Nicholas R. Miller University of Maryland Baltimore County (UMBC)

51
THE ALTERNATIVE VOTE (AND COOMBS) VERSUS FIRST-PAST-THE-POST: A SOCIAL CHOICE ANALYSIS OF ENGLISH CONSTITUENCY ELECTIONS, 1992-2010 Nicholas R. Miller University of Maryland Baltimore County (UMBC) Second World Congress of the Public Choice Societies Miami, March 8-11, 2012 http://userpages.umbc.edu/~nmiller/NRMILLER.AVvsFPTP.PCS12.pdf

description

THE ALTERNATIVE VOTE (AND COOMBS) VERSUS FIRST-PAST-THE-POST: A SOCIAL CHOICE ANALYSIS OF ENGLISH CONSTITUENCY ELECTIONS, 1992-2010. Nicholas R. Miller University of Maryland Baltimore County (UMBC) Second World Congress of the Public Choice Societies Miami, March 8-11, 2012 - PowerPoint PPT Presentation

Transcript of Nicholas R. Miller University of Maryland Baltimore County (UMBC)

Page 1: Nicholas R. Miller University of Maryland Baltimore County (UMBC)

THE ALTERNATIVE VOTE (AND COOMBS) VERSUS FIRST-PAST-THE-POST:

A SOCIAL CHOICE ANALYSIS OF ENGLISH CONSTITUENCY ELECTIONS,

1992-2010

Nicholas R. MillerUniversity of Maryland Baltimore County (UMBC)

Second World Congress of the Public Choice SocietiesMiami, March 8-11, 2012

http://userpages.umbc.edu/~nmiller/NRMILLER.AVvsFPTP.PCS12.pdf

Page 2: Nicholas R. Miller University of Maryland Baltimore County (UMBC)

Overview: An Opportunistic Paper• Peter K-K’s invitation for paper on “empirical social choice”• I initially expected to do something relating to the U.S. Electoral College.• I was also working “Monotonicity Failure and IRV” and wanted to examine 2010 UK election

data.• I found Pippa Norris’s Shared Datasets website, with 1992-2010 UK data.• The UK held a May 2011 referendum on electoral systems: AV vs. FPTP• The paper has no particular thesis or research hypothesis.• Rather it examines a sample of 2642 “real” ballot profiles, in terms of

– the plurality (and anti-plurality) status of candidates;– the Condorcet status of, and relationships among, the candidates ;– plurality-Condorcet interrelationships;– winners under the three alternative electoral systems: FPTP, AV [IRV], Coombs;– the votes-seats proportionality of results under these electoral systems; – spoiler effects under all three systems; and monotonicity failure under AV and Coombs.

• I also examine several more hypothetical sets of ballot profiles that “bracket” the primary set.• I do not here come to grips with “tactical voting” or a general assessments of the relative

merits of the three systems.• FPTP won the referendum by a large margin. • The pre-referendum campaign did not stimulate an especially enlightening discussion of the

properties and relative advantages and disadvantages of the two electoral systems.

Page 3: Nicholas R. Miller University of Maryland Baltimore County (UMBC)
Page 4: Nicholas R. Miller University of Maryland Baltimore County (UMBC)

Alternative Electoral Systems• On an FTPT (“First-Past-The Post”) ballot,

– voters put an “X” beside the name of the candidate they wish to vote for, and – the candidate with the most votes is elected.

• On an AV (“Alternative Vote”; known as Instant Runoff Voting [IRV] in US) ballot, voters rank the candidates in order of preference. – If one candidate has a majority of first preferences, that candidate is elected. – If no candidate is supported by a majority of first preferences,

• the candidate with the fewest first preferences is eliminated and • his or her ballots are transferred to other candidates on the basis of the second

preferences expressed on the ballots for the eliminated candidate. • This process is repeated until one candidate is supported by a majority of ballots

and is elected.

• “If you like the Alternative Vote, you ought to know about the Coombs rule” (Grofman and Feld, 2004): similar AV but with a different elimination rule: – the candidate with the most last preferences is eliminated.

Bernard Grofman and Scott Feld, “If You Like the Alternative Vote (a.k.a. the Instant Runoff), Then You Ought to Know about the Coombs Rule,” Electoral Studies, 2004.

