Religeous Freedom In India - Rajiv Dhavan.pdf

download Religeous Freedom In India - Rajiv Dhavan.pdf

of 47

Transcript of Religeous Freedom In India - Rajiv Dhavan.pdf

  • 8/18/2019 Religeous Freedom In India - Rajiv Dhavan.pdf

    1/47

    Citation: 35 Am. J. Comp. L. 209 1987

    Content downloaded/printed from

    HeinOnline (http://heinonline.org)

    Fri Mar 18 09:59:15 2016

    -- Your use of this HeinOnline PDF indicates your acceptance

      of HeinOnline's Terms and Conditions of the license

      agreement available at http://heinonline.org/HOL/License

    -- The search text of this PDF is generated from

    uncorrected OCR text.

    -- To obtain permission to use this article beyond the scope

      of your HeinOnline license, please use:

      https://www.copyright.com/ccc/basicSearch.do?

    &operation=go&searchType=0

    &lastSearch=simple&all=on&titleOrStdNo=0002-919X

  • 8/18/2019 Religeous Freedom In India - Rajiv Dhavan.pdf

    2/47

    R JEEV DHAVAN

    Religious

    Freedom

    in

    India

    I.

    It

    is

    impossible

    to understand

    religious

    freedom

    without

    under-

    standing

    the wider

    process

    of

    the political management

    of group

    life.

    Many years

    ago,

    when

    India's

    Constitution

    was

    being

    drafted,

    B.R.

    Ambedkar,

    who piloted

    various

    drafts

    through the

    Constituent

    As-

    sembly,

    stated

    that the

    individual

    rather

    than

    the

    group was the

    ba-

    sis

    of the

    Indian

    Constitution.'

    It

    is

    surprising

    that

    this

    terse

    assessment should have

    come

    from one who had fought against Gan-

    dhi and

    the

    Congress Party for

    the collective

    entitlements

    of the

    Untouchables.

    2

    However,

    Ambedkar's

    insight

    forcefully

    explains

    how

    groups and group

    life were to

    be viewed

    in

    the new

    dispensa-

    tion:

    their right

    to flower

    in civil

    society

    would be

    recognized, with

    the Constitution

    protecting

    religious,

    cultural

    and

    educational

    rights.

    3

    Some

    communities

    and

    disadvantaged

    castes and tribes

    would

    even

    have

    special

    political representation.

    4

    But

    the future

    was

    impeded for

    new groups and

    social

    combinations

    which came

    to-

    gether

    as a result

    of the voluntary

    and

    rationally

    directed

    choices

    of

    individuals.

    5

    RAJEEV

    DHAVAN is

    Reader, Dept.

    of

    Law,

    Brunel University,

    England.

    He

    would

    like to

    thank

    Professors Marc

    Galanter,

    Richard Lariviere

    and

    Upendra

    Baxi and

    Justices

    Chinappa

    Reddy,

    Krishna Iyer

    and

    Bhagwati

    for

    the

    opportunity

    to

    discuss

    many issues

    contained

    in

    this article.

    1.

    B.R.

    Ambedkar,

    Speech

    to

    the

    Constituent Assembly,

    VII C A D 38-9

    4

    No-

    vember

    1948).

    2.

    See, e.g., Ambedkar,

    Mr. Gandhi

    and the

    Emancipation

    of Untouchables

     1943);

    id.,

    What Congress

    and Gandhi

    have

    Done

    t the

    Untouchables

    1946);

    see

    Ga-

    lanter,

    Competing

    Equalities:

    Law and

    the

    Backward

    Classes n India

    28-40

    1984).

    3. Articles 25-30,

    Constitution

    of

    India.

    4.

    Articles

    330-4, Constitution

    of India.

    5.

    This

    voluntarist/rationalist

    approach

    represents

    just one point

    of view in

    an

    otherwise

    complex,

    intricate and continuing

    discussion

    about

    the

    nature

    of

    Indian

    secularism.

    Contrast the

    relatively

    unsubstantiated

    view of Watson,

    The

    Indian

    Constitution

    and the

    Hindu Traditions,

    at

    1183 (Ph.

    D. Thesis,

    Northwestern

    Uni-

    versity, 1957)

    that

    India's

    present Constitution

    espouses a

    Hindu polity.

    For

    other

    more

    incisive

    views,

    see

    Sundaram,

    A

    Secular

    State for

    India:

    Thoughts on India s

    Political

    Future 1944).

    For later

    views

    see

    Smith,

    India as a Secular

    State

    1963)

    and

    South

    Asian Politics

    and Religion

    1963);

    Luthera,

    The Concept

    of a

    Secular

    State

    and

    India

    1964);

    Sharma ed.), Secularism:

    Its Implications

    or

    Law and ife

      1966);

    Sinha ed.),

    Secularism

    n

    India 1968);

    Derrett, Religion,

    Law

    and the State

     n

    India

    1968);

    Saxena,

    A Secular

    State

    and its Institutional

    Patterns 1971);

    Gajen-

    dragadkar,

    Secularism

    and

    the

    Constitution of

    India

    1971);

    Bachal,

    Freedom

    of

  • 8/18/2019 Religeous Freedom In India - Rajiv Dhavan.pdf

    3/47

    210 THE AMERICAN JOURNAL OF COMPARATIVE LAW

    [Vol.

    35

    Although attractive on paper, the theory collapses in real life.

    If the

    key notions are 'voluntarism' and 'rationality', neither

    old nor

    new groups can claim

    a

    monopoly

    on

    one

    or the other. The distinc-

    tion between 'traditional' and

    'new'

    groups is also

    obscured

    as group

    life renews

    itself in

    various

    shapes

    and forms.

    6

    Even if these analyt-

    ical distinctions are unconvincing, the Constitution has

    the ideologi-

    cal

    objective

    of de-politicizing powerful traditional group

    formations

    while giving different

    groups

    varying degrees of legal recognition.

    Nonetheless, group life is

    constantly re-defined by social,

    political

    and economic forces in

    ways that threaten the fragile computations

    of

    the

    framers of the

    Constitution. While the framers were

    at-

    tracted

    to the 'top-down'

    notion of making social

    forces yield to

    new

    rational structures,

    they were aware as the British were

    before

    them that

    the actual

    management of

    the political economy would

    subvert these

    structures

    as

    India's

    emergent

    capitalism

    reconstituted

    the

    means through

    which

    it

    would articulate its demands.

    Some of the dilemmas of Independent

    India's rulers can be

    traced back to the Raj, which sought to

    establish

    a comprehensive

    all-inclusive legal system. The Anglo-Indian

    Codes 'secularized' a

    large part

    of the

    law

    relating

    to legal

    procedure,

    contract, the trans-

    fer

    of property, and commercial organizations.

    7

    However, this secu-

    Religion

    and

    the

    Indian Judiciary

    (1972); Ghouse, Secularism Society

    and

    the

    Law

    (1973);

    Jain, Law and Religion: A Comparative Study of

    the Freedom

    of

    Religion

    in

    India

    and the United

    States 1974); Glasner, The Sociology

    of

    Secularization:A Cri-

    tique

    of a Concept 1977);

    Dhavan, The

    Supreme Courtof

    India: A Socio-legal

    Analy-

    sis

    of

    its

    Juristic

    Techniques 422-31 1977);

    Srivastava,

    Religious

    Freedom

    in

    India:

    A

    Historical

    and Constitutional Study 1982).

    For

    journal literature,

    see

    Galanter,

     Secularism East and West, 7

    Comp. Stud.

    Society

    History 135-59 1965); id.,

      Hinduism, Secularism and the Indian

    Judiciary,

    21 Philosophy

    East

    and West

    467-

    487 1971); Seminar No. 67, Secularism:

    A

    Symposium

    on the

    implicationsof a na-

    tional policy 1965); Subhrahmaniam, Hinduism and

    Secularism, Bulletin

    of

    the

    Institute of

    Traditional

    Culture,

    Part I,

    1-21 1966);

    Tripathi, Secularism,

    Constitu-

    tional

    Provision and

    Judicial

    Review, 8 J L 1-29 1966); Ghouse, Secularism

    and

    the

    Constitution of India, 17

    Indian

    Year Book of

    International

    Affairs

    559-76

     1974); Nagpal,

    Secularism and

    the Constitution of India, Lawyer 112-7

    1971);

    Satyanarayana, Religion under the Constitution of

    India, 3 Journal of the Bar

    Council

    of India 310-16 1974); Minatur, Law and Religion in a Secular State, 8

    Lawyer

    79 1976);

    Akhishewar Singh,

    The

    Concept of Secularism

    in

    Indian Consti-

    tution, 12 J. Const. Parl.

    Stud. 15 1978); Chinappa Reddy, Religion in India, Ber-

    trand

    Russell Memorial Lecture, 1982,

    mimeo); and also,

    Derrett,

    Freedom of

    Religion in India,

    KL.T (Jnl.)

    91-3

    1979); Mittal,

    Motivated Conversion and

    Pro-

    tective Discrimination, 28 Punjab

    University L.R. 147 1976); Bhartiya,

    Propaga-

    tion

    of Religion..

    .

    . 19 J.I.L..

    325

    1977);

    Sharma,

    Article

    25

    of

    the

    Constitution

    Should we amend it? A.I.R.

    1985

    Jnl. 22-3.

    6.

    See

    Rudolph

    &

    Rudolph:

    The Modernity

    of Tradition: Political Develop-

    ment in India 1967) and

    the incisive review

    by

    Derrett in 71 Z.V R

    89-94 1968).

    7. On

    the

    legislation, see

    Stokes, The

    Anglo-Indian Codes, 2 vol. 1887);

    see Ga-

    lanter:

    The

    Displacement

    of

    Traditional

    Law

    in India

    24

    J.

