In the Mood for Democracy? Democratic Support as ...€¦ · but their preference for democracy...

18
American Political Science Review (2020) 114, 1, 3653 doi:10.1017/S0003055419000558 © American Political Science Association 2019 In the Mood for Democracy? Democratic Support as Thermostatic Opinion CHRISTOPHER CLAASSEN University of Glasgow P ublic support has long been thought crucial for the vitality and survival of democracy. Existing research has argued that democracy also creates its own demand: through early-years socialization and later-life learning, the presence of a democratic system coupled with the passage of time produces widespread public support for democracy. Using new panel measures of democratic mood varying over 135 countries and up to 30 years, this article nds little evidence for such a positive feedback effect of democracy on support. Instead, it demonstrates a negative thermostatic effect: increases in de- mocracy depress democratic mood, while decreases cheer it. Moreover, it is increases in the liberal, counter- majoritarian aspects of democracy, not the majoritarian, electoral aspects that provoke this backlash from citizens. These novel results challenge existing research on support for democracy, but also reconcile this research with the literature on macro-opinion. INTRODUCTION L iberal democracy is widely believed to be in a crisis (e.g., Diamond 2015). The crisis is not yet one of widespread democratic failure (Mechkova, L ¨ uhrmann, and Lindberg 2017); it is in- stead a crisis of condence or legitimacy. As Plattner (2017) puts it, democracy has a fading allure.Indeed, several scholars have claimed to nd evidence of this fading allure: diminishing support for democracy in long-established democracies, particularly among younger generations (Denemark, Donovan, and Niemi 2016; Foa and Mounk 2016, 2017; Norris 2017; cf. Voeten 2017). Such declines in democratic legitimacy are puzzling when viewed through the lens of existing research on public support for democracy. According to this re- search, citizens of democratic societies learn to sup- port democracyinitially through socialization in their adolescent years (Dalton 1994; Mishler and Rose 2007; Montero, Gunther, and Torcal 1997; Pop- Eleches and Tucker 2017; Rose, Mishler, and Haerpfer 1998), and later in life, as they experience such fruits of democratic citizenship as political freedoms and responsive government (Bratton and Mattes 2001; Evans and Whiteeld 1995; Magalhães 2014; Mattes and Bratton 2007; Mattes, Denemark, and Niemi 2016a; Mishler and Rose 2002; Rose, Mishler, and Haerpfer 1998). In sum, democracy is believed to create its own demand (e.g., Mattes, Denemark, and Niemi 2016b): democratic govern- ment coupled with the passage of time produces high levels of support for democracy. The notion that support for democracy might ebb and ow, even in long-established liberal democracies, is not consistent with these theories of democratic socializa- tion and lifetime learning. It is consistent, however, with a theory from another area of public opinion researchthe thermostatic model (Erikson, Mackuen, and Stimson 2002; Soroka and Wlezien 2010; Wlezien 1995). This model proposes that public opinion reacts to policy by moving in the opposite direction: when gov- ernment spending increases, citizens prefer that it de- crease; where policy shifts to the right, citizenspreferences move to the left. Applied to the opinion- democracy link, the thermostatic model predicts that publics would clamor for democracy when it is scarce, but their preference for democracy would weaken as democratic rights and institutions are supplied. If sup- port for democracyor democratic moodto adopt Stimsons(1991) coinageobeys a thermostatic logic, then we would expect to see it uctuating over time, even in established democracies, and particularly in response to recent changes in the level of democracy itself. The purpose of this article is to test whether the supply of democracy creates its own demand or whether citizens instead turn against democracy once it is supplied. In other words, this article tests theories of democratic learning against the thermo- static model. To carry out these tests, I make use of new country-by-year measures of democratic mood esti- mated using the Bayesian latent variable model of Claassen (2019b) and new nely grained measures of democracy provided by the Varieties of Democracy project (V-Dem Institute 2018b). These new meas- ures are used to assemble a large panel dataset varying over 135 countries and up to 30 years. This dataset, in turn, permits the use of dynamic models, which control for the effects of previous levels of mood, and rst difference models, which eliminate the confounding effects of time-invariant, country- specic factors. I nd little evidence that democracy creates its own demand. Higher levels of democracy do not have a ro- bust, positive effect on subsequent public support. Christopher Claassen , Senior Lecturer, School of Social and Po- litical Sciences, University of Glasgow, christopher.claassen@ glasgow.ac.uk. I would like to thank James L. Gibson, Robert Mattes, Lauren McLaren, William Mishler, and Christopher Wlezien for their helpful comments. Replication les are available at the American Political Science Review Dataverse: https://doi.org/10.7910/DVN/FECIO3. Received: July 22, 2018; revised: February 20, 2019; accepted: August 20, 2019; First published online: September 20, 2019. 36 Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core . IP address: 54.39.106.173 , on 14 Jun 2020 at 06:32:36, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms . https://doi.org/10.1017/S0003055419000558

Transcript of In the Mood for Democracy? Democratic Support as ...€¦ · but their preference for democracy...

Page 1: In the Mood for Democracy? Democratic Support as ...€¦ · but their preference for democracy would weaken as democratic rights and institutions are supplied. If sup-port for democracy—or

American Political Science Review (2020) 114, 1, 36–53

doi:10.1017/S0003055419000558 © American Political Science Association 2019

In the Mood for Democracy? Democratic Support as ThermostaticOpinionCHRISTOPHER CLAASSEN University of Glasgow

Public support has long been thought crucial for the vitality and survival of democracy. Existingresearch has argued that democracy also creates its own demand: through early-years socializationand later-life learning, the presence of a democratic system coupled with the passage of time

produces widespread public support for democracy. Using new panel measures of democratic moodvarying over 135 countries and up to 30 years, this article finds little evidence for such a positive feedbackeffect of democracy on support. Instead, it demonstrates a negative thermostatic effect: increases in de-mocracydepress democraticmood,while decreases cheer it.Moreover, it is increases in the liberal, counter-majoritarian aspects of democracy, not the majoritarian, electoral aspects that provoke this backlash fromcitizens. These novel results challenge existing research on support for democracy, but also reconcile thisresearch with the literature on macro-opinion.

INTRODUCTION

Liberal democracy is widely believed to be ina crisis (e.g., Diamond 2015). The crisis is notyet one of widespread democratic failure

(Mechkova, Luhrmann, and Lindberg 2017); it is in-stead a crisis of confidence or legitimacy. As Plattner(2017) puts it, democracy has a “fading allure.” Indeed,several scholars have claimed to find evidence of thisfading allure: diminishing support for democracy inlong-established democracies, particularly amongyounger generations (Denemark, Donovan, and Niemi2016; Foa and Mounk 2016, 2017; Norris 2017; cf.Voeten 2017).

Such declines in democratic legitimacy are puzzlingwhen viewed through the lens of existing research onpublic support for democracy. According to this re-search, citizens of democratic societies learn to sup-port democracy—initially through socialization intheir adolescent years (Dalton 1994;Mishler andRose2007; Montero, Gunther, and Torcal 1997; Pop-Eleches and Tucker 2017; Rose, Mishler, andHaerpfer 1998), and later in life, as they experiencesuch fruits of democratic citizenship as politicalfreedoms and responsive government (Bratton andMattes 2001; Evans and Whitefield 1995; Magalhães2014; Mattes and Bratton 2007; Mattes, Denemark,and Niemi 2016a; Mishler and Rose 2002; Rose,Mishler, and Haerpfer 1998). In sum, democracy isbelieved to create its own demand (e.g., Mattes,Denemark, and Niemi 2016b): democratic govern-ment coupled with the passage of time produces highlevels of support for democracy.

Thenotion that support for democracymight ebb andflow, even in long-established liberal democracies, is notconsistent with these theories of democratic socializa-tion and lifetime learning. It is consistent, however, witha theory from another area of public opinionresearch—the thermostatic model (Erikson, Mackuen,and Stimson 2002; Soroka and Wlezien 2010; Wlezien1995). Thismodel proposes that public opinion reacts topolicy by moving in the opposite direction: when gov-ernment spending increases, citizens prefer that it de-crease; where policy shifts to the right, citizens’preferences move to the left. Applied to the opinion-democracy link, the thermostatic model predicts thatpublics would clamor for democracy when it is scarce,but their preference for democracy would weaken asdemocratic rights and institutions are supplied. If sup-port for democracy—or democratic “mood” to adoptStimson’s (1991) coinage—obeys a thermostatic logic,then we would expect to see it fluctuating over time,even in established democracies, and particularly inresponse to recent changes in the level of democracyitself.

The purpose of this article is to test whether thesupply of democracy creates its own demand orwhether citizens instead turn against democracyonce it is supplied. In other words, this article teststheories of democratic learning against the thermo-staticmodel. To carry out these tests, Imakeuseof newcountry-by-year measures of democratic mood esti-mated using the Bayesian latent variable model ofClaassen (2019b) and new finely grained measures ofdemocracy provided by the Varieties of Democracyproject (V-Dem Institute 2018b). These new meas-ures are used to assemble a large panel datasetvarying over 135 countries and up to 30 years. Thisdataset, in turn, permits the use of dynamic models,which control for the effects of previous levels ofmood, and first difference models, which eliminatethe confounding effects of time-invariant, country-specific factors.

I find little evidence that democracy creates its owndemand. Higher levels of democracy do not have a ro-bust, positive effect on subsequent public support.

Christopher Claassen , Senior Lecturer, School of Social and Po-litical Sciences, University of Glasgow, [email protected].

I would like to thank James L. Gibson, Robert Mattes, LaurenMcLaren,WilliamMishler, and ChristopherWlezien for their helpfulcomments. Replication files are available at the American PoliticalScience Review Dataverse: https://doi.org/10.7910/DVN/FECIO3.

Received: July 22, 2018; revised: February 20, 2019; accepted:August 20, 2019; First published online: September 20, 2019.

36

Dow

nloa

ded

from

htt

ps://

ww

w.c

ambr

idge

.org

/cor

e. IP

add

ress

: 54.

39.1

06.1

73, o

n 14

Jun

2020

at 0

6:32

:36,

sub

ject

to th

e Ca

mbr

idge

Cor

e te

rms

of u

se, a

vaila

ble

at h

ttps

://w

ww

.cam

brid

ge.o

rg/c

ore/

term

s. h

ttps

://do

i.org

/10.

1017

/S00

0305

5419

0005

58

Page 2: In the Mood for Democracy? Democratic Support as ...€¦ · but their preference for democracy would weaken as democratic rights and institutions are supplied. If sup-port for democracy—or

Instead, I find a marked thermostatic effect, wherechanges in democracy are associated with immediateand opposite public reactions: increases in democracydampen public mood, while decreases cheer it. Imoreover demonstrate that it is the minoritarianrather than majoritarian aspects of democracy thatcitizens find troubling. While increases in electoraldemocracy do not affect changes in support, enhancedchecks on the executive and increased protection ofindividual rights do undermine mass support. Overall,the image of the democratic citizen that emerges fromthis article is a more mercurial and intolerant one thatthe existing literature on support for democracy hassuggested.

