The Limits of the Liberal State, Migration Identity and Belonging in Europe

18
The Limits of the Liberal State: Migration, Identity and Belonging in Europe Fiona B. Adamson, Triadafilos Triadafilopoulos and Aristide R. Zolberg What are the contemporary ‘limits of the liberal state’ with respect to immigration, citizenship and the rights of ethnic and religious minorities in contemporary Europe? The papers in this special issue of the Journal of Ethnic and Migration Studies examine how recent developments in Europe raise new questions regarding the relationship between liberalism, migration, identity and belonging. In this introduction, we identify three major themes that run through the papers in the issue*the use of liberal norms by states for exclusionary purposes; the possibility of the emergence of ‘illiberal liberalism’; and the extent to which identity politics and policy-making may be increasingly transcending and transforming the limits of the liberal democratic state in Europe. After briefly presenting these three themes, we summarise the arguments of the individual authors and suggest possible directions for future research. Keywords: Liberalism; Migration; Citizenship; Boundaries; Integration; Europe Contemporary developments in Europe raise complex and challenging questions regarding the ‘limits of the liberal state’ with respect to immigration, citizenship and the rights of ethnic and religious minorities. Whereas it has regularly been assumed that liberal norms and identities foster greater inclusion, openness and pluralism with respect to migration policies and minority rights, a number of events suggest the Fiona B. Adamson is Senior Lecturer in International Relations at the School of Oriental and African Studies, University of London. Correspondence to: Dr F.B. Adamson, Dept of Politics and International Studies, SOAS, University of London, Thornhaugh Street, Russell Square, London WC1H 0XG, UK. E-mail: [email protected]. Triadafilos Triadafilopoulos is Assistant Professor of Political Science at the University of Toronto. Correspondence to: Prof. T. Triadafilopoulos, Dept of Political Science, University of Toronto, 100 St George Street, Toronto, Ontario M5S 3G3, Canada. E-mail: [email protected]. Aristide R. Zolberg is Walter P. Eberstadt Professor of Political Science at the New School for Social Research, New York. Correspondence to: Prof. A.R. Zolberg, New School for Social Research, 6 East 16th Street, New York, NY 10003, USA. E-mail: [email protected]. Journal of Ethnic and Migration Studies Vol. 37, No. 6, July 2011, pp. 843859 ISSN 1369-183X print/ISSN 1469-9451 online/11/060843-17 # 2011 Taylor & Francis DOI: 10.1080/1369183X.2011.576188

description

A short text abut migration

Transcript of The Limits of the Liberal State, Migration Identity and Belonging in Europe

Page 1: The Limits of the Liberal State, Migration Identity and Belonging in Europe

The Limits of the Liberal State:Migration, Identity and Belonging inEuropeFiona B. Adamson, Triadafilos Triadafilopoulos andAristide R. Zolberg

What are the contemporary ‘limits of the liberal state’ with respect to immigration,

citizenship and the rights of ethnic and religious minorities in contemporary Europe? The

papers in this special issue of the Journal of Ethnic and Migration Studies examine how

recent developments in Europe raise new questions regarding the relationship between

liberalism, migration, identity and belonging. In this introduction, we identify three

major themes that run through the papers in the issue*the use of liberal norms by states

for exclusionary purposes; the possibility of the emergence of ‘illiberal liberalism’; and the

extent to which identity politics and policy-making may be increasingly transcending and

transforming the limits of the liberal democratic state in Europe. After briefly presenting

these three themes, we summarise the arguments of the individual authors and suggest

possible directions for future research.

Keywords: Liberalism; Migration; Citizenship; Boundaries; Integration; Europe

Contemporary developments in Europe raise complex and challenging questions

regarding the ‘limits of the liberal state’ with respect to immigration, citizenship and

the rights of ethnic and religious minorities. Whereas it has regularly been assumed

that liberal norms and identities foster greater inclusion, openness and pluralism with

respect to migration policies and minority rights, a number of events suggest the

Fiona B. Adamson is Senior Lecturer in International Relations at the School of Oriental and African Studies,

University of London. Correspondence to: Dr F.B. Adamson, Dept of Politics and International Studies, SOAS,

University of London, Thornhaugh Street, Russell Square, London WC1H 0XG, UK. E-mail: [email protected].

Triadafilos Triadafilopoulos is Assistant Professor of Political Science at the University of Toronto.

Correspondence to: Prof. T. Triadafilopoulos, Dept of Political Science, University of Toronto, 100 St George

Street, Toronto, Ontario M5S 3G3, Canada. E-mail: [email protected]. Aristide R. Zolberg is

Walter P. Eberstadt Professor of Political Science at the New School for Social Research, New York.

Correspondence to: Prof. A.R. Zolberg, New School for Social Research, 6 East 16th Street, New York, NY

10003, USA. E-mail: [email protected].