    Soc. Issues 65-91

    1968);

    id., The aborted restoration of Indian 'indigenous' law in India,

    14

    Comp.

    Stud. Soc.

      Hist. 53-70 1972);

    Derrett,

    Legal

    Science

    during the last

    century:

    India, in

    Rotondi

    ed.),

    Inchieste

    di

    derreto

    Comparato 413-35

    1975).

  • 8/18/2019 Religeous Freedom In India - Rajiv Dhavan.pdf

    4/47

    DHAVAN:

    RELIGIOUS

    FREEDOM

    IN INDIA

    larism did not extend to the

    'personal

    laws'

    of various communities

    even

    though these

    personal laws were used to control the

    distribu-

    tion

    of

    social and economic power. Decisions in the

    area

    of personal

    law

    were made

    by

    judges who, combining pragmatism and self

    inter-

    est with caution, constructed a body of Anglo-Hindu and Anglo-Mus-

    lim.

    8

    Each

    community

    was

    permitted

    self

    expression

    so

    long

    as

    it

    did

    not

    compromise

    the

    police

    duties of the

    State.

    These

    duties were

    not

    just

    concerned with law and order, but also with Chancery no-

    tions of equity, which were used

    not

    merely

    to

    transform the

    joint

    family

    9

    but also

    to

    'discipline'

    religious

    endowments

    which

    retained

    vast

    repositories

    of power and wealth.

    10

    Law courts absorbed, re-de-

    fined

    and

    resolved social and economic conflicts concerning

    land,

    credit and status.

    1

    Indigenous

    communities

    thus

    invited their

    ow n

    legal

    metamorphosis

    through

    one

    the

    most poweful, respected and

    subtle

    bureaucracies

    of

    the

    Raj the

    judiciary.

    12

    The Raj sought

    to

    fashion a policy of overall supremacy

    (based

    on

    notions

    of sovereignty) rather than to press for

    detailed moderni-

    zation

    of

    the

    system-an effort

    that

    met with resistance.

    At

    the

    same

    time

    the Raj sought to divide

    Indian

    society into

    stratified

    and

    disaggregated parts, each part nurtured

    by encouraging its desire fo r

    self-identification. Static images of what has

    been

    called India's

      compartmentalized

    society

    served

    many

    purposes.

    1

    3

    As

    Indian

    elite

    politics became

    more

    self-confident many leaders

    moderated

    their own

    enthusiasm

    for

    political change by convincing

    themselves

    that

    the

    social

    reform

    of

    India's static

    society

    must

    be

    a

    prerequisite

    for making

    wide-ranging political demands

    suited

    to a

    more

    dynamic

    society.

    14

    That

    'traditional'

    society contained a potential for

    reform,

    dynamism and

    change,

    was ignored both by scholars and govern-

    ment policy. Whenever peasant rebellions took place-and the Raj

    8. See,

    Derrett,

    The Administration of Hindu

    law

    by the British, 4 Comp.

    Stud.

    Soc.

    Hist. 10-52 1961); Fyzee, The impact of English law on the Shariat

    n

    India,

    66

    Bom. L.

    Rev.

    107-16

    1964).

    A reassessment

    of

    the

    impact

    of Imperial rule

    on personal laws

    is

    long overdue.

    9.

    Derrett, A

    history

    of the juridical

    framework

    of

    of the joint family, 6 Con-

    tributions

    of

    Indian

    Sociology

    17 1962); Sontheimer, The

    Joint

    Hindu Family: Its

    evolution as a Legal

    Institution

    1977).

    10.

    Derrett,

    Religion Law and the State ch. 14 1968); Sontheimer,

    Religious

    Endowments

    in

    India,

    67

    Z.

    VR. 45 1965).

    11.

    Washbrook,

    Law, State and Agrarian

    Society in

    India, 15 Mod.

    Asian

    Stud.

    649-721 1981);

    Appadorai,

    Worship and Conflict under Colonial Rule

    esp.

    ch.

    5

     1981 .

    12. Unfortunately, there has

    been

    very little assessment

    of

    the

    British

    judiciary

    as an institution

    of

    the

    State.

    This may

    in part have been because a strict law

    of

    constructive

    contempt

    stifled comment

    see

    Dhavan, Contempt of

    Court

    and

    the

    Press

    1981 .

    13. The phrase

    is

    taken from Galanter, supra

    n. 2 at 7.

    14. See K.T. Telang's famous speech, Must Social reform precede political re-

    form?, Selected Writings: Speches and Writings I, 288

    1892); see further L. Heim-

    sath,

    Indian

    Nationalism

    and Hindu

    Social Reform

    1964).

     98 ]

  • 8/18/2019 Religeous Freedom In India - Rajiv Dhavan.pdf

    5/47

    212

    THE

    AMERICAN JOURNAL OF COMPARATIVE

    LAW

    [Vol.

    35

    is littered

    with scores of them it

    was politically

    convenient

    to

    iden-

    tify the religious form in

    which protest was

    expressed as the sine

    qua

    non rather

    than

    to admit that

    discontent

    arose

    out of the ex-

    ploitative

    policies

    of

    the

    Raj. This

    method

    of

    cloaking

    social

    truth

    remains an

    important policy

    imperative in the hands of

    India's con-

    temporary

    rulers.

    The contradictions precipitated

    by this policy

    surfaced after

    In-

    dependence

    when politically

    re-defined communities

    and groups

    made

    political demands.

    The

    creation of Pakistan

    was the direct

    consequence of this policy.

    As socio-political

    life in Independent In-

    dia

    adapted

    itself

    to elections

    and the

    patronage

    that

    flowed from

    the

    electoral process,

    many

    of

    India's

    politicians

    favored the familiar

    policy

    of defining

    electoral

    support

    along communal

    lines. While

    formally espousing secularism,

    they manipulated traditional

    cultural

    loyalties. This manipulative process

    occurred not only in

    rural areas

    but also

    subtly penetrated highly

    urbanized

    communities,

    where loy-

    alties are predicated upon

    community

    and

    caste

    identification as

    well

    as

    upon

    class loyalties.

    15

    Indeed,

    the

    reasons for

    many

    alleg-

    edly 'communal'

    tensions and

    religious

    clashes in

    contemporary

    In-

    dia can

    be

    attributed to the manner in

    which politicians

    (and

    their

    supporting

    band

    of

    ideologists) have politically

    appropriated

    reli-

    gious

    group

    life

    to

    their

    own

    purposes.

    16

    II.

    Although

    India's Constitution

    borrowed greatly

    from the

    U.S.

    Constitution,

    the

    American solution of allowing the

    'free

    exercise' of

    religious

    freedoms (subject

    to

    the police

    power of the State)

    and cre-

    ating

    a

    wall of

    separation between the State and religion

    seems

    both

    contradictory

    and

    awkwardly over-simplified.

    While

    India's consti-

    tutional lawyers were

    sensitive to the

    post-New

    Deal prognosis

    that

    judges

    were not to

    be

    trusted

    with the determination of social

    wel-

    fare

    questions,

    17

    discussions

    about religious

    freedom evolved

    around

    more specific

    concerns.

    India's

    Constitution-makers

    did

    not

    want

    to

    15. Nehru stated: So

    far as I

    am

    concerned,

    I

    am

    prepared to lose

    every single

    election in India but

    to

    give

    no

    quarter

    to communalism

    or

    casteism .

    (Selected

    Speeches:

    1953-7

    37

    (1958)). Similar, but

    more

    guarded comments

    have been made

    by his grandson, Rajiv

    Gandhi; see ndianExpress 13

    September 1986.

    16.

    Indeed, reports

    on

    the

    turmoil

    following

    Mrs.

    Gandhi's assassination

    attri-

    bute

    the ghastly

    riots

    to

    political

    manipulation

    more than

    righteous anger.

    17.

    Much

    of the

    controversy

    surrounded the

    'due process' clause.

    It

    was

    argued

    that its introduction

    would make

    the

    judiciary the arbiter of all social

    reform ques-

    tions

    (e.g.,

    Rau's

    Notes on

    Fundamental

    Rights,

    II

    Shiva

    Rao infra

    n.

    18

    22-23;

    and

    151-52).

    It

    was felt that such a

    clause would not just

    affect agrarian reform

    (e.g.,

    II

    Shiva Rao 122

    26

    March

    1947). A.K. Ayyar

    (letter dated 4 April 1947 II

    Shiva Rao

    143-45)

    also pointed out

    that if

    the

    freedom of

    religion clause

    was too widely defined,

    social legislation would

    be impeded.

  • 8/18/2019 Religeous Freedom In India - Rajiv Dhavan.pdf

    6/47

    DHAVAN: RELIGIOUS

    FREEDOM

    IN

    INDIA

    indulge

    the intellectual

    excess

    of wholly disentangling

    the State

    from

    religious life.

    The State was

    to

    interact

    with

    religious groups

    in a supportive

    manner.

    However,

    no

    one

    had

    quite

    determined

    what

    the

    socially

    and politically assimilative effect

    of

    the

    new

    secu-

    larism

    was going

    to be, and

    discussions in

    the

    Constituent

    Assembly

    reflected tensions

    among

    various reformists

    and community

    leaders

    about

    the

    basic

    constitutional

    framework.

    1 8

    Political

    Representation

    The

    first and

    most

    complex problem

    involved a decision

    about

    whether

    religious and

    other

    groups

    should

    have separate

    and dis-

    tinct political

    representation

    in

    electoral

    processes and

    representa-

    tive

    bodies. The

    Raj s failure

    to actively

    promote

    unity '

    19

    and

    its

    residual

    legacy of

    encouraging

    religious manifestations

    of political

    demand

    had left expectations

    that were

    not

    satisfied

    by the

    creation

    of

    Pakistan.