These novel results challenge existing research onsupport for democracy. But they also reconcile thisresearch with studies of macro-opinion (Erikson,Mackuen, and Stimson 2002; Soroka andWlezien 2010;Wlezien 1995) and political intolerance (Gibson 1998),as well as normative debates regarding the role ofcounter-majoritarian institutions in democracy (Bickel1986).

LITERATURE REVIEW

Conceptualizing Democratic Mood

If the institutions and procedures that structure thepolitical lives of democracies are the “hardware” ofthese systems—as Rose, Mishler, and Haerpfer (1998,8) elegantly put it—then public opinion toward de-mocracy is the “software” that buttresses these insti-tutions and procedures. When a democratic systemenjoys widespread public support, the software andhardware are congruent (Eckstein 1966), renderingdemocracy legitimate (Lipset 1959), stable (Claassen2019a), and perhaps even consolidated (Linz and Ste-pan 1996).

Two major conceptualizations of this democratic“software” have emerged.1 One approach, which wemight refer to “implicit” support for democracy, fo-cuses on broader sociopolitical values, such as post-materialism and egalitarianism (Inglehart and Welzel2005; Welzel 2013). Here, democracy is legitimatewhen it is consistent with citizen’s deeper values andstrivings.

A second approach focuses more specifically ondemocratic and nondemocratic systems of gover-nance, and is thus concerned with “explicit” supportfor democracy. Such support requires not onlya positive principled appraisal of democracy, but alsoa rejection of autocratic alternatives (e.g., Inglehartand Welzel 2005; Linz and Stepan 1996; Mattes andBratton 2007; Rose, Mishler, and Haerpfer 1998). Inthis view, democracy is legitimate when it is viewed asthe most appropriate regime for the country and, in

particular, when it is preferred to some non-democratic alternative.

Explicit support for democracy versus autocracy is byfar the most widely used conceptualization of demo-cratic legitimacy used in the literature. Studies of ex-plicit support have been conducted for several decades,in every region of the world: Western Europe (Baker,Dalton, andHildebrandt 1981), Southern Europe (e.g.,Montero, Gunther, and Torcal 1997), the post-Sovietregion (e.g., Evans and Whitefield 1995; Pop-Elechesand Tucker 2017; Rose, Mishler, and Haerpfer 1998),sub-Saharan Africa (e.g., Bratton and Mattes 2001;Bratton, Mattes, and Gyimah-Boadi 2005; Mattes andBratton 2007), LatinAmerica (e.g., Booth and Seligson2009), East Asia (e.g., Dalton and Shin 2006), andglobally (Denemark, Donovan, and Niemi 2016; Klin-gemann 1999; Linz and Stepan 1996; Norris 2011). Itherefore focus in this articleoncitizens’explicit supportfor democratic versus nondemocratic regimes. More-over, since the focushere is thenational level of analysis,I adopt the notion of “mood” from previous studies ofmacro-opinion (e.g., Erikson, Mackuen, and Stimson2002). The dependent variable used in this article istherefore national levels of support for democracy or“democratic mood.”

The Drivers of Democratic Mood

Armed with the conviction that public support for de-mocracy is vital for democratic stability and consoli-dation, scholars have devoted considerable effort tounderstanding its determinants. Two main theorieshave emerged to explain how citizens and societiescome to support democracy: generational socializationand regime performance.

The first of these theories holds that support fordemocracy is transmitted through socialization, par-ticularly in the “impressionable” years of late adoles-cence and early adulthood (Jennings and Niemi 1974;Mannheim1952).Theassumption is that individuals aretaught (or perhaps indoctrinated) to support the regimein which they emerge into adulthood: if this is a de-mocracy, support for democracy is learned; if an au-tocracy, support for some nondemocratic regime isinstead instilled (e.g., Dalton 1994; Rose, Mishler, andHaerpfer 1998).

Viewed through the lens of socialization theory, thepolitical system comes to exert a strong influence onpublic opinion. Following democratization, supportincreases with the passage of time as one generationafter another becomes acculturated. Indeed, scholarssometimes speakofdemocracy creating its owndemand(Mattes, Denemark, and Niemi 2016b). Finally, afterseveral generations under a democratic system, supportfor democracy becomes ubiquitous. The system is thendescribed as consolidated (Linz and Stepan 1996).

Evidence for the theory of generational socializationhas been demonstrated in studies from such dispa-rate contexts as 1970s Germany (Baker, Dalton, andHildebrandt 1981), 1980s Spain (Montero, Gunther,and Torcal 1997), and 1990s Russia (Mishler and Rose

1 See Dalton and Welzel (2014) and Mattes (2018) for thoroughreviews of these literatures.

In the Mood for Democracy?

37

Dow

nloa

ded

from

htt

ps://

ww

w.c

ambr

idge

.org

/cor

e. IP

add

ress

: 54.

39.1

06.1

73, o

n 14

Jun

2020

at 0

6:32

:36,

sub

ject

to th

e Ca

mbr

idge

Cor

e te

rms

of u

se, a

vaila

ble

at h

ttps

://w

ww

.cam

brid

ge.o

rg/c

ore/

term

s. h

ttps

://do

i.org

/10.

1017

/S00

0305

5419

0005

58

Page 3: In the Mood for Democracy? Democratic Support as ...€¦ · but their preference for democracy would weaken as democratic rights and institutions are supplied. If sup-port for democracy—or

2007). Generational effects have also been detected inpooled cross-national analyses of support for de-mocracy (Mishler and Rose 2007; Pop-Eleches andTucker 2017).

Nevertheless, other studies find contradictory evi-dence. Mishler and Rose (2002) find no effect of gen-erations in an analysis ofCentral andEasternEuropeandata. Foa and Mounk (2016, 2017) have argued thatsupport for democracy has in fact declined amongyounger generations in established democracies. Al-though their conclusions have been disputed (e.g.,Voeten 2017), at least one of their critics agrees thatgenerationaldecline in support fordemocracy is evidentin a dozen or so democracies (Norris 2017). The mostserious challenge to the socialization hypothesis, how-ever, comes from several studies of Global Barometersurvey data. In region after region—most featuring newdemocracies with stark generational differences in ex-posure to democracy—little to no evidence of genera-tional socialization emerges (Mattes, Denemark, andNiemi 2016a).

The second theoretical account of how citizens cometo support or oppose democracy is the performance ofthe regime. Like socialization theory, performancetheory also assumes that citizens learn about democracythrough experience (Mattes and Bratton 2007; Mishlerand Rose 2002). Specifically, citizens’ support for de-mocracy depends both on how well their system func-tions, and whether it is democratic (Magalhães 2014).Where a democracy performs poorly (or an autocracyperforms well), support for democracy is thereforeexpected to be low.

Within this regime performance approach, a crucialdistinction exists between intrinsic and instrumentalperformance evaluations (Bratton and Mattes 2001;Evans and Whitefield 1995). Intrinsic performanceevaluations refer to citizens supporting democracybecause they enjoy some of the essential features ofa democratic system, such as personal and politicalfreedoms and responsive government (Bratton andMattes 2001; Rose, Mishler, and Haerpfer 1998). In-strumental performance evaluations, in contrast, referto citizens supporting democracy because they benefitfrom such desirable outputs of governance as economicgrowth and clean public administration (Dalton 1994;Magalhães 2014).

If support is primarily intrinsic in origin, then legiti-macy can only be achieved by delivering politicalfreedoms and responsive government. For autocracies,this effectively means transitioning to democracy. Fordemocracies, this implies that further democratizationor democratic deepening is required for increasedsupport. Both socialization theory and (intrinsic) re-gime performance theory therefore predict that de-mocracy creates its own demand. Guided by thesesimilarities, Rose, Mishler, and Haerpfer (1998) com-bine socialization and intrinsic performance theoriesinto a single model of “lifelong learning” (see alsoBratton, Mattes, and Gyimah-Boadi 2005; Mattes andBratton 2007).

With its central prediction being that a democraticsystem produces a supportive public, lifelong learning

theory appears unable to account for the crisis of le-gitimacy said to be afflicting many democracies. Analternative account that appears more suitable is thetheory of instrumental performance evaluations. Ifregimesupport canbegenerated through thedeliveryofinstrumental benefits, such as economic growth, thenboth democracies and autocracies can achieve popularsupport. Both, however, can also suffer from pooreconomic performance and therefore falling publicsupport.

Indeed, researchers have argued that democraticsatisfaction (if not quite democratic support) waseroded by the global economic recession of 2008–10(Armingeon and Guthmann 2014). Other studies havedemonstrated a link between support for democracyand economic performance (Dalton 1994; Krieckhauset al. 2014; Magalhães 2014; Rose and Mishler 1996).Yet, in studies that include measures of both in-strumental and intrinsic performance, it is the latter thatis more important (Evans and Whitefield 1995; Rose,Mishler, and Haerpfer 1998; Mattes and Bratton 2007;Mattes, Denemark, and Niemi 2016a). Moreover,Graham and Sukhtankar (2004) find that support fordemocracy in Latin America increased, rather thandecreased, during the economic crisis of the early 2000s.

As such, economic downturns (or some other in-strumental failing) do not appear to be a particularlycompelling explanation for the falling support for de-mocracy that analysts haveobserved. Instead, I proposeadopting a theory from another area of public opinionresearch—the thermostatic model (Erikson, Mackuen,and Stimson 2002; Soroka and Wlezien 2010; Wlezien1995)—as an alternative explanation.

A Thermostatic Model of Democratic Mood

The thermostaticmodel was first developed byWlezien(1995) to describe and explain the relationship betweenmacro-opinion and policy outputs (see also Erikson,Mackuen, and Stimson 2002; Soroka and Wlezien2010). It proposes that opinion shifts to the left as policymoves to the right and vice versa. The result is amarkednegative feedback loop between policy output andopinion.2

Applied to the democracy-opinion link, the ther-mostatic model would predict that public support fordemocracy begins to soften and then turn as the supplyof democracy is increased; on the other hand, it wouldalso predict that support for democracy increases as thesupply of democracy decreases.

There is, of course, a substantial difference betweenthe opinion-policy link and the opinion-democracy link:the former assumes democracy in general and electionsin particular as themechanism bywhich opinion shapespolicy (Erikson,Mackuen, andStimson2002).Electoral

2 Thepolicy-opinion literature, like thedemocratic support literature,invokes Easton’s (1965) classic systems theory of politics to make thelink between outputs and opinion. Indeed, the literature on demo-cratic support has long assumed a thermostatic effect of the con-sequences of public support on democracy, i.e., support helps sustaindemocracy (Claassen 2019a).

