A A R H U S U N I V E R S I T Y 1 Scandinavian Institute Ole Togeby, Pragmatics of deception...

124
A A R H U S U N I V E R S I T Y 1 Scandinavian Institute Ole Togeby, Pragmatics of deception Interpersonal deception: Jan. 26-27 Pragmatics of deception Ole Togeby Scandinavian Institute Aarhus University

Transcript of A A R H U S U N I V E R S I T Y 1 Scandinavian Institute Ole Togeby, Pragmatics of deception...

A A R H U S U N I V E R S I T Y

1

Scandinavian Institute

Ole Togeby, Pragmatics of deception Interpersonal deception: Jan. 26-27

Pragmatics of deception

Ole Togeby

Scandinavian Institute

Aarhus University

A A R H U S U N I V E R S I T Y

2

Scandinavian Institute

Ole Togeby, Pragmatics of deception Interpersonal deception: Jan. 26-27

Plan

I. Introduction II. Text interpretation III. Communication failures IV. Presupposition failures V. False implicatures

A A R H U S U N I V E R S I T Y

3

Scandinavian Institute

Ole Togeby, Pragmatics of deception Interpersonal deception: Jan. 26-27

Definition

Deceive : ‘to cause to believe what is untrue’, implies imposing a false idea or belief that causes ignorance, bewilderment, or helplessness; deception may involve lies, but is something different from lying.

Synonyms: beguile, bluff, cant, cheat, con, delude, fake, feign, fool, fox, frustrate by underhandedness, humour, hypocrisy, kid, lead astray, mislead, pass off, pretend, seduce, swindle, take in, trick.

A A R H U S U N I V E R S I T Y

4

Scandinavian Institute

Ole Togeby, Pragmatics of deception Interpersonal deception: Jan. 26-27

In this paper I’ll define the differences between the following related phenomena:

Obscurity: infelicitous reference and predication

Lying: false predication

Be mistaken: unintended untruth:

Deceiving: false presupposition

Leading astray: false implicating

Seduction: infelicitous illocutionary force

A A R H U S U N I V E R S I T Y

5

Scandinavian Institute

Ole Togeby, Pragmatics of deception Interpersonal deception: Jan. 26-27

Pragmatic methodology

All these concepts are pragmatic phenomena that can only be discussed when situated, that is to say when they occur as part of a situation in which all parts and elements have a fixed and known value, e.g. Who are the hearers? What do they know? What are their interests, and the speaker’s interest? And so on.

Consequently I’ll tell a couple of stories (in which all communication factors have fixed values) and only discuss communication failures committed in utterances made in such well defined situations.

A A R H U S U N I V E R S I T Y

6

Scandinavian Institute

Ole Togeby, Pragmatics of deception Interpersonal deception: Jan. 26-27

Example: The Blue-eyed Boy

‘When I was in Vienna twenty years ago,’ she began, ‘a pretty boy with big blue eyes made a great stir there by dancing on a rope blindfolded. He danced with wonderful grace and skill, and the blindfolding was genuine, the cloth being tied around his eyes by a person out of the audience. His performance was the great sensation of the season, and he was sent for to dance before the Emperor and Empress, the archdukes and archduchesses, and the court.

A A R H U S U N I V E R S I T Y

7

Scandinavian Institute

Ole Togeby, Pragmatics of deception Interpersonal deception: Jan. 26-27

The Blue-eyed Boy

The great oculist, Professor Heimholz, was present. He had been sent for by the Emperor, since everybody was discussing the problem of clairvoyance.

But in the end of the show he rose up and called out: “Your Majesty,” he said, in great agitation, “and your Imperial Highnesses, this is all humbug, and a cheat.”

‘ “It cannot be humbug,” said the court oculist, “I have myself tied the cloth around the boy’s eyes most conscientiously.”

A A R H U S U N I V E R S I T Y

8

Scandinavian Institute

Ole Togeby, Pragmatics of deception Interpersonal deception: Jan. 26-27

The Blue-eyed Boy

‘ “It is all humbug and a cheat," the great professor indignantly insisted. “That child was born blind.” ’

Isak Dinesen 1934: “The Deluge at Nordeney” in Seven Gothic Tales

A A R H U S U N I V E R S I T Y

9

Scandinavian Institute

Ole Togeby, Pragmatics of deception Interpersonal deception: Jan. 26-27

Example 2: The Emperor’s New Clothes

Many years ago there was an Emperor so exceedingly fond of new clothes that he spent all his money on being well dressed. (…) one day came two swindlers. They let it be known they were weavers, and they said they could weave the most magnificent fabrics imaginable. Not only were their colours and patterns uncommonly fine, but clothes made of this cloth had a wonderful way of becoming invisible to anyone who was unfit for his office, or who was unusually stupid.

A A R H U S U N I V E R S I T Y

10

Scandinavian Institute

Ole Togeby, Pragmatics of deception Interpersonal deception: Jan. 26-27

The Emperor’s New Clothes

They set up two looms and pretended to weave, though there was nothing on the looms. All the finest silk and the purest old thread which they demanded went into their travelling bags, while they worked the empty looms far into the night.

"I'd like to know how those weavers are getting on with the cloth," the Emperor thought, "I'll send my honest old minister to the weavers," the Emperor decided. (…) So the honest old minister went to the room where the two swindlers sat working away at their empty looms.

"Heaven help me," he thought as his eyes flew wide open, "I can't see anything at all". But he did not say so.

"Don't hesitate to tell us what you think of it," said one of the weavers. "Oh, it's beautiful -it's enchanting."

A A R H U S U N I V E R S I T Y

11

Scandinavian Institute

Ole Togeby, Pragmatics of deception Interpersonal deception: Jan. 26-27

The Emperor’s New Clothes

The Emperor presently sent another trustworthy official to see how the work progressed and how soon it would be ready. (…) He looked and he looked, but as there was nothing to see in the looms he couldn't see anything.

(…) He declared he was delighted with the beautiful colours and

the exquisite pattern. To the Emperor he said, "It held me spellbound."

A A R H U S U N I V E R S I T Y

12

Scandinavian Institute

Ole Togeby, Pragmatics of deception Interpersonal deception: Jan. 26-27

The Emperor’s New Clothes

All the town was talking of this splendid cloth, and the Emperor wanted to see it for himself while it was still in the looms. (…)

"What's this?" thought the Emperor. "I can't see anything. This is terrible!

Am I a fool? Am I unfit to be the Emperor? What a thing to happen to me of all people!

- Oh! It's very pretty," he said. "It has my highest approval."

A A R H U S U N I V E R S I T Y

13

Scandinavian Institute

Ole Togeby, Pragmatics of deception Interpersonal deception: Jan. 26-27

The Emperor’s New Clothes

Then the Emperor himself came with his noblest noblemen, and the swindlers each raised an arm as if they were holding something. They said, "These are the trousers, here's the coat, and this is the mantle," naming each garment. "All of them are as light as a spider web. One would almost think he had nothing on, but that's what makes them so fine."

A A R H U S U N I V E R S I T Y

14

Scandinavian Institute

Ole Togeby, Pragmatics of deception Interpersonal deception: Jan. 26-27

The Emperor’s New Clothes

So off went the Emperor in procession under his splendid canopy. Everyone in the streets and the windows said, "Oh, how fine are the Emperor's new clothes! Don't they fit him to perfection? And see his long train!" Nobody would confess that he couldn't see anything, for that would prove him either unfit for his position, or a fool.

A A R H U S U N I V E R S I T Y

15

Scandinavian Institute

Ole Togeby, Pragmatics of deception Interpersonal deception: Jan. 26-27

The Emperor’s New Clothes

"But he hasn't got anything on," a little child said. "Did you ever hear such innocent prattle?" said its

father. And one person whispered to another what the child had said, "He hasn't anything on. A child says he hasn't anything on."

"But he hasn't got anything on!" the whole town cried out at last.

A A R H U S U N I V E R S I T Y

16

Scandinavian Institute

Ole Togeby, Pragmatics of deception Interpersonal deception: Jan. 26-27

The Emperor’s New Clothes

The Emperor shivered, for he suspected they were right. But he thought, "This procession has got to go on." So he walked more proudly than ever, as his noblemen held high the train that wasn't there at all.

Hans Christian Andersen: The Emperor’s New Clothes, a translation of "Keiserens nye Klæder" 1837 by Jean Hersholt.

A A R H U S U N I V E R S I T Y

17

Scandinavian Institute

Ole Togeby, Pragmatics of deception Interpersonal deception: Jan. 26-27

Example 3: Three fools

Three fools should pass a test to be discharged from the madhouse. The first one was asked: With what body part do you make your thinking? He pointed at his fist and said: I use this one, and he was sent back to the madhouse. The second one was asked the same; he pointed at his fist and was sent back to the madhouse.