Journal of Ethnic and Migration Studies

Vol. 37, No. 6, July 2011, pp. 843�859

ISSN 1369-183X print/ISSN 1469-9451 online/11/060843-17 # 2011 Taylor & Francis

DOI: 10.1080/1369183X.2011.576188

Page 2: The Limits of the Liberal State, Migration Identity and Belonging in Europe

need to re-evaluate such assumptions. What are we to make, for example, of the

decision of French authorities to deny a Moroccan woman’s naturalisation

application because she wore the niqab?1 In its ruling upholding immigration and

social service officials’ initial 2005 decision, the Conseil d’Etat stated that the

applicant’s decision to wear the niqab constituted ‘a radical practice of her religion

(and) behaviour in society incompatible with the essential values of the French

community, notably the principle of equality between the sexes’ (Crumley 2008). The

proliferation of similar bans on religious attire in public spaces, restrictions on

speech, mandatory integration courses, citizenship tests and controls on the

admission of spouses through amendments to family reunification policies*all

defended on the grounds that they further liberal ends*suggest the need for a closer

interrogation of the relationship between liberalism, migration, identity and

belonging in contemporary Europe.

The papers brought together in this special issue of JEMS take up this central task

of exploring and untangling the boundaries of identity and belonging in the liberal

state in Europe. The authors in this issue employ a mix of empirical, normative and

legal analyses to make sense of the changing landscape of migration and integration

policy. In so doing, they contribute to an emerging area of debate and research on

changing migration and incorporation policies in European states (Guild et al. 2009;

Joppke 2007a; Schmidtke and Ozcurumez 2008). Collectively, the papers raise a

number of challenging questions for further exploration. When, for example, does

the deployment of ‘liberal norms’ become an illiberal practice? What are (and should

be) the symbolic boundaries of identity, belonging, membership and community in

liberal democratic states? Has liberalism replaced nationalism as the ideology of

belonging in Europe, and how do and should states respond to ideas, practices or

politics that can be interpreted as ‘illiberal’? Moreover, does it indeed make sense to

even discuss such issues with reference to individual states*or do the boundaries

and limits of contemporary identity politics, as well as state policy-making, now both

transcend, quite literally, the physical and policy-making limits of the liberal state?

As a prelude to the analyses in the individual papers that follow, we briefly discuss

here some of these key themes, situating them in broader scholarly debates. We focus

on discussions regarding the ‘exclusionary’ nature of liberal norms, the question of

when liberalism becomes illiberal and the changing nature of boundaries in liberal

states. We then turn to a short summary of the individual papers before making a few

concluding remarks.

Liberal Norms as Exclusionary?

The migration studies literature has traditionally conceptualised liberal norms as key

factors in producing open migration policies, fostering integration and securing

migrants’ rights (i.e. Freeman 1995a; Hollifield 1992; Soysal 1994). Yet states in

Europe increasingly appear to also be deploying liberal norms as boundary-markers

that delimit and demarcate the symbolic borders of the state. Liberal norms, it seems,

844 F.B. Adamson, T. Triadafilopoulos & A.R. Zolberg

Page 3: The Limits of the Liberal State, Migration Identity and Belonging in Europe

may in some cases be replacing or supplementing other boundary-markers, such as

ethnic or civic nationalism, in shaping migration and integration policies in

European states.2

In many respects, this trend stands in marked contrast to assumptions regarding

policy-making in the post-WWII period. The literature on postwar immigration and

citizenship politics has emphasised the opening up of liberal states to previously

excluded groups, through the renunciation and replacement of racially discrimina-

tory admissions policies (Joppke 2005a; King 2000; Tavan 2005; Triadafilopoulos

2010); the expansion of foreigners’ rights to family reunification (Hansen 2009;

Soysal 1994); and the relaxing of rules governing residency, the provision of civil and

social rights and the acquisition of citizenship (Carens 2002; Hammar 1990; Hansen

and Koehler 2006; Hansen and Weil 2001; Jacobson 1996; Jacobson and Ruffer 2003;

Joppke 1999; Howard 2009; Soysal 1994; Weil 2001). That states are using liberal

norms in an exclusionary fashion thus presents a challenge to much of the literature

on immigration and citizenship politics and policy-making.

How are we to understand these developments? Some might argue that they simply

represent a shift in the ‘immigration cycle’ (Brubaker 1995; Freeman 1995a, 1995b)

or, alternatively, that they are primarily a reaction to a specific set of real or imagined

security threats (Hampshire 2009; Tsoukala 2005). Such policies could also be viewed

as an extension of the increasingly hostile approaches taken by liberal states to

asylum-seekers and undocumented migrants in the 1980s and 1990s. These policies

have often been explained by reference to the influence of extreme-right-wing

parties*political actors whose adherence to liberal principles, however, is question-

able (Angenendt 2003; Betz 2003; Givens 2005; Messina 2007; Minkenberg 2001,

2002; Zaslove 2008).

The deployment of liberal norms in an exclusionary fashion could represent a

populist turn in European migration and integration policy*in effect a

‘democratising’ of policy-making in this area in ways which reflect popular sentiment

rather than entrenched interest groups, thus shifting what is considered to be

legitimate public discourse on migration (Brubaker 1995; Freeman 1995a; Guiraudon

and Joppke 2001). Arguably such developments could also be interpreted as symbolic

of a deeper transformation of state identity and community boundaries away from

nationalism and towards the notion of ‘civilisational’ identities of which liberalism

then becomes a key tenet (Huntington 1996).

Illiberal Liberalism?

