Toward a Metaphysical Historicism
-
Author
volodeatis -
Category
Documents
-
view
218 -
download
0
Embed Size (px)
Transcript of Toward a Metaphysical Historicism
-
7/23/2019 Toward a Metaphysical Historicism
1/10
Wiley and The American Society for Aesthetics are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to The
Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism.
http://www.jstor.org
Toward a Metaphysical HistoricismAuthor(s): Sondra BacharachSource: The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, Vol. 63, No. 2 (Spring, 2005), pp. 165-173Published by: on behalf ofWiley The American Society for AestheticsStable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/3700470Accessed: 16-08-2015 19:14 UTC
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at http://www.jstor.org/page/
info/about/policies/terms.jsp
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of contentin a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship.For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]
This content downloaded from 83.137.211.198 on Sun, 16 Aug 2015 19:14:24 UTCAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
http://www.jstor.org/http://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=blackhttp://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=tasfahttp://www.jstor.org/stable/3700470http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/stable/3700470http://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=tasfahttp://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=blackhttp://www.jstor.org/ -
7/23/2019 Toward a Metaphysical Historicism
2/10
SONDRA BACHARACH
Towarda
Metaphysical
Historicism
Historicism,
broadly
construed,
can
be
charac-
terized as
the view that
access
to
the
content
of
an
artwork,
or
to
the work
itself,
depends
n
part
on
the historical context in
which
the work is
created. Weaker
versions of
historicism
inter-
pret
this
dependency
relation as
an
epistemic
one: our
epistemic
access
to an
artwork's
prop-
erties
(but
not
the
properties
themselves)
may
alter
over
time.
According
to this
view,
an art-
work's
properties
exist as a
matterof fact
in
the
artworkfrom
the moment
of
its
inception,
but
our
epistemic
position may
prevent
us from
per-
ceiving
them.
If
anything changes,
we
do,
but
the work itself does not: its properties simply
remain
latent. Since this
view
holds
that our
epistemic
access
to an
artwork's
properties
changes
over
time,
call
it
epistemic
historicism.
Many prominent
philosophers
have endorsed
some version of
epistemic
historicism,
includ-
ing
Arthur
Danto,
Jerrold
Levinson,
and
No6l
Carroll.1
Perhaps
because
epistemic
historicism has
been
explicitly
endorsed
by
so
many,
it is sur-
prising
that it has
gone
essentially
unchal-
lenged.
This
paper
seeks to
change
that.
I
shall
argue
first
that
epistemic
historicism
leads
to
the
counterintuitive
result that
artworks
can
possess
inconsistent sets of
properties atently.
Second,
the
support
that
epistemic
historicism
appears
to
have
actually
provides
an
argument
for
endorsing
a
stronger,
ontological
form of
historicism,
according
to
which some
of
an art-
work's
properties change
over
time.
Call this
view
metaphysical
historicism.
At first
glance, metaphysical
historicism
might
seem
more radical
because it
allows
an
artwork'sproperties o changeover time, while
epistemic
historicism
might
seem
more
conser-
vative since
it construesan
artwork'sDroDerties
as
stable
and
unchanging.
One of the
purposes
of
this
paper,
however,
is to
dispel
this misun-
derstanding:
argue
hat
epistemic
historicism s
surprisingly
more
radical,
precisely
because it
does
not allow
properties
to
change.
In
fact,
I
shall
show
that
epistemic
historicismentails
the
view
that some
of an
artwork's
properties
are
determined
by
what
happens
after
the work has
been
created-a
view
that
Carroll calls "back-
ward
causation."2
This is
quite
ironic because
this
would
suggest
that
epistemic
historicists
make
the
very
mistake
that
they
attributeto
metaphysical
historicism.
At stakein this debateover historicism s the
nature
and
degree
of
art
historical
knowledge
that
we can
acquire.
If
epistemic
historicism is
correct,
then
one
should
resign
oneself to the
possibility
that
for some
artworks
one
may
never
be
able to learn
everything
there is
to
know
about
them,
and hence
that
one's
interpre-
tations
may
always
be
incomplete.
However,
if
metaphysical
historicism is
correct,
one can
be
assured
that,
at
any
given
moment,
t is
possible
to
construct
complete
interpretations
of
art-
works, but,
as we
shall
see,
one
must also
be
prepared
to
acknowledge
that
interpretations
must
be
indexed to
a
particular
oint
in time.
As
a
result,
what
can be known
about
an
artwork
may
well
change
over time.
This
is both
bad
and
good
news
for
interpreters
of art: the bad
news
stems
from
having
to
recognize
that
inter-
pretations
of artworks
will
always
be
changing
as
the
art-historical
ontext
changes,
but this
is
also
good
news,
as
it
confirms
our intuition
that
artworks
are rich
precisely
because
they
are
inexhaustible.
More
interestingly,
metaphysical
historicism, unlike epistemic historicism, can
also
explain
how correct
but
inconsistent nter-
Dretations
an
be true:
if the
interpretations
re
The
Journal
f
Aesthetics
andArtCriticism
3:2
Spring
2005
This content downloaded from 83.137.211.198 on Sun, 16 Aug 2015 19:14:24 UTCAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp -
7/23/2019 Toward a Metaphysical Historicism
3/10
166
The
Journal
of
Aesthetics and
Art Criticism
indexed to
a
given
moment in
time,
then it is
possible
for
a
work's
interpretation
t
one
point
to be
inconsistentwith
earlieror
later
nterpreta-
tions of the same work.
Before
turning
to
epistemic
historicism,
we
must be
careful to
distinguish
metaphysical
his-
toricism
from its
close
relative--relativism.