Christopher Claassen

38

Dow

nloa

ded

from

htt

ps://

ww

w.c

ambr

idge

.org

/cor

e. IP

add

ress

: 54.

39.1

06.1

73, o

n 14

Jun

2020

at 0

6:32

:36,

sub

ject

to th

e Ca

mbr

idge

Cor

e te

rms

of u

se, a

vaila

ble

at h

ttps

://w

ww

.cam

brid

ge.o

rg/c

ore/

term

s. h

ttps

://do

i.org

/10.

1017

/S00

0305

5419

0005

58

Page 4: In the Mood for Democracy? Democratic Support as ...€¦ · but their preference for democracy would weaken as democratic rights and institutions are supplied. If sup-port for democracy—or

dynamics are moreover also responsible for the ebbingand flowing of opinion that is characteristic of thethermostatic model. Winning coalitions implementpolicies favoring their supporters, not themedian voter,leading to policy outputs that are out of sync with av-erage public opinion. Policy outputs therefore “over-shoot”opinion (SorokaandWlezien2010). In response,opinion moves in the opposite direction, resulting inanother party or coalition being favored in the nextelection. Should theywin, policywouldagain shift—andagain overshoot.

Both of these dynamics—the overshooting ofoutputs and the resulting thermostatic shift inopinion—occur also in the democracy-opinion link.First, the supply of democratic rights and institutionslikely overshoots mass opinion. Autocratic elites whoare under pressure to democratize usually hope tomanage the transition but often lose control (Hun-tington 1991; Wood 2000). The increase in democraticrights has a compulsive quality that drives furtherdemocratization. For example, the liberalization ofrestrictions on civil society affords the oppositiongreater latitude for mobilization, while the installationof freer and fairer elections allows the opposition tochallenge directly for power (Gandhi and Lust-Okar2009; Levitsky and Way 2002).3

The second component of the thermostatic dy-namic is opinion change after policy change. Themass public are often depicted as favoring de-mocracy, with the elites more hesitant, if not outrightopposed (e.g., Acemoglu and Robinson 2006;Rueschemeyer, Stephens, and Stephens 1992; Wood2000). Yet if democratic support acts in a similarfashion to other forms of macro-opinion, it shouldalso diminish once the policy (here, democracy) issupplied. This presents something of a puzzle: whywould citizens not desire further democratic rightsand stronger democratic institutions? Indeed, whywould they desire diminished rights and weakenedinstitutions?

There are two possible explanations. The first comesfrom the literature on authoritarianism, especially itsearly, psychodynamic interpretation. As Erich Fromm(1941) argued, the transition from autocracy to de-mocracy may leave individuals unmoored and anxious.They therefore desire an “escape from freedom” anda return to the certainties of authoritarian rule (see alsoArendt 1951). In amore empirical vein, some studies ofpolitical support in newly democratic countries havefound a resurgence of “authoritarian nostalgia” afterdemocratic transitions (see, e.g.,Mishler andRose2007;Morlino 2010). According to this view, it is the coremajoritarian elements of democracy—thedevolutionofpower from autocrats to citizens—that prove to beunsettling. Increases in electoral democracy therefore

provoke authoritarian nostalgia and reduced supportfor democracy.

The second possible explanation comes from re-search on counter-majoritarian or “minoritarian”institutions and values. While majoritarian values arewidely endorsed, even in states without much ofa democratic tradition, minoritarian values—such assupport for judicial review of popular executivedecisions—are viewed in a far less favorable light (e.g.,Gibson 1998; Gibson and Caldeira 2003). It is not onlyamong the mass public that such disapproval ofcounter-majoritarianism can be found: a large legalliterature exists on the “counter-majoritarian diffi-culty” posed by judicial review (e.g., Bickel 1986).Moreover, not only may counter-majoritarian insti-tutions override majorities, they also protect minori-ties, some of whom are viewed unfavorably by thepublic at large. Research on political tolerance findsthat large proportions of citizens—even in establisheddemocracies—are unwilling to extend civil and polit-ical rights toward political and ethnicminorities (Duchand Gibson 1992; Gibson 2008). According to thissecond explanation, it is therefore the liberal minor-itarian aspects of democracy—those designed toprotect individual rights and offer checks and balanceson executives—that trouble citizens. When suchcounter-majoritarian institutions are strengthened,citizens may respond with diminished support fordemocracy in general.

Hypotheses

Having outlined the thermostatic theory of changein public support for democracy, I can now state thefirst testable hypothesis, H1: increases in democracyhave a negative effect on democratic mood. Thishypothesis stands in contrast with democratic learn-ing theories, which predict that the level of democ-racy has a positive and, possibly long-run, effect onsupport.

The second and third hypotheses map on to thepossible mechanisms by which the thermostatic effectoperates. H2a posits that increases in electoraldemocracy—i.e., majoritarian rights and electoralprocesses—have a negative effect on democratic mood.H2b instead proposes that increases in minoritariandemocracy—i.e., counter-majoritarian protections ofindividual and minority rights—have a negative effecton democratic mood.

DATA AND METHODS

Measuring Democratic Mood

The dependent variable used in this article is nationallevels of democratic mood. Mood is the extent towhich a public offers explicit support for a democraticsystem and rejects any autocratic alternatives (Linzand Stepan 1996; Mattes and Bratton 2007; Rose,Mishler, andHaerpfer 1998). It is principled or diffusesupport for democracy itself, rather than instrumental

3 Democracy may well also overshoot opinion in the other direction,when regimes experience a coup d’etat or some other descent intoautocracy. Here, rational fear of the new autocrat produces thephenomenonof the “dictator’s dilemma” (Wintrobe 1998), where fewhave an incentive to speak truth to power, leading the autocrat tobecome ever more suspicious and oppressive.

In the Mood for Democracy?

39

Dow

nloa

ded

from

htt

ps://

ww

w.c

ambr

idge

.org

/cor

e. IP

add

ress

: 54.

39.1

06.1

73, o

n 14

Jun

2020

at 0

6:32

:36,

sub

ject

to th

e Ca

mbr

idge

Cor

e te

rms

of u

se, a

vaila

ble

at h

ttps

://w

ww

.cam

brid

ge.o

rg/c

ore/

term

s. h

ttps

://do

i.org

/10.

1017

/S00

0305

5419

0005

58

Page 5: In the Mood for Democracy? Democratic Support as ...€¦ · but their preference for democracy would weaken as democratic rights and institutions are supplied. If sup-port for democracy—or

support for the outputs of government or the in-cumbent officeholders. Consequently, mood is mea-sured using existing survey questions, which askrespondents to evaluate the appropriateness or de-sirability of democracy, compare democracy to someundemocratic alternative, or evaluate one of theseundemocratic forms of government.4 Such items arewidely used to measure democratic support (e.g.,Dalton 2004; Klingemann 1999; Magalhães 2014;Mattes and Bratton 2007; Norris 2011). Questionsfocusing on related concepts such as satisfaction withthe performance of democracy and trust in nationalpolitical institutions were not included because nei-ther is a valid measure of principled support for de-mocracy (e.g., Bratton, Mattes, and Gyimah-Boadi2005; Canache, Mondak, and Seligson 2001; Lindeand Ekman 2003).

To the best of my knowledge, the database of 3,768nationally aggregated opinions, gathered by 14 sur-vey projects using 1,391 nationally representativesurveys, includes all existing measures of support fordemocracy that have been collected by cross-national survey projects. These data are, however,fractured, with numerous gaps in the national timeseries. They are further fragmented by the multitudeof different survey measures of democratic supportthat are fielded in the different survey projects.5

Moreover, even when they adopt broadly similarsurvey questions, these projects tend to adjust thewording of the questions somewhat. As a result, asmany as 52 different survey questions are present inthe dataset.

To obtain a “smooth panel” of mood from such un-ruly data, I use the Bayesian dynamic latent variablemodel developed by Claassen (2019b).6 The modeltreats theobservednumber of respondents y supportingdemocracy for each country i, year t, and survey item kas a binomially distributed count,

yikt;Binomial sikt;piktð Þ:A beta prior is then used to model the probability

parameter p,

pikt;Beta aikt;biktð Þ:This produces a beta-binomial distribution, which

allows for some additional dispersion in the observedsurvey responses beyond that induced by samplingalone. The two shape parameters of the beta

distribution can then be reparameterized to an expec-tation parameter h and a dispersion parameter f,

aikt ¼ fhikt;

bikt ¼ f 1� hiktð Þ:The expectation parameter h is then modeled as

a function of the latent country-year estimates u, itemparameters l, and item-country parameters d,

hikt ¼ logit�1 lk þ dik þ uitð Þ;

lk;N ml;s2l

� �;

dik;N 0;s2d

� �:

The definition of “item” here is a conservative one:two items fielded by different projects are classed asdistinct even if their wording appeared to be identical.This allows the model’s item bias parameters to cap-ture variation induced both by question wording andby idiosyncrasies in the methodology of the varioussurvey projects. The item parameters l therefore ad-just for the idiosyncratic effects of question wordingand also the methodological effects of particular sur-vey projects.

The item-country parameters d then allow the itemparameters to vary by country. This adjusts for cross-national “non-equivalence,” whereby the meaning ofseemingly identical itemsvariesacrossnational contexts(Ariely and Davidov 2011; Stegmueller 2011). For ex-ample, the word “democracy” is likely to have differentinterpretations and associations in different countries(Bratton 2010).

Finally, the latent opinion estimates are allowed toevolve smoothlyover timebymodeling the current levelof latent opinion uit in country i as a function of theprevious year’s level plus some random noise,

uit;N ui;t�1;s2u

� �:

The model is estimated using Bayesian Markovchain Monte Carlo (MCMC) simulation.7 The resultis a smooth country-by-year panel of estimates ofdemocraticmood.Althoughdata are available for 151countries and 30 years, the coverage of this panel islimited as follows. First, support is estimated only forthe 137 countries in which at least two separate yearsof survey data were available. Second, estimates weredropped for years prior to the year in which the firstpublic opinion survey measuring support for de-mocracy was fielded in each country. Each nationaltime-series therefore commences the year in whichthe first cross-national survey measuring support fordemocracy is fielded in the respective country.

The use of a time-varying, national-level measure ofdemocratic mood provides several advantages overexisting work on the determinants of democratic sup-port. First, thepresenceof temporal variation in support

4 A list of included survey items is provided in the online supple-mentary materials.5 For example, one widely used question asks respondents whetherdemocracy is preferable to any other kind of government, whether anauthoritarian government can instead sometimes be preferable, orwhether it makes little difference. Another question invitesrespondents to evaluate a system run by a strong leader who does nothave to bother with parliament and elections. A third requests thatrespondents rate the importance they ascribe to having a democraticsystem.6 I use Claassen’s “Model 5,”which performed best in validation testson a held-out portion of the data. Although Claassen (2019b) alsoapplies thismodel to the topicofdemocratic support, this articleuse anexpanded dataset of survey responses (see also Claassen 2019a).