Then the third fool was asked; he said: With my head and he was therefore discharged. Then they asked him: How could you figure it out? He pointed at his fist and said:

I used this one.

A A R H U S U N I V E R S I T Y

18

Scandinavian Institute

Ole Togeby, Pragmatics of deception Interpersonal deception: Jan. 26-27

Example 4: Examination

A candidate at the examination desk draws a question, and whispers to the examiner while the co-examiner overhears it:

This is not the question that we have arranged that I should have Alternative version: This question is not one that we have arranged I should

have.

Example 5: The Bricklayer A poor bricklayer brought a big lunch pack with him, but he was embarrassed only to be able

to afford one type of filling for his sandwiches, viz. cheese. So when he had finished nine cheese sandwiches and set about eating the tenth and last one, he said:

Now we end up with the cheese sandwich.

A A R H U S U N I V E R S I T Y

19

Scandinavian Institute

Ole Togeby, Pragmatics of deception Interpersonal deception: Jan. 26-27

Example 6: Freud

In 1938 the Nazis had promised Sigmund Freud an exit visa from Austria on condition that he sign a declaration purporting that he had been ”treated by the German authorities and particularly by the Gestapo with all the respect and consideration due to my scientific reputation”.

When the Gestapo official brought the document for his signature, Freud asked if he would be allowed to add one more sentence. Obviously sure of his one-up position, the official agreed, and Freud wrote in his own handwriting:

“I can heartily recommend the Gestapo to anyone”.

A A R H U S U N I V E R S I T Y

20

Scandinavian Institute

Ole Togeby, Pragmatics of deception Interpersonal deception: Jan. 26-27

II. Text interpretation

I. Introduction

II. Text interpretation III. Communication failures IV. Presupposition failures V. False implicatures

A A R H U S U N I V E R S I T Y

21

Scandinavian Institute

Ole Togeby, Pragmatics of deception Interpersonal deception: Jan. 26-27

Non-linguistic deception

Lying is always linguistic, while leading astray and deceiving can be linguistic or not linguistic. It is possible to mislead someone only by deceitful behaviour: e.g. in The Emperors new Clothes: They set up two looms and pretended to weave, though there was nothing on the looms. All the finest silk and the purest old thread which they demanded went into their travelling bags, while they worked the empty looms far into the night.

The blue-eyed boy did not lie, but pretended without words to be sighted by being blindfolded

In this paper I’ll only talk about linguistic deception.

A A R H U S U N I V E R S I T Y

22

Scandinavian Institute

Ole Togeby, Pragmatics of deception Interpersonal deception: Jan. 26-27

Inferential text interpretation

Regular text interpretation is a process of building a mental model of the situation talked about in the text and relate it to the model of the current situation.

The mental model is build by the hearers by 1) determining what is said from what is pronounced, and is related to the current situation by 2) determining what is communicated by what is said

A A R H U S U N I V E R S I T Y

23

Scandinavian Institute

Ole Togeby, Pragmatics of deception Interpersonal deception: Jan. 26-27

What is communicated Inference of what is implicated Integration of what is presupposed

What is said – what is said

Extraction the relevant implications Enrichment of elliptic expressions

Disambiguation of lexical items Recognition of reference

What is pronounced–what is pronounced–what is pronounced

Unconscous

Involuntary

obligatory

Inferential

Accessible

Optional

A model of interpretation process

A A R H U S U N I V E R S I T Y

24

Scandinavian Institute

Ole Togeby, Pragmatics of deception Interpersonal deception: Jan. 26-27

Inferential text interpretation

If we take the oral situation as basic, we can thus distinguish between: 1) what is pronounced (known as what is explicit) in

uttering a text, 2) what is said by what is pronounced (called the

explicature or the coded meaning), and 3) what is implicitly communicated by what is said (both

presupposition and implicature).

A A R H U S U N I V E R S I T Y

25

Scandinavian Institute

Ole Togeby, Pragmatics of deception Interpersonal deception: Jan. 26-27

Inferential text interpretation

On another dimension we can distinguish between a) information that the speaker indicates as something that

should be taking for granted, b) information that the speaker states as new in order to

make the audience take it in

It gives six type of information: names, predicates, what is named (the reference), what is

predicated, what is presupposed and the implicature.

A A R H U S U N I V E R S I T Y

26

Scandinavian Institute

Ole Togeby, Pragmatics of deception Interpersonal deception: Jan. 26-27

Types of information

Information Taken for granted Stated

What is pronounced

Names (definite noun phrases)

Predicates (verb phrases, adjectives, adverbials)

What is said in the proposition

What is named (the re-cognizable reference in the mental model)

What is predicated as relevant to the audience

What is communicated

What is presupposed by the utterance of the proposition

The implicature of the speaker’s claim of relevance of the predicated information

A A R H U S U N I V E R S I T Y

27

Scandinavian Institute

Ole Togeby, Pragmatics of deception Interpersonal deception: Jan. 26-27

Terminological note

The verb imply and the noun implication is used about entailments (logically necessary conclusive

information). The fact that the child was born blind implies ‘that he was and had

always been lacking the power to see’.

The Verb implicate and the noun implicature is used about pragmatically generated, but logically

cancellable information. The answer “-There is a garage round the corner” to the car driver’s remark “-I am out of petrol” implicates that ’you can probably get some petrol there’.

A A R H U S U N I V E R S I T Y

28

Scandinavian Institute

Ole Togeby, Pragmatics of deception Interpersonal deception: Jan. 26-27

Terminological note

In Grice’s original article Logic and Conversation 1967 the term conventional implicature is the name for ’what is presupposed’, and what I here call implicature Grice calls conversational implicature. Grice’s terminology did not catch on, however, so I will here use Levinson’s terminology:

Presuppositions are conventional, semantic and triggered by lexical items and syntactic constructions when they are uttered in a proposition.

Implicatures are conversational, pragmatic and triggered by the guarantee of relevance for the current purpose of talk exchange, given by the utterance of a speech act.

A A R H U S U N I V E R S I T Y

29

Scandinavian Institute

Ole Togeby, Pragmatics of deception Interpersonal deception: Jan. 26-27

What is said

What is said ( the explicature) is defined as follows: What is said is information about the stated relations

between named things, information that the audience extract from what is pronounced and its context, in order to grasp the meaning of the whole proposition that can be ascribed truth value.

This extraction takes place solely on the basis of knowledge of the grammatical rules and the lexicon of the language

A A R H U S U N I V E R S I T Y

30

Scandinavian Institute

Ole Togeby, Pragmatics of deception Interpersonal deception: Jan. 26-27

What is said This extraction of what is said from what is

pronounced consists of four operations: The audience must: 1) recognize what the pronounced names (np’s and

adverbials) refer to, 2) disambiguate (monosemiate) the lexical items and the

syntactic constructions, 3) enrich the meaning of the proposition by the information

omitted by ellipsis, and 4) extract the logical entailment (the implications) of the

proposition that are necessary for the building of a mental model of the situation

A A R H U S U N I V E R S I T Y

31

Scandinavian Institute

Ole Togeby, Pragmatics of deception Interpersonal deception: Jan. 26-27

What is said

1) Recognition of what the pronounced names refer to.

In When I was in Vienna twenty years ago,’ she began,

the audience must recognize that I (like she) refers to ’Miss Malin Nat-og-Dag’, and twenty years ago refers to ’the year 1815’ (because it is said in 1835).

A A R H U S U N I V E R S I T Y

32

Scandinavian Institute

Ole Togeby, Pragmatics of deception Interpersonal deception: Jan. 26-27

What is said

2) Disambiguation of lexical items and syntactical constructions.

The readers have to decide that sensation, in this context, means ‘a sensational event’, and not a sort of ‘feeling’ or ‘sense’; sensation as a lexical item can have both meanings.

In the construction by dancing on a rope blindfolded it has to be recognized that it is ‘the dancing boy’ that is ‘blindfolded’, and not ‘the rope’ although this attachment pattern is possible too, compare with: by dancing on a rope fastened to a tree

A A R H U S U N I V E R S I T Y

33

Scandinavian Institute

Ole Togeby, Pragmatics of deception Interpersonal deception: Jan. 26-27

What is said

3) enrichment of the meaning of the proposition by the information omitted by ellipsis

He danced with wonderful grace and skill has to be enriched with the information ‘on the rope’; it has been left out by ellipsis.