Not surprisingly, the challenge of understanding these developments has prompted

a lively debate. While some see the deployment of liberal norms*such as gender

equality*as a ploy for pursuing and extending long-standing exclusionary

programmes based on deeply entrenched racist mindsets (Fekete 2006; Razack

2008), others note that their support among ‘progressive’ actors is novel and

therefore worthy of more sustained analysis and explanation. Bans on religious attire

Journal of Ethnic and Migration Studies 845

Page 4: The Limits of the Liberal State, Migration Identity and Belonging in Europe

in public spaces can be squarely situated in a republican or secular liberal tradition

(Barry 2001; Bowen 2008; Laborde 2002). The deployment of liberal norms can be

viewed as a fundamentally progressive development, designed ultimately to protect

and safeguard basic liberal values of liberty, equality and tolerance in European

societies. Or, alternatively, such developments can be viewed as symptomatic of the

rise of a new form of ‘illiberal liberalism’ that draws boundaries against its ‘illiberal

others’ in a fashion that fundamentally undermines core principles of pluralism and

tolerance (Kostakopoulou 2010; Tebble 2006; Young 2002: 42�5).

This debate is not wholly new, of course. Critics of liberalism have always pointed

to its inherent contradictions, and the intimate relationship between the historical

development of liberal thought in Europe with empire, colonial domination and

racial hierarchies (McCarthy 2009; Mehta 1990, 1999). In a series of important books

and articles, Christian Joppke (2005b, 2007a, 2007b, 2009, 2010) has amended his

views on the intrinsic openness of the liberal state in diagnosing the causes of what he

has variously termed ‘regressive liberalism’ and ‘civic integrationism’. According to

Joppke (2007a: 268), recent trends warrant a Foucauldian reading of liberalism which

emphasises its power and disciplining aspects. This reading forces one to engage with

a deeply rooted repressive strain in liberal thinking. Joppke cites John Stuart Mill’s

1859/1974) approval of the use of illiberal means to achieve liberal goals as evidence

of how this strain can be seen as stemming from liberal theory itself.3 In a similar

vein, Adam Tebble (2006) argues that the use of exclusionary immigration and

integration policies reflects a distinctive mode of liberal nationalism*‘identity

liberalism’*which rejects multiculturalism’s emphasis on compromise and accom-

modation in favour of a more definitive assertion and defence of distinctively liberal

ways of life.

Both Joppke and Tebble note that new modes of liberal exclusion are indicative of

shifts in liberal theory and practice and not simply manifestations of racism, although

their effects often are*and are intended to be*exclusionary. As such, they echo and

build on Veronika Stolcke’s (1999) claim regarding the distinctiveness of contem-

porary exclusionary rhetoric and practice (see also Gilroy 2000). What Stolcke

referred to as ‘cultural fundamentalism’ has arguably been shaped into a distinctively

liberal fundamentalism that does not target foreigners per se, but rather particular

subsets of immigrants or minorities whose religious/cultural practices or political

demands are deemed incompatible with liberal ways of life. This targeting is reflected,

for example, in the deployment of integration and citizenship tests, perhaps the most

notorious of which was the German state of Baden-Wurttemberg’s ‘interview guide’

(Gesprachsleitfaden) for ascertaining the values of citizenship applicants from Muslim

countries (Joppke 2010; Prantl 2006). According to Joppke (2010), policies along

these lines seek to particularise universalism by demanding that membership in the

liberal state be reserved exclusively for liberal people. Making good on this demand

compels the liberal state to regulate the motivations and internal dispositions of

so-called ‘suspect groups’. It is precisely when liberal states move from regulating

individuals’ outward conduct to enquiring into and authoritatively prescribing

846 F.B. Adamson, T. Triadafilopoulos & A.R. Zolberg

Page 5: The Limits of the Liberal State, Migration Identity and Belonging in Europe

internal dispositions that liberalism becomes ‘regressive’ and ‘illiberal’. Joppke (2009)

maintains that European states’ distinctive forms of liberalism explain variation in the

degree and intensity of ‘illiberal liberalism’ in Europe. In so doing, he appears to

contradict his earlier (2007b) claim that the trend toward ‘civic integrationism’ had

made any talk of ‘national models’ of immigrant integration redundant. These

tensions in Joppke’s work suggest that there is still much to be done in making sense

of contemporary shifts in liberalism as it relates to issues of immigration and

integration policy in Europe.

The Boundaries of the Liberal State

Examining the ‘limits of the liberal state’ encourages us to pay closer attention to the

role that boundaries play in defining contemporary liberal democratic states. Such

boundaries can be symbolic and discursive, but may also call into question the

relationships that exist between the territorial, identity, governance and policy-

making dimensions of the European state. It is instructive that European states are

rethinking their criteria for naturalisation and incorporation of migrants at the same

time as they are facing what could be termed a ‘boundary crisis’ that is both symbolic

and literal.