7 Full details on priors, software, tests of convergence, and modelchecks are provided in the online supplementary materials.

Christopher Claassen

40

Dow

nloa

ded

from

htt

ps://

ww

w.c

ambr

idge

.org

/cor

e. IP

add

ress

: 54.

39.1

06.1

73, o

n 14

Jun

2020

at 0

6:32

:36,

sub

ject

to th

e Ca

mbr

idge

Cor

e te

rms

of u

se, a

vaila

ble

at h

ttps

://w

ww

.cam

brid

ge.o

rg/c

ore/

term

s. h

ttps

://do

i.org

/10.

1017

/S00

0305

5419

0005

58

Page 6: In the Mood for Democracy? Democratic Support as ...€¦ · but their preference for democracy would weaken as democratic rights and institutions are supplied. If sup-port for democracy—or

and democracy (see below for discussion of the latter)allows this article to separately estimate the effects ofprevious levels of democracy—which captures a long-run, socialization process—from the immediatechange in democracy—which is used to test the ther-mostatic hypothesis. Temporal variation in the datafurthermore means that fully dynamic models, whichinclude lagged dependent variables, can be used.These allow me to rule out the confounding effects ofprevious levels of mood on current levels of de-mocracy.8 Finally, the combination of temporal andcross-sectional variation permits the use of first dif-ference models, which examine only within-countrychanges in mood and democracy, thereby controllingfor all unobserved, country-specific, time-invariantconfounds. In sum, this time series, cross-sectionalresearch design permits rigorous tests of the threehypotheses.

Other Variables

Measures of democracy are drawn from version 8 ofthe Varieties of Democracy (V-Dem) project.9 Theseare preferable to alternatives because of the care andrigor that V-Dem employs in conceptualizing andmeasuring democracy.10 In particular, I employ threeof V-Dem’s democracy indices. First, to measure thelevel of electoral democracy in each state and year, Iuse V-Dem’s “electoral democracy index.” Thisclosely follows Dahl’s (1971) concept of “polyarchy”and correspondingly measures the extent to whicha country’s leaders are appointed through cleanelections, where all adult citizens enjoy the freedom tovote, associate with other citizens, and express theirpolitical views (Teorell et al. 2018). The electoraldemocracy index includes five subcomponents, eachmeasured with multiple indicators: (1) the extent towhich the chief executive and legislature areappointed through popular elections; (2) the integrityof those elections; (3) the share of adult citizens withthe right to vote in those elections; (4) freedom ofassociation; and (5) freedom of expression (V-DemInstitute 2018a). This index is used to test hypothesis2a.

Second, tomeasureminoritarian democracy, I use V-Dem’s “liberal component index.” This “emphasizesthe importance of protecting individual and minorityrights against the tyranny of the state and the tyranny ofthe majority” (V-Dem Institute 2018a, 43) and

therefore measures the strength of liberal, counter-majoritarian institutions in a given country and year.There are three subcomponents: (1) judicial and (2)legislative constraints on the executive, aswell as (3) thelegal equality of citizens and respect for individualrights. This measure of minoritarian democracy is usedto test hypothesis 2b.

Finally, theoverallmeasureof liberal democracyusedin this article is V-Dem’s “liberal democracy” index,which is simply a combination of the “electoral” and“liberal component” indices.Thiswill beused to test thegeneral thermostatic hypothesis, H1.

Two time-varying control variables are included.First is logged GDP per capita: in levels, this isa measure of socioeconomic development (seeKrieckhaus et al. 2014; Magalhães 2014); in differ-ences, it is a measure of instrumental perform-ance—specifically, economic growth (see Dalton1994).11 Second, the “corruption perceptions index”from Transparency International is used to measurecorruption—a form of regime (under)performancethat has been associated with diminished regimesupport (Anderson and Tverdova 2003; Mishler andRose 2007; Rose, Mishler, and Haerpfer 1998). Po-tential time-invariant confounds, such as demographyor electoral institutions, are handled through the useof first-difference models.

GLOBAL DYNAMICS OF DEMOCRACYAND MOOD

Before formally testing the hypotheses, I begin witha descriptive examination of trends in democracy andmood. In particular, I present and discuss time seriesplots for the 135 countries for which mood and de-mocracy estimates exist. The goal of this exercise toprovide a first indication of whether support for de-mocracy is falling, as some analysts have claimed, orwhether it is largely stable and rising as socialization andlearning theories would suggest.

The time series plots are displayed in Figures 1through 4. Countries are arranged into four groups.First are the established democracies, which had ex-perienced at least 20 years of democracy12 when theirmood time series commences. They are displayed inFigure 1.Next, in Figure 2, are newdemocracies, whichare democratic throughout the years under consider-ation, but where democracy commenced less than 20years prior to the start of the mood series. Third arestable autocracies, inFigure 3,whichwere autocratic inall the years for which data were available. Finally areregimes in transition, in Figure 4, which moved be-tween democracy and autocracy at some point in theyears under consideration.

8 Indeed, such a “supportive effect” of mood on the survival of de-mocracy is an article of faith among many scholars (e.g., Claassen2019a;Dalton andWelzel 2014;Lipset 1959;Mattes andBratton 2007;Norris 2011; Rose, Mishler, and Haerpfer 1998).9 https://www.v-dem.net. Two further cases—Belize and Malta—areexcluded the analysis because V-Dem does not provide data forsmaller countries.10 A discussion of the advantages offered by the V-Dem indices overalternativesprovidedbyPolity,FreedomHouse, etc. is provided in theonline supplementarymaterials. See alsoV-DemInstitute (2018b) fordetails on the rationale andmethodsof theV-Demproject andTeorellet al. (2018) for a discussion of the validity of V-Dem’s electoraldemocracy index.

11 Data were drawn from the World Bank World DevelopmentIndicators, with missing values replaced with data from the IMF andPenn World Tables and adjusted using a linear regression model.12 For this task, I use the V-Dem “Regimes in the World” indicator(Luhrmann, Tannenberg, and Lindberg 2018).

In the Mood for Democracy?

41

Dow

nloa

ded

from

htt

ps://

ww

w.c

ambr

idge

.org

/cor

e. IP

add

ress

: 54.

39.1

06.1

73, o

n 14

Jun

2020

at 0

6:32

:36,

sub

ject

to th

e Ca

mbr

idge

Cor

e te

rms

of u

se, a

vaila

ble

at h

ttps

://w

ww

.cam

brid

ge.o

rg/c

ore/

term

s. h

ttps

://do

i.org

/10.

1017

/S00

0305

5419

0005

58

Page 7: In the Mood for Democracy? Democratic Support as ...€¦ · but their preference for democracy would weaken as democratic rights and institutions are supplied. If sup-port for democracy—or

I begin with the established democracies. Sociali-zation and learning theories suggest that such regimesshould exhibit high and stable support. Having longexperience with democracy, even older generationswould hold positive evaluations of democracy. Thereis therefore little generational change. In suchregimes, the supply of democratic rights and institu-tions is also fairly stable over time, leading to littleincrease in support over the course of citizens’lifetimes.

Indeed, many of the cases shown in Figure 1 areconsistent with these expectations. Scandinaviancountries show the high and stable levels of supportthat the extant literature would predict (also Swit-zerland and Germany). Yet other long-establisheddemocracies exhibit different patterns. In Anglo-phone democracies, support is stable but generallyquite modest. The long-standing non-Western de-mocracies of India and Japan show fairly low levels of

support. Finally, although the mood in Western de-mocracies, such as Canada, the Netherlands, Ger-many, and the United States, began to turn againstdemocracy in the early 2000s—as Foa and Mounk(2016, 2017) have argued—it has rebounded some-what in recent years.

In newer democracies, lifelong learning theorywouldpredict a more mutable pattern of support, featuringa rising trend from varying initial levels. The impact offormative years socialization would be expected to leadto a substantial generational gap, where younger gen-erations are more supportive of democracy. With thepassage of time, and ensuing generational replacement,we should therefore observe increasing levels ofsupport.

As Figure 2 shows, democratic mood in this largegroup of cases is indeed more varied than that seen inthe long-established democracies. The earlierestablished of these new democracies (e.g., Greece

FIGURE 1. The Dynamics of Democracy and Mood: Established Democracies

Each plot shows V-Dem Liberal democracy (plotted using a black line) from 1988 to 2017 and estimates of democratic mood (plotted usinga blue line). The shaded regions around themood estimates indicate 90%uncertainty intervals. Vertical bars on themoodestimates indicateyears in which survey data were available. Liberal democracy and mood are unit-normal standardized.

Christopher Claassen

42

Dow

nloa

ded

from

htt

ps://

ww

w.c

ambr

idge

.org

/cor

e. IP

add

ress

: 54.

39.1

06.1

73, o

n 14

Jun

2020

at 0

6:32

:36,

sub

ject

to th

e Ca

mbr

idge

Cor

e te

rms

of u

se, a

vaila

ble

at h

ttps

://w

ww

.cam

brid

ge.o

rg/c

ore/

term

s. h

ttps

://do

i.org

/10.

1017

/S00

0305

5419

0005

58

Page 8: In the Mood for Democracy? Democratic Support as ...€¦ · but their preference for democracy would weaken as democratic rights and institutions are supplied. If sup-port for democracy—or

and Spain) show the high and stable levels of supportthat were observed earlier in many established de-mocracies. Elsewhere, change is the norm, with manycases exhibiting fairly marked increases and

decreases in democratic mood. In certain Africancountries (e.g., Botswana, Ghana, and Senegal),democratic support reaches the level of establisheddemocracies. In other countries (e.g., Brazil, Panama,

FIGURE 2. The Dynamics of Democracy and Mood: New Democracies

In the Mood for Democracy?

43

Dow

nloa

ded

from

htt

ps://

ww

w.c

ambr

idge

.org

/cor

e. IP

add

ress

: 54.

39.1

06.1

73, o

n 14

Jun

2020

at 0

6:32

:36,

sub

ject

to th

e Ca

mbr

idge

Cor

e te

rms

of u

se, a

vaila

ble

at h

ttps

://w

ww

.cam

brid

ge.o

rg/c

ore/

term

s. h

ttps

://do

i.org

/10.

1017

/S00

0305

5419

0005

58

Page 9: In the Mood for Democracy? Democratic Support as ...€¦ · but their preference for democracy would weaken as democratic rights and institutions are supplied. If sup-port for democracy—or

Poland), support ebbs and flows at a fairly low level.There are also cases with fairly stable but low support(e.g., Bulgaria, Mexico, South Africa), and others(e.g., the Czech Republic, Slovakia) where supporthas fallen markedly. The evidence from these newdemocracies therefore providesmixed support for thesocialization and intrinsic performance theories. Onthe one hand, support is rising in some newer de-mocracies and already fairly high in the more long-standing of these. On the other hand, support isstubbornly low in other new democracies and evenfalling in yet others.