    Muslims,

    Sikhs,

    Christians,

    Parsis, and

    others sought

    political

    representation.

    The

    basic policy

    of

    non-communal

    repre-

    sentation

    was approved

    in the Minorities

    Sub-Committee

    and

    the

    Advisory

    Committee

    and, amidst

    dissension,

    was adopted

    by

    the

    Constituent

    Assembly.

    The alternative

    policy

    of

    protecting minori-

    ties

    from majoritarian

    pressures

    through

    proportional

    representa-

    tion was

    passed

    over. The final

    agreed-upon

    constitutional

    solution

    dispensed with communal

    representation.

    It provided

    that

    . .

    no

    person shall be ineligible for inclusion in

    any

    elector l

    roll

    or

    claim

    to be included

    in

    any special electoral

    roll for

    any such constit-

    uency

    on

    grounds only of

    religion, race, caste,

    sex

    or

    any

    of them .

    20

    Constitutional

    decisiveness

    was supplemented

    by an electoral

    law

    that

    forbade

    appeals

    to

    religion,

    religious sentiment,

    and religious

    symbols.

    2

      The

    only exceptions

    were

    made for

    special

    electorates

    for India's

    socially

    and

    economically backward

    minorities

    (called

    Scheduled

    Castes

    and

    Scheduled

    Tribes) and

    the Anglo-Indian

    18 The

    most succinct

    account

    of

    these

    discussions

    is to be found in

    Shiva

    Rao,

    The

    Framing

    of India s

    Constitution:

    A Study

    (1968) (hereafter

    Shiva

    Rao

    Study),

    with

    the

    original

    documents in

    four connected

    volumes

    hereafter

    cited

    as Shiva Rao

    preceded

    by

    the Volume

    number. For further

    comments,

    see

    generally

    Austin,

    h

    Indian

    Constitution:

    Cornerstoneof

    a Nation

    (1966);

    the

    main discussions

    in the

    Constituent Assembly

    took place

    on VII

    C A D

    822

    (3

    Dec.

    1948), 823-840

    (6 Dec.

    1948); 859-890

    (7 Dec. 1948).

    19. Austin,

    supra

    n. 18

    at 147.

    20.

    Art. 325,

    Constitution

    of

    India.

    21.

    S 23(2)

    of the Representation

    of Peoples Act (43

    of) 1951

    prohibits undue

    influence which invokes

    social

    ostracism, excommunication,

    expulsion from

    caste

    or

    community,

    divine displeasure or

    spiritual

    censure. Sec.

    123(3)

    is

    concerned

    with

    ap -

    peals to

    religion,

    race, caste,

    community,

    language which

    would

    affect voting

    choices

    or

    (vide 3A)

    provoke

    enmity

    between

    classes.

    There is a

    formidable amount

    of

    case

    law on these

    kinds

    of

    electoral

    disputes.

    1987]

  • 8/18/2019 Religeous Freedom In India - Rajiv Dhavan.pdf

    7/47

    214 THE AMERICAN

    JOURNAL

    OF COMPARATIVE

    LAW

    [Vol.

    35

    community.

    2

    2

    This general

    constitutional approach

    was undermined

    by subse-

    quent political events.

    The Nehru and

    Indira governments

    made

    major

    concessions to linguistic

    minorities

    by

    creating

    Andhra

    Pradesh

    for

    the Telugu-speaking

    people, splitting

    Bombay

    into

    Ma-

    rathi-speaking

    Maharashtra and Gujarati-speaking

    Gujarat, and

    carving Hindi-speaking

    Haryana

    out of

    Punjab in 1967.

    Most of In-

    dia's other

    States began

    to

    support

    their linguistic

    identities.

    The system of

    patronage established around

    patterns of electo-

    ral support

    further

    reinforces

    religious and other

    identities. Politi-

    cians

    deliberately

    manipulate

    and

    manage religious,

    caste, linguistic

    and

    other identities

    in order to organize

    a basis

    for

    support

    and dis-

    pense return

    favors. At

    another level, India's

    remarkable

    compensa-

    tory

    discrimination

    program

    gives

    caste and religious-based groups

    a

    vested interest

    in their own identity.

    23

    This has

    presented

    Indian

    courts

    with

    enormous

    political

    and conceptual problems

    when in-

    vited to adjudicate

    electoral complaints

    about a

    successful candi-

    date's caste

    and religious

    identity.

    This

    task, already complex with

    listed ('Scheduled') groups,

    becomes

    even

    more

    intricate

    when

    the

    government is

    asked

    to dispense special

    favors to 'backward

    classes'.

    24

    A recent government committee's insistence

    that

    'caste'

    must

    be a

    central

    criterion for

    determining

    'backwardness'

    may

    well

    increase

    the

    importance

    of religious-based affiliations

    as

    the

    final

    de-

    terminant

    in the vast

    and crucial area

    of preferential treatment

    for

    educational

    opportunities and government

    jobs.

    25

    Some members

    of the Constituent Assembly

    had

    probably

    fore-

    seen

    this

    when

    they

    unsuccessfully

    supported

    a

    constitutional

    man-

    date

    to separate

    religion

    from

    politics. Even

    if

    such

    a

    provision

    had

    been introduced,

    however, it is unlikely

    that Indian politics

    would

    have abandoned its

    own

    level of Realpolitik.

    There is

    little

    ques-

    tioning

    of

    India's formal

    constitutional doctrine,

    partly because it is

    familiar

    and

    convenient

    and partly

    because there is

    a

    fear

    that

    ma-

    jority

    religious

    groups may assert

    their supremacy

    in politics

    and

    ad-

    ministration.

    26

    Even if

    the threat

    is

    not real,

    the

    anxieties

    of

    22.

    Arts. 330-334, Constitution of India.

    23.

    For a comprehensive

    account, see Galanter,

    supra

    n.

    2.

    Singh,

    Equality Res-

    ervation

    and iscrimination

    n

    India 1982);

    and

    for

    a

    comment on

    recent

    law,

    see

    Singh,

    Castes

    and

    Classes: The

    Doctrinal Puzzle from

    Balaji to Vasanth,

    S.C.C.

    J

    36-50

    (1986).

    For

    perceptions

    of how the

    program works,

    see Anant,

    Changing

    Caste Hindu

    Attitudes towards Harijans A

    Follow-up after Four

    Years,

    in

    Gupta

    (ed.), Cohesion and

    Conflict

    in

    Modern

    India

    (1978);

    Agarwal,

    Equality

    through

    Privileges:

    A Study of Special

    Privileges

    of

    Scheduled

    Castes

    in

    Haryana 1976).

    24.

    Galanter,

    Who

    are

    the Other Backward Classes:

    An Introduction to a

    Con-

    stitutional Puzzle,

    13 E.P.W 1812-88

    (1978);

    Galanter,

    supra

    n. 2

    at

    134-87.

    25. Government of India,

    Report

    of

    the

    Backward

    Classes

    Commission

    1981).

    26. However,

    as

    we

    shall see later, while courts display

    their adherence

    to famil-

    iar

    constitutional doctrine,

    their decisions mark a flexible

    accommodation of

    conflict-

  • 8/18/2019 Religeous Freedom In India - Rajiv Dhavan.pdf

    8/47

    DHAVAN:

    RELIGIOUS FREEDOM

    IN

    INDIA

    minority groups need

    not

    only

    to be

    assuaged

    but

    uncompromisingly

    laid

    to rest. Indeed,

    when

    India's Constitution

    was being overhauled

    during

    the

    Emergency,

    an

    important

    symbolic

    insertion into the

    Preamble

    identified India

    as

    a

    'secular'

    as

    well

    as

    a 'socialist', demo-

    cratic republic.

    These

    words

    were

    not

    changed

    by

    the Janata

    gov-

    ernment

    in its

    review

    of

    the

    Emergency

    amendments

    after

    Mrs.

    Gandhi's massive

    defeat

    at the

    polls.

    2 7

    But

    the gap

    between

    consti-

    tutional symbolism and

    political

    practice

    is

    so

    considerable

    that we

    need to examine

    it

    more

    closely.

    Social Practice nd Social

    Religion

    The constitutional

    discussion

    on freedom of

    religion started

    with

    a

    general

    consideration about

    the right to belief and

    practice.

    Two

    strategies

    were

    given

    attention.

    The

    first

    was

    the

    familiar

    'wall

    of

    separation'

    doctrine,

    with draft clauses specifically directed

    to

    non-compulsory

    religious

    education in

    State-aided

    schools

    and t

    non-payment

    of

    taxes to maintain any faith. The second

    was delim-

    iting the sweep of religious

    rights by denying

    constitutional protec-

    tion

    to

    'secular'

    (i.e. economic,

    political, financial,

    etc.) aspects of

    religious practice. However,

    this juxtaposition

    between the 'reli-

    gious' and the

    'secular' was greatly

    obscured by specific

    provisions

    recognizing the

    institutional basis

    of

    religious

    life and the

    right

    of

    religious

    denominations

    to own

    property

    and manage

    their own

    institutions.

    Although the

    earlier drafts and the final

    text reserved to the

    police

    the power

    to

    make

    these rights subject to

    public order, mo-

    rality

    or

    health , these draft

    provisions only

    aroused

    pessimism

    among

    social

    reformers, who

    warned

    that law

    courts would

    interpret

    the social control provisions

    restrictively. The

    reformers' concerns

    devolved

    on various

    specific

    issues.

    At the

    beginning, they

    were

    de-

    feated in an initial wrangle

    over the inclusion of

    the right to 'propa-

    gate'

    one's religion.

