberated as such but, through its own auto-suppression, makes liberation

    possible. It can never be includedin the political as it attests to the reliance of every

    relation of inclusion and exclusion, and every separation between life and politics,

    on the workings of the sovereign ban. Thus the remnant testifies to the wrong at the

    heart of every order of inclusion and, as the bearer of this absolute wrong, it cannot

    claim particular rights for itself. The remnant, as Marx said of the proletariat, has a

    universal character by its universal suffering and claims no particular rightbecause

    no particular wrong but wrong generally is perpetrated against it (in Agamben

    2005, p. 31). The remnant, Agamben argues, is the only real political subjectanon-substantial subject that is always the subject of its own desubjectivation

    (Agamben 2005, p. 57). Agamben therefore offers an account in which the

    separation of life and politics that has characterized Western politics since Aristotle

    is predicated on the absolute wrong of the sovereign ban. This means that any

    politics that is unable to overcome this separation will be unable to overcome the

    bloody mystification of a new planetary order (Agamben 1998, p. 12). If every

    relation of inclusion always implies an inclusive exclusion, or abandonment, then

    the only politics capable of overcoming this separation would be one that contested

    not merely specific exclusions, but the very constitution of the political spherethrough the inclusive-exclusion of bare life. Such a challenge, in Agambens view,

    must also overcome the metaphysical determination of the human, which is the

    ontological basis of both the separation of life and politics and the abandonment of

    bare life.

    If Agamben is not pessimistic, this is because in the collapse of the border of

    politics and life, which so distressed Arendt, he sees the condition of possibility of

    this new politics, in which it would no longer be possible to isolate a bare life.

    Where Rancieres critique is pertinent, however, is in his argument that Agambens

    critique depopulates the political stage of its actors. While Marxs hope, in the face

    of the desperate situation of early capitalism, was, at least in part, generated by his

    belief that capitalism creates its own gravediggers, in Agambens work these

    gravediggers are missing; in the place of political actors, struggling collectively

    against the system of which they are a product, Agambens work is populated by

    figures whose lives border on death and whose extreme manifestations are the

    Muselmann of the Nazi camps, and the neomort who survives merely by virtue of

    artificial respiratory technologies. In the absence of any discussion of other political

    possibilities, and in the subsumption of the logic of politics to the logic of the

    sovereign ban, Agamben offers little on what would make the difference between a

    form-of-life and life in the camp, between a collective form of desubjectivation

    reminiscent of the original vocation assigned to the Marxian proletariat and an

    individual form of hopeless desubjectivation imposed by sovereign power. To say

    this is not to ask Agamben to provide a programme towards an ideal end statea

    demand that would be contrary to his entire project, which aims to think a politics of

    Particular Rights and Absolute Wrongs 159

    123

  • 8/3/2019 whyte_agamben

    14/15

    pure means, in which political action could not be instrumentalized in the name of a

    state that would be actualized in the future. My point, rather, is that anyone

    interested in immanent social transformation must be interested in political struggles

    and concrete acts of resistance if they are not to fall into a teleological and

    deterministic understanding of such transformationas indeed was the fate ofMarxism in its social democratic and Stalinist forms, both of which forgot that

    Marxs optimism about capitalism was an optimism about its capacity to create the

    forms of political agency that could abolish it. While political practice that takes the

    form of rights claims ultimately presupposes the state and the relation of

    sovereignty and bare life, there are, even in the midst of our desperate situation,

    forms of political practice and experiments in the possible that seek to trace paths

    out of this relation. If we are to avoid an optimism sustained through teleological

    certainty, which pervaded so much of the Marxist traditionif we are not, in

    Marxs words, to go on hoping merely out of stupidityit is towards suchexperiments that we should direct our attention (Marx 1843).

    References

    Agamben, Giorgio. 1991. Language and death: The place of negativity. Minneapolis: University of

    Minnesota Press.

    Agamben, Giorgio. 1998. Homo Sacer: Sovereign power and bare life. Stanford: Stanford University

    Press.Agamben, Giorgio. 1999a. Remnants of Auschwitz. New York: MIT Press.

    Agamben, Giorgio. 1999b. Potentialities: Collected essays in philosophy. Stanford: Stanford University

    Press.

    Agamben, Giorgio. 2000. Means without ends. Minneapolis & London: University of Minnesota Press.

    Agamben, Giorgio. 2004. The Open. Stanford: Stanford University Press.

    Agamben, Giorgio. 2005. The time that remains: A commentary on the letter to the Romans . Stanford:

    Stanford University Press.

    Agamben, Giorgio. 2007. The work of man. In Giorgio Agamben: Sovereignty, life, ed. Calarco Matthew,

    and DeCaroli Steven. Stanford: Stanford University Press.

    Arendt, Hannah. 1958. The human condition. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Arendt, Hannah. 1976. The decline of the nation-state and the end of the rights of man. The origins of

    totalitarianism. London: Allen and Unwin.Arendt, Hannah. 1990. On revolution. London: Penguin Classics.

    Aristotle, 1942. The politics. Middlesex: Penguin.

    Aristotle, 1986. De Anima. London: Penguin Classics.

    Balibar, Etienne. 2007. (De)Constructing the human as human institution. Social Research 74: 3.

    Brown, Wendy. 2004. The most we can hope for: Human rights and the politics of fatalism. South

    Atlantic Quarterly 103: 451463.

    Douzinas, Costas. 2000. The end of human rights. Oxford: Hart.

    Marx, Karl. 1843. Letter to Arnold Ruge. Cologne: Marxists Internet Archive. http://www.marxists.org/

    archive/marx/works/1843/letters/43_05-alt.htm.

    Nancy, Jean Luc. 1993. Abandoned being. In The birth to presence. Stanford: Stanford University Press.

    Ranciere, Jacques. 1994. On the shores of politics. London: Verso.Ranciere, Jacques. 1998. Dis-agreement: Politics and philosophy. Minneapolis and London: University of

    Minnesota Press.

    Ranciere, Jacques. 1999. Dis-agreement: Politics and philosophy. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota

    Press.

    Ranciere, Jacques. 2004. Who is the subject of human rights? South Atlantic Quarterly 103: 297310.

    160 J. Whyte

    123

    http://www.marxists.org/archive/marx/works/1843/letters/43_05-alt.htmhttp://www.marxists.org/archive/marx/works/1843/letters/43_05-alt.htmhttp://www.marxists.org/archive/marx/works/1843/letters/43_05-alt.htmhttp://www.marxists.org/archive/marx/works/1843/letters/43_05-alt.htm
  • 8/3/2019 whyte_agamben

    15/15