18 Ongoing Discussion of Francis Crick and Christoph Koch (Vol. 2, No. 1): Commentary by Mortimer...

download 18 Ongoing Discussion of Francis Crick and Christoph Koch (Vol. 2, No. 1): Commentary by Mortimer Ostow (New York)

of 6

Transcript of 18 Ongoing Discussion of Francis Crick and Christoph Koch (Vol. 2, No. 1): Commentary by Mortimer...

  • 7/25/2019 18 Ongoing Discussion of Francis Crick and Christoph Koch (Vol. 2, No. 1): Commentary by Mortimer Ostow (New

    1/6

    This article was downloaded by: [Adelphi University]On: 23 August 2014, At: 00:26Publisher: RoutledgeInforma Ltd Registered in England and Wales Registered Number: 1072954 Registered office: MortimerHouse, 37-41 Mortimer Street, London W1T 3JH, UK

    Neuropsychoanalysis: An Interdisciplinary Journalfor Psychoanalysis and the NeurosciencesPublication details, including instructions for authors and subscription information:http://www.tandfonline.com/loi/rnpa20

    Ongoing Discussion of Francis Crick and ChristophKoch (Vol. 2, No. 1): Commentary by Mortimer Ostow(New York)Mortimer Ostow

    a

    a5021 Iselin Avenue, Riverdale, NY 10471, e-mail:

    Published online: 09 Jan 2014.

    To cite this article:Mortimer Ostow (2001) Ongoing Discussion of Francis Crick and Christoph Koch (Vol. 2, No. 1):Commentary by Mortimer Ostow (New York), Neuropsychoanalysis: An Interdisciplinary Journal for Psychoanalysis and the

    Neurosciences, 3:1, 107-111, DOI: 10.1080/15294145.2001.10773343

    To link to this article: http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/15294145.2001.10773343

    PLEASE SCROLL DOWN FOR ARTICLE

    Taylor & Francis makes every effort to ensure the accuracy of all the information (the Content) containedin the publications on our platform. However, Taylor & Francis, our agents, and our licensors make norepresentations or warranties whatsoever as to the accuracy, completeness, or suitability for any purpose ofthe Content. Any opinions and views expressed in this publicationare the opinions and views of the authors,and are not the views of or endorsed by Taylor & Francis. The accuracy of the Content should not be reliedupon and should be independently verified with primary sources of information. Taylor and Francis shallnot be liable for any losses, actions, claims, proceedings, demands, costs, expenses, damages, and otherliabilities whatsoever or howsoever caused arising directly or indirectly in connection with, in relation to orarising out of the use of the Content.

    This article may be used for research, teaching, and private study purposes. Any substantial or systematicreproduction, redistribution, reselling, loan, sub-licensing, systematic supply, or distribution in anyform to anyone is expressly forbidden. Terms & Conditions of access and use can be found at http://www.tandfonline.com/page/terms-and-conditions

    http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/15294145.2001.10773343http://www.tandfonline.com/action/showCitFormats?doi=10.1080/15294145.2001.10773343http://www.tandfonline.com/page/terms-and-conditionshttp://www.tandfonline.com/page/terms-and-conditionshttp://dx.doi.org/10.1080/15294145.2001.10773343http://www.tandfonline.com/action/showCitFormats?doi=10.1080/15294145.2001.10773343http://www.tandfonline.com/loi/rnpa20
  • 7/25/2019 18 Ongoing Discussion of Francis Crick and Christoph Koch (Vol. 2, No. 1): Commentary by Mortimer Ostow (New

    2/6

    Ongoing Discussion Vol. 2, No.1

    Ongoing Discussion of Francis Crick and C hristoph Koch Vol. 2,

    No.1 :

    Commentary by

    Mortimer

    Ostow New York)

    1 7

    The following is intended as a contribution to the dis

    cussions

    of

    consciousness, responding to the target

    article by Crick and Koch. In the interest of providing

    some clinical input to the subject, I offer here some

    chapter headings.