According
to
relativism,
the
correctness of an
interpretation
depends
not
only
on
the artwork
itself,
but
also on the
norms or
conventions
of a
community,
ndividual,
or context.3
As a
result,
a
relativist
may
suggest
that on
one inter-
pretation,
artwork A
has
property
p,
while on
another,
A
has
not-p.
In
other
words,
at
any
given moment,
an
artwork an
have
inconsistent
sets of
properties.
Fortunately,
nd
in
contrast
o
relativism,
metaphysical
historicism
s not com-
mitted to
such a view.
Metaphysical
historicism
differs from
relativism
by
proposing
that an
art-
work's
properties
are
indexed to
a
particular
time.
So,
while
metaphysical
historicism
endorses
the
possibility
that
some
of an art-
work's
properties
may
change
(so
that an
art-
work
may
even come
to have the
contrary
of a
property
that it
once
had),
an
artwork at
any
given
momentcould never have
two
inconsistent
properties.4
I.
EPISTEMIC
HISTORICISM
According
to
epistemic
historicism,
an artwork
possesses
all
of the
properties
relevant to its
appreciation
qua
artworkfrom
the
moment
of
its
creation.
However,
we do
not
always
see all
of
these
properties
when the
work
is
first
created.
Some
properties
are
hidden
or remain
undiscovereduntil some
time afterthe creation
of
the
artwork,
and can
be seen
only
after we
make other
relevant
discoveries.
Arthur
Danto,
Noel
Carroll,
and
Jerrold
Levinson
have all
endorsed
epistemic
histori-
cism in
some form or
another.
Arthur
Danto has
most
famously
supportedepistemic
historicism
in
his
concept
of the
style
matrix.
He believes
that
many
artworks
possess
style
properties
hat
exist from
the
moment of the
artwork's crea-
tion,
even if
they
were hidden
at
that
time.5
No1l
Carroll
endorses
epistemic
historicism
mainly because he believes that the alternative
would
require
admitting
o
backward
causation,
a view
that he
rightly rejects
as
implausible.6
Jerrold
Levinson has the most
extended
defense of
epistemic
historicism in
his
paper
"Artworks and the
Future."7
He
argues
that
when artworks seem to change, this pheno-
menon is
best
explained
by
appealing
to
an
epistemic
change
in
us,
ratherthan to a
meta-
physical
change
in the work itself. For
example,
one
might suggest
that Picasso's
Guernica
has
taken
on
new
significance
in
light
of the
events
of
September
11,
2001.
In such
cases,
there
are
two
possible
explanations
available:
t
might
be
that the work
itself has
changed,
or it
might
simply
be that
we have
changed
and we now
see
the artwork
n a different
ight
as a result of
the
changes
in us.
Levinson
argues
that
epistemic
historicism
provides
the most
plausible
expla-
nation in such
cases,
as
well as in
a
number
of
other cases
where
one
might
(in
his
view,
wrongly)
believe
that
only metaphysical
histori-
cism could
help.8
Let us examine an
extended
example
in order to understand
epistemic
historicism
n more detail.
During
the 1890s
and
1900s,
C6zanne
created
a series of
paintings
of the mountain
Mont
Sainte
Victoire.
Even
though
they
were
madeat
the same
time as
some
Impressionist
works
(including one of the very same mountainby
the
Impressionist
Renoir),
Erle
Loran
argues
that
the
right
way
to understand
C6zanne's
work is not in relation
o
the
Impressionists
who
were
his
contemporaries,
but
rather n relation
to
Cubism,
which
emerges
a few
years
after
C6zanne's
death
n
1906.
With
the
same
outworn,
uncontemporary
pproach
the
ate
Abstract
rt
of
Picasso,
Braque,
ndothers
s
often
rejected oday
because
of its so-called ack
of
spaceanddepth.Butthere s
an
ever-growingppre-
ciationand
understanding
f the
sensational
pace
effects
n suchAbstract rt.And it is
only
with
this
contemporary,
evised
conception
of
space
that
C6zanne
can
be
understood
n
relation
either
to
typical Impressionism
or
to
later Abstraction
[Cubism]
..
The essential
difference
between
Impres-
sionist form
and
C6zanne's
orm
could
never
be
explained
n wordsas
forcefully
s
it
is
demonstrated
by
the
comparison
f
paintings
by
C6zanne
and
Renoir
rom
he same
motif,
he mountainalled he
SainteVictoire.
The
glaring
ifference
pparent
here
is notmerely hatC6zanne's aintings firm n its
contourswhereRenoir's s
soft,
but that
C6zanne
actually uperimposes
efinite ines at the
contours,
This content downloaded from 83.137.211.198 on Sun, 16 Aug 2015 19:14:24 UTCAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp -
7/23/2019 Toward a Metaphysical Historicism
4/10
Bacharach
Toward
Metaphysical
Historicism
167
notably
in
the
distant mountain.
Renoir's
mountain
fades
away
in
typical
Impressionistic,
aerial
perspec-
tive;
Cdzanne's
is
stepped
back with
overlapping
planes, so that,through hese moreconstructiveplas-
tic
means,
its
location
in
deep
space
is
absolutely
clear.
And,
being firmly
outlined and
expanded
in
size,
it takes its
place
again
with the
foreground,
and
maintains,
also,
its relation o the
pictureplane.9
According
to
Loran,
Cdzanne
relies on the flat-
ness of
the
color
patches
to
highlight
a tension
between
the
two-dimensionality
of
the
canvas
and
the
three-dimensionality
of the
object
repre-
sented. This is
particularly
evident
in
Cdzanne's
paintings
of
Mont
Sainte
Victoire.
Not
only
is
the
mountain
made
as clear
and
promi-
nent as
the
foreground
orms;
the outlines
of its outer
contours are
even
more forceful and
deliberate.It
is
obvious
that
Cdzanne wished to avoid
the
fading
away
that
characterizes
the
mountain in the
pho
tograph
of the
motif.