A A R H U S U N I V E R S I T Y

34

Scandinavian Institute

Ole Togeby, Pragmatics of deception Interpersonal deception: Jan. 26-27

What is said

4) Extraction of the logical entailments (implications) of the proposition that are necessary for the building of a mental model of the situation.

From the fact ‘that the child was born blind’ the readers have to extract the implication ‘that he was and had always been lacking the power to see’

A A R H U S U N I V E R S I T Y

35

Scandinavian Institute

Ole Togeby, Pragmatics of deception Interpersonal deception: Jan. 26-27

What is communicated

The next step in the inferential text interpretation process is to determine what is communicated by what is said in uttering the speech act in a specific situational setting.

It involves for members of the audience: a) accepting and integrating in the mental model what is

presupposed, and b) inferring what is implicated.

A A R H U S U N I V E R S I T Y

36

Scandinavian Institute

Ole Togeby, Pragmatics of deception Interpersonal deception: Jan. 26-27

What is presupposed

Presupposition (called a conventional implicature by Grice) is defined as:

What is presupposed is the pieces of information that the speaker by lexical and syntactic choices signals to the audience that they must take as given (and incorporate in their mental model if it isn’t already there) in order to understand what is said as part of existing mental model of the situation talked about.

What falls outside the scope of the sentential negation.

A A R H U S U N I V E R S I T Y

37

Scandinavian Institute

Ole Togeby, Pragmatics of deception Interpersonal deception: Jan. 26-27

What is presupposed

Normally what is presupposed is signalled by lexical items, e.g. all verbs of transition (perfective verbs) presuppose that the previous state was in force when the transition sets in:

In But in the end of the show he rose up and called out: It is presupposed ‘that he was sitting’ when ‘he rose up’,

although it has not been said explicitly. But this is trivial and uncontroversial and is not noticed as something it is necessary to incorporate.

A A R H U S U N I V E R S I T Y

38

Scandinavian Institute

Ole Togeby, Pragmatics of deception Interpersonal deception: Jan. 26-27

What is presupposed A well known example of presupposition is:

When did you stop beating your wife? In this example your wife presupposes that the

addressee is married, stop presupposes that the process or activity was in force when it stopped; When presupposes that the information in the rest of the sentence is true. If the addressee hasn’t stopped beating his wife, has not ever beaten her, is not married, or is not male, what is presupposed is not given. This is called bullying, which is a sort of presupposition failure. (Harder & Kock 1976)

A A R H U S U N I V E R S I T Y

39

Scandinavian Institute

Ole Togeby, Pragmatics of deception Interpersonal deception: Jan. 26-27

What is presupposed

It is often said that the verb know presupposes the truth of what is known. When uttering the sentence

The professor knew that the boy was born blind the speaker takes for granted that it is a fact ‘that the boy was

born blind’. And with the sentence: The court oculist did not know that the boy was born blind it is also taken for granted ‘that the boy was born blind’. In

this way it is a simple test for what is presupposed that it is outside the scope of the sentential negation.

A A R H U S U N I V E R S I T Y

40

Scandinavian Institute

Ole Togeby, Pragmatics of deception Interpersonal deception: Jan. 26-27

What is presupposed

Conjunctions and adverbials can presuppose information too, e.g. but presupposes that there is an opposition between the preceding and the subsequent word:

The waiter is negro but well-groomed. presupposes that there is an opposition between ‘being negro’

and ‘being well-groomed’ – an example of bullying which reveals the prejudice of the speaker, a controversial prejudice which is also forced on the audience; they cannot react against it, unless they impolitely interrupt the flow of information by discussing something that is not relevant for the message of the utterance.

A A R H U S U N I V E R S I T Y

41

Scandinavian Institute

Ole Togeby, Pragmatics of deception Interpersonal deception: Jan. 26-27

If information bullied on the audience is neither given nor controversial, the result is only confusion:

• Den kvinde, der blev fundet i Fredericia centrum sent fredag aften, er nu identificeret. Hun er en 28-årig tysker, der kommer fra en institution i Hamborg. Den retarderede kvinde blev fundet i en rundkørsel ved Norgesgade ved 23-tiden fredag aften, men hun har intet sprog.

• Politiken 8.4.2003 I side 6.

• The woman found i Fredericia Centre late Friday night, has been identified. She is a 28 -year-old German from Hamburg. The mentally retarded woman was found in a roundabout near Norgesgade about 11 o’clock Friday night, but she has no language

A A R H U S U N I V E R S I T Y

42

Scandinavian Institute

Ole Togeby, Pragmatics of deception Interpersonal deception: Jan. 26-27

What is presupposed

Here it is presupposed that there is an opposition between ’to be found in a round about’ and ’to have no language’, a statement that is neither given nor controversial and must be looked on as a communication failure.

(It is probably the case that the sub-editor of the paper has cut the last sentence which could have been: så man kan ikke finde ud af hvordan hun er kommet frem til rundkørslen i Fredericia. (So it was impossible to find out how she has come to the round about in Fredericia)

A A R H U S U N I V E R S I T Y

43

Scandinavian Institute

Ole Togeby, Pragmatics of deception Interpersonal deception: Jan. 26-27

What is implicated

Information Taken for granted Stated

What is pronounced

Names (definite noun phrases)

Predicates (verb phrases, adjectives, adverbials)

What is said in the proposition

What is named (the recognizable reference)

What is predicated as relevant to the audience

What is com- municated

What is presupposed by the utterance of the proposition

The implicature of the speaker’s claim of rele-vance of the predicated information

A A R H U S U N I V E R S I T Y

44

Scandinavian Institute

Ole Togeby, Pragmatics of deception Interpersonal deception: Jan. 26-27

What is implicated

What is implicated (the implicature) Grice’s conversational implicature, which I suggest called

underforståelse in Danish, is defined: What is implicated is the unspoken information that the

members of the audience have licence to infer from what is said in order to see the relevance for them against the background of the current situation. By uttering the speech act the speaker issues a guarantee for the relevance for them of what is said, for the accepted purpose of talk exchange.

A A R H U S U N I V E R S I T Y

45

Scandinavian Institute

Ole Togeby, Pragmatics of deception Interpersonal deception: Jan. 26-27

What is implicated

Optimal relevance is achieved if what is said is the shortest formulation of the truth and the whole truth about the situation talked about, such as required for the accepted purpose of talk exchange.

A: - I am out of petrol. B: - There is a garage round the corner

Example from Grice 1975

By B’s speech act it is guaranteed that it provides a piece of information relevant for A in the current situation, and that it is the whole truth. A can now infer that she presumably can get some petrol there, but that B does not know for certain (otherwise he would have said so).

A A R H U S U N I V E R S I T Y

46

Scandinavian Institute

Ole Togeby, Pragmatics of deception Interpersonal deception: Jan. 26-27

What is implicated

The truth of the implicature is – contrary to what holds for presupposition – cancellable; B can cancel the implicature ‘that you can have petrol at the garage’ by adding:

B: - but perhaps it is not open

A A R H U S U N I V E R S I T Y

47

Scandinavian Institute

Ole Togeby, Pragmatics of deception Interpersonal deception: Jan. 26-27

What is implicated

I am passing through the customs (where I can import up to two liters of spirits) carrying a bag with six bottles of aqua vitae. When asked by the customs officer I declare:

I have two bottles of aqua vitae in my bag. That is not a blatant lie, because if I have six bottles it is a

logical implication that I have two too. It is in fact the truth and nothing but the truth. But it is not the

whole truth, and that (the whole truth relevant for accepted purpose of talk exchange) is exactly what I have issued a guarantee for when uttering my remark.

So I am with justice accused for cheating (but not for lying).

A A R H U S U N I V E R S I T Y

48

Scandinavian Institute

Ole Togeby, Pragmatics of deception Interpersonal deception: Jan. 26-27

What is implicated

Many remarkable examples will show both presupposition and implicature; in the example:

The waiter is negro but well-groomed it is, as mentioned, presupposed that there is an

opposition between for a waiter ‘to be negro’ and ‘well-groomed’, but it is at the same time implicated:

’and therefore we can have our lunch at this restaurant’.

A A R H U S U N I V E R S I T Y

49

Scandinavian Institute

Ole Togeby, Pragmatics of deception Interpersonal deception: Jan. 26-27

What is implicated

It is an implication that when the speaker introduces an opposition by means of the word but, the conclusion is drawn from the second of the pieces of information coordinated by but. The person who says:

The waiter is well-groomed but negro implicates: ‘and therefore we cannot have our lunch at this

restaurant’.