    If

    we follow the suggestions

    of

    Panksepp 1998),

    Damasio 1999), and Watt 2000), we may start with

    the assumption that the evolutionary rudiments of sen

    tience appeared as components of instinct. Presumably

    the stimulus or need for instinctual response elicited

    a demand felt

    as

    some kind

    of

    uncomfortable sensa

    tion, and presumably the instinctual response was ac

    companied by a complementary agreeable sensation

    that erased the former.

    Presumably too, was the effect

    of

    this advance to

    supplement the hard-wired instinctual systems, as well

    as those systems modified by the flexibility achieved

    by susceptibility to conditioning, so as to make it pos

    sible to select one or more potentially optimal re

    sponses in preference to others. That process entailed

    the capacity to anticipate the consequences of each,

    that is, to imagine, and, on a higher evolutionary

    plane, to fantasy. These mechanisms supplement but

    do not replace the hard-wired and conditionable in

    stincts that still preempt behavior in the presence

    of

    adequate or unusually intense stimuli.

    These are simple speculations, based upon rea

    sonable assumptions, and they lead us to certain con

    clusions about conscious experience in the

    contemporary human. Conscious mentation must in

    clude the sensitivity to certain biological including

    social) needs, the opportunity to dispel unpleasant

    stimuli by taking certain actions that will, in turn, re

    place them with agreeable experiences; and the ability

    to consider possible responses in order to select the

    optimal response. Such a mechanism would provide

    the capacity for imagery, imagination, fantasy, and the

    ability to anticipate the future.

    Fantasy has important clinical significance be

    cause it guides the selection of response, but also be

    cause it is often used to substitute for action. It c an

    do so because as trial action it probably elicits an elab-

    Mortimer Ostow, M.D., is President of the Psychoanalytic Research

    and Development Fund, and Cochairman of its Study Group on Neurosci

    ence, Psychopharmacology and Psychoanalysis.

    oration

    of

    appropriate neurotransmitters in the same

    pattern though in much smaller amounts, than the full

    action would. Conscious affective selection requires

    an accumulation of stored relevant memories. These

    memories must be available for recall on appropriate

    occasions. However, the durability of memory proba

    bly varies with its age and other constraints of

    re

    cording.

    We come to the subject of attention. Needless to

    say, one is conscious

    of

    whatever is attended to, but

    some images and events can become conscious even

    when they are not the objects

    of

    attention. They are

    sometimes said to be a t the periphery

    of

    conscious

    ness. Not all percepts and memories can be conscious

    simultaneously. Those become conscious that either

    demand attention by virtue of their intensity or imme

    diacy, promising instant or important gratification or

    threat, or those that are called for by current thought,

    imagination, or problem solving. What neuroscientists

    have called procedural memory records events that

    were consciously perceived when they occurred, when

    attention was required. However, with practice, atten

    tion is no longer required. But attention can restore

    them to consciousness at any moment.

    The psychoanalytic clinician

    is

    concerned with

    memories that cannot be retrieved simply by at

    tempting to focus attention on them. That is, attention

    may a sk

    for

    them, but it cannot liberate them into

    consciousness. Clinical experience teaches us that

    these memories were laid down very early, or were

    associated with significant trauma, or were repressed

    in the course of

    development, or were repressed be

    cause they were involved in neurotic conflict. We

    know of their existence because they appear directly

    or symbolically in dreams, or because they can be

    recaptured during the course

    of

    analysis.

    Not all fantasies are intended to anticipate the

    consequence of choice of behavior strategies. Some

    are created so as to organize the memories

    of past

    experience. These fo rm a myth of greater or lesser

    degree of veridicality that offers a mythical explana

    tion of the course of the individual s life, and antici

    pates his future. We speak of these as organizing

    fantasies; they are not usually consciously known by

    the subject, but appear often in the course of analysis,

    opposed by stronger or weaker repressive forces.