Immigration and incorporation processes always raise the issue of group

boundaries of identity and belonging (Alba 2005; Korteweg and Yurdakul 2009;

Lamont and Molnar 2002). The state has historically used immigration policy as a

tool in fostering a particular national identity (Triadafilopoulos 2010; Zolberg 2006),

balancing its pursuit of economic and strategic interests against concerns of national

integration and social cohesion (Adamson 2006; Chin 2009). Zolberg and Long

(1999: 8�9) note that boundary-crossing, boundary-blurring and boundary-shifting

all represent possible patterns of identity negotiation in migration contexts, in which

the redeployment of liberal norms as boundary-markers rather than principles of

inclusion could be viewed as a form of boundary-shifting that is occurring in

European states*with the blurring of racial, ethnic and religious boundaries through

such developments as anti-discrimination legislation (Joppke 2007a)*accompanied

by the simultaneous emergence of a bright boundary of membership based on liberal

criteria.

The challenges of setting the symbolic and discursive boundaries of belonging in

Europe are compounded by additional ‘boundary challenges’ that are increasingly

relevant for understanding the limits of the liberal state. The greater openness of these

liberal states has allowed for the emergence and thickening of ‘transnational fields’

and ‘social spaces’, which temper the importance of territoriality both in scholarly

analyses of migration and in migrants’ lived experiences (Basch et al. 1993;

Bloemraad et al. 2008; Faist 2000). Meaningful transnational identities*whether

national, religious or ideational*may include political identifications that transcend

the physical boundaries of the state (Adamson and Demetriou 2007). How might

liberal states react to actions on the part of their residents*citizens and non-citizens

Journal of Ethnic and Migration Studies 847

Page 6: The Limits of the Liberal State, Migration Identity and Belonging in Europe

alike*that signal allegiance, political or spiritual, to extra-territorial authorities and/

or communities? In some contexts, the boundary negotiations occurring within

particular national contexts may also mirror broader negotiations and contestations

that occur within a geopolitical context. In this sense, they are not merely national

negotiations, but are tied into larger global circuits of power and identity. Within the

UK, for example, identity claims and political demands made by Muslims are often

articulated using language that evokes a broader geopolitical context of British

foreign policy and US hegemony. The liberal state may be viewed not simply as a

domestic arena for identity negotiation, but as a component of a broader geopolitical

structure of liberal hegemony (Adamson 2005). Similarly, Muslim political demands

articulated within a domestic context may also reference debates and discourses that

emerge within the broader context of a transnational Muslim public sphere.

The challenge faced by liberal democratic states is therefore how to reconcile liberal

principles and identities that transcend the state (Soysal 1994) with competing

principles or sources of authority which also transcend it. An example of this type of

conflict would be the liberal principle of equality under the law, with demands for the

recognition of a plurality of legal frameworks within the liberal state. Such questions

have, of course, been the staple of long-standing debates on multiculturalism and

communitarianism. Jonathan Laurence’s (2006) work on the incorporation of Islam

in contemporary European liberal democracies suggests that concerns regarding

religious transnationalism among Muslims (encouraged in part by European

receiving states’ tendency to leave the spiritual needs of immigrants to sending

countries and/or Muslim states claiming authority in religious matters) is leading

European states to forge formal consultative links to domestic groups representing

Muslims. Here transnationalism has provoked noteworthy and consequential

boundary shifts featuring the adaptation of existing corporatist institutions

regulating church�state relations to better capture the realities of societies

transformed by postwar immigration. In a similar vein, Matthias Koenig (2007)

has demonstrated that global human-rights norms have pushed European states to

extend religious rights previously reserved for Christians and Jews to Muslim

immigrants. Here an unbounded, broadly encompassing ‘logic of appropriateness’

has provoked shifts in domestic institutions and practices in a more-or-less

inclusionary trajectory. These examples of integrative boundary shifting stand in

stark contrast to the more exclusionary tendencies pointed out in discussions of

illiberal liberalism, suggesting that approaches to integration may be informed by

quite distinctive logics, ranging from corporatist/problem-solving to partisan/

political.

These various challenges point to the tenuous nature of the identity boundaries of

the liberal state in an age in which territorial nationalism is increasingly being

challenged (Wimmer and Glick Schiller 2002, 2003). The importance of territory is

being called into question, for example, in the emergence of ‘external integration

measures’ in which some European states are administering integration tests abroad

(Guild et al. 2009: 9�14). This can be viewed as an extension of the ‘remote control’

848 F.B. Adamson, T. Triadafilopoulos & A.R. Zolberg

Page 7: The Limits of the Liberal State, Migration Identity and Belonging in Europe

border policies of the 1990s (Guiraudon and Lahav 2000; see also Torpey 2000;

Zolberg 1997). At the same time, questions relating to the boundaries of membership,

identity and belonging are being raised in a period marked by shifting boundaries of

policy-making and governance, as regional institutions are increasingly involved in

shaping migration and incorporation policy at the state level. With the transfer of

immigration policy competence to the EU in 1999, the issuing of the EU Race

Directive in 2000, and the emergence of the EU framework on integration that

produced a set of ‘Common Basic Principles for Immigrants’ Integration’ in 2004,

aspects of policy-making in liberal democratic states in Europe are now increasingly

being delegated, at least in part, to Brussels (Guild et al. 2009; Joppke 2007a;

Thielemann 2008).