A A R H U S U N I V E R S I T Y

50

Scandinavian Institute

Ole Togeby, Pragmatics of deception Interpersonal deception: Jan. 26-27

What is implicated

‘a pretty boy with big blue eyes made a great stir there by dancing on a rope blindfolded. Here it is implicated, but not presupposed,

‘that the boy had the capacity to see (if he was not blindfolded). If he was born blind it would not be relevant that he was

blindfolded.

A A R H U S U N I V E R S I T Y

51

Scandinavian Institute

Ole Togeby, Pragmatics of deception Interpersonal deception: Jan. 26-27

What is implicated

Implicatures always involve some kind of reasoning, the implicature being either the premise or the conclusion, sometimes both: In the example about the waiter the implicature is the conclusion. Here is an example where the non-trivial implicature is the premise: Two university teachers meet in the corridor:

A: - Where are you going? B: - To the departmental meeting. A: - But, it’s only for the research-active staff.

Example from Carston 2002

A A R H U S U N I V E R S I T Y

52

Scandinavian Institute

Ole Togeby, Pragmatics of deception Interpersonal deception: Jan. 26-27

What is implicated

departmental meetings are only for the research-active staff.

{You are not research-active} . {You have no need to go there} Here one premise is implicated, and the conclusion is

the implicature of the word but.

A A R H U S U N I V E R S I T Y

53

Scandinavian Institute

Ole Togeby, Pragmatics of deception Interpersonal deception: Jan. 26-27

What is implicated

In the case of A: - But, it’s only for the research-active staff the implicature is offensive and insulting. In other cases implicatures are naïve and symptomatic; in a book with children’s scribbling one can read:

Den første tand kommer I munden The first tooth comes in the mouth. The reasoning about the implicature is something like:

The first tooth comes in the mouth. {the other teeth come somewhere else, e.g. on the knee

{The First tooth is the best (working) tooth}

A A R H U S U N I V E R S I T Y

54

Scandinavian Institute

Ole Togeby, Pragmatics of deception Interpersonal deception: Jan. 26-27

What is implicated

On a box with Italian lasagne it could be read:Denne lasagne er forkogt. Den skal ikke koges i 20 minutter i letsaltet vand. (This lasagne is parboiled. It shall not be boiled for 20 minutes in lightly salted water) .

Here it is implicated that ’it is to be boiled for 20 minutes in fully salted water’. If the lasagne should not be boiled at all, the formulation

should have been: It need not be boiled. The actual formulation is not the shortest and most economical

possible for the current purpose of talk exchange.

A A R H U S U N I V E R S I T Y

55

Scandinavian Institute

Ole Togeby, Pragmatics of deception Interpersonal deception: Jan. 26-27

I. Introduction II. Text interpretation

III. Communication failures IV. Presupposition failures V. False implicatures

A A R H U S U N I V E R S I T Y

56

Scandinavian Institute

Ole Togeby, Pragmatics of deception Interpersonal deception: Jan. 26-27

Types of false information

Information Taken for granted Stated

What is pronounced

Infelicitous names: obscurity

Infelicitous predicates: obscurity

What is said in the proposition

Infelicitous reference: obscurity

False predication is a blatant lie (unlawful) or a mistake

What is communicated

False presupposition forms deception

False implicature could be called leading stray (seduction)

A A R H U S U N I V E R S I T Y

57

Scandinavian Institute

Ole Togeby, Pragmatics of deception Interpersonal deception: Jan. 26-27

Indirect speech acts

Some people say that Speech act can be indirect. At a dinner table a person says: Can you pass the salt! which has

the form of a question, but the illocutionary force of a request. The question of indirect speech acts was discussed at conference

in Copenhagen some years ago in which both Johnson-Laird, Fodor and Searle were participating. At that occasion I revealed to John the true meaning of his example: Can you pass the salt! the meaning being: ‘Are you able to travel through the salt desert’. So what is communicated by a speech act is always indirect – that is inferred from what is said.

A A R H U S U N I V E R S I T Y

58

Scandinavian Institute

Ole Togeby, Pragmatics of deception Interpersonal deception: Jan. 26-27

Obscurity

Obscurity is defined as infelicitous naming, reference or predication:

Two young men, one of them carrying a pistol, were caught by a police man. The other man said to the one with the gun: Let him have it! And then he shot the police officer.

Later in court the man without the gun said that his remark Let him have it! was meant to mean: ‘Give it to him’, but the gunman had understood it as meaning: ‘Shoot him!’.

That is an example of obscurity, both the reference of it and the meaning of let have are infelicitous.

A A R H U S U N I V E R S I T Y

59

Scandinavian Institute

Ole Togeby, Pragmatics of deception Interpersonal deception: Jan. 26-27

Obscurity

Then the Emperor himself came with his noblest noblemen, and the swindlers each raised an arm as if they were holding something. They

said, "These are the trousers, here's the coat,

and this is the mantle," naming each garment.

A A R H U S U N I V E R S I T Y

60

Scandinavian Institute

Ole Togeby, Pragmatics of deception Interpersonal deception: Jan. 26-27

Blatant lie

Example of a blatant lie, defined as false predication: Then the Emperor himself came with his noblest noblemen, and the swindlers each raised an

arm as if they were holding something. They said, "These are the trousers, here's the coat, and this is

the mantle," naming each garment.

A A R H U S U N I V E R S I T Y

61

Scandinavian Institute

Ole Togeby, Pragmatics of deception Interpersonal deception: Jan. 26-27

IV. Presupposition failures

I. Introduction II. Text interpretation III. Communication failures

IV. Presupposition failures V. False implicatures

A A R H U S U N I V E R S I T Y

62

Scandinavian Institute

Ole Togeby, Pragmatics of deception Interpersonal deception: Jan. 26-27

Types of false information

Information Taken for granted Stated

What is pronounced

Infelicitous names: obscurity

Infelicitous predicates: obscurity

What is said in the proposition

Infelicitous reference: obscurity

False predication is a blatant lie (unlawful) or a mistake

What is communicated

False presupposition forms deception

False implicature could be called leading stray (seduction)

A A R H U S U N I V E R S I T Y

63

Scandinavian Institute

Ole Togeby, Pragmatics of deception Interpersonal deception: Jan. 26-27

Presupposition failures

Peter Harder & Christian Kock 1976: The Theory of presupposition Failure Copenhagen: Akademisk Forlaghas invented the following notational system:

S+ indicates that the presupposition of a utterance belongs to the background assumptions of the speaker, and H+ that it belongs to the background assumptions of the hearer; S- and H- that it does not belong to their respective background assumptions.

HS+ indicates that H assumes that it belongs to the background assumptions of S, and SHS+ that S is aware of that. In the same way for SH- and HSH-, and so on for SHSH+ and HSHS-.

So the standard situation has got the following notation: S+ H+ SH+ HS+ SHS+ HSH+ SHSH+ HSHS+

A A R H U S U N I V E R S I T Y

64

Scandinavian Institute

Ole Togeby, Pragmatics of deception Interpersonal deception: Jan. 26-27

Presupposition failures

Failure is the occurrence of a minus sign in the diagram. The first failure is when the presupposition does not belong to the background assumption of the hearer: H-

S+ H- SH HS SHS HSH SHSH HSHS He pointed at his fist and said: I used this one.

A A R H U S U N I V E R S I T Y

65

Scandinavian Institute

Ole Togeby, Pragmatics of deception Interpersonal deception: Jan. 26-27

Presupposition failures

The second deviation is called insincerity: the presupposition does not belong to the background assumptions of S:

S- H+ SH HS SHS HSH SHSH HSHS

Now it is time for the cheese sandwich. H: fellow bricklayers; PR: there is only one identifiable cheese

sandwich

A A R H U S U N I V E R S I T Y

66

Scandinavian Institute

Ole Togeby, Pragmatics of deception Interpersonal deception: Jan. 26-27

Presupposition failures: mistakes

A mistake is defined as a situation in which one party has a false assumption about the other party’s back-ground assumptions: H- & SH+, e.g.: Naïveté on the part of S:

S+ H- SH+ HS+ SHS+ HSH+ SHSH+ HSHS+ He pointed at his fist and said: I use this one. PR: ‘the power to think is located in the fist’

A A R H U S U N I V E R S I T Y

67

Scandinavian Institute

Ole Togeby, Pragmatics of deception Interpersonal deception: Jan. 26-27

Presupposition failures: name-dropping

Name-dropping is intentional, achieved mistake of H: S+ H- SH- HS+ SHS+ HSH+ SHSH+ HSHS+ At that occasion I revealed to John the true meaning of the

sentence: Can you pass the salt!