  • 7/25/2019 18 Ongoing Discussion of Francis Crick and Christoph Koch (Vol. 2, No. 1): Commentary by Mortimer Ostow (New

    3/6

    8

    Performing all

    of

    these functions and involved in

    all

    of

    these activities, consciousness yet is called upon

    to present a seamless aspect, to continue without inter

    ruption to integrate all percepts, both those arising ex

    ternally and those arising internally, into a continuous

    surface. It is called upon to exclude impressions from

    any source, that are not compatible with the current

    account of events in the world, and yet not to ignore

    impressions of serious significance. Hypnagogic and

    hypnopompic phenomena are examples of intrusive

    impressions that are usually excluded from conscious

    ness. Even dream consciousness, which seems to oc

    cur without the mobilization

    of

    attention, attempts to

    rationalize and organize the impressions that intrude

    into dreams. For example, an external sound or light

    or a touch or insect contact, or an excretory stimulus,

    is usually seamlessly integrated into the dream. Freud

    spoke

    of

    a censor that excludes the repressed from

    consciousness.

    Hartmann spoke

    of

    the synthetic function

    of

    the

    ego; that is, the tendency of

    the conscious ego to inte

    grate impressions into a consistent whole, eliminating

    inconsistencies and arbitrary sequences. These

    smoothing tendencies often create illusions. The post

    hoc propter hoc fallacy is a logical illusion born

    of

    the

    need for causality, a principle described by Herman

    Nunberg 1959 . The scientific method was devised

    for the purpose of overcoming illusory verification of

    one s

    expectations. We speak

    of

    these

    as

    functions

    of

    the ego but they seem to be functions of consciousness.

    Despite its tendency to distort data so

    as

    to protect its

    integrated picture, consciousness is expected to distin

    guish between the real and the unreal, the familiar and

    the unfamiliar.

    Consciousness also takes the self as its object,

    including the very function of consciousness. Neuro

    scientists attempt to deal with this self-reflective func

    tion

    of

    consciousness. Psychoanalysts speak

    of

    self

    observation. I have suggested that we can recognize

    three types

    of

    self-observation. Primary self-observa

    tion consists of taking note

    of

    one s subjective feel

    ings; secondary self-observation consists of noting

    one s objective qualities; tertiary self-observation con

    sists of regarding the impressions of one s self

    as

    seen

    by outside observers. I have found that in general, the

    self-observation

    of

    the depressed patient is primary;

    the self-observation

    of

    the manic is tertiary; and sec

    ondary self-observation occurs only in the absence of

    both mood deviations. These regularities can help in

    the monitoring

    of

    psychiatric drug therapy. At the ex

    tremes

    of

    mood deviation, primary and tertiary self

    observation may become delusional hypochondria in

    Mortimer Ostow

    the former instance and delusional paranoia in the

    latter.

    Some neuroscientists consider consciousness and

    affect not intrinsically associated,

    as

    opposed to others

    Panksepp, 1998 who consider consciousness essen

    tially an instrument for appreciating affect. As a clini

    cian, it seems

    to

    me that every conscious state carries

    its own affect. The affect need not be a distinct phasic

    feeling change; it may be only a relatively constant

    underlying mood.

    Part

    of

    the neuropsychoanalytic problem is that

    investigators speak

    of

    affect and

    of

    pleasure and pain

    or unpleasure nonspecifically,

    as

    though what is true

    of

    one affective state is true

    of

    all. I have been con

    tending for some time that a taxonomy of affect is

    needed for clarifying the issues.

    Instinctual behavior carries specific affects.

    f

    we

    address ourselves to the phasic instincts such as the

    sexual, nutritive, defensive, and thermal homeostasis

    promoting instincts, we can recognize several types

    of

    affect. The instinctual sequence is initiated by an

    experience of discomfort specific to the instinct being

    triggered, whether hunger, thirst, danger, pain, exces

    sive warmth or cold, or felt need for sexual experience.

    There follows an interval of appetitive striving, a

    search for opportunities for gratification

    of

    the felt

    need, characterized by its specific affect, similar to

    and anticipating the consummatory feeling that fol

    lows. The strongest affective experiences are associ

    ated with the consummation

    of

    the instinct, but the

    phase

    of

    relaxation that follows the consummation

    carries still another affective experience, pleasant sa

    tiety.