Page 5: Nicholas R. Miller University of Maryland Baltimore County (UMBC)

Political Context• Since they were displaced by Labour as the main opposition

to the Conservatives in the inter-war period, the Liberals have joined the Electoral Reform Society in advocating the Single Transferable Vote for general elections.

• STV is– the multi-member district generalization of AV and – (quasi-) proportional in nature.

• More recently the Liberal Democrats have advocated AV as less radical but more acceptable alternative to FPTP.– Nick Clegg: “AV is a baby step in the right direction – only because

nothing can be worse than the status quo.” • The Liberals demanded the AV referendum a condition for

joining the Conservatives in a coalition government after the May 2010 general election.

Page 6: Nicholas R. Miller University of Maryland Baltimore County (UMBC)

Political Context (cont.)• As a generally centrist party, the Liberals have a lot of second preference support,

though relatively little first preference support.– Since AV asks voters to rank candidates and often counts second preferences, at first

blush it seems that AV would help the Liberals.– But while second-preference support helps a candidate if and when he gets into a

runoffs, second-preference support doesn’t help a candidate get into a runoff in the first place.

– As Aldrich et al. (2012) observe, if AV were applied at the national level (e.g., in a direct election of Prime Minister), the Liberals would still lose, since their candidate would not get into the runoff.• Aldrich et al. examine four alternatives to FPTP (Condorcet, AV, Coombs, and Borda)

and conclude that the Liberals would have won such a national vote in 2010 under all four systems except the one they actually advocated.

– A basic question is the extent to which individual constituencies are approximate replicas of the national electorate, implying that Liberal candidates would consistently fail to get into runoffs in which their second-preference support could elect them.

• Coombs should be much more advantageous to Liberals because – second preferences not only help candidates win a runoff in the event they get in, but also– help them get into a runoff in the first place (by leaving them fewer last preferences).

John Aldrich et al., “Strategic Voting in the 2010 U.K. Election,” APSA Meeting, 2012.

Page 7: Nicholas R. Miller University of Maryland Baltimore County (UMBC)

Social Choice Analysis• The analysis is based on three simplifying conditions:– there are only three candidates,

• so there is at most only one “instant runoff.”– voters ranks all three candidates.

• In practice, AV may allow “truncated” ballots, – but Coombs really cannot do so.– In practice Coombs (even more than AV) may be vulnerable to

“donkey voting.”

– there are no plurality (or anti-plurality) or pairwise ties.

• A ballot profile is a set of n rankings of three candidates X, Y, and Z, where n is the number of voters.

Page 8: Nicholas R. Miller University of Maryland Baltimore County (UMBC)

Plurality Status• Given a particular profile B:

– the candidate with the most first preferences is the Plurality Winner, – the candidate with the second most first preferences is the Plurality Runner-

Up, and – the candidate with the fewest first preferences is the Plurality Loser. – Let n(PW), n(P2), and n(PL) be the number of ballots that rank the Plurality

Winner, the Plurality Runner-Up, and Plurality Loser first. – Given three candidates, n(PW) > n/3 > n(PL). – If n(PW) > n/2, the Plurality Winner is also a Majority Winner. – The AV winner is

• the Majority Winner if one exists and • otherwise either the Plurality Winner or the Plurality Runner-Up, depending on

the outcome of the instant runoff between them.

• Note that all these definitions depend on the distribution of first preferences only.

Page 9: Nicholas R. Miller University of Maryland Baltimore County (UMBC)

Condorcet Relationships• Condorcet relationships take account of second (and lower)

preferences.• Given ballot profile B,

– candidates X, Y, and Z have x, y, and z first preferences respectively, where x + y + z = n.

• Likewise xy is the number of voters who have a first preference for X and second preference for Y (and therefore a third preference for Z), xz is the number who have a first preference for X and a second preference for Z, so xy + xz = x; and likewise for other candidates.

• If under election profile B a majority of voters rank X over Y, i.e., if x + zx > y + zy, we say that ‘X beats Y’ in a “straight fight” (to use an appropriately British phrase). – This is the basic Condorcet relationship.

Page 10: Nicholas R. Miller University of Maryland Baltimore County (UMBC)

Condorcet Relationships (cont.)• Given three candidates and a particular profile B:

– a Condorcet Winner is a candidate who beats both other candidates.– a Condorcet Loser is a candidate who is beaten by both other

candidates; and – Condorcet Carrier is a candidate who beats one candidate and is

beaten by the other.• In the theory of directed graphs, a carrier is a point with ‘in-degree’ and ‘out-

degree’ both equal to 1.