Summary of Articles

The papers in this special issue of JEMS employ a mix of analytical, normative and

legal reasoning to contribute to these emerging debates and areas of research. In

developing their arguments, the contributors draw on a wide range of perspectives

and literatures, including comparative politics, sociology, political theory, interna-

tional relations and EU law. The papers collectively explore the contemporary policy

challenges and contexts with which liberal states are grappling; examining what

liberal states are doing empirically in terms of policy and, in some cases, what they

ought to do if they are to live up to their status as liberal states and achieve their

policy objectives. Hence, the articles in this issue contribute both to recent empirical

work on migration and integration politics and more-philosophically oriented works

on multiculturalism and the so-called ‘limits of toleration’ in contemporary liberal-

democratic states.

Not surprisingly, given the variety of disciplinary and philosophical perspectives

the authors bring to their work, the range of diagnoses and prescriptions vary*at

times quite widely*making for a lively exchange of ideas and interpretations. Here

we briefly summarise the main arguments of the authors in this issue before

concluding with some thoughts as to how research on the limits of the liberal state in

the spheres of immigration, integration and ethnic and minority rights in Europe

might move forward.

Triadafilos Triadafilopoulos argues in the next article that the turn to a more

aggressive ‘civic integrationism’ among European states is based on a complex

confluence of factors, including the breakdown of the postwar economic order and

consequent hollowing out of welfare states, the dissolution of party systems and the

rise of ‘new’ parties of the Left and Right, the end of the Cold War, the deepening and

expansion of European integration and the emergence of the so-called ‘war on terror’,

which has emphasised civilisational distinctions based in part on religious differences.

Triadafilopoulos argues that these factors form a backdrop for the emergence of a

distinctively ‘Schmittian liberalism’, which rejects multicultural accommodation and

compromise and seeks instead to protect liberal publics from migrant groups whose

Journal of Ethnic and Migration Studies 849

Page 8: The Limits of the Liberal State, Migration Identity and Belonging in Europe

unfamiliarity with liberal values and putatively illiberal practices calls for either their

full assimilation into liberal ways of life (through integration courses and bans on

religious attire and practices) or outright exclusion, either at the border (through

more stringent admissions policies, especially as regards family reunification) or into

the citizenry (through rigorous naturalisation tests). Triadafilopoulos notes that,

while some manifestations of Schmittian liberalism may be consistent with certain

strands of the liberal tradition*indeed, they are a logical outcome of perfectionist

approaches taken to their extremes*they are not likely to be helpful in terms of

furthering integration and social cohesion. As Triadafilopoulos concludes, Schmittian

liberals ‘risk alienating the very groups they seek to integrate*turning potential

friends into enemies’. Thus, he calls for integration policies that are ‘consistent with

liberal-democratic values but also respectful of deeply held differences and open to

dialogue and mutual accommodation’.

Randall Hansen next offers a competing perspective in his contribution to the

debate. Drawing on survey data on Muslims in Britain and France, he argues that

European states must reconsider the particular form of liberalism they embrace, if

they are to harness immigration in a manner consistent with their interests. With

regards to the economy, Hansen notes that overly generous Continental European

welfare states have tended to integrate immigrants into welfare rather than work,

leading to ‘unemployment rates among immigrants [that] are at best double the

national average and, at worst, over three times it’. He therefore counsels a laissez faire

direction, as represented first and foremost by the United States, so that immigrants

are given greater incentives to enter the labour market. According to Hansen, ‘[t]he

solution for Europe...is a bit of tough love: reduce or remove welfare benefits for

migrants, and make it clear to them that they are welcome, but that their welcome is

contingent upon their willingness to enter the labour market’.

With regard to identity, Hansen rejects liberal multiculturalism, arguing that it

weakens bonds of commonality among immigrants and members of the host society.

He recommends instead that European states adopt more assertive, self-confident

expressions of national identity modelled after the French republican tradition, as

doing so will provide immigrants with a clearer sense of what the society they are

joining holds up as its core values. While the freedom of religion remains deeply

embedded in liberal states’ practices, it should be limited to the private sphere and

granted to individuals rather than groups*with special exemptions and accom-

modations granted only in rare circumstances. The broader public sphere should be

governed by civic mores and clear expectations, reinforced by state power where

necessary.

Fiona Adamson’s article also examines the relationship between Muslims and the

liberal state in Europe. She examines the growing use of ‘Muslim’ as a category by

both Muslims and state authorities in Europe. Placing contemporary domestic

debates surrounding Islam in Europe in a broader geopolitical context, Adamson

argues that the emergence of ‘Muslim identity politics’ in European states cannot be

understood only as a domestic-level development internal to states, but must also be

850 F.B. Adamson, T. Triadafilopoulos & A.R. Zolberg

Page 9: The Limits of the Liberal State, Migration Identity and Belonging in Europe

seen as deeply connected with geopolitics and with broader debates and discourses

that are occurring in globalised Muslim public spheres that extend beyond the state.