    The

    opening

    up

    of

    Hindu (including Sikh,

    Jain,

    and Buddhist) temples

    to all

    classes and

    sections of Hindus proved

    not

    to be

    an issue.

    28

    But

    the reformers were defeated

    in their at-

    ing

    intuitions and demands

    from

    society

    and

    the State. This is

    as true

    of

    the

    Supreme Court's

    decision-making

    in

    areas

    other than

    religious

    freedom; see

    gener-

    ally Dhavan, supra n. 5. For

    a restatement of the fear

    of majoritarianism, see Khur-

    shid,

    At

    Home n India

    1986).

    27.

    Inserted

    by

    the Constitution 42nd Amendment)

    Act,

    1976;

    see also

    Dhavan,

    The

    Amendment

    Conspiracyor Revolution 1978)

    esp. Chapter IV for

    parliamen-

    tary discussions on this and other

    matters.

    28. The

    opening

    up of temples

    first

    surfaced

    in the

    Draft

    Constitution

    (Article

    19 2) b)).

    There

    was

    some

    attempt to

    extend

    these reforms

    to

    all

    religious

    institu-

    tions see, e.g.,

    Tajamul Hussain

    IV

    Shiva Rao 41-42).

    Sikh, Jain and Buddhist

    tem-

    ples

    were included in the final

    text (Article

    25

    Explanation

    II) following

    an

    amendment by K.T.

    Shah on 6 Dec. 1948 VII CA D 828

    ff.).

     98 ]

  • 8/18/2019 Religeous Freedom In India - Rajiv Dhavan.pdf

    9/47

    216

    THE

    AMERICAN

    JOURNAL

    OF COMPARATIVE

    LAW

    [Vol.

    35

    tempt to

    prevent

    religious

    denominations

    from

    administering

    insti-

    tutions

    and owning

    property. The

    reformers in

    the Assembly

    also

    pressed

    for

    an

    over-riding

    provision

    in

    the

    freedom

    of

    religion

    clauses that

    would

    not only

    permit

    regulating and

    restricting

    of

    economic,

    financial, political or

    other

    secular

    activity..,

    which may

    be associated

    with

    religious

    practice

    but would

    also

    promote

    social

    welfare

    and

    reform.1

    29

    However, the

    major debate

    concerned

    reli-

    gious

    instruction

    in State-aided

    institutions.

    Even

    more

    than

    places

    of

    worship, educational

    institutions

    were

    inextricably

    bound

    up with

    the religious

    life

    of many communities.

    The

    communities

    had much

    to lose if

    their educational

    institutions

    either lost

    State aid

    or

    were

    constitutionally

    pressured

    into

    relinquishing religious

    instruction

    as

    the

    social price

    for the

    State's financial

    support.

    The initial

    compro-

    mise

    permitting such

    instruction outside

    working

    hours

    30

    was

    super-

    seded by

    a

    more accommodating provision prohibiting religious

    instruction

    in 'wholly

    maintained'

    State

    educational

    institutions

    and

    allowing

    'voluntary'

    participation

    in

    religious

    instruction

    programs

    in

    institutions

    administerd

    by,

    recognized

    by,

    or

    receiving

    aid

    from

    the

    State.

    3

    1

    Some

    of these

    constitutional

    protections

    were

    also extended

    to

    all minorities

    (including,

    no doubt, religious

    ones) who were

    allowed

    to

    establish

    and

    administer

    educational

    institutions

    of their

    choice.

    3

    2

    These

    institutions

    could

    not be denied

    State aid

    because

    of

    their

    reli-

    gious and linguistic

    identity, and, in

    turn, could

    not deny admission

    to

    anyone

    on grounds

    of

    race,

    caste, or

    language.

    Any

    'section

    of the

    citizens'

    residing

    in the

    territory

    of

    India

    has

    also been

    given

    the

    right to conserve

    its

    distinct

    language,

    script, or culture.

    These

    pro-

    visions,

    which

    are especially

    relevant to

    maintaining

    the

    cohesive-

    ness

    and

    identity of

    religious

    groups

    (for many

    groups

    conserve

    their

    religious

    identity through

    language),

    were

    introduced

    almost

    by

    accident.

    The

    reformers

    obtained

    an open-ended

    power

    to

    sustain the

    so-

    cial

    reform of religion

    but

    religious

    groups

    had won the

    right

    to in-

    stitutional

    existence, to

    own

    property

    and manage

    their

    own

    affairs,

    to

    be partly

    funded

    by the

    State

    (even

    if

    they imparted religious

    in-

    struction), and to propagate

    their

    beliefs. However, even

    if

    the

    reli-

    gious

    groups

    had

    held

    their ground

    against

    the reformers

    in the

    Constituent

    Assembly,

    the overall

    constitutional

    framework bor-

    29 The

    fact that the

    'secular'

    aspects of

    religion

    could be

    controlled

    was present

    in

    virtually

    all the

    drafts presented

    to

    various

    committees

    at

    various

    stages

    of

    t

    constitutional

    discussion.

    30.

    The initial

    compromise

    was expressed

    in

    Art.

    22(3)

    of the Draft Constitution.

    31.

    The final

    version is

    in

    Art.

    28(3).

    Minority

    institutions

    dominate

    various sec-

    tors

    of

    education in India.

    For

    State

    attempts

    to regulate

    and assimilate

    minority

    educational institutions,

    see Part

    IV of

    this

    article.

    32. Arts.

    29 and

    30 Constitution

    of

    India.

  • 8/18/2019 Religeous Freedom In India - Rajiv Dhavan.pdf

    10/47

    DHAVAN:

    RELIGIOUS

    FREEDOM

    IN

    INDIA

    rowed

    from American

    doctrine had delimited

    their

    sphere

    of

    opera-

    tion. Relegated

    to

    operate

    in civil

    society, denied

    political

    representation and

    the

    full State

    support

    given

    to

    non-religious

    groups,

    they were

    accorded freedom

    of speech and

    conscience

    and a

    right

    to

    equality

    that

    most

    other groups

    enjoyed

    as a

    matter of

    fact.

    Thus, communist,

    socialist, and

    non-religious

    reformist and

    con-

    servative

    groups

    enjoyed virtually

    all the

    rights

    given

    to religious

    groups

    without

    many

    of

    the limitations.

    By earmarking

    religious

    groups

    for

    special

    attention,

    the Constitution

    effectively segregated

    and

    depoliticized

    them.

    III.

    The

    careful

    deliberations

    in

    the

    Constituent

    Assembly

    left

    too

    many unresolved issues

    that,

    in

    turn,

    were passed on to

    the

    judiciary

    for

    resolution. In

    the

    Common

    law world,

    the

    judiciary

    is

    often in-

    vited

    to resolve

    complex and

    politically

    sensitive

    subjects.

    33

    How-

    ever,

    many questions

    do not reach

    the judiciary

    at the direction

    of

    other political agencies

    of the

    State,

    but

    are the

    product

    of

    forum

    shopping

    among

    social

    and

    political rivals

    fighting

    for the

    spoils of

    religious

    power,

    status, and

    office. Thus,

    if governmental

    interven-

    tion

    results

    in the

    displacement

    of existing

    managers

    of religious

    and

    educational

    institutions

    by new incumbents,

    the

    displaced man-

    agers

    may turn

    to the

    law

    courts

    to

    reopen

    the dispute.

    3 4

    The

    courts

    33

    The

    general image of

    a

    common

    law judge

    as

    a neutral

    third

    party presiding

    over disputes

    seems

    to have

    been

    tarnished in recent

    years.

    While faith in

    the capac-

    ity of

    Anglo-American judges

    to balance

    out

    rights remains

    (e.g.,

    Dworkin, Taking

    Rights Seriously

    1977)),

    outspoken

    research

    speaks

    of the

    instrumental predilec-

    tions of

    common law judges,

    (e.g.,

    Horwitz,

    The

    Transformation

    of American

    Law

    1780-1860

    (1977);

    Atiyah, The

    Rise

    and

    Fall

    of Freedom

    of Contract

    (1979)), and their

    class

    bias (J.A.G.

    Griffith,

    The Politics of

    the Judiciary (1977);

    Das Gupta,

    Justice

    and the

    PoliticalOrder n

    India

    (1979)). For

    a

    recent attempt to evaluate

    common

    law models

    of judicial decision

    making,

    and, especially

    their application

    to India,

    see

    Dhavan,

    Sudarshan

    Khurshid

    (eds.) Judges

    and the JudicialPower

    (1985).

    34. E.g., Ramalinga

    v. Sundara, A.I.R.

    1929

    Mad.

    526 (where

    Curgenen J. hints

    that

    the (Hindu)

    District

    Judge may have got

    involved

    in a dispute

    about when

    t

    trustees of

    a temple could celebrate

    Navaratri,

    a religious

    festival);

    Narayan

    v. State

    of Madras,

    A.I.R. 1954

    Mad. 385

    (where the

    board

    appears

    to

    reject certain names

    proposed);

    Commr.

    HRE v.

    LT Swamiar,

    A.I.R. 1954

    S.C.

    282; and

    K.A. Samajan

    v.

    Commr.,

    A.I.R.

    1971

    S.C. 8 appear to

    be riddled

    with long

    case

    histories

    (on

    Samajan

    see further

    A.V.

    Sabha v.

    Commr., A.I.R. 1976

    S.C. 475); note

    the

    nominees

    in Namboodripad

    v.

    C.D. Board, A.I.R.

    1956

    T.C. 19 at prs.

    7 8 p. 22;

    and the very

    complex

    decision

    concerning

    the

    pious

    nuns

    of

    Madhya

    Pradesh in

    State of Madhya

    Pradesh v.