• If X beats Y, Y beats Z, and Z beats X or if Y beats X, X beats Z, and Z beats Y, – there is a Condorcet cycle, and – all three candidates are Condorcet carriers.

Page 11: Nicholas R. Miller University of Maryland Baltimore County (UMBC)

Anti-Plurality Status• Given ballot profile B:

– the candidate with the fewest last preferences is the Anti-Plurality Winner,

– the candidate with the second fewest last preferences is the Anti-Plurality Runner-Up, and

– the candidate with the most last preferences is the Anti-Plurality Loser.

– Let n(APW), n(AP2), and n(APL) be the number of ballots that rank the Anti-Plurality Winner, the Anti-Plurality Runner-Up, and Anti-Plurality Loser last.

– Given three candidates, it follows that n(APW) < n/3 < n(APL). – The Coombs winner

• is the Majority Winner if one exists and • otherwise is either the Anti-Plurality Winner or the Anti-Plurality Runner-

Up, depending on the outcome of the instant runoff (based on the Condorcet relationship) between them.

Page 12: Nicholas R. Miller University of Maryland Baltimore County (UMBC)

Plurality--Condorcet Interrelationships• Some elementary social choice propositions for the case of three candidates:

PROPOSITION 1. A Majority Winner is always a Condorcet Winner.PROPOSITION 2. The Plurality Winner always wins under FPTP (by definition).PROPOSITION 3. Plurality and Condorcet status are completely independent, in particular,

• the Plurality Winner may be a Condorcet Loser, and• the Plurality Loser may be a Condorcet Winner, so• a Condorcet Winner may fail to be elected under FPTP; and• a Condorcet Loser may be elected under FPTP.

PROPOSITION 4. Either the Plurality Winner or Plurality Runner-Up may be elected under AV,

• so FPTP and AV may produce different winners.PROPOSITION 5. The Plurality Loser cannot be elected under AV,

• because it is eliminated from the instant runoff.PROPOSITION 6. A Condorcet Loser cannot be elected under AV,

• because, even if it gets into the runoff, it will be beaten in the runoff.

Page 13: Nicholas R. Miller University of Maryland Baltimore County (UMBC)

Plurality---Anti-Plurality—Condorcet Interrelationships

• For the case of three candidates:

PROPOSITION 7. Plurality and anti-plurality status are completely independent; in particular,

• the Anti-Plurality Winner may be the Plurality Loser, and• the Anti-Plurality Loser may be the Plurality Winner.

PROPOSITION 8. Condorcet and anti-plurality status are in the general case completely independent; in particular,

• the Anti-Plurality Winner may be a Condorcet Loser, and• the Anti-Plurality Loser may be a Condorcet Winner.

PROPOSITION 9. However, in the special case of single-peaked preferences,• the Condorcet winner has no last preferences and therefore is always the

Anti-Plurality winner, so• Coombs always elects the Condorcet winner.

– In fact, this is true regardless of the number of candidates.

Page 14: Nicholas R. Miller University of Maryland Baltimore County (UMBC)

Empirical Data• The empirical analysis that follows is based on constituency-level

data from U.K. general elections from 1992 through 2010. • However, I use data from English constituencies only,

– because virtually all constituency elections in England are essentially three-party (Labour, Liberal Democrat, and Conservative) affairs,

– while those in Wales, Scotland, and Northern Ireland almost always include strong (and often winning) candidates of ‘nationalist’ parties as well.

– A handful of English constituencies that do not fit the three-party pattern are also excluded.

• Over the five general elections, this gives us a sample of 2642 three-candidate elections (527 to 531 per year).

This data comes from Pippa Norris’s Shared Datasets website (http://www.hks.harvard.edu/fs/pnorris/ Data/Data.htm). I am extremely grateful to Professor Norris for making this valuable data readily available.