Focusing on the variety of Muslim political organisations operating in the UK,

Adamson points out that the deployment of the political identity category of

‘Muslim’ vis-a-vis the liberal state can be used by different actors for different

purposes. On the one hand, there are groups such as the Muslim Council of Britain

(MCB) that can be viewed largely as a standard interest-group*an umbrella

organisation that presents itself as primarily interested in collective claims-making,

lobbying and interest representation on behalf of British Muslims seeking to secure

their rights to exercise religious freedom. On the other hand, a group such as Hizb

ut-Tahrir uses the category of ‘Muslim’ as a means of asserting a political identity that

stands in opposition to the liberal state. This group has explicitly juxtaposed a

‘Muslim’ identity with a ‘British’ or ‘Western’ variant and has, at times, publicly

encouraged British Muslims to reject liberalism, disengage from institutionalised

participation in British politics, and instead identify themselves primarily with a

broader global ummah in the form of working for the re-establishment of a global

caliphate. While a group such as Hizb ut-Tahrir represents a minority perspective, it

nonetheless provides an explicit example of a form of ‘illiberal politics’ which liberal

states must then respond to*with some liberal states banning such a group

(as Germany did in 2003) and others accepting it as one amongst a multitude of

competing voices that are expressed as part of free debate in a liberal state’s civil

society.

Erik Bleich’s article examines this dilemma in greater detail by exploring the limits

of free speech in liberal states. Tracing liberal states’ approaches to the regulation of

hate speech and hate crimes since World War II, Bleich argues that liberal states are

capable of enacting and enforcing laws that limit the ‘freedom to be racist’ while

maintaining liberal principles of freedom of opinion and freedom of expression. The

‘slow creep’ that has typified policy development in this area reflects states’ efforts to

balance respect for freedom of speech with ‘[v]alues such as community cohesion,

public order [and] human dignity’. This ‘value shift’ is a distinctively post-WWII

phenomenon, rooted in liberal states’ reactions to the horrors of Nazism, the

emergence of human rights norms, and the discrediting of racism. Bleich notes that

liberal states’ particular approaches to the regulation of racist speech and conduct

differ; while most European states have implemented ‘laws against forms of racist

speech such as incitement to racial hatred and Holocaust denial’, the US has bucked

this trend by ‘elevating the value of free speech over protections against racist

language’. However, as Bleich goes on to note, the US has also introduced laws that

penalise racially motivated crimes, such as assault and battery, ‘despite their potential

to infringe on freedom of opinion and expression’. This distinctive feature of the

American approach has been picked up by some European countries and especially

by Great Britain, where policy-makers explicitly drew on legislation introduced in

the US.

Journal of Ethnic and Migration Studies 851

Page 10: The Limits of the Liberal State, Migration Identity and Belonging in Europe

While Bleich sees the regulation of racist speech and conduct as broadly in line

with liberal norms, he fears that recent trends push the limits of this compatibility.

As an example, he notes that the ‘British government has used the ‘‘war on terror’’ to

justify expanding its laws to cover incitement to religious hatred [while] also

enact[ing] provisions to punish the glorification of terrorism, which could prohibit

statements made against racial, ethnic or religious groups that have been the targets

of attacks’. The elevation of national cohesion and public order through these laws

may lead to further curbs on speech. In another case, France’s efforts to outlaw

denials of the Armenian genocide may open the door to claimants who want to

establish their victimhood as legally unassailable. According to Bleich, the key to

avoiding such slippery slopes lies in proceeding cautiously, cognisant of the

particulars of the case at hand, the difference between ‘racist expression that incites

violence and stirs up extreme hatred’ and ‘speech that is merely offensive, even if

hurtfully so’.

Gallya Ruffer’s article focuses on recent debates over family reunification policy, at

both the EU and member-state levels. Ruffer notes that the rationale animating

family reunification policies has changed; whereas ‘family reunification was thought

of as a socially just and practical solution that would enable the integration of

long-term labour migrants’ in the past, more recently it has been used to shape

‘cultural integration’ by limiting access to particular groups of immigrants,

particularly Muslims. States such as Denmark, France, the Netherlands, Germany,

Austria and Britain have introduced provisions ostensibly aimed at preventing forced

and fraudulent marriages and enhancing the ‘assimilability’ of immigrants through

integration tests and courses to be taken outside the destination country in advance of

admission. Ruffer maintains that such policies are best thought of as means

undertaken by states to weed out undesirable migrants and thus reassert control

over nation-building. This leads to perverse situations where immigrants who hold

citizenship in an EU member-state enjoy rights to family reunification and mobility

that are withheld from Third Country Nationals (TCNs). Efforts aimed at improving

and streamlining the treatment of TCNs at the EU level have been tempered by

member-states’ insistence on maintaining their sovereign right to guide societal

integration through immigration controls.

Ruffer also notes that European courts’ adjudication of the rights of immigrants

versus states has been uneven, owing in part to differences in their conceptualisations

of the ‘right to family life’. Though subtle, these differences have allowed

policy-makers at the member-state level to justify restrictions on family reunification

that would otherwise be unconstitutional under domestic law. The end result is a

situation where children and spouses face new barriers to their ability to join family

members in European countries. Ruffer maintains that such positions hark back to an

antiquated conceptualisation of membership, unsuited to an increasingly mobile

world. As such, she argues in favour of a very different approach to family

reunification, premised on the recognition that ‘under conditions of migration,

cultures will remain in flux’.

852 F.B. Adamson, T. Triadafilopoulos & A.R. Zolberg

Page 11: The Limits of the Liberal State, Migration Identity and Belonging in Europe

James Hampshire’s article focuses on debates over naturalisation courses and tests,

asking whether demands for evidence of immigrants’ societal integration on the part

of the state as a precondition for their being granted citizenship are warranted.