A A R H U S U N I V E R S I T Y

68

Scandinavian Institute

Ole Togeby, Pragmatics of deception Interpersonal deception: Jan. 26-27

Presupposition failures: name-dropping

Name-dropping can be abortive if it is seen through by H: S+ H- SH- HS+ SHS+ HSH- SHSH+ HSHS+

SHSHS+ HSHSH+ At that occasion I revealed to John the true meaning of the

sentence: Can you pass the salt!

A A R H U S U N I V E R S I T Y

69

Scandinavian Institute

Ole Togeby, Pragmatics of deception Interpersonal deception: Jan. 26-27

Presupposition failures: feigning

Feigning: is a situation in which S is not sincere, but assumes that H is not aware of this: S- & SHS+

S- H SH HS SHS+ HSH SHSH HSHS "Oh, it's beautiful - it's enchanting."

A A R H U S U N I V E R S I T Y

70

Scandinavian Institute

Ole Togeby, Pragmatics of deception Interpersonal deception: Jan. 26-27

Presupposition failures: feigning

Achieved feigning: S- H- SH- HS+ SHS+ HSH+ SHSH+ HSHS+ "Don't hesitate to tell us what you think of it," said

one of the weavers. PR: there is cloth on the loom

A A R H U S U N I V E R S I T Y

71

Scandinavian Institute

Ole Togeby, Pragmatics of deception Interpersonal deception: Jan. 26-27

Feigning

A poor bricklayer brought a big lunch pack with him, but he was embarrassed only to be able to afford one type of filling for his sandwiches, viz. cheese. So when he had finished nine cheese sandwiches and set about eating the tenth and last one, he said:

Now we end up with the cheese sandwich. PR: ‘There were various sandwiches and only one identifiable with cheese’

S- H+ insincerity SH+ HS+ non-solidarity SHS+ HSH+ feigning SHSH+ HSHS+

A A R H U S U N I V E R S I T Y

72

Scandinavian Institute

Ole Togeby, Pragmatics of deception Interpersonal deception: Jan. 26-27

Presupposition failures: feigning

Feigning seen through: S- H- SH- HS- SHS+ HSH- SHSH+ HSHS+ At that occasion I revealed to John the true meaning

of the sentence: Can you pass the salt!

A A R H U S U N I V E R S I T Y

73

Scandinavian Institute

Ole Togeby, Pragmatics of deception Interpersonal deception: Jan. 26-27

Presupposition failures: trust

Mistrusted naïveté (mistakes from both parties): S+ H- SH+ HS- SHS+ HSH- SHSH+ HSHS+ At that occasion I revealed to John the true meaning

of the sentence: Can you pass the salt!

A A R H U S U N I V E R S I T Y

74

Scandinavian Institute

Ole Togeby, Pragmatics of deception Interpersonal deception: Jan. 26-27

Presupposition failures

Solidarity: no non-solidarity Non-solidarity (ordinary): S presupposes something

but nevertheless assumes that H does not recognize it, marked with yellow, e.g. name-dropping

S+ H SH- HS SHS+ HSH SHSH+ HSHS

A A R H U S U N I V E R S I T Y

75

Scandinavian Institute

Ole Togeby, Pragmatics of deception Interpersonal deception: Jan. 26-27

Presupposition failures: solidarity

Non-solidarity (humouring): S presupposes something not part of his own background assumptions, but nevertheless assumes that H does recognize it, marked with yellow

S- H SH+ HS SHS+ HSH SHSH+ HSHS Now we end up with the cheese sandwich

A A R H U S U N I V E R S I T Y

76

Scandinavian Institute

Ole Togeby, Pragmatics of deception Interpersonal deception: Jan. 26-27

Presupposition failures:

Rhetorical behaviour: S is not sincere and expects H to be aware of this:

S- H SH HS SHS- HSH SHSH HSHS A poor bricklayer brought a big lunch pack with

him… S: I, H: You, PR: ‘There in fact was a bricklayer’

A A R H U S U N I V E R S I T Y

77

Scandinavian Institute

Ole Togeby, Pragmatics of deception Interpersonal deception: Jan. 26-27

Presupposition failures:

Rhetorical behaviour: H is aware of insincerity but misses rhetorical behaviour:

S- H SH HS- SHS- HSH SHSH HSHS+ jkjkjkjkj

A A R H U S U N I V E R S I T Y

78

Scandinavian Institute

Ole Togeby, Pragmatics of deception Interpersonal deception: Jan. 26-27

Presupposition failures:

Rhetorical behaviour: H misses both rhetorical behaviour and insincerity:

S- H SH HS+ SHS- HSH SHSH HSHS+

A A R H U S U N I V E R S I T Y

79

Scandinavian Institute

Ole Togeby, Pragmatics of deception Interpersonal deception: Jan. 26-27

Presupposition failures

Sincerity : S+ Insincerity: S-, marked with blue Mistakes: false beliefs about the other party, marked with red:

S- & HS+ or H- & SH+ … One-up-ness: situation when one party is mistaken, the other party is one-up,

marked with green Communicative balance: no party is mistaken Non-solidarity (ordinary): S presupposes something but nevertheless assumes that

H does not recognize it, marked with yellow: S+ & SH- or S- & SH+ Rhetorical behaviour: S is not sincere and expects H to be aware of this:

S- & SHS- Feigning, whenever S believes that H is mistaken, marked with violet: S- & SHS+

and SH- & SHSH+ Suspicion of mistakes: H- & HSH+ ; of deception: HS- & HSHS+

A A R H U S U N I V E R S I T Y

80

Scandinavian Institute

Ole Togeby, Pragmatics of deception Interpersonal deception: Jan. 26-27

Presupposition failures: fun

S makes fun of H: S insincere, no mistakes, no solidarity

S- H+ SH+ HS- SHS- HSH+ SHSH+ HSHS- “I can heartily recommend the Gestapo to anyone”. PR: the declaration and Freud’s addition are cooperating, the latter being

stronger than the former.

A A R H U S U N I V E R S I T Y

81

Scandinavian Institute

Ole Togeby, Pragmatics of deception Interpersonal deception: Jan. 26-27

Presupposition failures:

Stylistic behaviour: cynicism: S- H- SH- HS- SHS- HSH- SHSH- HSHS- The Emperor shivered, for he suspected they were

right. But he thought, "This procession has got to go on." So he walked more proudly than ever, as his noblemen held high the train that wasn't there at all.

A A R H U S U N I V E R S I T Y

82

Scandinavian Institute

Ole Togeby, Pragmatics of deception Interpersonal deception: Jan. 26-27

Presupposition failures:

Bullying: no mistakes, no solidarity, no suspicion S+ H- SH- HS+ SHS+ HSH- SHSH- HSHS+ When did you stop beating your wife

A A R H U S U N I V E R S I T Y

83

Scandinavian Institute

Ole Togeby, Pragmatics of deception Interpersonal deception: Jan. 26-27

Deception

Deception, whenever S believes that H is mistaken, marked with violet:

S- H S H SH HS SH- HS SHS+ HSH SHS HSH SHSH HSHS SHSH+ HSHS

A A R H U S U N I V E R S I T Y

84

Scandinavian Institute

Ole Togeby, Pragmatics of deception Interpersonal deception: Jan. 26-27

Deception

Deception, achieved: Deception, aborted S- H S- H SH HS+ SH HS- SHS+ HSH SHS+ HSH SHSH HSHS SHSH HSHS

A A R H U S U N I V E R S I T Y

85

Scandinavian Institute

Ole Togeby, Pragmatics of deception Interpersonal deception: Jan. 26-27

Deception

"Don't hesitate to tell us what you think of it," said one of the weavers. H: The Emperor; PR: ‘there is some cloth on the loom’

Deception, achieved (S double one-up): S- H-

SH- HS+ SHS+ HSH+ SHSH+ HSHS+

A A R H U S U N I V E R S I T Y

86

Scandinavian Institute

Ole Togeby, Pragmatics of deception Interpersonal deception: Jan. 26-27

Deception

Deception, achieved, and mistake (no one-up): S- H- SH+ HS+ SHS+ HSH+ SHSH+ HSHS+

Everyone in the streets and the windows said, "Oh, how fine are the Emperor's new clothes! Don't they fit him to perfection? And see his long train!“ PRESUPPOSED: THE CLOTHES EXIST; HEARERS: EVERYONE IN THE STREETS

A A R H U S U N I V E R S I T Y

87

Scandinavian Institute

Ole Togeby, Pragmatics of deception Interpersonal deception: Jan. 26-27

Deception

Naive deception, achieved (no one-up-ness): S- H- SH+ HS+ SHS+ HSH+ SHSH+ HSHS+

"Magnificent," said the two officials already duped. "Just look, Your Majesty, what colours! What a design!" PRESUPPOSED: THERE IS SOME CLOTH;

A A R H U S U N I V E R S I T Y

88

Scandinavian Institute

Ole Togeby, Pragmatics of deception Interpersonal deception: Jan. 26-27

Deception

Naïve, abortive deception, (H one-up twice): S- H- SH+ HS- SHS+ HSH+ SHSH+ HSHS+

"What's this?" thought the Emperor. "I can't see anything. This is terrible! Am I a fool? Am I unfit to be the Emperor? What a thing to happen to me of all

people!