Page 15: Nicholas R. Miller University of Maryland Baltimore County (UMBC)

The Problem of Second Preferences• An obvious problem is that these elections were conducted under FPTP and

therefore the election data provides us only (what we take to be) the first-preferences of voters, – while analysis of AV (and Coombs) elections requires voters’ full preference rankings of the

three major-party candidates. • I have addressed this problem in a way that is fairly standard among those British

psephologists, which is to allocate second preferences (and by default third preferences) in each district in proportion to second preferences nationwide, as determined by surveys that produce individual level data about second preferences. – Data for 1992 through 2005 comes from Curtice (2009), which in turn comes from the British

Election Study (post-election) for 1992 and 1997 and from ICM/BBC (pre-election) for 2001 and 2005. Data for 2010 comes from Ritchie and Gardini (2012), which in turn was taken a (pre-election) poll conducted for ITV News and The Independent newspaper.

• Survey respondents who gave a ‘nationalist’ or other fourth-party second preference, or who did not give a second-preference were excluded in these calculations, and proportions were calculated on the basis of Labour plus Liberal plus Conservative second preferences only.

John Curtice, “Recent History of Second Preferences” (http://news.bbc.co.uk/ nol/shared/ spl/hi/uk_politics/10/ alternative _vote/alternative_vote_june_09_notes.pdf)Ken Ritchie and Alessandro Gardini, “Putting Paradoxes into Perspective — In Defence of the Alternative Vote,” in Dan S. Felsenthal and Moshé Machover, eds., Electoral Systems: Paradoxes, Assumptions, and Procedures, 2012

Page 16: Nicholas R. Miller University of Maryland Baltimore County (UMBC)

Survey-Based Second Preferences

• As we would expect, that British voter preferences are “partially single-peaked,”– that is, most but not all Labour (presumptively ‘left-of-center’) voters have the Liberals

(the presumptively ‘centrist’ party) as their second preference, and – most but not all Conservative (presumptively ‘right-of-center’) voters likewise have the

Liberal as their second preference, while – Liberal voters have second preference more equally divided between the two other

parties (though generally leaning in the Labour direction but with the proportion varying considerably from election to election).

Page 17: Nicholas R. Miller University of Maryland Baltimore County (UMBC)

Other Second-Preference Assumptions • Strictly Single-Peaked Preferences: all Labour

and Conservative voters have Liberal as their second preferences.

• No ideological structuring of preferences: – Random second preferences: on average,

second preferences are equally split, and– Impartial second preferences: on each

ballot profile, the second preference of each voter is determined by a flip of a coin.

• SSP and Random/Impartial in effect “bracket” survey-based data.

• In addition, we occasionally compare the English data with – wholly random ballot profiles and – wholly impartial (culture) ballot profiles.,– in which first as well as second

preferences are determined “randomly” or “impartially.”

Page 18: Nicholas R. Miller University of Maryland Baltimore County (UMBC)

Plurality Status of Party Candidates(All Second-Preference Assumptions)

Page 19: Nicholas R. Miller University of Maryland Baltimore County (UMBC)

Plurality Rankings of Party Candidates (All Second-Preference Assumptions)

Page 20: Nicholas R. Miller University of Maryland Baltimore County (UMBC)

Condorcet Relationships(All Second-Preference Assumptions Plus Random Profiles and

Impartial Culture)

Page 21: Nicholas R. Miller University of Maryland Baltimore County (UMBC)

Plurality-Condorcet Interrelationships

Page 22: Nicholas R. Miller University of Maryland Baltimore County (UMBC)

AV vs. FTPT Winners

• Given a switch from FPTP to AV, an average 7.5% constituencies change party hands. • Liberals are consistently helped by AV, losing not a single seat, gaining on average

4.3% of all seats (a 65% gain in seats). • Conservatives are almost as consistently hurt by AV, gaining a handful of seats (from

Labour in 1992) but losing on average 6.3% of all seats (a 14.5% loss in seats).• Labour is inconsistently affected by AV, gaining seats in good Labour years, losing

seats in bad Labour years, and gaining on average 1.9% of all seats (a 3.8% gain in seats.

Page 23: Nicholas R. Miller University of Maryland Baltimore County (UMBC)

Coombs vs. FPTP Winners

• Given a switch from FPTP to Coombs, an average 16% constituencies change party hands.

• Liberals are greatly and consistently helped by Coombs, losing not a single seat, gaining on average 11.2% of all seats (a 170% gain in seats), and placing second in three years.

• Conservatives are almost as consistently hurt by Coombs, gaining seats from Labour in 1992 but losing on average 11.4% of all seats (a 26% loss in seats).

• Labour is inconsistently affected by Coombs, gaining seats in good Labour years, losing seats in bad Labour years, and gaining/losing nothing on average.