Even
more
important
s the fact
that in
Cdzanne's
painting
the mountain
s
enlarged,
expanded
n
size.
Perspective
s
again
reversedto the
end
that the
background
or
distance
should not
fall
away
and thus
destroy
he mural
quality
of
the
picture
plane. The monumental effect, the grandeur of
Cdzanne's
mountain,
clearly
drawn n
deep space
but
decoratively
remaining
on the
pictureplane,
is a
good
example
of
the
difference between
Cezanne's form
and
that of the
Impressionists.10
So,
unlike
the
Impressionists
who
clearly
were
painting
in
perspective,
so that
some
objects
receded
into
the
background,
and others
came
forward into
the
foreground,
Loran
argues
that
Cdzanne's
flatness
is
used to
eliminate our
sense of
perspective altogether
and
to
produce
a
sense
of
tension.
Cdzanne
has
made
use
of
all
these elements of
deep
space,
but he
has
organized
them and confined
them
within
a
seemingly
shallower
depth
of total
space...
Three-dimensionality
s
clearly
established;
yet
in
this
painting,
as
in
the entire
series
[of
paint-
ings
of
Mont
Sainte
Victoire]
to
which
it
belongs...
the
all-over
patchwork
of
color
planes
produces
a
pronounced
wo-dimensionality.11
The mountain s the lastparallelplane,andinstead of
being
faded out it is
boldly
outlined...Its
position
in
the distant
deep space
is
actually
clearer
than in
Renoir's
painting
becauseof the firm
drawing
of
planes
that
overlap
from the
foreground
back to the
distant
mountain...But
because
of its
clarity
and
parallelrelationto the pictureplane a strongtension
canbe
felt
between
he
plane
of themountain nd he
flat
plane
of the
foreground
assof
trees.12
For
our
purposes,
what
is
interesting
s how to
make
philosophical
sense
of Loran's
interpreta-
tion.
How do we
explain
the
properties
that
Loran
attributes o
Cdzanne's
works,
if we can
only
see
these
properties
once later Cubist
works
are created?
Epistemic
and
metaphysical
historicism
offer
competing
explanations.
If
epistemic
historicism
is
correct,
then these
properties
were
there
all
along,
but we
simply
could
not
have
seen
them before Cubist works
were
created.
According
to
epistemic
histori-
cism,
once we
see
where Cezanne's work is
headed,
we
reinterpret
his earlier works
as
exhibiting
tension.
Looking
at Cdzanne's
earlier
landscapes
of Mont
Sainte
Victoire in
light
of
later Cubist
developments
helps
us discover
new
properties
in
his
early
works. The
earlier
works
really
did
possess
tension,
but this
remained
latent,
undiscovered
at the
time of
their creation.It is only laterthatwe are able to
realize the
importance
and
interest of the
flatness as
expressing
tension in
Cdzanne's
work.
We are able
to discover
these new
proper-
ties
in Cdzanne's
work
because
of a
change
in
our
epistemic
approach
toward
the
work.
In
particular,
Cubism
allows
us to discover new
properties
n
Cdzanne's
paintings.
This
explains
how
we
gain
new
knowledge
as new
artworks
are
created: we
discern
new features
of
art
as
the art-historical
ontext
changes
and
develops.
If
epistemic
historicism
is
correct,
then
placing
Cdzanne's
early
work
in
the
context of
later
works
reveals
properties
of
Cdzanne's
work
that we
could
not
have seen
in
the
1880s.
With
the
development
of
Cubism,
we are able
to see Cdzanne's
work as
expressing
tension.
But
we
could
not
have discovered
this
about
Cdzanne's
work
except against
the
backdrop
of
the works
from the 1900s.
In
other
words,
the
historical
evolution
leading
up
to
the 1900s
reveals
to us these
new
properties
n
Cdzanne's
work-this
evolution
uncovers
properties
like
flatness and tension, which we could not have
seen before. Of
course,
these
properties
were
there in the work
all
along,
but we
only
discover
This content downloaded from 83.137.211.198 on Sun, 16 Aug 2015 19:14:24 UTCAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp -
7/23/2019 Toward a Metaphysical Historicism
5/10
168
The Journal
of
Aesthetics and Art Criticism
this
fact once
these later works
emerge,
and
we
could
not
have known
as much when
the works
were first
created.
II.
WHY WE
CANNOT SEE PROPERTIES
ACCORDINGTO
EPISTEMIC
HISTORICISM
The
above
explanation
for
why
we can
make
sense
of tension in
Cezanne's
works
only
in
light
of
Cubism
presupposes
hat
some
proper-
ties
are
closely
tied to the
artwork's uture art-
historical
context.
However,
I
believe
that there
is
a
problem
with
the
epistemic
historicist's
assumption.
Consider the
following
argument
againstepistemichistoricism.(1) if latentprop-
erties
are in the
work from the
moment of its
inception,
then
they
are
independent
of
any
future
art-historical
progress.
(2)
However,
it is
possible
for art
history
to
progress
in
a number
of
different
ways,
such that
an
artwork could
have a
latent
property
p
on
one
path,
and a latent
property
not-p
on
another
path.
(3)
So,
epistemic
historicism
must admit
that
artworkscan have
inconsistent sets
of latent
properties.
Let
me
defend each
of the
premises
n this
argument.
First, recall the epistemic historicist's posi-
tion. If
an
artwork's atent
properties
are in the
work
from
the moment of its
inception,
then
these
latent
properties
must
inhere in
the work
independently
of the artist's
ater
work.
If
latent
properties
did
depend
on the
future,
then which
latent
properties
an artwork
has
would be differ-
ent if
the
history
of artwere
different.