Hampshire distinguishes liberal arguments in favour of quick access to citizenship

after a short period of residency to nationalist positions which hold that

naturalisation can only move forward where immigrants demonstrate assimilation

into a national culture. Hampshire notes that the nationalist position is problematic

on both philosophical and empirical grounds. With regard to norms, liberal states’

commitment to neutrality makes the imposition of a particular view of the good life

illegitimate: ‘[a] requirement that naturalising citizens assimilate to a thick national

culture amounts to the imposition of a particular conception of the good and is to

that extent illiberal’. This commitment to neutrality is also based on the recognition

that life in contemporary liberal states is shaped by the ‘fact of pluralism’; thus the

onus is on nationalists to identify a particular national culture which naturalising

citizens could be expected to assimilate into. While there may indeed be a ‘majority

culture’, there will also be important areas of disagreement on what the national

culture is and what the principal goals of the nation should be. In short, ‘in pluralist

societies there simply is no consensus about national identity’.

Yet, the discrediting of the nationalist argument does not vindicate a minimalist

liberal position. Hampshire maintains that democratic politics depends on citizens

sharing some core competencies or ‘civic skills’, including the ability to understand

and interact with each other in a common language. Moreover, ‘flourishing liberal

societies are founded upon liberal citizens who are reflective and self-critical, and who

accept and endorse the public values of a pluralistic and tolerant public culture’.

These insights lead Hampshire to endorse a thickening of the liberal position on

naturalisation: while assimilation into a common culture is ruled out, demands that

immigrants demonstrate some knowledge of the host states’ official language(s) and

the ‘generic liberal values that govern public life’ are justifiable on liberal grounds.

While immigrants should be expected to take advantage of opportunities to engage in

language and civics training provided by the state, tests should not determine

whether citizenship is conferred. In other words, a normatively defensible liberalism

accepts compulsory attendance in integration courses but looks suspiciously at tests

which can be used to deny access to citizenship.

Conclusion

We trust that the contributions to this special issue of JEMS will provoke further

debate and research on the ‘limits of the liberal state’ in Europe. In particular, we

hope the collection demonstrates the fruitfulness of interdisciplinary engagement. By

combining insights from both empirical and theoretically oriented literatures, and by

taking perspectives that focus on national policy-making as well as the regional and

transnational context within which liberal states are embedded, we present a complex

and nuanced view of the multiple ways in which boundaries of membership,

Journal of Ethnic and Migration Studies 853

Page 12: The Limits of the Liberal State, Migration Identity and Belonging in Europe

belonging and identity are being renegotiated in Europe with respect to migration,

citizenship and ethnic and minority rights.

As a research agenda, much work needs still to be done to understand the

limits of the liberal state in Europe. States*liberal or otherwise*‘do not

function as autonomous actors . . . but rather as instruments manipulated by

internal actors who have gained the upper hand in this particular sphere at a

given time’ (Zolberg 2006: 12); hence, we need to pay closer attention to the

influence of parties, the media, opinion-makers and social movements. Recent

work by Marc Howard (2009) and Erik Bleich (2009) offers stimulating insights

into how distinctively political processes, featuring discreet actors and institu-

tions, may be analysed to better understand liberal-democratic states’ responses

to immigration- and membership-related challenges.

Secondly, more work needs to be undertaken to explain the variation in particular

states’ approaches to the regulation of practices, speech and other embodied forms of

cultural difference. Here scholars in the field of migration studies could benefit from

paying closer attention to the contributions of students of social policy, who

emphasise the mediating role of formal and informal institutions (for a good

overview see Amenta 2003). Koenig’s (2005) research on varieties of church�state

relations and their influence on liberal states’ approaches to the integration of

religious minorities generally, and Muslims in particular, offers a good example of

such an approach. More-ethnographically oriented work also points to the

importance of local understandings in shaping outcomes.

Thirdly, there needs to be a greater level of dialogue between comparative or

single-country scholars of migration and scholars of International Relations and

transnationalism, whose work can help to illuminate broader global trends in, for

example, the structure of global civil society, the role of regional and international

organisations in norm promotion, and in shaping policy-making and policy

outcomes, as well as drawing attention to the geopolitical context within which

national-level debates and policy developments take place. As Peter Gourevitch

(1978) pointed out long ago, domestic politics is embedded in global structures and

processes. Identifying and theorising these linkages will go a long way toward better

understanding trends in liberal states’ conduct over time in the fields of immigration,

citizenship and integration policy.

Fourthly, and finally, there is the important issue*largely unaddressed in these

papers*of liberalism’s lack of guidance with regard to the formulation of admission

policies. Given the steadily growing demand from the developing world for entry to

states in Europe, which is unlikely to abate in the foreseeable future, there must be

some grounds for limiting admissions; and if admissions are going to be limited,

there is a need for selection criteria among the demand. Should liberal states privilege

the entry of temporary foreign workers in a bid to meet domestic needs while

simultaneously creating an indirect mode of international development assistance

driven by remittances, as recommended by economists such as Lant Pritchett (2008),

or should liberal principles counsel that labour migration of any kind be downplayed

854 F.B. Adamson, T. Triadafilopoulos & A.R. Zolberg

Page 13: The Limits of the Liberal State, Migration Identity and Belonging in Europe

in an effort to meet the needs of refugees and thus stem the misery of the world’s

most vulnerable individuals and groups? While there have been some important

responses to these questions (see, for example, Carens 1987, 2010; Ruhs and Martin

2008; Zolberg 2010), more sustained attention is sorely needed to both clarify liberal

principles and guide liberal states’ policies and practices.