- Oh! It's very pretty, “PR: there is some cloth; H: the weavers

A A R H U S U N I V E R S I T Y

89

Scandinavian Institute

Ole Togeby, Pragmatics of deception Interpersonal deception: Jan. 26-27

Deception

Deception, achieved (S one-up three times): S+ H- SH- HS- SHS- HSH+

SHSH+ HSHS+

To the Emperor he said, "It held me spellbound.“ PR: spellbound menas: ‘I COULDN’T SEE ANYTHING’.

Translation better (more funny) than the original: Ja, det er ganske allerkaereste

A A R H U S U N I V E R S I T Y

90

Scandinavian Institute

Ole Togeby, Pragmatics of deception Interpersonal deception: Jan. 26-27

Deception

Suspicion of mistakes: H- HSH+ Suspicion of deception: HS- HSHS+ S H- S H SH HS SH HS- SHS HSH+ SHS HSH SHSH HSHS SHSH HSHS+

A A R H U S U N I V E R S I T Y

91

Scandinavian Institute

Ole Togeby, Pragmatics of deception Interpersonal deception: Jan. 26-27

V. False implicatures

I. Introduction II. Text interpretation III. Communication failures IV. Presupposition failures

V. False implicatures

A A R H U S U N I V E R S I T Y

92

Scandinavian Institute

Ole Togeby, Pragmatics of deception Interpersonal deception: Jan. 26-27

Types of false information

Information Taken for granted Stated

What is pronounced

Infelicitous names: obscurity

Infelicitous predicates: obscurity

What is said in the proposition

Infelicitous reference: obscurity

False predication is a blatant lie (unlawful) or a mistake

What is communicated

False presupposition forms deception

False implicature could be called leading stray (seduction)

A A R H U S U N I V E R S I T Y

93

Scandinavian Institute

Ole Togeby, Pragmatics of deception Interpersonal deception: Jan. 26-27

False implicatures are not deceptions. I suggest to call such examples leading astray; it is not unlawful, and can not be accounted for by the SH+ notational system.

False implicatures are the stuff jokes are made of

A A R H U S U N I V E R S I T Y

94

Scandinavian Institute

Ole Togeby, Pragmatics of deception Interpersonal deception: Jan. 26-27

False implicatures

Test question With what body part do you make your thinking? IMPLICATED: ‘We don’t know’

Lie With my head IMPLICATED: ‘I am not a fool’

Speak the truth I used this one (pointing at his fist) PRESUPPOSED: ‘You think by the fist’

A A R H U S U N I V E R S I T Y

95

Scandinavian Institute

Ole Togeby, Pragmatics of deception Interpersonal deception: Jan. 26-27

Mistakes

Speak the truth, but mistaken I used this one (pointing at his fist) PR: ‘The power to think is located in the fist’

S+ H- SH+ HS- SHS+ HSH- SHSH+ HSHS-

A A R H U S U N I V E R S I T Y

96

Scandinavian Institute

Ole Togeby, Pragmatics of deception Interpersonal deception: Jan. 26-27

False implicatures: decoys in jokes

In texts such as jokes, puns, short stories and detective novels, the speaker has seductively (but not lying) implicated certain trivial but untrue state of affaires, that members of the audience more or less unconsciously have integrated in their mental model of the situation talked about. These seducing implicatures are called decoys.

In the last sentence but one members of the audience realize that they have met a dead end. They cannot integrate all information they have been told and hold as true, in one consistent mental model. There are self-contradictions.

A A R H U S U N I V E R S I T Y

97

Scandinavian Institute

Ole Togeby, Pragmatics of deception Interpersonal deception: Jan. 26-27

Punch-lines

Then, at the punch-line, they are forced to make a reversal (peripeti) in their mental model building, to abandon their first interpretation and reinterpret the whole story.

When hearing the punch-line, they will have an aha-experience of what, contrary to what they thought, is the truth about the situation talked about, an experience that is immediate, intuitive and evident.

Simon Borchmann 2005

A A R H U S U N I V E R S I T Y

98

Scandinavian Institute

Ole Togeby, Pragmatics of deception Interpersonal deception: Jan. 26-27

Decoys - Dead endsDead ends – Evidential reversal

‘When I was in Vienna twenty years ago,’ she began, ‘a pretty boy with big blue eyes made a great stir there by dancing on a rope blindfolded. He danced with wonderful grace and skill, and the blindfolding was genuine, the cloth being tied around his eyes by a person out of the audience. His performance was the great sensation of the season, and he was sent for to dance before the Emperor and Empress, the archdukes and archduchesses, and the court.

A A R H U S U N I V E R S I T Y

99

Scandinavian Institute

Ole Togeby, Pragmatics of deception Interpersonal deception: Jan. 26-27

The Blue-eyed Boy

The great oculist, Professor Heimholz, was present. He had been sent for by the Emperor, since everybody was discussing the problem of clairvoyance.

But in the end of the show he rose up and called out: “Your Majesty,” he said, in great agitation, “and your Imperial Highnesses, this is all humbug, and a cheat.”this is all humbug, and a cheat.”

“It cannot be humbug,” said the court oculist, “I have myself tied the cloth around the boy’s eyes most conscientiously.”

A A R H U S U N I V E R S I T Y

100

Scandinavian Institute

Ole Togeby, Pragmatics of deception Interpersonal deception: Jan. 26-27

The Blue-eyed Boy

“It is all humbug and a cheatIt is all humbug and a cheat," the great professor indignantly insisted. “That child was born blind.” ’

Isak Dinesen 1934: “The Deluge at Nordeney” in Seven Gothic Tales

A A R H U S U N I V E R S I T Y

101

Scandinavian Institute

Ole Togeby, Pragmatics of deception Interpersonal deception: Jan. 26-27

References

Aristoteles (350 BC): Poetics Borchmann, Simon, 2005: Funktionel tekstteori og fiktivt fortællende tekster med refleksiv funktion,

København

Bergler, Edmond 1956: Laughter and the Sense of Humor, New York Carston, Robyn 2002: Thoughts and Utterances. The Pragmatics of Explicit Communication, Oxford:

Blackwell Publishing. Freud, Sigmund (1906) 1979: Der Witz und seine Beziehung zum Unbewussten, Frankfurt am Main Grice, H.P. (1967) 1975: ”Logic and conversation” in Cole, Peter, and Jerry Morgan, 1975: Syntax and

Semantics, vol 3, Speech Acts, New York: Academic Press Peter Harder & Christian Kock 1976: The Theory of Presupposition Failure, København: Akademisk

Forlag Kant, Immanuel (1781) 1996: Kritik der reinen Vernunft, Frankfurt am Main Koestler, Arthur 1964: The Act of Creation, London Togeby, Ole 2003: Fungerer denne sætning? Funktionel dansk sproglære, København Zijderveld, A. 1976: Humor und Gesellschaft. Eine Soziologie des Humors und des Lachens, Graz Wittgenstein, Ludwig 1969: On Certainty, London Yule, George 1996: Pragmatics, Oxford

A A R H U S U N I V E R S I T Y

102

Scandinavian Institute

Ole Togeby, Pragmatics of deception Interpersonal deception: Jan. 26-27

A A R H U S U N I V E R S I T Y

103

Scandinavian Institute

Ole Togeby, Pragmatics of deception Interpersonal deception: Jan. 26-27

Remaining Problems

The Harder & Kock theory is very powerful predicting 255 different types of presupposition failure (besides the standard situation). I have shown you some exemplified types, but there are other types predicted, but which I have not found yet. Here comes my preliminary analysis of some of them.