    M.S.

    Convent

    School, A.I.R.

    1958

    M.P.

    362; State

    of Bihar

    v. Bhabaprita-

    nanda

    Ojha (1959) S.C.R.

    Supp. 624

    is

    clearly

    a case of

    Government involvement

    in

    a

    dispute

    between

    pandas and

    the priest;

    Note

    the State selling

    right

    to

    perform

    santhis in

    temples

    by auction in

    V. Raman

    Embran

    v. Tahsildar, A.I.R.

    1960 Kerala

    312; or

    where

    the government appointed

    a management committee

    by

    general

    reso-

    lution in respect

    of a rahmo

    Samaj endowment

    and

    claiming to

    follow

    American

    case

    law in

    Dipendra

    Nath v. State

    of Bihar, A.I.R. 1962

    Patna 101.

    For

    a similar

    case

    of

    alleged

    interference with the

    Charodhi

    community,

    see

    State of

    Mysore

    v.

    1987]

  • 8/18/2019 Religeous Freedom In India - Rajiv Dhavan.pdf

    11/47

    218 THE AMERICAN JOURNAL OF COMPARATIVE LAW

    [Vol.

    35

    of

    British

    India

    were replete with examples

    of

    such

    social

    disputes

    over power

    and property inundating the courts--disputes that virtu-

    ally

    submerged

    the

    legal system.

    35

    Like

    their

    counterparts

    in

    In-

    dependent

    India,

    the judges

    of

    the Raj backed away from

    pronouncing on

    purely religious

    disputes.

    36

    However, the ingenuity

    of Indian lawyers was

    able

    to transform most social

    claims

    into

    legal

    ones. That

    the

    Constitution

    permitted

    direct access

    to the High

    Courts and Supreme Court over breaches of

    Fundamental

    Rights

    (and

    also to the High Courts to review

    most governmental

    action)

    increased

    the

    potential

    and

    actual

    use

    of

    courts.

    3

    7

    Broadly speaking,

    the Supreme

    Court was

    invited

    to

    consider

    (a)

    what constituted 'religion';

    and

    (b) what was the

    range of

    permis-

    sible constitutional

    limitations.

    Following the

    British

    policy

    of

    en-

    trenching traditionalism and pragmatically leaving the resolution of

    most issues to common sense

    rather

    than

    consistent high doctrine,

    the

    Supreme

    Court began its

    reconceptualization of

    the

    'religious

    freedom'

    clauses cautiously.

    Defining

    Religion: The Legal Limits of Justiciability

    The question of defining religion -and,

    therefore, deciding

    whether

    a

    particular claim

    is, prima

    facie justiciable

    as a

    bill

    of

    rights question-is as crucial as it

    is

    complex. The courts of British

    India had

    encountered this problem, but

    in

    a different form. To be-

    gin

    with,

    they were

    often

    asked to pronounce on

    social

    disputes mas-

    querading

    as

    legal

    questions.

    3

    This involved

    the

    converse problem

    Charodhi Abhyudha 1972)

    1 Mys L J

    431.

    On

    the installation and removal of idols

    and the response

    of

    both government and

    the

    courts to

    local factional

    disputes,

    see

    Ramachandra v.

    Gavalaksha

    1972)

    75 Bom L Rev

    668;

    Bhikamchand

    v. Kasturbhai

     1976)

    Born.

    1905.

    For a

    view that

    previous

    official policy was

    more sensitive, see

    J.

    Krishnan v. G.D.M. Committee, A.I.R. 1978

    Kerala

    68. These are a

    few

    illustrative

    examples of direct government involvement

    and how government

    is

    mobilized to

    take sides in

    socio-political disputes.

    35.

    For a reaction

    of an

    official government to

    the rising tide

    of

    litigation, see

    Rankin

    Committee, Report

    on

    Civil

    Justice (1924).

    Since

    then,

    successive

    reports

    of

    the

    Law Commission

    and

    various

    other

    committees view

    the increasing litigation

    with apprehension and helplessness. For a review

    of

    the

    literature

    and critique of

    the

    problem,

    see

    Dhavan,

    Litigation

    Explosion

    n

    India

    1986).

    36. E.g. Ushaben

    v.

    Bhagyalaxmi Chitra Mandir, A.I.R. 1978 Gujarat

    13 (on

    the

    depiction

    of the

    three

    goddesses as jealous). For disputes

    accepted

    as

    'legal'

    disputes,

    see

    Pahota Chinamma v. R. Dty.

    Director

    of Pub.,

    A.I.R. 1964

    A.P. 277;

    or

    Mohandas

    v.

    Travancore Devaswom Board

    1975)

    1 Kerala 55 (can a Christian

    playback film

    singer enter a Hindu temple?).

    37.

    On

    how

    the

    new constitutional reliefs created a new anti-government litiga-

    tion, see Dhavan, On the

    Future

    of Western Law and

    Justice

    in India: Reflections

    on the Predicament of the Post-Emergency Court, 1981 Journal of Bar Council

    India

    61-86; For

    an

    analysis

    of the

    new

    litigation,

    see Dhavan, The

    Supreme

    Court

    under Strain:

    The

    Challenge of Arrears

    (1979); and

    more

    generally,

    Dhavan,

    supra

    n.

    35.

    38. E.g. Vasudev and another

    v.

    Vannaji

    and another (1880) 5

    Born.

    80 esp. at 31-

    32 (whether ornaments should

    be

    put

    on

    an

    idol);

    Vathiar

    Ramanuja v.

    Aiyanchariar

  • 8/18/2019 Religeous Freedom In India - Rajiv Dhavan.pdf

    12/47

    DHAVAN:

    RELIGIOUS

    FREEDOM

    IN INDIA

    of determining

    the

    extent of any

    specific

    legal

    right without

    delving

    too

    deeply

    into the

    question

    of the

    'religious'

    point at

    issue.

    How-

    ever,

    at a

    more

    complex

    level, British

    courts

    did

    have

    to consider

    the extent

    of 'religious

    rights'. Following

    the Roman

    law

    formula

    of

    'justice, equity,

    and good

    conscience',

    the

    British

    committed

    them-

    selves

    to

    using

    the

    personal

    law of the

    Hindus,

    Muslims

    and other

    communities

    in order

    to

    control

    land,

    credit status,

    and

    other

    dis-

    putes.

    39

    The policy

    necessitated

    determining

    the preliminary

    claim

    whether

    a

    particular

    cause

    of action

    was or

    was not

    recognized

    by

    the

    personal

    law in question.

    In a

    sense,

    the British

    policy

    on

    the

    determination

    of

    personal

    law

    changed

    in a way quite

    analogous

    to

    the

    development

    of

    the

    policy

    of the post-independence

    Supreme

    Court

    on determining

    the

    constitutional

    justiciability

    of religious

    claims. The

    British

    began

    by

    seeking

    the

    advice

    of religious

    pandits

    and

    moulvis

    (Hindu and

    Muslim

    learned

    wise

    men

    respectively),

    who acted

    as

    experts

    advising the

    courts.

    But

    these

    often

    self-styled

    experts

    came

    in for much

    criticism,

    and recourse

    to

    them

    was abol-

    ished in 1864.

    Concurrently,

    the British

    had

    also commissioned

    t

    compilation

    of many

    treatises

    on the

    ancient

    texts and

    contempo-

    rary

    customs

    of

    various religions,

    sects, and

    geographic

    areas. Even-

    tually,

    the courts

    took

    over completely,

    continuing

    their

    alleged

    fidelity

    to the

    essence

    of

    the

    personal

    laws

    but

    seasoning

    their

    quest

    for

    authenticity

    with

    the imperatives

    of

    State

    policy.

    In

    any

    event,

    no

    ancient

    hermeneutic

    tradition

    could

    have

    assisted

    the

    judges

    not

    just

    to

    identify

    the

    personal law

    but

    also

    to

    interpret

    and

    adapt it

    to

    a rapidly

    transforming

    political

    economy

    and

    political system.

    If

    Anglo-Hindu

    and Anglo-Muslim

    law

    was

    faithful

    to the

    invocations

    of the ancients,

    judges

    of

    British

    India

    consciously

    remolded

    the law,

    often

    making

    what

    Gandhi

    was later

    to

    call 'egregious

    blunders'.

    After 1950

    the

    definition

    of 'religion'

    had

    to be considered

    in

    the context

    of constitutional

    provisions.

    At

    first,

    the

    High

    Courts

    replicated

    the

    dilemma

    of the

    Constitution-makers,

    with

    some

    judges

    taking

    the

    strongly

    reformist

    line

    of extending

    constitutional

    protection

    only

    to such

    beliefs

    and

    practices

    as

    were

    consistent

    with

    the new 'secularism'.

    40

    The constitutional

    argument acquired

    con-

     1912)

    17

    Ind.

    Cases

    219

    (annoyance

    to feelings);

    Behari

    Lal v. Shiva

    Lal 1902)

    24

    All. 499

    (cutting

    of branches

    of sacred pipal

    tree); see also Abdul

    Hakim

    Baig

    v. Bur-

    ramuddin,

    A.I.R. 1926 Mad.

    559;

    Jamolinga

    v. Sundara,

    A.I.R.

    1929

    Mad. 526;

    and also

    Ramachandra

    v. Gavalakshya

    1972)

    75 Born. 668

    at pr. 5

    p.

    671.

    For

    a

    recent exam-

    ple

    of abuse of

    process

    to

    harrass a

    minority

    community

    see Chandanmal

    Chopra

    v.

    State A.I.R.