Socialization theory predicts that the third group ofcountries, stable autocracies (Figure 3), should ex-hibit low support for democracy as their citizens havenot been exposed to a democratic political culture.

Indeed, this appears to be the case for several of theautocracies for which we have data (e.g., China,Algeria, Vietnam, and Saudi Arabia). However, oth-ers (e.g., Azerbaijan, Uganda, and Zimbabwe) displaya different pattern: despite being autocratic, they havehigh and perhaps even increasing support for de-mocracy. In conclusion, although the evidence fromsomeof the autocratic cases are consistentwithexistingaccounts of support for democracy, evidence fromothers is inconsistent, with citizens showing support fordemocracy despite having little to no experience withit.

Finally, I consider regimes thatexperienceda transitionbetween autocracy and democracy during the period ofthe study (Figure 4). These provides greater insights intothe immediate effects on mood when the supply of

FIGURE 3. The Dynamics of Democracy and Mood: Autocracies

Christopher Claassen

44

Dow

nloa

ded

from

htt

ps://

ww

w.c

ambr

idge

.org

/cor

e. IP

add

ress

: 54.

39.1

06.1

73, o

n 14

Jun

2020

at 0

6:32

:36,

sub

ject

to th

e Ca

mbr

idge

Cor

e te

rms

of u

se, a

vaila

ble

at h

ttps

://w

ww

.cam

brid

ge.o

rg/c

ore/

term

s. h

ttps

://do

i.org

/10.

1017

/S00

0305

5419

0005

58

Page 10: In the Mood for Democracy? Democratic Support as ...€¦ · but their preference for democracy would weaken as democratic rights and institutions are supplied. If sup-port for democracy—or

democracy changes, which, of course, is where we wouldexpect to see a thermostatic effect, if oneexists. In someofthese regimes in transition, patterns consistent with

learning theories can be observed. Support increases afterUkraine’s experiments with democracy, for example, andperhapsafterMalawi’s too.Yet inmanyothercases,avery

FIGURE 4. The Dynamics of Democracy and Mood: Transitioning Regimes

In the Mood for Democracy?

45

Dow

nloa

ded

from

htt

ps://

ww

w.c

ambr

idge

.org

/cor

e. IP

add

ress

: 54.

39.1

06.1

73, o

n 14

Jun

2020

at 0

6:32

:36,

sub

ject

to th

e Ca

mbr

idge

Cor

e te

rms

of u

se, a

vaila

ble

at h

ttps

://w

ww

.cam

brid

ge.o

rg/c

ore/

term

s. h

ttps

://do

i.org

/10.

1017

/S00

0305

5419

0005

58

Page 11: In the Mood for Democracy? Democratic Support as ...€¦ · but their preference for democracy would weaken as democratic rights and institutions are supplied. If sup-port for democracy—or

different pattern is evident: increases in democracy thatare accompanied by decreases in support (e.g., Croatia,Kenya, and Peru) and decreases that are accompaniedby increases in support (e.g., Venezuela, Belarus, andThailand). Such negative feedback between opinionand output is the hallmark of a thermostatic process.Indeed, in Venezuela, the dynamics of democracy andsupport display a classically thermostatic relationship.Soon afterChavezwas elected in 1998, themood turnedtoward democracy. In the ensuing years, as he begandismantling democratic institutions and procedures,support increased further. It is hard to avoid inter-preting these dynamics as anything other than theVenezuelan public demanding stronger democraticrights and institutions, and doing so in response to theattack on these rights and institutions that they wereobserving.

In sum, this descriptive analysis of mood and de-mocracy reveals patterns, in certain countries, whichare consistent with existing socialization and intrinsicperformance theories of democratic support. In othercountries, however, the relationships between moodand democracy are clearly inconsistent with thesetheories. These include democracies (new andestablished) with falling support for democracy andautocracies with high (or rising) support. Particularlytelling are the regimes in transition. In many of thesecases, there appears to be a thermostatic effect wherechanges in supply produce an immediate and oppositereaction in citizens’ opinions.

With some descriptive evidence in favor of existingtheories of support, and other evidence against, I nowturn to our dynamicmodels, which offermore definitivetests of the hypotheses.

TESTING THE THERMOSTATIC MODEL OFDEMOCRATIC MOOD

Empirical Strategy

The primary modeling specification employed in thisarticle is the general error correction model (ECM).This model allows one to examine both the effects ofthe lagged level of an independent variable, as well asthe effects of its immediate change, on changes in thedependent variable. This provides an ideal modelingframework for the three hypotheses. Including im-mediate changes in democracy permits a test of thethermostatic theory that increases (decreases) in de-mocracy prompt a temporary decrease (increase) inmood.And the inclusionof a lagged level of democracypermits a test of the alternative theory of “lifelonglearning” through socialization and intrinsic perfor-mance evaluations.

Error correction models require, however, that alltime series be either stationary or co-integrated (DeBoef and Keele 2008). I therefore run two tests ofstationarity for panel data (the Im–Pesaran–Shin andLevin–Lin–Chu tests) on all included variables. Theresults of all tests indicate stationarity (see the sup-plementary materials), permitting the use of error

correction models. Next, I include two lags of demo-cratic mood to model the enduring effects of de-mocracy on mood. In particular, public support haslong been thought to affect subsequent levels of de-mocracy (e.g., Claassen 2019a; Linz and Stepan 1996;Qi and Shin 2011), including lagged dependent vari-able controls for this possibility.13 These lagged de-pendent variables also remove most of the serialcorrelation in the mood series.14 Arellano–White ro-bust standard errors, which allow for serial correlationand heteroskedasticity, are additionally used in allmodels.

More formally, for i countries and tyears, Imodel thechange in mood (Dmit 5 mit 2 mit21) as a function oftwo lags of mood, immediate change in democracy(Ddit), the lagged level of democracy (dit21), and kadditional covariates, both their changes and laggedlevels,15

Dmit ¼ aþ f1mit�1 þ f2mit�2 þ b1Ddit þ b2dit�1

þ�K

k¼1g1kDxkit þ�

K

k¼1g2kxkit�1 þ «it:

The immediate effect of changes in democracy onchanges in mood is given by b1 while the effect ofprevious levels of democracy is given by b2. If there isa thermostatic effect of democracy onmood, it will bereflected in a negative estimate of b1; if there isa lifelong learning effect, it will be indicated witha positive estimate of b2. However, these effects areshort-run estimates. Since the model includes laggeddependent variables, and is therefore dynamic, bothchanges and levels of support might have very dif-ferent impacts in the long run (De Boef and Keele2008). In particular, the effects of changes in moodwill dissipate over time while the effects of laggedlevels of mood will accumulate. These long-runeffects can be calculated using formula such as (b22 b1)/(12f11f2), but also, as I demonstrate below,using simulation methods.

Results of the General Thermostatic Test

Table 1 presents the results of four models testinghypothesis 1, that is, changes in liberal democracyhave a negative effect on public support. The first twomodels (1.1 and 1.2) show that the immediate effect ofa change in democracy is negative and significant.

13 Tests of model fit indicate that two lags are required.With one lag,AIC 5 210,048; with two lags, AIC 5 210,701.14 Breusch–Godfrey test of (first-order) serial correlation for panelmodels, with two lags of mood included: x2 5 0.37, p 5 0.54.15 Note that this model can also be expressed using the autore-gressive distributed lag (ADL) specification, which uses levels, notdifferences, in dependent and independent variables (Beck andKatz 2011; De Boef and Keele 2008). The ADL specification is as

follows: mit¼aþf�1mit�1þf2mit�2þb1ditþb�

2dit�1þ�K

k¼1g1kxkitþ�K

k¼1g�2kxkit�1þ«it , where f�

1¼f1þ1, b�2¼b2�b1, and g�

2¼g2�g1.Although the ECM and ADL specifications are interchangeable,the ECM maps more readily on the theories being tested here.

Christopher Claassen

46

Dow

nloa

ded

from

htt

ps://

ww

w.c

ambr

idge

.org

/cor

e. IP

add

ress

: 54.

39.1

06.1

73, o

n 14

Jun

2020

at 0

6:32

:36,

sub

ject

to th

e Ca

mbr

idge

Cor

e te

rms

of u

se, a

vaila

ble

at h

ttps

://w

ww

.cam

brid

ge.o

rg/c

ore/

term

s. h

ttps

://do

i.org

/10.

1017

/S00

0305

5419

0005

58

Page 12: In the Mood for Democracy? Democratic Support as ...€¦ · but their preference for democracy would weaken as democratic rights and institutions are supplied. If sup-port for democracy—or

Increases in democracy, in other words, are associ-ated with decreases in support and vice versa. Thesetwo error correction models therefore provide evi-dence that democratic mood behaves thermostati-cally in response to changes in the supply ofdemocracy.

In Model 1.1, the lagged level of democracy also hasa significant and positive effect on subsequent change indemocratic mood. Such positive feedback is consistentwith the processes of socialization and intrinsic per-formance incorporated in lifelong learning theory. Yetthis effect is not particularly robust. InModel 1.2, whichalso includes corruption, the positive effect of laggeddemocracy vanishes.16 There is therefore little evi-dence, in this national-level data, that democracy cre-ates its own demand.

How robust is the finding that changes in democracyproduce a significant and opposite effect on mood? InTable 1, I employ a simpler and more conservativespecification:first differencemodels.These includeonlythe differences in all variables. Like the closely relatedfixed-effects specification, such first difference modelstherefore restrict their attention to variance across timeand within country. This removes the possible con-founding effects of country-specific time-invariantfactors thatmaybe thought to influencebothdependent

and independent variables.17 Democracy and politicalculture, for example, might be jointly determined bysuch country-specific key moments, or “critical junc-tures,” as a nation’s experience under colonial rule(Rueschemeyer, Stephens, and Stephens 1992).18

Results from the first difference models are consistentwith the error correctionfindings. The thermostatic effect ofchange in democracy on subsequent change in moodremains negative and significant. In the online supplemen-tary materials, I report additional robustness tests: one- andtwo-way fixed effects models, Mundlak within-betweenmultilevel models, as well as first-difference and error cor-rection models including additional time-varying controls(education and income inequality). Evidence for a negative,thermostatic effect of change in democracy is present in allthese models, save one.19 However, no evidence for a posi-tive, lifelong learning effect of lagged democracy emerges.