A A R H U S U N I V E R S I T Y

104

Scandinavian Institute

Ole Togeby, Pragmatics of deception Interpersonal deception: Jan. 26-27

The Harder & Kock theory is very powerful predicting 255 different types of presupposition failure (besides the standard situation). I have shown you some exemplified types, but there are other types, predicted that I have not found yet. Here comes some of them:

A A R H U S U N I V E R S I T Y

105

Scandinavian Institute

Ole Togeby, Pragmatics of deception Interpersonal deception: Jan. 26-27

To trick someone

A candidate at the examination desk draws a question, and whispers to the examiner while the co-examiner overhears it:

This is not the question we have arranged I should have H: the examiner; PR: ‘we have arranged another question’

S- H- insincerity SH- HS+ SHS- HSH+ feigning suspicion of mistake

SHSH+ HSHS+ deception

A A R H U S U N I V E R S I T Y

106

Scandinavian Institute

Ole Togeby, Pragmatics of deception Interpersonal deception: Jan. 26-27

Cheating

A candidate at the examination desk draws a question, and whispers to the examiner while the co-examiner overhears it:

This is not the question that we have arranged I should have H: the co-examiner; PR: ‘we have arranged another question’

S- H- insincerity SH- HS+ non-solidarity SHS+ HSH- feigning SHSH+ HSHS+ deception

A A R H U S U N I V E R S I T Y

107

Scandinavian Institute

Ole Togeby, Pragmatics of deception Interpersonal deception: Jan. 26-27

Deception

Perfidy: S- H SH- HS SHS- HSH SHSH+ HSHS ???????????????

A A R H U S U N I V E R S I T Y

108

Scandinavian Institute

Ole Togeby, Pragmatics of deception Interpersonal deception: Jan. 26-27

Presupposition failures:

Manipulation (e. g.: bullying) S+ H SH- HS SHS+ HSH SHSH+ HSHS ????????????????

A A R H U S U N I V E R S I T Y

109

Scandinavian Institute

Ole Togeby, Pragmatics of deception Interpersonal deception: Jan. 26-27

A case studyBLADR VIDERE!

Der står noget meget mere spændende på næste side.

Havde du bare gjort, som vi bad om.

Så ville du ikke have anet noget om de nye Volkswagen modeller med DK-pakker. Du ville ikke have vidst, at en DK-pakke er en vifte af originalt, fabriksmonteret ekstraudstyr. F.eks. til en Golf. Den omfatter Climatic aircondition, justerbar varme i forsæderne, opvarmelige skrinklerdyser og forlygte sprinklere. Havde du bare bladret videre, ville du have troet, at den slags luksus fordyrer en Golf med mange tusinde kroner. Det er jo ikke gratis at køre på 1. klasse. Især ikke her i landet. Så en merpris på 20.000 kr. må siges at være rimelig, ikke? Men nu er du nået så langt, at du godt kan få sandheden at vide. Vores tyske leverandør har pålagt os at sælge hele pakken for 5.000,-. Det er 15.000 kr. lige ned i foret. Eller lige ud af vinduet – alt efter hvilken side man ser det fra.

A A R H U S U N I V E R S I T Y

110

Scandinavian Institute

Ole Togeby, Pragmatics of deception Interpersonal deception: Jan. 26-27

• BLADR VIDERE! • Der står noget meget mere spændende på

næste side. • Havde du bare gjort, som vi bad om.• Så ville du ikke have anet noget om de nye

Volkswagen modeller med DK-pakker. • Du ville ikke have vidst, at en DK-pakke

er en vifte af originalt, fabriksmonteret ekstraudstyr. F.eks. til en Golf. Den omfatter Climatic aircondition, justerbar varme i forsæderne, opvarmelige skrinklerdyser og forlygte sprinklere.

• Havde du bare bladret videre, ville du have troet, at den slags luksus fordyrer en Golf med mange tusinde kroner. Det er jo ikke gratis at køre på 1. klasse. Især ikke her i landet. Så en merpris på 20.000 kr. må siges at være rimelig, ikke? Men nu er du nået så langt, at du godt kan få sandheden at vide. Vores tyske leverandør har pålagt os at sælge hele pakken for 5.000,-. Det er 15.000 kr. lige ned i foret. Eller lige ud af vinduet – alt efter hvilken side man ser det fra.

• TURN OVER TO ANOTHER PAGE!• There is something much more interesting on

the next page. • If only you had done what we asked you.• Then you would not have known anything about

the new Volkswagen models (?) with DK-packages.

• You would not have known that a DK-package is a a wide range of extra accessories

• ….

• If you had turned over the page, you would have thought that this type of luxury raise the price of a Golf with many thousands of kroner …

A A R H U S U N I V E R S I T Y

111

Scandinavian Institute

Ole Togeby, Pragmatics of deception Interpersonal deception: Jan. 26-27

A case study

BLADR VIDERE! (Turn over to another page!) Here it is predicated ‘that I, the reader, will turn over the page’, and the

illocutionary force is a request to me to make it happen. The direction of fit is from word to world.

It is implicated - as in all requests - that it is in the interest of the advertiser that I, the addressee, do so

(and in this case it is indicated to be in my interest too, since – as the next sentence says: There is something much more interesting on the next page)

But I doubt if the advertiser sincerely wants me to turn over the page and not read the text – since such an advertisement is very expensive

So I take it as a sort of rhetorical behaviour, by which the advertiser communicates a request, not to skip, but to read the advertisement.

And consequently I do so.

A A R H U S U N I V E R S I T Y

112

Scandinavian Institute

Ole Togeby, Pragmatics of deception Interpersonal deception: Jan. 26-27

A case study

Havde du bare gjort, som vi bad om (If only you had done what we asked for).

It is implicated (by bare) that ‘you would have been happier if you had done what we asked for’, viz. to turn over the page,

and it is (by past tense) presupposed ’that you have not done what we asked you to do’ - and certainly I have not, I didn’t skip the ad.

This presupposition is like a punch line. It suddenly becomes evident that I have been double crossed by the advertiser; BLADR VIDERE! should have been taken at face value. I should not have stayed at the page and red this foolish ad.

And it is - even through the written medium – a feeling of being deluded by someone with whom I engage in a talk exchange. The advertiser fooled med by a false implicature.

A A R H U S U N I V E R S I T Y

113

Scandinavian Institute

Ole Togeby, Pragmatics of deception Interpersonal deception: Jan. 26-27

A case study

Så ville du ikke have anet noget om de nye Volkswagen modeller (Then you would not have known anything about the new Volkswagen models)

This is in a way a revolution of the revolution (and we are back where we began), because it is here implicated that I would not have been happy if I had missed all that wonderful information about the cheap extra accessories to the Volkswagen.

But that is another story.

A A R H U S U N I V E R S I T Y

114

Scandinavian Institute

Ole Togeby, Pragmatics of deception Interpersonal deception: Jan. 26-27

Bladr videre (Turn over the page!) PR: ‘It is in the interest of S that H does it’

S- H- SH- HS- SHS- HSH+ (?) SHSH+ HSHS-

A A R H U S U N I V E R S I T Y

115

Scandinavian Institute

Ole Togeby, Pragmatics of deception Interpersonal deception: Jan. 26-27

Sarcasm: “I can heartily recommend the Gestapo to anyone”. H: Gestapo official. PR: ‘the two sentences cooperate; the second one being a

stronger argument than the first one to the same conclusion: ‘The Gestapo is OK’

S- H+ SH+ HS- SHS-HSH- SHSH-HSHS

A A R H U S U N I V E R S I T Y

116

Scandinavian Institute

Ole Togeby, Pragmatics of deception Interpersonal deception: Jan. 26-27

The Emperor's New Clothes A translation of Hans Christian Andersen's "Keiserens nye Klæder" by Jean Hersholt.

Many years ago there was an Emperor so exceedingly fond of new clothes that he spent all his money on being well dressed. He cared nothing about reviewing his soldiers, going to the theatre, or going for a ride in his carriage, except to show off his new clothes. He had a coat for every hour of the day, and instead of saying, as one might, about any other ruler, "The King's in council," here they always said. "The Emperor's in his dressing room."

In the great city where he lived, life was always gay. Every day many strangers came to town, and among them one day came two swindlers. They let it be known they were weavers, and they said they could weave the most magnificent fabrics imaginable. Not only were their colours and patterns uncommonly fine, but clothes made of this cloth had a wonderful way of becoming invisible to anyone who was unfit for his office, or who was unusually stupid.

"Those would be just the clothes for me," thought the Emperor. "If I wore them I would be able to discover which men in my empire are unfit for their posts. And I could tell the wise men from the fools. Yes, I certainly must get some of the stuff woven for me right away." He paid the two swindlers a large sum of money to start work at once.

A A R H U S U N I V E R S I T Y

117

Scandinavian Institute

Ole Togeby, Pragmatics of deception Interpersonal deception: Jan. 26-27

They set up two looms and pretended to weave, though there was nothing on the looms. All the finest silk and the purest old thread which they demanded went into their travelling bags, while they worked the empty looms far into the night.

"I'd like to know how those weavers are getting on with the cloth," the Emperor thought, but he felt slightly uncomfortable when he remembered that those who were unfit for their position would not be able to see the fabric. It couldn't have been that he doubted himself, yet he thought he'd rather send someone else to see how things were going. The whole town knew about the cloth's peculiar power, and all were impatient to find out how stupid their neighbours were.