However,
this is
problematic
because,
first,
in
that
case,
these
properties
could not
be latent from the
moment of the
work's
creation;
second,
if an
artwork's
properties
were
different
depending
on the artist'sfuture
works,
then future events
would
determine
which
properties
a
given
art-
work
had
latently-a
form
of backwardcausa-
tion
according
to
which
future events fix the
latent
properties
of earlier
works.
Since both
these
implications
are
problematic,
epistemic
historicism
is
committed
to
accepting
that
whether
an artwork
possesses
a
latent
property
p
at a
given
time is
independent
of
what future
artworksare
created.13
To
defend the second
premise,
consider that
arthistorycould have evolved in many,even if
not
infinitely many,
different directions. For
any
contingentpath
of art
history,
later artworks
allow
us to discover
some,
though
maybe
not
all,
properties
of earlierworks.14Which
proper-
ties
we discover
in earlier artworks
depends
on
the contingent evolution of art history. How-
ever,
this
holds
for
every
possible path
of art
history.
This means
that for
any
possible
path
that art
history
could
have
taken,
we could
have
discerned
different
properties
rom the ones
we
actually
discovered.
In
particular,
an
artwork
could
have
two
different,
inconsistent sets of
properties
as a result of two different
paths
of
art
history.
As a
result,
the
epistemic
historicist
is committed
to
granting
that an artwork
can
have
inconsistent
ets
of
properties
hatare atent.
At this
point,
two
possible objections
can
be
raised
against
this second
premise.
First,
one
might
object
to this
line of
reasoning
on
the
grounds
that,
at
most,
it shows
that
there
is
a
potentially
infinite
number of
ways
that we
could
have
discovered
the
properties
that
the
work
actually
has.15
In other
words,
one
might
object
that
artworks
simply
cannot have incon-
sistent sets
of
properties
hat
are
latent
from
the
moment of
its
inception.
To
illustrate
he
initial
plausibility
of
this line
of
reasoning,
imagine
Cdzanne's Mont
Sainte
Victoireof 1888 in two different uturehistories
of art.
First,
on
our current
history,
we discover
its
tension,
thanks
to the
arrival
of Cubism
and
C6zanne's
later
works. On the actual
path,
it
is
dynamic
and
exciting
as a result of the tension
between
the
two-dimensional
canvas
and the
three-dimensional
mountain.
ndeed,
t is
usually
seen as
a wonderful
formulationof the
problem
of
painting
a three-dimensional
bject
on a
two-
dimensional
canvas-a
problem
that is later
solved
by
Cubism.
However,
we
can
imagine
an
alternative
path
that
art
history might
have
taken
that leads
us elsewhere.
Perhaps,
nstead,
it leads
us to
a
prolonged
period
devoted
exclu-
sively
to
Fauvism.
Fauvism
s
characterized
ri-
marily
by
a
reliance on
brilliant
colors,
a sense
of liberation
from traditional
representational
techniques,
and a
preference
or more
primitive
images.
On
this alternative
path,
Cezanne's
interest
in
landscapes
and still-lifes is conser-
vative and
staid
while his
muted
colors
are bor-
ing
and
uninventive.
But
the
painting
cannotbe
both
dynamic
and
staid,
exciting
and uninven-
tive, or expressive and not expressive of ten-
sion.
Unfortunately,
epistemic
historicism
entails this
very
consequence.16
This content downloaded from 83.137.211.198 on Sun, 16 Aug 2015 19:14:24 UTCAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp -
7/23/2019 Toward a Metaphysical Historicism
6/10
Bacharach
Toward
Metaphysical
Historicism
169
Another
objection
to
the
second
premise
is
that
two future
paths
of art
history
result in
the
creation of
two
different
artworks,
rather han a
single artworkwith two potentiallyinconsistent
properties.17
Returning
to
our earlier
example,
if
we
imagine
that
Cezanne's Mont
Saint
Victoire of
1888
continues to exist in
two dif-
ferent
histories of
art-one with
Cubism and
one
with
Fauvism-then we have
two different
artworks,
with two
different
sets of
properties.
In
other
words,
having
two different
future
histories of
art
results in two
different
artworks.
The
problem
with
this
objection,
however,
is
as
follows.
Imagine
that an artworkA
at
tl
is
created.
Suppose
further
that
the future of art
history
can
continue
down either
path
P1
or P2.
If
the two
future
paths
of art
history diverge,
then
according
to
this
objection,
we shall
have
two
different
artworks
at
t2-call them B
and
C.
In
addition,
by hypothesis,
B
at t2 is
the same
artwork
as A at
tl,
and C
at
t2 is the
same art-
work
as
A
at
t2. The
problem
s
A
at
tl
cannot
be
identical
to two
different
artworks If we
believe that
we
have two different
artworks
because of
the
different
paths
of
art
history,
though,
we
shall be
committedto
saying
that
A
at tl is identicalto two laterworks at t2 that are
themselves
distinct
and different
from one
another.
This,
however,
is
logically impossible.
On the other
hand,
notice that if
metaphysical
historicism s
correct,
then we can
simply grant
that the
artwork
has
changed
over
time;
how it
changes depends
on
the
path
that art
history
has
taken.
So,
the
metaphysical
historicist
will
not
have a
problem
with
this kind of
case.
However,
such a
response
is
not
open
to
someone who
denies that
an
artwork
might change
over
time.
So, if one's intuition in this kind of situation s
that we
have
two
different
artworks,
then,
for
consistency,
one
ought
to
endorse
metaphysical
historicism as
well.18
Of
course,
epistemic
historicism
would
be off
the
hook
if
it held
that an artwork's
atent
prop-
erties
depend
only
on art
history's
actual
progress
(rather
han
on
merely possible,
altern-
ative
paths
of
art
history).