    The social instincts carry their own set

    of

    affects.

    Establishing and breaking attachment are each accom

    panied by specific affects, the former gratifying and

    the latter distressing. The need for attachment may be

    considered a tonic rather than a phasic instinct, and

    the affects accompanying it are relatively enduring

    rather than fleeting such

    as

    that accompanying the or

    gasm. But one may recognize also affective states that

    drive efforts to establish a desired status in society

    and to maintain it. All complementary affects are elic

    ited by failure to do so. These include pride in the first

    instance and shame in the second.

    elf esteem

    is a

    term that designates one s affective estimate

    of

    one s

    status within society.

    Mood

    is

    still another important and omnipresent

    affect. It seems to recede when other stronger and

    phasic affects supersede it, and recurs when these oth

    ers subside. Good mood is encouraged by success

    of

    instinctual endeavors, and bad mood ensues in the

  • 7/25/2019 18 Ongoing Discussion of Francis Crick and Christoph Koch (Vol. 2, No. 1): Commentary by Mortimer Ostow (New

    4/6

    Ongoing Discussion Vol. 2, No.1

    presence

    of

    failure

    of

    these and the prevalence

    of

    dis

    tressing experiences.

    It is mood, I believe, that is established by the

    action

    of

    Panksepp s 1998) seeking system, driven

    primarily by dopamine transmitters, and active always

    during both waking life and sleep, including dreaming.

    It is mood too t hat is abnormal in mani c-dep ressiv e

    illness, and it is mood that is affected by pharmacolog

    ical agents that are u sed to treat the several forms

    of

    this illness. They are essentially mood regulators that

    does not include the sedative and antiseizure drugs).

    In ad dition to the affects in ciden t to instinctual

    behavior, and in addition to mood, we recognize cer

    tain affectiv e states that seem independ en t o f both. I

    refer here to the experience of humor, to the pleasures

    of

    listening to music or the enjoyment of any aesthetic

    experience, the feeling

    of

    the uncanny, among others.

    There are th rills, su rprises, an d states of confusion.

    Each

    of

    these affective states calls for analysis

    of

    its

    n ature and of its relatio n to the instinctively b ased

    affects. With a little ingenuity, I believe they can each

    be assigned their proper classification. Some of these

    affective states I relate to the experien ce o f crossin g

    categ orical b oun daries. Fo r example, humor is ap

    preci at ed when o ne uses a word or expression ordi

    narily tho ug ht

    of in one logical category, in a

    surprisingly different one. The pun, which is an ele

    mentary form of humor, is the simplest example. How

    ever, fairly sophisticated examples

    of

    wit also

    fit

    that description.

    Accordingly, when we speak of pleasure we must

    acknowledge that there are a number

    of

    different vari

    eties of pleasure: the pleasure associated with anticipa

    tory appetitive activities; the pleasure associated with

    consummation; the pleasure associated with postcon

    summatory relaxation; the pleasure associated with el

    evated mood; the pleasure associated with some

    category-crossing moods such as humor and pleasant

    surprise; the pleasure associated with aesthetic activi

    ties; the pleasure associated with establishing and

    maintaining attachments, either personal or social; the

    pleasure associated with problem solving. Panksepp

    relates problem solving to appetitive activity since it

    represents instinctual attempts to discern threats and

    discover opportunities for pleasurable gratification

    1998).

    Similarly, there are various categories of pain in

    cluding the pain

    of

    the stimuli to instinctual gratifica

    tion; the pain of

    frustration or initiated instinctual

    behavior; the pain of depressive mood; the pain of loss

    of attachment, the discomfort of sleep deprivation.

    Spiritual experiences are usually pleasant but may be

    9

    painful; for example, when, under the influence of a

    depressive mood, they result in the fear

    of

    being vis

    ited by malignant spirits, ghosts, or revenants.