Next, to demonstrate how the various effects of de-mocracy on mood play out over the long run, I plot thesimulated effects of a one standard deviation increase in

TABLE 1. Testing the Effects of Democracy on Change in Mood

Error-correctionModels

First-differenceModels

(1.1) (1.2) (1.3) (1.4)

Intercept 20.033 0.018 20.009* 20.011*(0.019) (0.028) (0.004) (0.004)

Democratic moodt21 0.473* 0.433*(0.026) (0.028)

Democratic moodt22 20.487* 20.451*(0.025) (0.027)

D Liberal democracy 20.058* 20.067* 20.076* 20.082*(0.023) (0.031) (0.028) (0.034)

Liberal democracyt21 0.007* 0.002(0.003) (0.004)

D log GDP per capita 0.063 0.037 0.108* 0.089(0.040) (0.044) (0.052) (0.051)

Log GDP per capitat21 0.003 20.003(0.002) (0.003)

D Corruption 20.008 20.022(0.016) (0.017)

Corruptiont21 20.012*(0.004)

Residual standard error 0.098 0.102 0.112 0.115Adjusted R2 0.254 0.217 0.006 0.006N countries 135 135 135 135N observations 2,300 1,949 2,435 2,040

*p , 0.05. Arellano–White robust standard errors, clustered by country, in parentheses. Liberal democracy and mood are unit-normalstandardized.

16 As Model 1.2 shows, lagged levels of corruption also appear todampen democratic mood (but economic growth has no effect).

17 I do not include lagged dependent variables in the first differencemodels. These would create a correlation between the first-differenced effects and the first-differenced error term that inducesbias, especially a problem the number of time periods is small.18 The first difference version of the model is

Dmit ¼ aþ b1Ddit þ�K

k¼1gkDxkit þ «it .19 When including years of education, change in liberal democracy nolonger has a significant effect in the error correction specification. Itremains significant in the first difference specification.

In the Mood for Democracy?

47

Dow

nloa

ded

from

htt

ps://

ww

w.c

ambr

idge

.org

/cor

e. IP

add

ress

: 54.

39.1

06.1

73, o

n 14

Jun

2020

at 0

6:32

:36,

sub

ject

to th

e Ca

mbr

idge

Cor

e te

rms

of u

se, a

vaila

ble

at h

ttps

://w

ww

.cam

brid

ge.o

rg/c

ore/

term

s. h

ttps

://do

i.org

/10.

1017

/S00

0305

5419

0005

58

Page 13: In the Mood for Democracy? Democratic Support as ...€¦ · but their preference for democracy would weaken as democratic rights and institutions are supplied. If sup-port for democracy—or

democracy inFigure 5.Suchaplot is not straightforwardwhen using dynamic models, because the predictedeffects at time tbecome lagged independent variables attime t1 1. I use amethod of simulation based on that ofWilliams and Whitten (2012) (see the online supple-mentary materials for a full explication).

The two plots in Figure 5 show the simulated effectson democratic mood (in levels, not differences) whenthe level of democracy increases by one standarddeviation—a moderate increase in democracy. The leftplot shows the simulated results fromModel 1.1, whichexcludes corruption; the right plot shows the resultswithcorruption included (Model 1.2).

According to both models, mood drops immediatelyas democracy increases, falling by 0.058 (left) and 0.067(right) in that first year (which of course are the coef-ficients of change in democracy in Table 1). Democraticmood continues to weaken over the following years. Itfalls for another two years in the left plot, dropping bya total of 0.084 from its initial level, and falls for anotherfour years in the right plot, for a total decrease of 0.104.

In both plots, democratic mood then starts turningpositiveagain.This is aproductnotonlyof thediminishingnegative effects of that initial increase in democracy, butalso the positive effect of lifelong learning. Although thelatter is small in magnitude, it accumulates relentlesslyover time. In the left plot, the larger effect of lagged de-mocracy produces a more rapid cheering of democraticmood. Indeed, ten years after the increase in democracy,moodhas regained its initial level.Mood thencontinues toincrease, at a diminishing pace, over the next 20 years. Inthe left plot, thepositive long-runeffects of democracyaremuch weaker once corruption is accounted for (indeed,

the effect in Model 1.2 is not significant). Yet mood stillrecovers, although it now takes 27 years to do so.

In sum, the results presented in this section haveshown that changes in democracy generate sharp andopposite reactions from the public: increases depresssupport, and decreases revitalize it. This is the well-known thermostatic effect of public opinion, heredemonstrated on democratic mood for the first time.There is, additionally, little evidence that democracygenerates its own demand. Whether by socialization orintrinsic performance evaluations, the effect of the levelof a country’s democracy on subsequent changes innational democratic mood is small and fragile.

The long-run simulations then reveal two furtherpoints. First, the negative thermostatic effects of increasesin democracy, although particularly marked in the initialyears,donot last forever(evenif theydolastageneration).Second, while the positive effects of democratic sociali-zation and learning are tiny (and typically insignificant) inthe short run, they accumulate over the years and do helpto return democratic mood to its former level. Yet wereturn to the paradox discussed earlier. Although it mayseemanatural reaction for citizens to increasingly supportdemocracy where it is under assault by authoritarianleaders, why would the reverse be true? Why, in otherwords, would the public favor reduced democratic rights?I turn to an analysis of these questions—and thereforetests of hypotheses 2a and 2b—in the next subsection.

Why Do Citizens Desire Less Democracy?

Table 2 includes four models that offer tests of hy-potheses 2a and 2b. These models parallel those in

FIGURE 5. Simulated Effects of Change in Democracy on Mood

Simulated effects are estimated using coefficients from Models 1.1 (without corruption; left) and 1.2 (with corruption; right). The solid linesindicate the mean simulated effect; the shaded regions indicate the 95% confidence intervals of these effects.

Christopher Claassen

48

Dow

nloa

ded

from

htt

ps://

ww

w.c

ambr

idge

.org

/cor

e. IP

add

ress

: 54.

39.1

06.1

73, o

n 14

Jun

2020

at 0

6:32

:36,

sub

ject

to th

e Ca

mbr

idge

Cor

e te

rms

of u

se, a

vaila

ble

at h

ttps

://w

ww

.cam

brid

ge.o

rg/c

ore/

term

s. h

ttps

://do

i.org

/10.

1017

/S00

0305

5419

0005

58

Page 14: In the Mood for Democracy? Democratic Support as ...€¦ · but their preference for democracy would weaken as democratic rights and institutions are supplied. If sup-port for democracy—or

Table 1 in all ways but one. Instead of the generalmeasure of liberal democracy, I now include its twodisaggregated components: electoral democracy, whichmeasures the strength of majoritarian institutions andprocesses, and minoritarian democracy, which meas-ures the strength of liberal, counter-majoritarian insti-tutions and processes.

All four models show that changes in electoral de-mocracy have positive but insignificant effects ondemocratic support. Increases in majoritarian rightsand institutions therefore neither depress nor cheermood to any significant degree. The results are starklydifferent for changes in minoritarian democracy, whichproduce a marked negative effect on changes in mood.These thermostatic effects are significant in all of thefour models presented here.20 Increased counter-majoritarian protections of individual rights thereforedampen democratic mood, while diminished pro-tections of these rights revitalizes it, producing in-creased public demand for democracy.

The coefficients reported in Table 2 represent theshort-run effects of change in, and levels of, minoritarian

and electoral democracy. As in the previous section, Itherefore include simulation plots showing how thelong-run effects of these dynamics unfold over decades(Figure 6).

The plots in the first row show the effects of a stan-dard deviation increase in electoral democracy,holding minoritarian democracy constant. When cor-ruption is omitted from the model (plots on the left;Model 2.1), electoral democracy exerts little effect ondemocratic mood, even over the long run. Whencorruption is included, however (plots on the right;Model 2.2), the two—separately insignificant—effectsof increased electoral democracy combine togetherand accumulate over time, resulting in a marked in-crease in democratic mood (a total increase of 0.110after ten years).

The plots in the second row then show the effects ofa standard deviation increase in minoritarian de-mocracy, holding electoral democracy constant. Re-gardless of whether or not corruption is included, animmediate decrease in mood is evident (corre-sponding to the coefficients of change in minoritariandemocracy in Models 2.1 and 2.2). The trajectory ofmood then depends on whether corruption is in-cluded. When it is—in Model 2.2, arguably the morerobust specification—mood never recovers. The

TABLE 2. Testing the Effects of Electoral and Minoritarian Democracy on Change in Mood

Error-correctionModels

First-differenceModels

(2.1) (2.2) (2.3) (2.4)

Intercept 20.042* 0.020 20.008* 20.011*(0.019) (0.026) (0.004) (0.003)

Democratic moodt21 0.473* 0.432*(0.025) (0.028)

Democratic moodt22 20.487* 20.450*(0.025) (0.027)

D Electoral democracy 0.014 0.028 0.011 0.021(0.031) (0.039) (0.033) (0.040)

Electoral democracyt21 0.002 0.006(0.006) (0.006)

D Minoritarian democracy 20.053* 20.066* 20.076* 20.087*(0.022) (0.029) (0.025) (0.029)

Minoritarian democracyt21 0.003 20.004(0.006) (0.006)

D log GDP per capita 0.062 0.034 0.102 0.082(0.040) (0.045) (0.053) (0.051)

Log GDP per capitat21 0.004 20.003(0.002) (0.003)

D Corruption 20.007 20.021(0.016) (0.017)

Corruptiont21 20.013*(0.004)

Residual standard error 0.098 0.102 0.112 0.115Adjusted R2 0.252 0.216 0.006 0.006N countries 135 135 135 135N observations 2,300 1,949 2,435 2,040

*p, 0.05. Arellano–White robust standard errors, clustered by country, in parentheses. Mood and democracy and support (electoral andminoritarian) are unit-normal standardized.

20 The same pattern of results is obtained when including the addi-tional covariates of education and income inequality, and using fixedeffects models. See the online supplementary materials.

In the Mood for Democracy?

49

Dow

nloa

ded

from

htt

ps://

ww

w.c

ambr

idge

.org

/cor

e. IP

add

ress

: 54.

39.1

06.1

73, o

n 14

Jun

2020

at 0

6:32

:36,

sub

ject

to th

e Ca

mbr

idge

Cor

e te

rms

of u

se, a

vaila

ble

at h

ttps

://w

ww

.cam

brid

ge.o

rg/c

ore/

term

s. h

ttps

://do

i.org

/10.

1017

/S00

0305

5419

0005

58

Page 15: In the Mood for Democracy? Democratic Support as ...€¦ · but their preference for democracy would weaken as democratic rights and institutions are supplied. If sup-port for democracy—or

deleterious impact of an increase in minoritariandemocracy is permanent.

In sum, this analysis has demonstrated that thethermostatic effect of changes in democracy can betraced back to the counter-majoritarian, liberal, orminoritarian components of democracy. It is not im-provements in majoritarian institutions and processesthat damage democratic mood, but, instead, increasedlegislative and judicial oversight and enhanced pro-tectionsofminority and individual rightswhichprovokethe backlash.