The
epistemic
histori-
cist
might
then
be
tempted
to
suggest
that
artworks do
not
have
an
infinite
number of
latent
properties
since latent
properties
would
be tied to the artwork's actual position in art
history-that
is,
to
the events
leading
up
to and
persisting hroughout
he creation f the
artwork.
Even if
epistemic
historicism restricts itself
to
suggesting
that an artwork's atent
properties
depend
on art
history's
actual
progress,
rather
than on merely possible alternativepathsof art
history,
a
serious
problem
still arises.
Since
these latent
properties
are
supposed
to exist in
the artwork
rom the moment of its
inception,
future
artworks
will determine which
latent
properties
an
artwork
has
when
it
is first cre-
ated.
To the extent
that
future artworksdeter-
mine the
latent
properties
of an artworkat the
time
of its
creation,
epistemic
historicism
itself
falls
prey
to the
very
criticism raised
against
metaphysical
historicism.
Recall that Carroll
and
Levinson
both
object
to the
possibility
that
an artwork
may acquire
properties
as a result of
futureevents-and
this
is
precisely
what
occurs
when
we
accept
epistemic
historicism.
Once
again,
it is ironic that so
many
are
eager
to
defend
epistemic
historicism,
for this is
pre-
cisely
the
complaint
they
raise
against
meta-
physical
historicism.
Relying
on the
intuition that
an artwork
may
acquire
properties
as a result of future
events,
the
epistemic
historicist
might
be
tempted
to
suggest
that
latent
properties
remain latent
because they are relational. Some properties
only
come to
exist as
a
result of
being
related
n
relevant
ways
to later
artworks.
So,
we cannot
discover
these
properties
until after
these later
works
are created.
9
Returning
o
C6zanne,
sup-
pose
his Mont
Sainte
Victoire
of 1888
possesses
the
latent
property
"tension"
in virtue
of its
relation
to
his later works
from
the
early
1900s.
The
epistemic
historicist wants
to
say
that
expressing
tension
is a
property
hat we
come
to
discover
in the
early
1900s,
but this
property
was there all along, latent in the work. How-
ever,
if
C6zanne's
Mont Sainte Victoire
exhibits
tension
at least
partly
n virtue
of its relations
to
future
artworks
n the
early
1900s,
then
in
1888,
we
cannot
say
that it
exhibits
tension. In
fact,
nothing
in 1888
can have
the
property
"exhibit-
ing
tension"
because
the relevant relations
to
future artworks
n the 1900s
have
not
yet
been
established
n
1888.
What
can
a
latency
theorist
say?
He or
she
can
say
that
the
following
is
a latent
property
of
C6zanne's
Mont Sainte
Victoire even
in
1888:
"will exhibit tension in the early 1900s (in vir-
tue of its relations
to later
works)."
But notice
that
"exhibiting
tension" is an
importantly
This content downloaded from 83.137.211.198 on Sun, 16 Aug 2015 19:14:24 UTCAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp -
7/23/2019 Toward a Metaphysical Historicism
7/10
170
The
Journal
of Aesthetics and Art
Criticism
different
property
rom
"will exhibit
tension
in
the
early
1900s,"
in
that
the
latter,
but not the
former,
is a
latent
property
that
correctly
describes Cezanne's Mont Sainte Victoire even
in
1888. "Will
exhibit
tension
in
the
early
1900s"
is a
property
that
applies
even at the
time of
the
artwork's
creation,
and hence
quali-
fies
as
a
latent
property
even if we will
not dis-
cover
this fact until
much
later.
Exhibiting
tension,
on
the
other
hand,
does not exist from
the moment of
the
creation
of the
1888
work,
and
therefore
cannot be a
latent
property
of it.
Only
the
time-indexed
property
"will
exhibit
tension
in
the
early
1900s"
can.
It
is
tempting
to want
to fix
this
problem by
including
time
references n
the
characterization
of
latent
properties.
So,
for
example,
instead of
claiming
that
"exhibiting
tension" is a latent
feature of
C6zanne's work
all
along,
we
simply
time index
the
property
so
that "will
exhibit
tension in
the
early
1900"
(rather
than
simply
"exhibiting
tension"
tout
court)
is latent in the
1888 work.
However,
notice that
even
though
it is
pos-
sible to
say
that "will
exhibit
tension
in
the
early
1900s" is a latent
property,
his takes
away
the
force of the epistemic historicist'sposition for
two
reasons.
First,
it
is not
clear what it
really
means to
say
that an
artwork
has the
property
"will
exhibit
tension in the
early
1900s,"
or
what
this
actually
amounts to.
When the
epistemic
historicist claims that
some
property
is
latent,
we
naturally
do
not take
him
or her to be refer-
ring
to
properties
hat
only
come to exist
after
the
creation of
the
work. In
fact,
it is not
logically
possible
for a
property
hat
is
latent
in
the work to
come to exist
only
after
the creation
of
a
later work. But if
a
propertyonly comes to
exist after the
creationof
a
later
work,
then
it is
not
logically possible
for
that
property
o be
in
the
earlier
work.
The
epistemic
historicist
also has a
problem
with
an entire
class of
properties-that
is,
prop-
erties
that the artist
could
not
have known about
because
they
involve
concepts
that were not
yet
available. For
example,
an
artist in the
1600s
could not
have
construed
his or
her
work as
being Impressionist.
mpressionism
had not
yet
been
formulated in
the
1600s,
and so it is
unavailable to anyone in the 1600s, not just
because
the artist did not
happen
to think of
characterizing
his or her
work in
this
way,
but
also because
it was
impossible
for the artist to
do so.
In the
1600s,
nobody
had the relevant
concept
of
Impressionism
that
we would
later
apply to other works. This example highlights
how
certain
properties
are constituted
by
their
relation
to
later works. If these works do not
exist,
the
dependency
relation
necessary
for
these
properties
o exist will also fail to obtain.