    Still dealing with the various states

    of

    conscious

    ness, we cannot ignore the several important manifes

    tations

    of

    detachment; that is, alterations of affective

    consciousness that alter the impression

    of

    one s dis

    tance from the world that is normally perceived as

    real. Dep erso nalization is the feeling of being es

    tranged from oneself. It is not merely tertiary self

    o bserv atio n, wh ich is reg arding o ne s s elf and one s

    attributes as others would see them. Depersonalization

    is the feeling of no long er being o ne s familiar self.

    What has been called derealization is not really a loss

    of

    the sense

    of

    reality, but loss of the sense of familiar

    ity with reality, estran gemen t from it. Deja vu, o n the

    other hand, is an illusory sense

    of

    familiarity. It is not

    a specific memory of having done something before.

    One can usually not specify when or under what cir

    cumstances one has done it or been there, which would

    imply a previous exposure to the scene. Since these

    phenomena occur during temporal lobe seizures, it is

    lik ely that the sense of familiarity involves temporal

    lobe function. Recent observations that familiar and

    unfamiliar faces are recorded at slightly different

    p oin ts in and aro un d the fu sifo rm gyrus, seem to cor

    roborate that impression. However, these detachment

    p heno men a o ccur also in the intact individual. They

    h av e b een d escrib ed as resp on ses to anxiety. I am n ot

    sure that that conclusion is always correct.

    Still within the realm of normality, we find states

    of

    detachment complemented by attachment to virtual

    objects.

    Of

    these, the most definitive is the my stical

    episode. Here the subject, usually psychiatrically nor

    mal, describes a direct and immediate experience of

    hallucinated or felt contact with a supernatural object,

    a deity, o r aspect of nature or the cosmos. I call this

    a virtual object because it is a personified representa

    tion of a subjectively felt psychic influence. The mysti

    cal state is o ften an ticipated by a state of depression,

    anxiety, or loneliness, and results in a feeling

    of

    grati

    fying achievement.

    I see mysticism as one extreme of a series,

    namely, awe, spirituality, and mysticism. Awe is pri

    marily elicited by en coun tering a sight o r sou nd that

    seems larger than life, that engenders a feeling of being

    small o r in significant in the p resen ce of something

    grand, cosmic, portentous. The affect of being awed

    may be a gratifying, comforting one, or an intimidat

    ing, frightening one. Although itis not conventionally

    attribu ted to awe, I believ e that a sense of familiarity

    contributes an element as well. When we enco un ter

  • 7/25/2019 18 Ongoing Discussion of Francis Crick and Christoph Koch (Vol. 2, No. 1): Commentary by Mortimer Ostow (New

    5/6

    an awesome experience, we feel personally related

    to it.

    Spirituality refers to an experience intermediate

    between awe and the full mystical experience. The

    spiritual experience is a feeling of transcendence,

    of

    contact with supernatural entities or forces. It differs

    from awe in that one is not merely impressed by the

    perceived magnificent display, but one feels the influ

    ence of a source of comfort and inspiration. (Note that

    both the word

    spiritu lity

    and

    inspir tion

    are derived

    from the Latin root

    spir r

    meaning to breathe. The

    spirit, in both cases, is something that may be

    breathed in.)

    All these are alterations

    of

    consciousness associ

    ated with strong affects. Since awe is usually inspired

    by exposure to larger than life displays, I guess that

    awe reproduces the child s earliest experiences of

    mother. Mountains, oceans, tremendous edifices,

    sweet melodies, loud rumbling noises, all suggest the

    infant s earliest impressions

    of

    caretakers. These ex

    periences are not remembered, probably because at

    that early point, the brain has not yet acquired the

    capacity to retain discrete iconic or phonic memories.

    It may, however, be capable of recording and retaining

    the affects associated with these. When these affects

    are retrieved later in life, they are virtually ineffable,

    orphan affects. Since they all include a component of

    yearning, when invoked they encourage the impres

    sion

    of

    contact with a virtual object.