    1986

    Cal. 104

    where the

    petitioner

    pleaded that

    all copies

    of

    the Holy

    Koran in

    the State of West

    Bengal

    be

    forfeited

    and

    destroyed( );

    see also

    Chopra:

    The Calcutta

    Quran etitions

    1986).

    39.

    Derrett,

    "Justice,

    Equity

    and

    Good Conscience,"

    in Anderson

    (ed.),

    Changing

    Law

    n Developing

    Countries114-53

    (1963);

    Derrett,

    "Justice,

    Equity

    and

    Good

    Con-

    science

    in

    India," 64

    Born.

    L. Rev.

    129

    145

    (1962);

    Dhavan,

    supra

    n.

    5 at

    95-101.

    40.

    E.g.,

    State

    of

    Bombay

    v. Narasu Appa, A.I.R.

    1952

    Born. 85

    (on

    Hindu

    polyg-

     98 ]

  • 8/18/2019 Religeous Freedom In India - Rajiv Dhavan.pdf

    13/47

    220

    THE

    AMERICAN

    JOURNAL OF

    COMPARATIVE

    LAW

    [Vol.

    35

    siderable

    political

    complexity when

    proponents

    of

    agrarian

    reform

    sought

    to acquire

    the property

    belonging

    to religious

    endowments

    and bring it

    under the scrutiny

    of

    various State administrations,

    which

    also possessed

    the

    default powers to create new management

    if the occasion

    demanded it.

    In the rirur

    ath

    case 1954),

    41

    Justice

    B.K. Mukerjea-an

    expert

    on

    the

    law relating

    to Hindu

    religious

    en-

    dowments-delivered

    a

    judgment

    for a unanimous

    Supreme Court.

    This

    judgment

    has become

    the focal

    point

    of constitutional

    discus-

    sion

    on

    religious freedoms.

    Asked

    to

    decide

    which

    aspects

    of any particular

    religion were

    entitled

    to

    constitutional protection,

    the

    Court

    impliedly rejected

    what

    could be

    called

    the

    'assertion'

    test, whereby

    a

    petitioner

    could

    simply assert

    that

    a

    particular

    practice was

    a

    religious

    practice.

    Ac-

    cordingly,

    the

    Court's

    task

    would

    be

    to

    assess

    the

    sufficiency of

    evi-

    dence required

    to establish

    the existence

    of

    such a

    practice.

    Mukerjea

    made

    it clear that

    the Court's

    inquiry into

    assertions

    of

    what

    beliefs, thoughts,

    and practices

    constituted

    a

    part of

    any partic-

    ular religion

    would be more far-ranging.

    He proposed

    the dangerous

    test that

    a 'practice' or

    set

    of

    beliefs must

    not

    only exist,

    but must

    be

    'essential'

    to

    that

    religion.

    4

    2

    To

    restore

    some

    objectivity

    into

    this

    process of judicial

    determination,

    it was

    expected

    that the

    courts

    would follow the

    intuitions

    of the

    Privy Council in

    determining 'es-

    sentiality'

    by

    reference

    to the doctrine

    and

    practice of

    the religion

    in

    question.

    43

    Mukerjea's

    test appeased

    traditionalists

    by

    assuring

    them

    that the

    Court would

    be

    sympathetic

    to

    their respective

    reli-

    gious faiths. It

    also supported

    state

    sponsored

    reform

    by leaving one

    agency

    of

    the State the

    judiciary with

    the

    power to

    determine

    and

    pronounce

    upon (perhaps,

    transform)

    religious practice

    and

    be-

    lief. Years

    later,

    another Supreme

    Court judge less

    sensitive

    to the

    conservation

    of

    religious

    tradition had

    no hesitation

    in stating

    that

      [ilt

    was obvious

    that religion

    undefined

    by

    the Constitution [was]

      ncapable of

    precise definition

    and

    judicial

    definition

    [was]

    ex-

    planatory

    and not

    definitive .

    44

    Although

    the rirur ath

    case has

    amy) Chagla,

    C.J.

    at

    pr.

    7

    p.

    86

    (on

    the

    State's

    legitimate

    interest

    in marriage);

    pr.

    13

    p.

    89

    (uniform

    civil code); also

    Gajendragadkar,

    J. at

    pr. 8

    p.

    94 Religion

    in

    a mod-

    ern

    State

    is purely a

    matter

    between

    an individual

    and

    his

    God.

    41.

    Commr.,

    H.R.E.

    v.

    L.T.

    Swamiar, A.I.R.

    1954

    S.C.

    282.

    42. Id.

    at

    pr.

    19 p.

    290.

    43.

    Id.

    at

    pr. 19

    p.

    290 where

    he refers

    to

    detailed aspects of

    the Hindu religion.

    However,

    at pr.

    2 p.

    291

    he

    talks

    of

    the Government

    monitoring wasteful

    expendi-

    tures

    on

    rites and

    ceremonies .

    44.

    Chinnappa

    Reddy, in S.P.

    Mittal v.

    Union of India, A.I.R.

    1983

    S.C.

    1

    at pr. 20

    p.

    8; pr.

    21

    p.

    9. Earlier

    at pr.

    1 p.

    3

    he

    states

    I

    apprehend I share

    the

    views of

    those

    who have

    neither

    faith

    nor belief

    in religion

    and who

    consider

    religion

    as

    entirely

    unscientific

    and irrational

    chanting of

    prayers

    appears to

    me to be

    mere

    jingoism

    and observance

    of

    ritual,

    plain superstition ; see

    also his

    decision

    in

    Bijoe

    Emman-

  • 8/18/2019 Religeous Freedom In India - Rajiv Dhavan.pdf

    14/47

    DHAVAN

    RELIGIOUS FREEDOM

    IN INDIA

    been commended for its balance and

    objectivity,

    it has always been

    an invitation to

    both

    judicial

    statesmanship and

    mischief.

    Indian

    society presents

    numerous

    awkward judicial

    issues. Are

    followers

    of

    the

    Saint Kabir Hindus?

    45

    Can

    the

    government

    cele-

    brate

    the

    2500th

    year

    of

    Lord

    Mahavira,

    the

    founder

    of

    Jainism?

    4

    6

    If new Hindu sects like the fanatical

    Ananda Margis were a religious

    denomination within

    the

    meaning of

    the Constitution,

    47

    why

    was

    this recognition not extended

    to followers

    of a modern religious

    leader like Sri Aurobindo?

    48

    How many kirpans (daggers) could a

    Sikh wear?

    49

    Is

    there a

    religious

    injunction

    against

    photographing

    Hindu

    women?

    50

    Does the secular

    preference for

    granting custody

    of small

    children to

    mothers

    violate contrary religious

    preferences

    in

    favor

    of

    other

    members of

    the family?

    51

    Must

    boys and

    girls

    wear

    modest

    apparel or

    can they invoke religious requirements, which in

    India

    extend to questions of dress as well as

    diet?

    52

    Was the

    preven-

    tion of

    cow

    slaughter

    just

    a Hindu attempt to deprive Muslim butch-

    ers of

    their livelihood

    or also an interference with an essential

    practice

    mandated

    by

    the Holy

    Koran?

    5 3

    What were the

    judges to

    do

    with these

    questions?

    What traditions

    were they expected to ex-

    amine in order to determine whether any

    particular

    aspect

    was

    an

     essential

    practice ?

    Confronted with these problems and

    aware that

    some

    litigation

    is

    inspired by

    social

    quarrels rather than deeply felt

    sentiment, the

    Courts have refused

    to

    consider seriously some of

    the

    questions

    brought

    before

    them.

    Emphasizing

    common

    sense,

    they

    have often

    sought

    to diffuse such

    situations by mediating

    acceptable com-

    uel, infra n.

    69, that Jehovah

    Witness children

    do not have

    to

    sing the

    national

    anthem.

     

    45.

    Baiyananda

    v.

    State

    of

    Bihar,

    A.I.R.

    1954

    Patna

    266.

    Cf.

    the

    case

    of

    the

    Arya

    Samaj in Arya Samaj

    Trust,

    Delhi v. Director

    of

    Education 1976)

    2

    Delhi 93 espe-

    cially on the Arya

    Samaj (pr.

    29 p. 112), Jains (pr. 31 p. 113), and

    Sikhs

    (pr. 32 p. 113-

    4).

    46.

    Suresh Chandra v.

    Union of

    India, A.I.R. 1975 Delhi 168.

    47.

    Jagdishwarranand

    v. Police

    Commissioner,

    Calcutta A.I.R.

    1984 Cal. 51.

    48. S.P.

    Mittal v.

    Union of

    India, supra

    n. 44.

    49. E.g. R. v. Dhyan Singh, A.I.R. 1952 Allahabad 53; for

    earlier

    cases see Em-

    peror

    v.

    Daljit

    Singh

    1930) 32

    Bom.

    L.Rev.

    106

    (carrying

    32

    kirpans ;

    Hari

    Singh

    v.

    Emperor 1924) 5 Lahore 308

    on

    S. 191 f)

    and

    Sch. II(3)(6) of Indian Arms Act (XI)

    of 1978.

    50.

    Nirmal

    Kumar

    v.

    Chief

    Election

    Officer,

    A.I.R.

    1961

    Cal.

    289,

    295-97,

    pr.

    9-12

    for the

    view that there

    was nothing in the Hindu and Muslim religions obviating the

    need for taking photographs for electoral

    purposes

    treating these

    arguments

    as

    poignant but

    unconvincing.

    51. Marggarate

    v. Chacko, A.I.R. 1970 Kerala 1

    at

    pr. 22 p.

    10.

    52. Rajendra Nair v. Principal, University College 1978) KL.T.

    204

    (the student

    member

    of

    the Siddhu Samaj

    was

    not

    allowed

    to wear a

    dhoti

    and

    shawl

    instead of

    a

    shirt).