Page 24: Nicholas R. Miller University of Maryland Baltimore County (UMBC)

Coombs vs. AV Winners

• Given switch from AV to Coombs, an average 9.5% constituencies change party hands. • Liberals are consistently helped by AV, losing not a single seat, gaining on average 6.9%

of all seats (a 63% gain in seats). • Conservatives are almost as consistently hurt by AV, gaining a few seats (from Labour

in 1992) but losing on average 5.1% of all seats (a 13.8% loss in seats).• Labour is inconsistently impacted by AV, gaining seats in good Labour years, losing

seats in bad Labour years, and losing on average 1.8% of all seats (a 3.5% loss in seats.

Page 25: Nicholas R. Miller University of Maryland Baltimore County (UMBC)

AV and FPTP Winners with DifferentSecond Preferences

• The Liberals gain slightly fewer seats under AV if preferences are strictly single peaked.• With random second preferences, there is very little difference between AV and FPTP

(random “erosion” of the FPTP distribution).• With impartial second preferences, there is essentially no difference between AV and

FPTP.

Page 26: Nicholas R. Miller University of Maryland Baltimore County (UMBC)

Coombs and FPTP Winners with DifferentSecond Preferences

• The Liberals gain vastly more seats under Coombs if preferences are strictly single-peaked, winning more seats than either Labour or the Conservatives,– exactly paralleling Condorcet Winner status (from previous table).

• With random second preferences, there is almost no difference between AV and FPTP (random “erosion” of the FPTP distribution).

• With impartial second preferences, there is essentially no difference between AV and FPTP.

Page 27: Nicholas R. Miller University of Maryland Baltimore County (UMBC)

Coombs and AV Winners with DifferentSecond Preferences

• The Liberals gain vastly more seats under Coombs if preferences are strictly single-peaked, winning more seats than either Labour or the Conservatives,

• With random second preferences, there is almost no difference between AV and FPTP (random “erosion” of the FPTP distribution).

• With impartial second preferences, there is essentially no difference between AV and FPTP.

Page 28: Nicholas R. Miller University of Maryland Baltimore County (UMBC)

Disproportionality(Survey Second Preferences)

• Gallagher Index of Disproportionality =

• Coombs delivers quite proportional results in 2010 but highly disproportional results in 1997 and 2001.

• But overall all three system are substantially and approximately equally disproportional.

Michael Gallagher, “Proportionality, Dispropor-tionality and Electoral Systems,” Electoral Studies, 1991

Page 29: Nicholas R. Miller University of Maryland Baltimore County (UMBC)

Disproportionality(Strictly Single-Peaked)

• In this data, Coombs vastly overcorrects the penalty imposed on the Liberals by FPTP and generally is less proportional than FPTP and AV.

• Overall all three system are substantially disproportional, FPTP and AV being about equal disproportional as under the previous data.

Page 30: Nicholas R. Miller University of Maryland Baltimore County (UMBC)

Spoiler Effects• Given a potential three-candidate (X, Y, and Z) election, the entry of

candidate X into what would otherwise be a two-candidate contest (or X’s exit from a three-candidate contest) can have three effects:

(1) No Spoiler Effect I: the same candidate (Y or Z) wins in either event;(2) No Spoiler Effect II: X wins if X enters, Y or Z wins otherwise; or(3) Spoiler Effect: X does cannot win even if X enters, but Y wins if X is out and Z wins if X is in, i.e., X’s entry “spoils” Y’s election (or X’s exit “spoils” Z’s election).

• Two types of spoiler effects:– unilateral spoiler: X’s entry spoils Y’s election but Y’s entry does not spoil X’s

election;– mutual spoilers: X’s entry spoils Y’s election and Y’s entry spoils X’s election

(e.g., X and Y are “clones”);• In the following discussion, majority, plurality, anti-plurality, and

Condorcet status refers to (potential) the three-candidate ballot profile.

Page 31: Nicholas R. Miller University of Maryland Baltimore County (UMBC)

Spoiler Effects (cont.)• PROPOSITION 10. If there is a Majority Winner, no spoiler effects

occur under FTPT, AV, or Coombs. • Otherwise we examine eight possible election configurations with

respect to – the plurality status of the candidates and the Condorcet relationships among

them (for FPTP and AV); and– the anti-plurality status of the candidates and the Condorcet relationships

among them (for Coombs).• There are two configurations of each following type:

– PW (or APW) is CW [(1a) and (1b)];– P2 (or AP2) is CW [(2a) and (2b)];– PL (or APL) is CW [(3a) and (3b)];– there is no CW (cyclical) [(4a) and (4b)].