Hence,
these
properties
do not exist at all-
latently
or
otherwise.
As a
rule,
properties
whose
characterization
nvokes
concepts
that
are even
partially
constituted
by
their relationto
future artworks
will also
always
have
to
specify
the
time reference
o those futureartworksn their
characterization.
More
generally,
any
relational
property
that
is even
partially
constituted
by
its
relation
to
future artworks
ails
to
qualify
as a latent
prop-
erty.
Relational
properties
whose existence
depends
on
future
artworks will
always
have
to
specify
the time reference to those
future
artworks
n
their characterization.As we have
seen,
this can
be done in two
ways:
either the
time reference
can be
built
directly
into
the
description
of the
style predicate
tself,
or
not. If
the
predicate
s defined with reference to
time,
then it is impossible for these propertiesto be
latent. On
the
other
hand,
if
the
predicate
is
defined
without
reference to
time,
such
proper-
ties can
be
latent,
but then one
must
admit
that
these
properties
can
change.
In
either
case,
the
spirit
of
epistemic
historicism
s
lost.
Finally,
even
if we could
make
sense of
these
relational
properties
as time
indexed,
this
still
does
not address
the
original
problem
that
plagues
epistemic
historicism-that
epistemic
historicism
entails
that an artworkcould
have
inconsistent
sets of
properties. Providing
an
account
of time-indexed
relational
properties
does not
solve
this
problem.
Clearly,
we
need an
alternative.
would
like
to
suggest
that
a
stronger
form of
historicism,
according
to
which at least some of an
art-
work's
properties
may change
over
time,
is
a
step
in the
right
direction.
Returning
to
C6zanne,
metaphysical
historicism has
a far
more natural
way
of
thinking
about
properties
such as
exhibiting
tension.
Instead
of
saying
that this
property
is latent, a more
plausible
sug-
gestion might simply be thatexhibitingtension
becomes a
new
property
hat
we
can attribute
o
C6zanne's earlier
Mont Sainte
Victoire
once
This content downloaded from 83.137.211.198 on Sun, 16 Aug 2015 19:14:24 UTCAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp -
7/23/2019 Toward a Metaphysical Historicism
8/10
Bacharach
Toward
Metaphysical
Historicism
171
later
works,
which
are
related to
the
previously
existing
work in
relevant
ways,
are
created.
According
to
metaphysical
historicism,
the
path
thatarthistory actually takes does in fact help
to
create
these
properties.
f
this
is
the
right
way
to think
about
these
properties,
then
stronger
forms of
historicism
that
allow
an
artwork's
properties
to
change
over
time
will be
more
plausible
and more
defensible than
epistemic
historicism.
The
epistemic
historicist
might
be
tempted
to
argue
that
latent
properties
could be
relational
in
just
this
way.
If
we think of an
artwork's
latent
properties
as
potential
properties,
then
it
might
be
that an
artwork has the
potential
to
have
properties
p
and
q,
but
not
r,
in
virtue of
a
given
future
path
of
art
history,
in
the
same
way
that
a
hydrangea
eedling
(that
has not
yet
flow-
ered)
can
have
the
potential
o have
pink
or blue
flowers,
but not
orange
ones,
in
virtue of
a
given
future
gardening history.
Just as
we
think
of this
nonblooming
hydrangea
eedling's
flower color
as
latent, so,
too,
can
we think
of
an
artwork's
properties
as
latent.20
The
reason we
might
explain why
having
pink
or
blue
flowers,
but
not
orange
ones,
is
latentis this:whethera hydrangeaat tl has the
potential
to
have
pink
or
blue
flowers at
t2
depends
at
least
in
part
on
the
acidity
of the
soil,
which
fixes the
color.21
So,
flower color
depends
importantly
on
certain
underlying
intrinsic
properties
of the soil
(its
acidity)
and
the
flower's
relation
to the soil
in
the
future.
This
dependency
relation
is
sufficiently
fixed
that,
given
the
relevant
informationabout
plant
and
soil
conditions,
we
can
easily
predict
at
tl
what
properties
he
flower
will have at
t2.
So,
prima facie, at t1 we can state which flower
colors are
latent n
a
flower and which
will
then
emerge
and
become
accessible at t2.
Although
this
line
of
reasoning
may
be
plausible
for
flowers,
there is
an
important
dis-
analogy
between the
way
that
a
hydrangea
eed-
ling's
future
depends
on
certain
underlying
flower
properties
and the
way
that an
artwork's
future
depends
on
certain
underlying
rt-historical
properties.
Unlike
in the
hydrangea
case,
there
are no
corresponding
kinds of
underlying
ntrin-
sic
properties
of a
given painting
that
constrain
whatpotentialfeaturesan artworkmay have in
the future in
virtue
of
the
future
art-historical
context. Unlike
the connections between
flower
color and future
gardening
conditions,
the
con-
nection between
an artwork's
properties
and
its
future art-historical ituationare not
sufficiently
fixed to enableus to make the kinds of predic-
tions
that
we
can in the
case of flowers.
That there are
no
underlying
fixed
connec-
tions between
an artwork's
properties
and
its
future art-historical
ontext should
come as
no
surprise;
after
all,
artworks
are
by
their
very
nature
creative,
and
are therefore
constantly
changing
and
challenging
traditions.As
such,
it
would be
surprising
o
imagine
that there
could
be fixed connections
between
artworksand the
future
art
history
that would
allow us to
predict
which
properties
were latent in the same
way
that
we
can
for natural
properties
ike a
flower's
color.
So,
while
it is true that for
objects
like
flowers the color
of a
plant's
future
lowers
may
well
be
potential
and
latent,
the same does
not
hold
of
an artwork's
properties.