    This

    interpretation was

    based

    on

    college

    rules rather than

    higher

    legal con-

    stitutional questions about

    freedom of religion.

    53. M.H. Qureshi v.

    State

    of

    Bihar,

    A.I.R. 1958

    S.C.

    731; A.H. Qureshi v. State of

    Bihar,

    A.I.R.

    1961 S.C.

    448;

    Mohd. Faruk

    v.

    State

    of

    M.P., A.I.R. 1970 S.C. 93.

    1987]

  • 8/18/2019 Religeous Freedom In India - Rajiv Dhavan.pdf

    15/47

    222

    THE AMERICAN JOURNAL OF COMPARATIVE

    LAW [Vol.

    35

    promises through judicial pronouncements.

    For

    example,

    faced

    with

    complaints

    from Hindus (on

    wall of

    separation grounds)

    and

    Jains

    (for

    interfering

    with

    their

    religion),

    a Delhi

    judge

    followed

    his intui-

    tion

    that

    litigation questioning

    the

    government s

    celebration

    of

    Lord

    Mahavira s birthday was mischievious.

    54

    In

    the given fact situation,

    this was understandable,

    even

    salutary. But the judge sought

    consti-

    tutional

    clarity when

    he argued for:

     

    a

    secular

    way

    of remembering Bhagwan

    Mahavir is de-

    vised

    by the government to suit all people

    irrespective

    of

    the

    religion

    to which they

    belong. It

    is

    of the essence of a

    common

    cultural activity

    that everyone should

    participate

    in

    it.

    5

    5

    If this rationale is extended, it is surely

    not unconstitutional for

    the

    Ministry

    of

    Culture

    to celebrate all religion out

    of

    existence,

    in

    the name of

    common

    culture .

    And, if it

    did, one

    would undoubt-

    edly be

    more

    than curious about the origins of its constitutional

    mandate. Yet,

    the judge s

    dilemma

    was as

    real

    as

    it

    was complex.

    A

    judicial decision ordering the government

    to stop its celebration

    would

    have offended

    the sentiment of a

    larger number

    of Jains,

    in-

    cluding

    many on

    the government s

    celebration

    committee.

    To

    take

    another

    example,

    consider

    the

    Cow

    Slaughter

    cases.

    56

    How could the

    judges have ignored the fact that

    Hindus,

    holding

    the

    cow in great

    reverence,

    find the

    idea

    of

    the slaughter of cows for

    food

    repugnant?

    57

    Yet what was

    at issue

    was

    not

    Hindu sentiment

    but the

    content

    of

    Islam. The

    argument

    that

    cow

    slaughter might

    be

    a religious

    practice was

    referred to

    as a bald allegation

    58

    and,

    after

    a brief

    reference

    to

    the Koran and Hamilton s translation

    of the

    Hedaya

    9

    the

    Court dismissed the argument on the

    ground

    that the

    Koran, by giving an option of the slaughter

    of goat for

    one

    person,

    or

    a cow

    or

    camel for seven, did not

    oblige the Muslim to slaughter a

    cow.

    60

    The Hindu position

    (which

    was

    not at issue before the Court)

    was explained by interveners, but

    regarding

    the

    Muslim position the

    Court was

    content

    to

    declare:

    We

    have

    no

    affidavit

    before

    us by any Maulana

    explaining

    the

    implications

    of

    those verses or

    throwing

    any

    light

    on

    this

    problem?

    6

    1

    54.

    Supra n. 46 .

    55. Id para.

    14 p. 174.

    56. Supra

    n.

    53

    at

    pr. 20 p 8; pr. 21

    p.

    9

    .

    57.

    Qureshi,

    supra n. 53 at pr. 22 p 745 col.

    2.

    58. Id.

    at pr. 13 p 739 col. 2.

    59. Id. at pr. 13 pp

    739 40 citing

    the

    Holy

    Koran

    Surah

    22 verses 28 and 33 and

    Surah 107.

    60. Id.

    pr.

    13 p.

    740,

    col. 1.

    61. Id pr. 11

    pp. 738-9. On

    the

    Supreme Court and interveners in cases gener-

    ally, see

    Dhavan, supra

    n.

    5 at 105-112.

  • 8/18/2019 Religeous Freedom In India - Rajiv Dhavan.pdf

    16/47

    DHAVAN:

    RELIGIOUS

    FREEDOM

    IN

    INDIA

    But,

    if the

    petitioners

    had requested

    the Court

    to

    hear their

    religious leaders,

    it

    is

    not

    clear

    whether the

    Court would have

    al-

    lowed

    them

    to intervene. So, how

    is the

    Court

    to

    determine what

    an

    'essential

    practice'

    is?

    Should

    it

    rely

    on

    religious

    leaders?

    Should

    it

    call for evidence?

    Should

    judges

    pursue these questions on

    the

    basis

    of

    their

    own research? Should

    the

    judge interpret

    the

    tradition

    through the

    techniques available

    to a

    'common law' judge?

    And,

    if as

    has been suggested-the

    judge

    should

    enter that tradition to

    ascertain

    its own internal rules and techniques, its methods of as-

    sessing the relative importance

    of its various

    elements and

    the

    ad-

    missibility of innovations ,

    62

    can he wholly

    avoid

    creative

    interpretation

    or ignore social discontent?

    Indian judges have

    not

    been discerning in dealing

    with

    the

    many difficulties raised

    in

    employing the 'essential practice' test.

    Mechanically citing

    the

    rirur

    Math

    case

    they have assumed

    that so

    long as some kind of inquiry into religious tradition

    takes

    place, the

    manner and form

    in

    which

    these inquiries are

    to

    be

    conducted have

    not

    been

    elaborated

    by

    even the highest

    court of

    the land.

    63

    There

    are no indicators as

    to

    what kind of evidence should be considered

    authoritative, no rules of interpretation, no emphasis on detailed

    re-

    search, and no

    requirement

    to consult authoritative

    exponents

    and

    material. Some

    judges

    are careful about their consultation of texts.

    An Allahabad

    judge

    took

    pains over

    the Koranic

    texts in order to

    determine

    a

    Muslim

    husband's duty

    to

    maintain

    his

    first

    wife

    (who

    left him

    on

    the

    arrival

    of

    her

    successor).

    64

    The Supreme Court,

    ex-

    amining

    the

    same question twenty-five years later, was much more

    dramatic

    in

    its

    examination

    and decided to

    throw

    judicial caution to

    the winds.

    65

    Some

    judges simply

    resort to whatever information

    they

    can

    lay their

    hands

    on.

    At least

    one judge on the

    Supreme Court, Justice

    Gajendragad-

    kar, has superimposed another 'secular'

    requirement

    on the 'essen-

    tial

    practice' test,

    namely the requirement

    of

    rationality. In

    the

    62.

    Galanter, Hinduism, Secularism and

    the Indian Judiciary, 21 Philosophy

    East and West 467 at 482-83 1971).

    63.

    For the

    random

    nature

    of

    the

    inquiry into

    religious practice using

    the

    Srirur

    Math

    case

    supra n. 41, see Jagdishwaranand v. Police Commissioner, supra n.

    47

    prs.

    10 11 pp. 56-71. In other cases virtually no

    inquiry

    is made at all (Tulzapurkar,

    J.

    in

    Abdul Jalil v. U.P.,

    A.I.R. 1984

    S.C.

    882

    prs.

    22-24 pp. 883-84 on whether Sunni

    graves can be shifted, relying solely on the

    police power

    to control; see also Krishna

    Iyer, J. on planning

    law

    and samadhis (commemorative remembrances) in Mahan

    Ram

    Kishan Dass

    v.

    Punjab, A.I.R.

    1981

    S.C. 1576). Consider

    the

    difference of

    opin-

    ion

    in the

    B.M.

    Basha case in the Madras High Court

    Statesman,

    27

    August,

    1986)

    where

    a

    Divisional Bench

    stayed

    the order of

    a

    single judge

    to

    the effect that grow-

    ing a

    beard was not an essential

    part

    of Islam. Mr. Basha,

    a

    security

    officer in

    Bharat Heavy Electrical

    Ltd.,

    had been denied permission

    to

    grow

    a

    beard.

    64. Itwari

    v.

    Ashghari, A.I.R. 1960 All. 680.

    65.

    Mohd. Ahmed Khan v. Shah Bano Begum, A.I.R. 1985 S.C.

    945.

    1987]

  • 8/18/2019 Religeous Freedom In India - Rajiv Dhavan.pdf

    17/47

    224 THE AMERICAN JOURNAL OF COMPARATIVE

    LAW

    [Vol. 35

    Durgah

    Committee

    case,

    Gajendragadkar

    denied

    validity

    to

    prac-

    tices

    which,

    though

    religious,

    may have

    sprung from

    superstitious

    and

    unessential

    accretions

    to religious

    itself.

     66

    Under

    this

    ration-

    ale, an 'essential practice'

    did

    not

    just

    have to satisfy an

    internal

    test

    of

    being integral

    to

    a religion,

    but

    an

    additional

    external

    require-

    ment that

    it was

    not the

    product

    of superstition.

    Gajendragadkar

    enlarged

    his argument

    in various

    cases concerning

    religious

    endow-

    ments,

    67

    culminating

    in

    the

    Swami Narayan

    case,

    68

    which

    involved

    throwing

    open

    Hindu

    temples

    to

    all 'classes

    of

    people'.

    But

    the

    Swami Narayans

    claimed

    they

    were

    not Hindus.

    In insisting

    that

    they

    are,

    Gajendragadkar

    seems to

    have sacrificed traditional

    claims

    to a reformist

    modernity.