• The outcome of every straight fight is determined by the Condorcet (“beats”) relationship.

Page 32: Nicholas R. Miller University of Maryland Baltimore County (UMBC)

Spoilers under FPTP

• Under FPTP, the winner of the three-candidate contest is (by definition) always PW.

• The number by each candidate shows the spoiler effect that results when that candidate enters/exists the election.

Page 33: Nicholas R. Miller University of Maryland Baltimore County (UMBC)

Spoiler Effects under FPTP• PROPOSITION 11. The Plurality Winner can never be a spoiler

under FPTP. – PW wins whenever it enters, so always No Spoiler Effect II.

• PROPOSITION 12. FPTP is invulnerable to spoiler effects if and only if PW = CW [(1a) and (1b)].

• PROPOSITION 13. FPTP is vulnerable to mutual spoiler effects if and only if PW = CL [(2b) and (3b)].

• PROPOSITION 14. Otherwise FPTP is always vulnerable to unilateral spoiler effects.

Page 34: Nicholas R. Miller University of Maryland Baltimore County (UMBC)

Spoilers under AV

• Under AV, the runoff (if any) is between PW and P2.

• So the winner of a three-candidate election is– PW if PW P2, and– P2 if P2 PW.

Page 35: Nicholas R. Miller University of Maryland Baltimore County (UMBC)

Spoiler Effects Under AV• PROPOSITION 15. The Plurality Loser can never be a spoiler

under AV. – PL never makes the runoff and, in the runoff, second preferences are

distributed just as they would be if PL never entered.• PROPOSITION 16. The Condorcet Winner is never a spoiler

under AV• PROPOSITION 17. AV is vulnerable to spoiler effects if and

only if PL = CW or the profile is cyclical [(3a), (3b), (4a), (4b)].• PROPOSITION 18. AV is invulnerable to mutual spoiler effects.• PROPOSITION 19. AV does not [logically] “dominate” FPTP

with respect to resisting spoiler effects; in particular, PW can be a spoiler under AV (if it is not the AV winner).

Page 36: Nicholas R. Miller University of Maryland Baltimore County (UMBC)

Spoilers under Coombs

• Under Coombs, the runoff (if any) is between APW and AP2.

• So the winner of a three-candidate election is – APW if APW AP2,

and– AP2 if AP2 APW.

Page 37: Nicholas R. Miller University of Maryland Baltimore County (UMBC)

Spoiler Effects under Coombs• PROPOSITION 20. The Anti-Plurality Loser can never be a spoiler

under Coombs. [APL never makes the runoff, and second preferences are distributed just as they would be if APL did not enter.]

• PROPOSITION 21. The Condorcet Winner is never a spoiler under AV.• PROPOSITION 22. Coombs is vulnerable to spoiler effects if and only

if APL = CW or in the event of a cycle [(3a), (3b), (4a), (4b)].• PROPOSITION 23. Coombs is invulnerable to mutual spoiler effects.• PROPOSITION 24. Coombs does not [logically] “dominate” FPTP with

respect to resisting spoiler effects. • If preferences are single-peaked,

– the Condorcet Winner has no last preferences, and – the Anti-Plurality Winner is therefore always the Condorcet Winner,– so only configurations (1a) and (1b) can occur.

• PROPOSITION 25. If preferences are single-peaked, Coombs is invulnerable to spoiler effects.

Page 38: Nicholas R. Miller University of Maryland Baltimore County (UMBC)

Frequency of Spoilers in England under FPT, AV, and Coombs

• Overall, in this data AV and Coombs are considerably less vulnerable to spoilers effects than FPTP.

• The incidence of spoilers is slightly greater under Coombs than AV, even though – the data is partially single-

peaked, and – Coombs in invulnerable to

spoilers given strictly single-peaked profiles.

• It is notable than the 2010 election (close to a three-way tie with respect to first preferences) was highly vulnerable to spoiler effects under both FPTP and AV but not Coombs.