"I'll send my honest old minister to the weavers," the Emperor decided. "He'll be the best one to tell me how the material looks, for he's a sensible man and no one does his duty better."

So the honest old minister went to the room where the two swindlers sat working away at their empty looms.

"Heaven help me," he thought as his eyes flew wide open, "I can't see anything at all". But he did not say so.

Both the swindlers begged him to be so kind as to come near to approve the excellent pattern, the beautiful colours. They pointed to the empty looms, and the poor old minister stared as hard as he dared. He couldn't see anything, because there was nothing to see. "Heaven have mercy," he thought. "Can it be that I'm a fool? I'd have never guessed it, and not a soul must know. Am I unfit to be the minister? It would never do to let on that I can't see the cloth."

"Don't hesitate to tell us what you think of it," said one of the weavers. "Oh, it's beautiful -it's enchanting." The old minister peered through his spectacles. "Such a pattern, what

colours!" I'll be sure to tell the Emperor how delighted I am with it." "We're pleased to hear that," the swindlers said. They proceeded to name all the colours and to explain the

intricate pattern. The old minister paid the closest attention, so that he could tell it all to the Emperor. And so he did.

A A R H U S U N I V E R S I T Y

118

Scandinavian Institute

Ole Togeby, Pragmatics of deception Interpersonal deception: Jan. 26-27

The swindlers at once asked for more money, more silk and gold thread, to get on with the weaving. But it all went into their pockets. Not a thread went into the looms, though they worked at their weaving as hard as ever.

The Emperor presently sent another trustworthy official to see how the work progressed and how soon it would be ready. The same thing happened to him that had happened to the minister. He looked and he looked, but as there was nothing to see in the looms he couldn't see anything.

"Isn't it a beautiful piece of goods?" the swindlers asked him, as they displayed and described their imaginary pattern.

"I know I'm not stupid," the man thought, "so it must be that I'm unworthy of my good office. That's strange. I mustn't let anyone find it out, though." So he praised the material he did not see. He declared he was delighted with the beautiful colours and the exquisite pattern. To the Emperor he said, "It held me spellbound."

All the town was talking of this splendid cloth, and the Emperor wanted to see it for himself while it was still in the looms. Attended by a band of chosen men, among whom were his two old trusted officials-the ones who had been to the weavers-he set out to see the two swindlers. He found them weaving with might and main, but without a thread in their looms.

"Magnificent," said the two officials already duped. "Just look, Your Majesty, what colors! What a design!" They pointed to the empty looms, each supposing that the others could see the stuff.

"What's this?" thought the Emperor. "I can't see anything. This is terrible! Am I a fool? Am I unfit to be the Emperor? What a thing to happen to me of all people! - Oh!

It's very pretty," he said. "It has my highest approval." And he nodded approbation at the empty loom. Nothing could make him say that he couldn't see anything.

A A R H U S U N I V E R S I T Y

119

Scandinavian Institute

Ole Togeby, Pragmatics of deception Interpersonal deception: Jan. 26-27

His whole retinue stared and stared. One saw no more than another, but they all joined the Emperor in exclaiming, "Oh! It's very pretty," and they advised him to wear clothes made of this wonderful cloth especially for the great procession he was soon to lead. "Magnificent! Excellent! Unsurpassed!" were bandied from mouth to mouth, and everyone did his best to seem well pleased. The Emperor gave each of the swindlers a cross to wear in his buttonhole, and the title of "Sir Weaver."

Before the procession the swindlers sat up all night and burned more than six candles, to show how busy they were finishing the Emperor's new clothes. They pretended to take the cloth off the loom. They made cuts in the air with huge scissors. And at last they said, "Now the Emperor's new clothes are ready for him."

Then the Emperor himself came with his noblest noblemen, and the swindlers each raised an arm as if they were holding something. They said, "These are the trousers, here's the coat, and this is the mantle," naming each garment. "All of them are as light as a spider web. One would almost think he had nothing on, but that's what makes them so fine."

"Exactly," all the noblemen agreed, though they could see nothing, for there was nothing to see.

"If Your Imperial Majesty will condescend to take your clothes off," said the swindlers, "we will help you on with your new ones here in front of the long mirror."

A A R H U S U N I V E R S I T Y

120

Scandinavian Institute

Ole Togeby, Pragmatics of deception Interpersonal deception: Jan. 26-27

The Emperor undressed, and the swindlers pretended to put his new clothes on him, one garment after another. They took him around the waist and seemed to be fastening something - that was his train-as the Emperor turned round and round before the looking glass.

"How well Your Majesty's new clothes look. Aren't they becoming!" He heard on all sides, "That pattern, so perfect! Those colours, so suitable! It is a magnificent outfit."

Then the minister of public processions announced: "Your Majesty's canopy is waiting outside." "Well, I'm supposed to be ready," the Emperor said, and turned again for one last look in the mirror. "It is

a remarkable fit, isn't it?" He seemed to regard his costume with the greatest interest. The noblemen who were to carry his train stooped low and reached for the floor as if they were picking

up his mantle. Then they pretended to lift and hold it high. They didn't dare admit they had nothing to hold.

So off went the Emperor in procession under his splendid canopy. Everyone in the streets and the windows said, "Oh, how fine are the Emperor's new clothes! Don't they fit him to perfection? And see his long train!" Nobody would confess that he couldn't see anything, for that would prove him either unfit for his position, or a fool. No costume the Emperor had worn before was ever such a complete success.

"But he hasn't got anything on," a little child said. "Did you ever hear such innocent prattle?" said its father. And one person whispered to another what the

child had said, "He hasn't anything on. A child says he hasn't anything on." "But he hasn't got anything on!" the whole town cried out at last. The Emperor shivered, for he suspected they were right. But he thought, "This procession has got to go

on." So he walked more proudly than ever, as his noblemen held high the train that wasn't there at all.

A A R H U S U N I V E R S I T Y

121

Scandinavian Institute

Ole Togeby, Pragmatics of deception Interpersonal deception: Jan. 26-27

Example 3: Three fools

Three fools should pass a test to be discharged from the madhouse. The first one was asked: With what body part do you make your thinking? He pointed at his fist and said: I use this one, and he was sent back to the madhouse. The second one was asked the same; he pointed at his fist and was sent back to the madhouse.

Then the third fool was asked; he said: With my head and he was therefore discharged. Then they asked him: How could you figure it out? He pointed at his fist and said:

I used this one.

A A R H U S U N I V E R S I T Y

122

Scandinavian Institute

Ole Togeby, Pragmatics of deception Interpersonal deception: Jan. 26-27

Example 4: Examination

A candidate at the examination desk draws a question, and whispers to the examiner while the co-examiner overhears it:

This question is not one that we have arranged I should have. This is not the question that we have arranged that I should have

Example 5: The Bricklayer A poor bricklayer brought a big lunch pack with him, but he was embarrassed only to be able

to afford one type of filling for his sandwiches, viz. cheese. So when he had finished nine cheese sandwiches and set about eating the tenth and last one, he said:

Now it is time for the cheese sandwich.

A A R H U S U N I V E R S I T Y

123

Scandinavian Institute

Ole Togeby, Pragmatics of deception Interpersonal deception: Jan. 26-27

Example 6: Freud

In 1938 the Nazis had promised Sigmund Freud an exit visa from Austria on condition that he sign a declaration purporting that he had been ”treated by the German authorities and particularly by the Gestapo with all the respect and consideration due to my scientific reputation”.

When the Gestapo official brought the document for his signature, Freud asked if he would be allowed to add one more sentence. Obviously sure of his one-up position, the official agreed, and Freud wrote in his own handwriting:

“I can heartily recommend the Gestapo to anyone”.

A A R H U S U N I V E R S I T Y

124

Scandinavian Institute

Ole Togeby, Pragmatics of deception Interpersonal deception: Jan. 26-27

Deception

Insincerity: S- Mistakes: false beliefs about the other party: S- & HS+ or H- & SH+ One-up-ness: only one party is mistaken, the other party is one-up,

otherwise: Communicative balance: no party is mistaken Non-solidarity (ordinary): S presupposes something but nevertheless

assumes that H does not recognize it, marked with: S+ & SH- or S- & SH+ Rhetorical behaviour, acting, irony: S is not sincere and expects H to be

aware of this: S- & SHS- Feigning and deception, whenever S believes that H is mistaken:

S- & SHS+ and SH- & SHSH+

Suspicion of mistakes: H- & HSH+ ; of deception: HS- & HSHS+