CONCLUSION

Using new national-level measures of democracy anddemocratic mood for 135 countries and up to 30 years,this article revisits the question of why the public sup-ports or opposes a democratic system. Leading theoriesargue that the presence of democracy plus the passageof time produces higher levels of support as generationafter generation learns about democracy and comes tovalue the freedoms and responsive government itprovides. Yet such positive feedback between democracy

FIGURE 6. Simulated Effects of Changes in Electoral and Minoritarian Democracy on Mood

Predicted effects, estimated using coefficients from Model 2.1 (without corruption; left) and Model 2.2 (with corruption; right). Effects ofa change in electoral democracy are shown in top row; effects of change inminoritarian democracy in the bottom row. The solid lines indicatethe mean predicted effect; the shaded regions indicate the 95% confidence intervals of these predicted effects.

Christopher Claassen

50

Dow

nloa

ded

from

htt

ps://

ww

w.c

ambr

idge

.org

/cor

e. IP

add

ress

: 54.

39.1

06.1

73, o

n 14

Jun

2020

at 0

6:32

:36,

sub

ject

to th

e Ca

mbr

idge

Cor

e te

rms

of u

se, a

vaila

ble

at h

ttps

://w

ww

.cam

brid

ge.o

rg/c

ore/

term

s. h

ttps

://do

i.org

/10.

1017

/S00

0305

5419

0005

58

Page 16: In the Mood for Democracy? Democratic Support as ...€¦ · but their preference for democracy would weaken as democratic rights and institutions are supplied. If sup-port for democracy—or

andmood stands in contrastwith emerging narratives ofdemocracy’s fading allure (Plattner 2017) and decliningsupport (Foa and Mounk 2016, 2017). Indeed, as thearticle shows in its descriptive analysis of the trends ofdemocracy and democratic mood, support can ebb andflow, even in long-established democracies.

In contrast to theories of democratic socialization andlifelong learning, this article has proposed a thermo-static model of democratic mood. The evidence sup-ports this thermostatic model: increases in democracydampen public mood, while decreases cheer it. Thearticle thenattempts tounpick thepuzzleofwhy citizenswould favor diminished democracy, finding that it is notimprovements in majoritarian rights and institutionsthat damage democratic mood, but, instead, it isimprovements in counter-majoritarian rights andinstitutions that provoke the backlash.Moreover, thereis little evidence in favor of the theory that democraticsupport is learned, whether through socialization orlater-life experience with democratic freedoms. Theshort-run effects of lagged democracy are tiny andusually insignificant. Over the long run, these effectstake decades to add up to anymarked increase inmood.Democracy therefore does not appear to create its owndemand.

Withdoubt cast on the theory that thepublic becomesmore supportive the longer their experience with de-mocracy (see also Denemark, Donovan, and Niemi2016), itwouldbea fruitful avenue for future research toexamine the processes of democratic socialization andlearning more closely. Studies of existing data would,however, have to consider the separate impacts of age,generation, and period effects, as well as navigate theshoals of potentially nonequivalent cross-nationalmeasures of democratic support. Alternatively, an-other lens on the thermostatic effect identified in thisarticle could be obtained by fielding a panel survey ina new democracy, which would allow researchers toidentify micro-level reactions to democratic change.

The findings of this article resonate with long-standing arguments in the literatures on judicial re-view and political tolerance. The former has long beenconcerned with the “counter-majoritarian difficulty”thrown up by judicial review of majority decisions (e.g.,Bickel 1986)—and it seems that publics in many soci-eties share these concerns. The latter has shown thatextending democratic rights and legal protections tominorities is the most difficult and unappetizing aspectof democracy formany citizens (e.g.,Gibson 2008).Thisstands in contrast to majoritarian principles such as“rule by the people,” which are readily and widelyendorsed by majorities in autocratic and democraticsocieties alike (Gibson 1998).

This article also have implications for the crisis saidto be currently facing democracy (Diamond 2015;Mechkova, Luhrmann, and Lindberg 2017; Plattner2017). In particular, the decreases in support that followincreases in democracy pose a challenge to democraticconsolidation. After a significant transition to de-mocracy, public support for democracy declines exactlywhen the fledgling democracy is most vulnerable(especially if thenewregime features extensive counter-

majoritarian institutions). On a brighter note, the re-verse of this dynamic is also evident: should electedleaders start dismantling democratic institutions andrights, public mood is likely to swing rapidly towarddemocracy again, providing something of an obstacle todemocratic backsliding.

Yet, the findings of this article also undermine theconcept of democratic consolidation, echoing Foa andMounk (2016, 2017). One of the key pillars of a con-solidateddemocracy is that“theoverwhelmingmajorityof the people” are committed to a democratic form ofgovernment (Linz and Stepan 1996, 5). Yet if demo-cratic mood can weaken even in long-established de-mocracies, then we cannot be certain that anydemocracy will retain majority support in future. Assuch, we cannot be certain that any democracy—nomatter how long-standing—is consolidated. Indeed,because democracy does not appear to create its owndemand, an equilibrium of “consolidated democracy,”where high levels of democracy both promote, and aresustainedby,high levelsofpublic support,maynotexist.

SUPPLEMENTARY MATERIAL

To view supplementary material for this article, pleasevisit https://doi.org/10.1017/S0003055419000558.

Replication materials can be found on Dataverse at:https://doi.org/10.7910/DVN/FECIO3.

REFERENCES

Acemoglu, Daron, and James A. Robinson. 2006. Economic OriginsofDictatorship andDemocracy. Cambridge: CambridgeUniversityPress.

Anderson, Christopher J., and Yuliya V. Tverdova. 2003. “Corrup-tion, Political Allegiances, and Attitudes toward Government inContemporary Democracies.” American Journal of Political Sci-ence 47 (1): 91–109.

Arendt, Hannah. 1951. The Origins of Totalitarianism. New York:Harcourt, Brace and Co.

Ariely, Gal, and EldadDavidov. 2011. “CanWeRate Public SupportforDemocracy in aComparableWay?Cross-NationalEquivalenceof Democratic Attitudes in the World Value Survey.” SocialIndicators Research 104 (2): 271–86.

Armingeon, Klaus, and Kai Guthmann. 2014. “Democracy in Crisis?The Declining Support for National Democracy in EuropeanCountries, 2007–2011.” European Journal of Political Research 53(3): 423–42.

Baker, Kendall L., Russell J. Dalton, and Kai Hildebrandt. 1981.Germany Transformed: Political Culture and the New Politics.Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

Beck,Nathaniel, and JonathanN.Katz. 2011. “ModelingDynamics inTime-Series–Cross-Section Political Economy Data.” Annual Re-view of Political Science 14: 331–52.

Bickel, Alexander M. 1986. The Least Dangerous Branch: The Su-premeCourt at theBarofPolitics, 2ndedition.NewHaven,CT:YaleUniversity Press.

Booth, JohnA.,andMitchellA.Seligson.2009.TheLegitimacyPuzzleinLatinAmerica:PoliticalSupportandDemocracy inEightNations.Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Bratton,Michael. 2010.“TheMeanings ofDemocracy:Anchoring the‘D-Word’ in Africa.” Journal of Democracy 21 (4): 106–13.

Bratton, Michael, and Robert Mattes. 2001. “Support for Democracyin Africa: Intrinsic or Instrumental?” British Journal of PoliticalScience 31 (3): 447–74.

In the Mood for Democracy?

51

Dow

nloa

ded

from

htt

ps://

ww

w.c

ambr

idge

.org

/cor

e. IP

add

ress

: 54.

39.1

06.1

73, o

n 14

Jun

2020

at 0

6:32

:36,

sub

ject

to th

e Ca

mbr

idge

Cor

e te

rms

of u

se, a

vaila

ble

at h

ttps

://w

ww

.cam

brid

ge.o

rg/c

ore/

term

s. h

ttps

://do

i.org

/10.

1017

/S00

0305

5419

0005

58

Page 17: In the Mood for Democracy? Democratic Support as ...€¦ · but their preference for democracy would weaken as democratic rights and institutions are supplied. If sup-port for democracy—or

Bratton,Michael, RobertMattes, andE.Gyimah-Boadi. 2005.PublicOpinion, Democracy, and Market Reform in Africa. Cambridge:Cambridge University Press.

Canache,Damarys, Jeffery J.Mondak,andMitchellA.Seligson. 2001.“Meaning and Measurement in Cross-National Research on Sat-isfaction with Democracy.” Public Opinion Quarterly 65 (4):506–28.

Claassen,Christopher. 2019a.“DoesPublic SupportHelpDemocracySurvive?” American Journal of Political Science. https://10.1111/ajps.12452.

Claassen, Christopher. 2019b. “Estimating Smooth Country-YearPanels of Public Opinion.” Political Analysis 27 (1): 1–20.

Dahl, Robert A. 1971. Polyarchy: Participation and Opposition. NewHaven, CT: Yale University Press.

Dalton, Russell. 1994. “Communists and Democrats: DemocraticAttitudes in the Two Germanies.” British Journal of Political Sci-ence 24 (4): 469–93.

Dalton, Russell J. 2004.Democratic Challenges, Democratic Choices:The Erosion of Political Support in Advanced Industrial De-mocracies. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Dalton, Russell J., and ChristianWelzel. 2014. “Political Culture andValue Change.” In The Civic Culture Transformed: FromAllegiantto Assertive Citizens, eds. Russell J. Dalton and Christian Welzel.Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1–16.

Dalton, Russell J., and Doh Chull Shin, eds. 2006. Citizens, De-mocracy, andMarkets Around the Pacific Rim: Congruence Theoryand Political Culture. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

De Boef, Susanna, and Luke Keele. 2008. “Taking Time Seriously.”American Journal of Political Science 52 (1): 184–200.

Denemark, David, Todd Donovan, and Richard G. Niemi. 2016.“Advanced Democracies: The Erosion of Traditional DemocraticCitizenship.” In Growing up Democratic: Does it Make a Differ-ence?eds.DavidDenemark,RobertMattes, andRichardG.Niemi.Boulder, CO: Lynne Rienner, 181–206.

Diamond, Larry. 2015. “Facing up to the Democratic Recession.”Journal of Democracy 26 (1): 141–55.

Duch, Raymond M., and James L. Gibson. 1992. “‘Putting up with’Fascists inWestern Europe: A Comparative, Cross-Level Analysisof Political Tolerance.” The Western Political Quarterly 45 (1):237–73.

Easton, David. 1965.A Systems Analysis of Political Life. New York:Wiley.

Eckstein, Harry. 1966.ATheory of Stable Democracy. Princeton, NJ:Princeton University Press.

Erikson,Robert S.,MichaelB.Mackuen, and JamesA. Stimson. 2002.The Macro Polity. New York: Cambridge University Press.