    In each of these three states, awe, spirituality, and

    mysticism, we find detachment, transcendence,

    yearning, a feeling of being in contact with a supernal,

    supernatural entity. In each case the experience may

    be preceded by anxiety or depression, loneliness, and

    followed by a sense of exaltation and exhilaration. I

    have observed that the spiritual expression especially,

    follows the death of a loved person or separation for

    other reasons.

    In the case of the spiritual and mystical experi

    ence, the feeling of detachment may proceed to the

    point

    of

    trance, a significant detachment from reality,

    complete diversion of

    attention from the real world.

    It suggests the hypnotic or hysterical trance state. Per

    haps trance is the complete diversionof attention from

    the real world to the illusory world of archaic affects,

    complemented by virtual objects suggested by these

    affects.

    Continuing with our listing of the various states

    of consciousness, we come now to hynagogic and hyp

    nopompic experiences. These have not been exten

    sively described. Mostly what are seen are images,

    somewhat distorted, varying in shape and color that

    Mortimer Ostow

    intrude into consciousness but are fugitive. When one

    attempts to attend to them, they disappear,

    as

    they do

    when one wakes fully. They give us an illustration

    of

    the organizing effect

    of

    attention

    on

    the images

    secreted

    spontaneously by memories. Sleep onset

    and offset may also be accompanied by auditory expe

    riences, that are less bizarre but equally irrelevant.

    Dreaming has been perhaps the most commonly

    studied and discussedof the variants of consciousness.

    But it is content of dreams that has been studied more

    than the formal characteristics of dream conscious

    ness. Dreams are not visualized as the result

    of

    the

    direction of attention. They intrude into the dreamer s

    consciousness and preempt attention.

    If

    the dream be

    comes too horrid or frightening, the dreamer will often

    attempt to arrest or dissipate it and his efforts seem

    to involve mobilizing attention. If attention is mobi

    lized, the dream disappears.

    Like waking consciousness, dreaming conscious

    ness is suffused with affect. The dreams

    of

    individuals

    with mood disorder include apocalyptic scenarios with

    representation

    of

    affects

    of

    death and destruction, al

    ternating with representation and affects of rebirth.

    The waking state of mind determines which of the

    two elements predominates in the dreams. But even

    in dreams in which content seems more dominant than

    affect, we always find an affect accompaniment. For

    monitoring patients who may require medication or

    who are taking it, the affective signature

    of

    the dream

    can reinforce or modify the clinical impression with

    respect to the selection of the medication, and how to

    vary the dose. It seems to me more clearly evident in

    the case of dreaming that consciousness is there for

    the purpose

    of

    registering the affect. Since actively

    and consciously focused attention are absent, cogni

    tive integration in the dream is only partial.

    In an interesting pathologic variant, an individual

    may awaken while dreaming an unpleasant dream,

    but be unable to banish it from his mind. So he remains

    unpleasantly in a state of partial dreaming, partial

    waking. Full waking consciousness, attention, and dis

    tress do not terminate the dream consciousness. Ap

    parently, waking consciousness and dream

    consciousness can coexist, though they seldom do.

    Turning now to states of pathologic conscious

    ness, we encounter confusion as the most common

    example. It may be brought about by either structural

    or toxic disorders, or nonstructural functional disor

    ders. Among the latter, psychic shock, acute stress,

    sudden anxiety, or depression or psychosis may induce

    confusion. In the case of structural or toxic disorder,

    confusion may be accompanied by impairmentof con-

  • 7/25/2019 18 Ongoing Discussion of Francis Crick and Christoph Koch (Vol. 2, No. 1): Commentary by Mortimer Ostow (New

    6/6

    Ongoing Discussion

    sciousness. In the case of purely psychic states, when

    consciousness is not seriously impaired, the confusion

    consists

    of

    impaired cognitive function and may in

    clude impaired memory. Attention

    is

    difficult or im

    possible and it cannot repair the cognitive dysfunction.

    Simple unconsciousness, or coma, or coma vigil are

    usually the result

    of

    severe brain dysfunction and ordi

    narily fall outside the psychiatric situation.