Page 39: Nicholas R. Miller University of Maryland Baltimore County (UMBC)

The “Nader Effect”• A fundamental virtue of AV (and Coombs) is that it precludes the

“Nader effect,” i.e.,– the fact that a minor candidate (i.e., one who wins only a small percent of

the vote) can be a spoiler under FPTP (in the manner of Ralph Nader in FL [and therefore the US as a whole] in 2000).

• Under AV (and Coombs), (most) Nader voters could have (and presumably would have) ranked Gore second, so – their votes would have transferred to Gore in the runoff (as if Nader were

not on the ballot or all Nader voters had voted “tactically” under FPTP).• However, if Nader and been a third “major” candidate, rather than

a “minor” candidate, he might still have been a spoiler under AV.– Suppose that Nader had been more “centrist,”

• so Gore had been “squeezed” between Bush and Nader, • rendering Gore the Plurality Loser, while still the Condorcet winner.

– The runoff then would have been Bush and Nader, rather than Bush and Gore, and Bush would (as the near Majority Winner, even if most [but not quite all] Gore voters ranked Nader over Bush) have won the runoff.

Page 40: Nicholas R. Miller University of Maryland Baltimore County (UMBC)

The “Nader Effect” (cont.)

• We have seen that under AV, only the Plurality Runner-Up or Plurality Winner can be a spoiler.– Since spoiler effects can occur only in the absence of a Majority Winner, the

smallest vote the Plurality Runner-Up can receive and possibly be a spoiler is slightly more than 25%.

– Thus a candidate who wins less than 25% of the (first-preference) vote cannot be a spoiler under AV.

– Note that this does not imply that that AV is invulnerable to spoiler effects if the Plurality Loser in a prospective three-way contest wins less than 25% of the vote.• Such a prospective Plurality Loser may prevent the Plurality Winner from

being a Majority Winner, and thereby allow the Plurality Runner-Up to be a spoiler, i.e.,– the Plurality Loser (e.g., Gore “squeezed between Bush and Nader) wins

a straight fight with the Plurality Winner (e.g., Bush) but Plurality Winner wins if the Plurality Runner-Up (e.g., Nader) enters and displace the Plurality Loser from the runoff.

Page 41: Nicholas R. Miller University of Maryland Baltimore County (UMBC)

Propensity to Spoiler Effects by Support for the (Prospective) Plurality Loser and Plurality Runner-Up

Page 42: Nicholas R. Miller University of Maryland Baltimore County (UMBC)

Are The Same Elections

Vulnerable to Spoiler Effects

Under the Different Electoral Systems?

• In this data, elections subject to spoiler effects under AV are a subset of those likewise subject under FPTP.

• In contract, elections subject to spoiler effects under Coombs and FPTP and under Coombs and AV are almost disjoint.

Page 43: Nicholas R. Miller University of Maryland Baltimore County (UMBC)

Frequency of Spoilers by Party• Liberal candidate

are never spoilers under AV,– evidently because

they are typically Plurality Losers and/or Condorcet Winners.

• As we would expect, mutual spoilers are always ideologically adjacent, i.e., “near clones.”

Page 44: Nicholas R. Miller University of Maryland Baltimore County (UMBC)

Monotonicity Failure• A disconcerting feature of AV (and Coombs) is that

– getting more (first preference) votes can cause a candidate to lose an election, and

– getting fewer votes can cause a candidate to win. • While FPTP is monotonic, electoral systems that incorporate

(actual or ‘instant’) runoffs are subject to (upward and/or downward) monotonicity failure.

• Though AV (and Coombs) are unarguably non-monotonic, the question arises how often instances of monotonicity failure arise in practice.– The English data provide a good opportunity to address this question.

Page 45: Nicholas R. Miller University of Maryland Baltimore County (UMBC)

Conditions for Monotonicity Failure under AV• Given that Z is the Plurality Loser, two separate conditions must hold for an AV

ballot profile to be vulnerable to (Upward or Downward) Monotonicity Failure in the event that candidate X is moved up or down in some ballot orderings.

• Condition 1 pertains to X’s runoff opponent; it requires that the ballot changes – deprive Y of enough first preferences (for Upward Monotoncity Failure), – or give Z enough additional first preferences (for Downward Monotoncity

Failure), – to convert Z into the Plurality Runner-Up, – so the runoff that had been between X and Y is now between X and Z.