Evans, Geoffrey, and Stephen Whitefield. 1995. “The Politics andEconomics ofDemocratic Commitment: Support forDemocracy inTransition Societies.” British Journal of Political Science 25 (4):485–514.

Foa, Roberto Stefan, and Yascha Mounk. 2016. “The Danger ofDeconsolidation: The Democratic Disconnect.” Journal of De-mocracy 27 (3): 5–17.

Foa, Roberto Stefan, and Yascha Mounk. 2017. “The Signs ofDeconsolidation.” Journal of Democracy 28 (1): 5–16.

Fromm, Erich. 1941. Escape from Freedom. New York: Holt.Gandhi, Jennifer, and Ellen Lust-Okar. 2009. “Elections under Au-

thoritarianism.” Annual Review of Political Science 12: 403–22.Gibson, James L. 1998. “ASober SecondThought:AnExperiment in

Persuading Russians to Tolerate.” American Journal of PoliticalScience 42 (3): 819–50.

Gibson, James L. 2008. “Intolerance and Political Repression in theUnited States: A Half Century after McCarthyism.” AmericanJournal of Political Science 52 (1): 96–108.

Gibson, James L., and Gregory A. Caldeira. 2003. “Defenders ofDemocracy? Legitimacy, Popular Acceptance, and the South Af-rican Constitutional Court.” The Journal of Politics 65 (1): 1–30.

Graham,Carol, andSandipSukhtankar. 2004.“DoesEconomicCrisisReduce Support for Markets and Democracy in Latin America?Some Evidence from Surveys of Public Opinion and Well Being.”Journal of Latin American Studies 36 (2): 349–77.

Huntington, Samuel P. 1991. “Democracy’s Third Wave.” Journal ofDemocracy 2 (2): 12–34.

Inglehart, Ronald, and Christian Welzel. 2005. Modernization, Cul-tural Change, andDemocracy: TheHumanDevelopment Sequence.Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Jennings, M. Kent, and Richard G. Niemi. 1974. The Political Char-acter of Adolescence. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

Klingemann, Hans-Dieter. 1999. “Mapping Political Support in the1990s: A Global Analysis.” In Critical Citizens: Global Support forDemocratic Governance, ed. Pippa Norris. Oxford, UK: OxfordUniversity Press, 31–56.

Krieckhaus, Jonathan, Byunghwan Son, Nisha Mukherjee Bellinger,and Jason M. Wells. 2014. “Economic Inequality and DemocraticSupport.” The Journal of Politics 76 (1): 139–51.

Levitsky, Steven, and LucanA.Way. 2002. “TheRise of CompetitiveAuthoritarianism.” Journal of Democracy 13 (2): 51–65.

Linde, Jonas, and Joakim Ekman. 2003. “Satisfaction with De-mocracy: A Note on a Frequently Used Indicator in ComparativePolitics.” European Journal of Political Research 42 (3): 391–408.

Linz, Juan J., and Alfred Stepan. 1996. Problems of Democratic Tran-sition and Consolidation: Southern Europe, South America, and Post-Communist Europe. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press.

Lipset, Seymour Martin. 1959. “Some Social Requisites of De-mocracy: Economic Development and Political Legitimacy.”American Political Science Review 53 (1): 69–105.

Luhrmann,Anna,MarcusTannenberg, andStaffan I. Lindberg. 2018.“Regimes of the World (RoW): Opening New Avenues for theComparative Study of Political Regimes.” Politics and Governance6 (1). http://dx.doi.org/10.17645/pag.v6i1.1214.

Magalhães, PedroC. 2014.“GovernmentEffectiveness andSupport forDemocracy.” European Journal of Political Research 53 (1): 77–97.

Mannheim, Karl. 1952. “The Problem of Generations.” In Essays onthe Sociology of Knowledge, ed. Paul Kecskemeti. London:Routledge, 276–320.

Mattes, Robert. 2018. “Support for Democracy.” In Oxford Re-search Encyclopedia in Politics, ed. William Thompson. NewYork: Oxford University Press, https://doi.org/10.1093/acrefore/9780190228637.013.622.

Mattes, Robert, David Denemark, and Richard G. Niemi. 2016a.“Generational Change in Postauthoritarian Democracies?” InGrowing up Democratic: Does it Make a Difference? eds. DavidDenemark, Robert Mattes, and Richard G. Niemi. Boulder, CO:Lynne Rienner, 263–82.

Mattes, Robert, David Denemark, and Richard G. Niemi. 2016b.“Growing up Democratic?” In Growing up Democratic: Does itMake a Difference? eds. David Denemark, Robert Mattes, andRichard G. Niemi. Boulder, CO: Lynne Rienner, 1–24.

Mattes, Robert, and Michael Bratton. 2007. “Learning about De-mocracy in Africa: Awareness, Performance, and Experience.”American Journal of Political Science 51 (1): 192–217.

Mechkova, Valeriya, Anna Luhrmann, and Staffan I. Lindberg. 2017.“How Much Democratic Backsliding?” Journal of Democracy 28(4): 162–9.

Mishler, William, and Richard Rose. 2002. “Learning and Re-Learning Regime Support: The Dynamics of Post-CommunistRegimes.” European Journal of Political Research 41 (1): 5–36.

Mishler, William, and Richard Rose. 2007. “Generation, Age, andTime: The Dynamics of Political Learning during Russia’s Trans-formation.” American Journal of Political Science 51 (4): 822–34.

Montero, Jose Ramon, Richard Gunther, and Mariano Torcal. 1997.“Democracy in Spain: Legitimacy, Discontent, and Disaffection.”Studies in Comparative International Development 32 (3): 124–60.

Morlino,Leonardo. 2010.“AuthoritarianLegacies,Politicsof thePastand the Quality of Democracy in Southern Europe: Open Con-clusions.” South European Society and Politics 15 (3): 507–29.

Norris, Pippa. 2011. Democratic Deficit: Critical Citizens Revisited.Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Norris, Pippa. 2017.“IsWesternDemocarcyBacksliding?DiagnosingtheRisk.” JournalofDemocracy.OnlineExchangeon“DemocraticDeconsolidation”. https://www.journalofdemocracy.org/online-exchange-democratic-deconsolidation.

Plattner,MarcF. 2017.“LiberalDemocracy’s FadingAllure.” Journalof Democracy 28 (4): 5–14.

Pop-Eleches, Grigore, and Joshua A. Tucker. 2017. Communism’sShadow: Historical Legacies and Contemporary Political Attitudes.Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

Christopher Claassen

52

Dow

nloa

ded

from

htt

ps://

ww

w.c

ambr

idge

.org

/cor

e. IP

add

ress

: 54.

39.1

06.1

73, o

n 14

Jun

2020

at 0

6:32

:36,

sub

ject

to th

e Ca

mbr

idge

Cor

e te

rms

of u

se, a

vaila

ble

at h

ttps

://w

ww

.cam

brid

ge.o

rg/c

ore/

term

s. h

ttps

://do

i.org

/10.

1017

/S00

0305

5419

0005

58

Page 18: In the Mood for Democracy? Democratic Support as ...€¦ · but their preference for democracy would weaken as democratic rights and institutions are supplied. If sup-port for democracy—or

Qi,Lingling, andDohChull Shin. 2011.“HowMassPoliticalAttitudesAffect Democratization: Exploring the Facilitating Role CriticalDemocrats Play in the Process.” International Political ScienceReview 32 (3): 245–62.

Rose, Richard, and William Mishler. 1996. “Testing the ChurchillHypothesis: Popular Support for Democracy and its Alternatives.”Journal of Public Policy 16 (1): 29–58.

Rose, Richard, William Mishler, and Christian Haerpfer. 1998. De-mocracy and its Alternatives: Understanding Post-Communist So-cieties. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press.

Rueschemeyer, Dietrich, Evelyne Huber Stephens, and John D.Stephens. 1992. Capitalist Development and Democracy. Chicago:University of Chicago Press.

Soroka, Stuart N., and Christopher Wlezien. 2010. Degrees of De-mocracy: Politics, Public Opinion, and Policy. Cambridge: Cam-bridge University Press.

Stegmueller, Daniel. 2011. “Apples and Oranges? The Problem ofEquivalenceinComparativeResearch.”PoliticalAnalysis19(4):471–87.

Stimson, James A. 1991. Public Opinion in America: Moods, Cycles, andSwings,TransformingAmericanPolitics.Boulder,CO:WestviewPress.

Teorell, Jan, Michael Coppedge, Staffan Lindberg, and Svend-ErikSkaaning. 2018. “Measuring Polyarchy Across the Globe,1900–2017.” Studies in Comparative International Development.forthcoming. https://doi.org/10.1007/s12116-018-9268-z.

V-Dem Institute. 2018a. Codebook: v8—April 2018: V-Dem Institute,University ofGothenburg. https://www.v-dem.net/media/filer_public/64/ad/64ad9308-45fa-473e-8e2b-e1c0c4e421e6/v-dem_codebook_v8.pdf.

V-Dem Institute. 2018b. Democracy for All? V-Dem Annual De-mocracy Report 2018: V-Dem Institute, University of Gothenburg.https://www.v-dem.net/media/filer_public/3f/19/3f19efc9-e25f-4356-b159-b5c0ec894115/v-dem_democracy_report_2018.pdf.

Voeten, Erik. 2017. “Are People Really Turning Away from De-mocracy?” Journal of Democracy. Online Exchange on “Demo-cratic Deconsolidation”. https://www.journalofdemocracy.org/online-exchange-democratic-deconsolidation.

Welzel, Christian. 2013. Freedom Rising: Human Empowerment andthe Quest for Emancipation. Cambridge: Cambridge UniversityPress.

Williams, Laron K., and Guy D. Whitten. 2012. “But Wait, There’sMore! Maximizing Substantive Inferences from TSCS Models.”The Journal of Politics 74 (3): 685–93.

Wintrobe, Ronald. 1998. The Political Economy of Dictatorship.Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Wlezien, Christopher. 1995. “The Public as Thermostat: Dynamics ofPreferences for Spending.”American Journal ofPolitical Science 39(4): 981–1000.

Wood, Elisabeth Jean. 2000. Forging Democracy from below:Insurgent Transitions in South Africa and El Salvador. Cambridge:Cambridge University Press.

In the Mood for Democracy?

53

Dow

nloa

ded

from

htt

ps://

ww

w.c

ambr

idge

.org

/cor

e. IP

add

ress

: 54.

39.1

06.1

73, o

n 14

Jun

2020

at 0

6:32

:36,

sub

ject

to th

e Ca

mbr

idge

Cor

e te

rms

of u

se, a

vaila

ble

at h

ttps

://w

ww

.cam

brid

ge.o

rg/c

ore/

term

s. h

ttps

://do

i.org

/10.

1017

/S00

0305

5419

0005

58