    In the case

    of

    psychosis, consciousness remains

    clear and attention can be deployed. What

    is

    altered

    is contact with consensual reality, while reality testing

    is perverted so

    as

    to validate the departure from per

    ceived reality and the adversion to the delusional real

    ity of the psychosis. The process parallels that of the

    full mystical experience in which reality is abdicated

    in favor

    of

    an illusory reality. The difference lies in the

    reversibility

    of

    the process. The mystical experience is

    reversible, brief in duration (minutes or hours), and

    usually consistent with the subject s religious tradition

    or some variant thereof. Psychosis is not really revers

    ible (without intervention such

    as

    medication), endur

    ing (often for years), and idiosyncratic in content.

    The transition from realism to psychosis, the

    psychotic break, is often marked by a delusional

    symbolic rebirth accompanied by the illusion that the

    subject now sees what he should have seen all along:

    Now I see it

    alL

    The delusion, usually a delusional

    conspiracy, now reveals itself

    as

    the objective truth,

    heretofore hidden from everyone s eyes. Similarly,

    most mystical episodes are accompanied by a revela

    tion. In religious mysticism the revelation

    is

    a mes

    sage from God, for example, the Revelation

    of

    St.

    John. It is the transit ion (or transport) from reality

    orientation to pseudoreality in each case that is de

    scribed as the revelation. What is involved here is not

    a change in the function of consciousness, attention,

    or

    of

    the sense

    of

    familiarity, but primarily the sense

    of reality and reality testing. It is the illusion or delu

    sion

    of

    rebirth that is the affective component of the

    alteration

    of

    ego function, but the instinctual, insistent

    need for attachment that drives both the mystical and

    psychotic fantasy.

    I hoped, in this communication, to list some of

    the variants

    of

    consciousness and its deformations

    along with accompanying alterations in attention. I

    hoped to show too that consciousness is invariably

    linked to affect. In fact, I believe, that the facts support

    the proposition that consciousness evolved concomi

    tantly with affect as the perceptual organ for affect.

    Some

    of

    the variants may provide data for the neuro

    scientific study of consciousness, attention, and affect.

    References

    Damasio, A (1999), The Feeling of What Happens. New

    York: Harcourt, Brace.

    Nunberg,

    H

    (1959), Principles of Psychoanalysis. New

    York: International Universities Press.

    Panksepp,

    J

    (1998), Affective Neuroscience. New York:

    Oxford University Press.

    Watt, D. (2000), Emotion and consciousness. Part II. A

    Review

    of

    Antonio Damasio s

    The Feeling

    of

    What Hap-

    pens. Consciousness Studies

    7 3 :52-73.

    5021 Iselin Avenue

    Riverdale 10471

    e mail: [email protected]

    Ongoing Discussion of Yoram Yo

    veIl

    (Vol. 2, No.2 :

    Commentary by Joseph W. Slap (Philadelphia) and

    Jodi

    H. Brown (Philadelphia)

    Whether psychoanalysis can become a respected

    member of the scientific community, or is destined

    to be regarded as an early 20th-century intellectual

    movement, may hinge on a principle enunciated by

    Joseph Slap, M.D., is a Training and Supervising Analyst at The

    Psychoanalytic Center

    of

    Philadelphia.

    Jodi Brown, M.D., is a Lecturer

    of

    Psychiatry at the Thomas Jefferson

    Medical College.

    The central thesis

    of

    this response was presented in a paper t it led

    Congruence of the Neuroscience of Perception andMemory with a Model

    Dr. Yovell, namely, psychoanalytic theory can and

    should go beyond our current neurobiological under

    standing

    of

    the mind, but never contradict

    it

    (pp.

    1-2). He states further that psychoanalytic theory

    should be continuously reexamined and revised, to

    ensure its coherence with emerging neurobiological

    research findings (p. 2). Here is the problem: As we

    of

    the Mind at the Spring Meeting

    of

    the American Psychoanalytic Asso

    ciation in Washington, DC, May 1999.