An
artwork's
properties
are
underwritten
by
the
art-historical
context,
something
that is
always changing.
A better
way
of
thinking
about how
an
art-
work's
properties
depend
on the
art-historical
context
s
to
compare
t to the
way
the
grammati-
cality
of
a sentence
depends
on the
grammatical
rules in place at a given moment in time. The
correctness
of
a sentence
depends
on the
lin-
guistic
context
in the
same
way
that the
exist-
ence
of
a
given
aesthetic
property
depends
on
the art-historical
ontext.
To see
why,
consider
a
given
sentence
Si.
Suppose
that at
tl,
gram-
maticalrule
G1
is
in
place,
such
that f one
were
to utter
S1
at
tl,
it would be
grammatically
correct. It
is
no stretch
of the
imagination
to
envision
a
future
history
t2 in which our
gram-
matical rules
have
changed.
In
such a
future,
supposethatrule G2 has replacedrule G1. As a
result,
if
one
were
to utter
S1
at
t2,
it would be
ungrammatical.
One of the
properties
of
the
sentence-being grammatical
or
ungrammati-
cal-has
changed
over
time. The reason it
has
changed
is
that the
linguistic
context has been
altered.
Similarly,
a
particular
artwork
A
might
be
related o
the
art-historical ontext
n
such a
way
that a
given
property
would
apply
at
tl,
but
not
at
t2.
C6zanne's
Mont
Sainte
Victoire
will be
post-Impressionist,
ut not
exhibit
tension in the
late 1890s, because of the way that the work is
related
to
the then-current
rt-historical ontext
at
tl.
However,
the
workwill exhibit
tension
in
This content downloaded from 83.137.211.198 on Sun, 16 Aug 2015 19:14:24 UTCAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp -
7/23/2019 Toward a Metaphysical Historicism
9/10
172
The
Journal
of
Aesthetics
and
Art Criticism
the
early
1900s because of
the
way
that
it is
relatedto
the
new
art-historical ontext contain-
ing
Cubist
works
at t2.
The
properties
of the
artworkchange as the artworkbecomes related
in
relevant
ways
to
the
art-historical ontext in
the
same
way
that
the
grammaticality
f a
given
sentence
changes
as the
sentence
becomes
related in
relevant
ways
to
different
linguistic
rules.
Just
as an
artwork
acquires
new
properties
as
the
art-historical
context
changes,
so, too,
does
the
grammaticality
f a
sentence
change
as
the
rules of
grammar
hange
over
time.
To
summarize,
epistemic
historicism faces
some
serious
problems.
For
one,
we have
trouble
understandingwhy
we cannot
always
discover
various
purportedly
atent
properties.
For
another,
the
epistemic
historicist ends
up
being
committed
to
the
possibility
of
logically
inconsistent
sets of
properties.
The
ways
around
this
problem,
however,
either entail
giving
up
the
basic
spirit
of
epistemic
historicism
altogether
or entail
endorsing
some form of
backward
causation-the
ultimate
irony,
since
this
is
precisely
he
criticism
hat
atency
heorists
try
to
pin
on their
opponents.Finally,
we cannot
make
sense
of
certain
properties
as
latent,
and
so epistemichistoricismwill be unable o account
for
some of
an
artwork's
properties
at all.
As an
alternative,
propose
that
we consider
metaphysical
historicism's
suggestion
that
an
artwork's
properties
change
over time. In
addi-
tion
to
being
more
plausible
than
epistemic
his-
toricism for
reasons
suggested
above,
it also can
account
for
two
familiar
problems
n art
history:
first,
it
seems to take
time
to discover certain
properties
of
artworks
and, second,
our
concept
of
a
given
style appears
to
change
as
a
result
of
discovering properties. The metaphysical
historicist
has
a
compelling
explanation
for
these two
phenomena
that
avoids talk of
latent
properties.
It
is not
that
it
takes a lot of
time
to
discover
certain
properties
of
artworks;rather,
certain
properties
are not
createduntil the
relev-
ant
art-historical
elations
among
artworks
have
been
established.
So,
they
are not
discovered at
all,
but
rather
come to
exist
This
is
precisely
why
our
concept
of
style
evolves-because
the
relevant
artworks
come to
be related in
certain
ways
that did not
obtain earlier. Not
only
can
metaphysicalhistoricismexplainthesephenom-
ena,
but it
can do so
without
appealing
to
unwieldy,
hidden,
and
inaccessible
properties.
Of
course,
crucial to
defending
an
account
like
metaphysical
historicism will
be to
explain
which causal
relations
among
artworks
are
relevant o fixing new propertieshat areattribu-
table
to earlierworks. After
all,
only
some
rela-
tions
among
artworkswill license
the
creation
of new
properties.
I
hope, though,
that
this
paper
will motivate
philosophers
of art to
con-
sider new
ways
of
thinking
about
an
artwork's
properties
that have so far been
neglected
for
some
of the
wrong
reasons.22
SONDRA BACHARACH
Philosophy
rogramme
VictoriaUniversityfWellington
Wellington
NewZealand
NTrERNET:
1. Jerrold
Levinson
has defended such an account in
his
"Artworksand the Future"
n
Music,
Art and
Metaphysics
(Cornell
University
Press,
1990),
though
he has
more
recently
modified
his view in "Work and Oeuvre"
(seem-
ingly
heading
toward
a
stronger
orm of
historicism,
hough
not
as
strong
as
the
metaphysical
historicism I defend
here)
in The Pleasures of Aesthetics (Cornell University Press,
1996).
Danto's
position
on the
style
matrix also assumes
a
form
of
epistemic
historicism.
Noel
Carroll
has
also
endorsedthis
position
in his
"Danto,
Style
and
Intention,"
The
Journal
of
Aesthetics and Art Criticism 53
(1995):
251-257.