    This was

    partly

    done for

    the

    purpose

    of

    bringing

    a particular

    sect

    within

    the ambit

    of the social

    reform

    of

    opening temples

    to Untouchables.

    Gajendragadkar

    had

    no

    other

    choice

    but

    to

    extend

    the

    Act

    as

    widely

    as

    possible to

    as

    many

    de-

    nominations

    as

    possible.

    Had

    he not

    done

    so

    each

    sect

    could have

    claimed

    a

    modern, distinct

    and non-Hindu

    ancestry.

    However, the

    judgment

    attempts more

    than this

    salutary purpose.

    It seeks

    to allo-

    cate

    a

    new

    reformist

    role to

    the courts. The

    courts are

    not

    just

    ex-

    pected to

    interpret

    social

    reform

    statutes

    liberally,

    but also to

    reform

    religions from within

    by

    liberating

    them from irrationality.

    But

    whom are

    these judicial

    pronouncements

    supposed

    to

    convince?

    The

    petitioners?

    The

    religious

    groups in

    question? The

    general

    populace?

    As part

    of

    a

    plan

    to

    lay the

    intellectual

    foundations

    of a

    new dispensation based

    on

    rationality, this

    approach lacks sensitivity

    and

    conviction. It also

    lays the

    path

    open for

    an

    unmanageable

    ju-

    risprudence

    of religious

    freedoms.

    The

    latest judgment

    which

    caused

    a

    national

    furor by absolving

    Jehovah's

    Witnesses

    from

    sing-

    ing the National

    Anthem

    affirms

    a wayward

    and

    eclectic

    approach

    by

    abandoning

    any

    kind of

    sensitive inquiry

    into

    religious

    claims

    and

    providing

    no

    reasoned

    justification

    for

    the

    new

    secularism.

    69

    66.

    Durgah Committee

    v.

    Hussain

    Ali, A.I.R.

    1962

    S.C.

    1402

    at pr.

    33 p.

    1415.

    67

    Apart

    from

    urgah

    Committee

    id., see

    Tilkayat

    v. State of

    Rajasthan, A.I.R.

    1963

    S.C. 1638 at

    pr. 61 p. 1661

    where

    he assumes that

    a right to

    management must

    be a

    purely

    secular

    matter;

    see also

    M.

    Dasaratharami

    Reddi

    v.

    D.

    Subba

    Rao,

    A.I.R.

    1957

    S.C.

    797.

    68 Yagnapurushdasji

    v.

    Muldas,

    A.I.R. 1966

    S.C.

    1119.

    For incisive

    comment,

    see

    Galanter,

    supra n.

    62; Derrett, Hindu:

    A

    definition

    wanted for

    the purpose of ap-

    plying Hindu

    Law,

    70 Z

    V.R.

    110 (1968); Derrett,

    The definition

    of

    a Hindu,

    2

    S.C.J.

    67-74

    (1966).

    69.

    Bijoe Emmanuel

    v. State

    of Kerala,

    C.A.

    No.

    870,

    reversing A.I.R.

    1986

    Ker-

    ala

    32 and creating an

    unexpected

    controversy.

    For other

    important

    recent

    exam-

    ples,

    see

    two

    recent cases.

    The

    Anand

    Margis

    were

    treated as a

    denominational sect,

    but their tandava dance

    was not regarded

    as an 'essential practice'

    even though

    they

    passionately

    believed it

    was (see Jagdishwaranand

    v.

    Police

    Commissioner,

    Calcutta,

    supra

    n. 47,

    esp.

    pr. 12

    p.

    57).

    However,

    the

    followers

    of Aurobindo

    did

    not

    even

    succeed

    in

    getting their religious

    status recognized:

    see S.P.

    Mittal v.

    Union

    of

    India,

    supra

    n. 44 (note

    the

    dissent

    of Chinnappa Reddy

    at pr.

    33

    p. 11.

  • 8/18/2019 Religeous Freedom In India - Rajiv Dhavan.pdf

    18/47

    DHAVAN:

    RELIGIOUS

    FREEDOM

    IN

    INDIA

      onstitutionalLimitations

    Although

    one Supreme

    Court

    judge

    emphasized

    that rights,

    rather

    than limitations, were

    fundamental

    in the interpretation

    of

    civil

    liberties,

    the

    courts

    have generally expanded

    limitations

    and

    marginalized

    rights.

    The

    Constitution

    employs

    various

    schemes to

    limit the

    rights

    enumerated in

    the

    Chapter

    on

    Fundamental

    Rights.

    The most

    gen-

    eral

    of these schemes is

    the leg l

    m nd te

    approach.

    The original

    Constitution

    envisaged that

    life, liberty and property

    could

    be

    taken

    away

    by

    procedure

    established

    by law .

    70

    All

    that was

    required to

    legitimate

    interference

    with rights

    was

    legislative

    authority.

    Over

    the

    years,

    a

    notion

    of

    due process has been

    read into

    these any pro-

    cess

    provisions.

    7

    1

    In

    the

    second scheme,

    termed the

    c tegoriz tion

    approach,

    t

    Court

    asks

    whether any

    particular activity

    falls within

    the

    ambit

    of

    a right ( X )

    or whether

    it belongs

    to

    some

    different

    category ( Y ).

    We have

    already

    seen

    how the Supreme

    Court

    struggled

    over X

    questions

    while defining religion.

    Its

    moral reformist

    approach

    to

    determining

    X

    questions

    was replicated

    in other areas when

    it de-

    cided that

    activities such

    as gambling,

    selling

    liquor

    and rural

    money-lending

    were

    too morally

    offensive

    to

    be protected under

    the

    broad

    rubric

    of the

    right to practice

    any profession

    and

    to carry on

    any occupation or

    business .

    An

    alternative

    approach is

    to concen-

    trate

    on the Y question.

    By this method

    the

    Court

    argues

    that

    if

    an

    activity

    falls within

    any category

    of

    permissible

    restriction,

    it auto-

    matically

    falls outside

    the

    ambit

    of

    the

    right. The

    Supreme

    Court

    has

    implicitly

    followed

    this

    reasoning

    in its approach

    to

    free

    speech

    questions.

    Wherever

    the

    Court

    found

    a

    restriction

    that

    fell within

    one

    of the categories

    of permissible

    restriction

    (i.e.,

    public

    order,

    contempt

    of

    court,

    official

    secrecy, morality,

    defamation,

    etc.)

    it

    as-

    sumed

    that because

    it fell within

    a Y

    category

    (of restraint),

    this

    obviated the need

    to look

    at

    X questions

    (concerning

    the

    extent

    of

    the

    right) with

    any

    rigor,

    if at all.

    A

    third

    approach

    has

    been

    to evolve

    a theory

    of

    reasonableness

    drawn

    from procedural due process notions

    of

    anti-arbitrariness

    and

    permissible

    classification

    (drawn

    from

    the

    equality

    article),

    substan-

    tive due

    process

    (drawn from

    the reasonable

    restrictions

    permitted

    70.

    Art. 21

    (life

    and liberty)

    and Art.

    31 (property),

    Constitution

    of

    India.

    71

    After

    the any

    process

    view in Gopalan

    v

    State of Madras,

    A.I.R.

    1950

    S C

    27,

    the transformation

    into due

    process

    was

    affected by Kochuni

    v.

    Madras,

    A.I.R.

    1960

    S.C. 1080;

    and

    R.C. Cooper

    v.

    Union

    of India,

    A.I.R. 1970

    S.C.

    564

    and settled in

    Maneka

    Gandhi v. Union of India

    1978)

    1

    S.C.C.

    249;

    Charles Sobhraj v. Supt.,

    Cen-

    tral

    Jail,

    A.I.R. 1978

    S.C.

    1514;

    M.H. Hoskot

    v. State

    of

    Maharashtra,

    A.I.R. 1978

    S.C.

    1548; Sunil

    Batra v.

    Delhi Administration, A.I.R.

    1978

    S.C.

    1675;

    Hussainara

    Khatoon

    v. State

    of

    Bihar,

    A.I.R. 1979

    S.C.

    1360, 1369,

    1377,

    8 9

    98 ]

  • 8/18/2019 Religeous Freedom In India - Rajiv Dhavan.pdf

    19/47

    226

    THE AMERICAN

    JOURNAL

    OF

    COMPARATIVE

    LAW

    [Vol.

    35

    in respect

    of seven enumerated

    freedoms

    in Article

    19 ,

    and

    eminent

    domain (derived

    from

    the

    now

    abolished right

    to

    property).

    72

    The

    fourth

    approach

    emphasizes

    social

    reform

    through

    such

    measures

    as

    the

    abolition

    of

    untouchability,

    the

    prevention

    of

    ex-

    ploitation,

    police

    power pertaining

    to public

    order, health

    and

    moral-

    ity

    provisions,

    the

    opening

    up

    of temples,

    and

    blanket

    immunity

    provisions

    pertaining

    to various

    measures

    of

    agrarian

    reform

    and

    public

    policy.

    These

    social

    reform

    provisions

    have been

    given

    fur-

    ther

    direction

    by the

    Directive

    Principles

    of State

    Policy

    which

    have,

    of

    late,

    loomed

    large in

    the Supreme

    Court's

    interpretation

    of

    Fundamental

    Rights.

    Finally,

    there are

    'wall

    of separation'

    questions

    that

    have

    been

    specifically

    delineated

    for operation

    in relation

    to particular

    aspects

    of

    the

    exercise

    of

    religious freedoms.

    7

    3

    All

    these

    approaches have

    been

    used

    in the

    interpretation

    of religious

    freedoms,

    albeit

    with

    dif-

    ferent emphases.