• Condition 2 pertains to the runoff outcome; it requires that – X must lose (for Upward Monotoncity Failure) or win (for Downward

Monotonicity Failure) the new runoff with Z. • The conjunction of the two conditions is necessary and sufficient to make profile

B vulnerable to (Upward or Downward) Monotonicity Failure. • Note that Condition 1 depends on the distribution of first preferences only, while

Condition 2 depends on second preferences as well.

Page 46: Nicholas R. Miller University of Maryland Baltimore County (UMBC)

Upward Monotonicity Failure under AV• If ballot profile B is vulnerable to Upward Monotonicity failure,

– Condition 1 requires that X can gain enough first preference ballots at Y’s expense that two things are simultaneously true in the resulting profile Bʹ:

– X is still not a Majority Winner, and – Y becomes the Plurality Loser instead of Z.

• This requires that n/2 − x > y − z. – Condition 2 requires that Z beat X under Bʹ, i.e., that zʹ + yzʹ > xʹ + yxʹ.

• It turns out that Condition 1 can be simplified and Condition 2 can be restated in terms of the original ballot profile B, as follows:

PROPOSITION 26. A ballot profile B in which X is the IRV winner and Z is the Plurality Loser is vulnerable to Upward Monotonicity Failure if and only if:

(1) z > n/4; and (2) z + yz > x + yx.

Nicholas R. Miller, “Montonicity Failure in IRV Elections with Three Candidates,” PCS, 2012Dominique Lapelley et al., “The Likelihood of Monotonicity Paradoxes in Run-Off Elections,” Mathematical Social Sciences, 1996

Page 47: Nicholas R. Miller University of Maryland Baltimore County (UMBC)

Downward Monotonicity Failure under AV• If ballot profile B is vulnerable to Downward Monotonicity failure,

– Condition 1 requires that it is possible for X to lose enough first preference ballots in favor of Z that two things are simultaneously true in the resulting companion profile Bʹ:

– Z is no longer the Plurality Loser, and – Y, rather than X, becomes the Plurality Loser.

• Thus it must be that x − y > y − z. • Furthermore, in order for Z to gain these first preferences rather than Y, these (y − z)

new first preference ballots for Z must all come from the xz ballots that initially ranked Z rather than Y second.

– Condition 2 stipulates that X beats Z under Bʹ, i.e., xʹ + yxʹ > zʹ + yzʹ. – Again these conditions can be simplified and restated in terms of the original

ballot profile B only: PROPOSITION 27. A ballot profile B in which Y is the IRV winner and Z is the Plurality Loser is vulnerable to Downwards Monotonicity Failure if and only if: (1) y < n/3 and xz > y − z; and (2) y + yz < n/2.

Nicholas R. Miller, “Montonicity Failure in IRV Elections with Three Candidates,” PCS, 2012Dominique Lapelley et al., “The Likelihood of Monotonicity Paradoxes in Run-Off Elections,” Mathematical Social Sciences, 1996

Page 48: Nicholas R. Miller University of Maryland Baltimore County (UMBC)

Monotonicity Failure in English Data vs. Random Profiles

Page 49: Nicholas R. Miller University of Maryland Baltimore County (UMBC)

Contrast Between English and Random Data• The English data contains considerably fewer profiles vulnerable to

monotonicity failure (1.7%) than the random data (14.1%).• This might suggest that simulated data is irrelevant and misleading: once we

look at “real” electoral data, the problem of monotonicity failure under AV almost disappears.

• However, this low incidence reflects particular features of the English election data, and does not demonstrate that IRV’s non-monotonicity problem is practically irrelevant.

• The primary determinant of vulnerability to monotonicity failure is election closeness, but very few of these English elections represented closely contested three-candidate contests (in part because they were actually conducted under FPTP, not AV).– In all English ballot profiles

• 60% had a Majority Winner, and• in only 4.2% did the Plurality Loser get as much as 25% of first-preference

support (and 39.2% of these profile were vulnerable to Monotonicity Failure).• Controlling for elections closeness, vulnerability to Monotonicity Failure looks

very similar in the two data sets.

Page 50: Nicholas R. Miller University of Maryland Baltimore County (UMBC)

Monotonicity Failure by Closeness in English vs. Random Data

Page 51: Nicholas R. Miller University of Maryland Baltimore County (UMBC)

Monotonicity Failure by Election Closeness in English, Random, and SPWC Data