Any
intentionalist,
n
fact,
wouldseem to be
com-
mitted to this
view.
2.
This
is
somewhat of a misnomer for an
artwork's
properties
may
well be determined
by
what
happens
after
the
work
has
been
created without
those
properties
hereby
having
been
caused
by
those future events.
This
point
will become
important
ater
when we
see
how
epistemic
historicismentails
this
very
position.
3.
See,
for
example,
David Carrier's
Principles
of
Art-
writing (Penn State University Press, 1991); "PieroDella
Francesca
and
His
Interpreters:
s There
Progress
in
Art
History?"
History
and
Theory
26
(1987):
150-165;
"Art
History
in
theMirror
Stage: Interpreting
Un
Bar
Aux
Folies
Bergers,"
History
and
Theory
29
(1990):
295-320.
For
stronger
versions
of
relativism,
see
Joseph Margolis's
work,
for
example,
"PlainTalk about
Interpretation
n a
Relativi-
stic
Model,"
The
Journal
of
Aesthetics and Art Criticism
53
(1995):
1-7.
4.
Stephen
Davies
makes a
similar
point
in
his
discussion
of
Margolis's
robust brand
of relativism in his
"Relativism
in
Interpretation,"
The Journal
of
Aesthetics and
Art
Criticism53
(1995):
8-13.
5.
The
entire
system
of the
style
matrix is underwritten
by a commitment to latent properties.However, for an
explicit
endorsement
of latent
properties,
see,
for
example,
Arthur
Danto,
After
the
End
of
Art
(Princeton
University
Press,
1997),
pp.
161-162.
This content downloaded from 83.137.211.198 on Sun, 16 Aug 2015 19:14:24 UTCAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp -
7/23/2019 Toward a Metaphysical Historicism
10/10
Bacharach
Toward
Metaphysical
Historicism
173
6. See
Nodl Carroll, "Danto,
Style
and
Intention,"
The
Journal
ofAesthetics
and Art
Criticism 3
(1995):
251-257.
7.
Jerrold
Levinson,
"Artworks
nd
the
Future."
8.
Interestingly,
however,
Levinson has
recently
granted,in "Workand Oeuvre,"thatmetaphysicalhistori-
cism
is a
plausible
position
in
the case
of
intra-oeuvral
works of a
single
artist.
However,
he
argues
that
epistemic
historicism
applies
in
all other
cases.
9. Erle
Loran,
Cdzanne's
Composition:Analysis of
his
Form,
with
Diagrams
and
Photographs of
his
Motifs
(University
of
California
Press,
1963),
p.
12.
10.
Loran,
Cdzanne's
Composition,
p.
99.
11.
Loran,
Cdzanne's
Composition,
p.
104.
12.
Loran,
Cdzanne's
Composition,
p.
100.
13. Of
course,
whether
an
artwork's
atent
properties
are
discovered
does
depend
on
whether certain later
artworks
are
created.
This
is
not in
dispute.
14.
I
grant
that a
later artwork
may
not
allow
us
to
dis-
cover all or even many latentfeatures of an earlier work. I
simply
want
to draw our
attention
to the case
where two
paths
allow
us to
discover some
but not all latent
features of
an
earlier
work.
15.
I
thank
Robert
Stecker
for
having
originally
raised
this
concern.
16.
One
response
available to
epistemic
historicism
s to
suggest
that
artworksdo
not
have
an infinite
numberof
pos-
sible
latent
properties
because
an
artwork's atent
properties
are
tied
to
the artwork's
actual
position
in art
history.
I
shall
discuss this
case later.
17.
I
thank
RobertStecker for
raising
this
concern.
18. One
might
think there are
two
different
artworks
not
because the
future s
different,
but
because the
past
is
differ-
ent. This
may
be,
but is not the
relevantly
nteresting
case-
the
question
at
hand is whether futureevents in
part
consti-
tute
the
properties
of an artworkor
not.
19. Levinson
has noted that
ust
because certain
proper-
ties of artworksonly come into existence as a result of
being
related to certain
other,
later artworks
does not
nec-
essarily
entail
that we cannot
discover these
properties
until
these
later
properties
have been created. To show that
this
entailment
ails,
he
points
out that a
perfect
predictor
could
know what was
going
to exist in the
future,
and
hence
could know
that
an artwork had certain
properties
that
depended
on
later
artworks,
even before those later
art-
works were
created. I
certainly
grant
that a
perfect
predic-
tor
can
know,
at
tl,
that at
t2,
artworkA will come to
have
property
p,
in virtue
of
being
appropriately
elated to
art-
work B that is created at t2. But this is different from
knowing
that
at
tl
an artwork
has a
property
p
in virtue
of
being appropriately
related
to B created at t2-but it
is
impossible at tl for an artwork o have p, if p depends on
B,
which will
only
come to exist at t2. For
the
perfect pre-
dictor
to
make
this
claim,
he or she would
not
only
need
to
predict
the
future,
but create
it,
too.
20.
I
thank
an
anonymous
referee for
bringing up
this
kind of
example
and
way
of
thinking
about atent
properties.
21. Of
course,
having
flowers
also
depends
on
the
amount of
fertilizer,
sunlight,
and
water,
for without
these,
the
flower would
not
bloom at all.
But
flower
color
alone
depends
entirely
on the
acidity
of the soil.
22.
I
thankJerrold
Levinson,
Bob
Stecker,
Stephen
Davies,
Pradeep
Dhillon,
David
Eng,
and,
especially,
Lee Brown
and Susan
Feagin
for
helpful
comments
on earlier drafts
of
this
paper.
Thi t t d l d d f m 83 137 211 198 S 16 A 2015 19 14 24 UTC