Ultimately, we believe that the papers in this special issue of JEMS should

encourage scholars to take more care to combine insights generated by both

empirically and normatively driven research programmes. With some all-too-rare

exceptions, empirically and normatively oriented scholars have tended to ignore each

others’ insights, preferring to operate on more familiar, specialist terrains. We believe

this is a mistake and hope that the papers in this special issue demonstrate the

benefits of combining empirically and more-normatively driven lines of inquiry. This

will allow for well-grounded theories and observations that also provide direction to

policy-makers grappling with the challenges of immigration and integration in

contemporary liberal-democratic states.

Acknowledgements

We would like to acknowledge the generous support of the Foundation for

Population, Migration and the Environment (PME) in Switzerland for the

sponsorship of the workshop ‘The Limits of the Liberal State: Migration, Identity

and Belonging in Europe’ at University College London (UCL) in December 2006,

from whence these papers are derived. Additional support was provided by the

School of Public Policy (SPP) at UCL. We are particularly grateful to Sally Welham,

who managed the logistics of the workshop. In addition to the authors included in

this special issue, additional workshop participants and observers*including

Michael Bodemann, Khadijah Elshayyal, Pontus Odmalm, Saime Ozcurumez and

Gokce Yurdukal, along with an anonymous JEMS reviewer*provided helpful

comments that informed this introduction and the editing of the special collection.

We would also like to thank the Council of European Studies (CES) for supporting

our grant application to the PME Foundation in the context of the Council’s

Immigration Research Group (IRG). Finally, our thanks extend to Jenny Money and

Russell King at the Journal of Ethnic and Migration Studies for their facilitation of this

special issue.

Notes

[1] The much-publicised case of Faizi Silmi, often referred to in the context of ‘banning the

burqa’, actually involved the wearing of the niqab (Erlanger 2009).

[2] On ethnic and civic nationalism, see Brubaker (1992, 1998); Greenfeld (1992); Yack (1996).

For an argument espousing the compatibility of liberalism and nationalism, see also

Kymlicka (2001); Tamir (1995).

[3] ‘Despotism is a legitimate mode of government in dealing with barbarians, provided the end

be their improvement and the means justified by actually effecting that end’ (Mill 1859).

Journal of Ethnic and Migration Studies 855

Page 14: The Limits of the Liberal State, Migration Identity and Belonging in Europe

References

Adamson, F.B. (2005) ‘Global liberalism vs. political Islam: competing ideological frameworks in

international politics?’, International Studies Review, 7(4): 547�69.

Adamson, F.B. (2006) ‘Crossing borders: international migration and national security’,

International Security, 31(1): 165�99.

Adamson, F.B. and Demetriou, M. (2007) ‘Remapping the boundaries of ‘‘state’’ and ‘‘national

identity’’: incorporating diasporas into IR theorizing’, European Journal of International

Relations, 13(4): 489�526.

Alba, R. (2005) ‘Bright vs. blurred boundaries: second generation assimilation and exclusion in

France, Germany and the United States’, Ethnic and Racial Studies, 28(1): 20�49.

Amenta, E. (2003) ‘What we know about the development of social policy: comparative and

historical research in comparative and historical perspective’, in Mahone, J. and Rueschemeyer,

D. (eds) Comparative Historical Analysis in the Social Sciences. Cambridge: Cambridge

University Press, 91�130.

Angenendt, S. (2003) ‘Einwanderung und Rechtspopulismus: eine Analyse im europaischen

Vergleich’, Internationale Politik, 58(4): 3�12.

Barry, B. (2001) Culture and Equality. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

Basch, L., Glick Schiller, N. and Szanton-Blanc, C. (1993) Nations Unbound: Transnational Projects,

Postcolonial Predicaments, and Deterritorialized Nation States. New York: Routledge.

Betz, H.-G. (2003) ‘Rechtspopulismus in Westeuropa: Aktuelle Entwicklungen und Politische

Bedeutungen’, Osterreichische Zeitschrift fur Politikwissenschaft, 31(3): 251�64.

Bleich, E. (2009) ‘State responses to ‘‘Muslim’’ violence: a comparison of six West European

countries’, Journal of Ethnic and Migration Studies, 35(3): 361�79.

Bloemraad, I., Korteweg, A. and Yurdakul, G. (2008) ‘Citizenship and immigration:

multiculturalism, assimilation, and challenges to the nation-state’, Annual Review of

Sociology, 34: 1�27.

Bowen, J.R. (2008) Why the French Don’t Like Headscarves: Islam, the State and Public Space.

Princeton: Princeton University Press.

Brubaker, R. (1992) Citizenship and Nationhood in France and Germany. Cambridge, MA: Harvard

University Press.

Brubaker, R. (1995) ‘Comments on modes of immigration politics in liberal democratic states’,

International Migration Review, 29(4): 903�8.

Brubaker, R. (1998) ‘Myths and misconceptions in the study of nationalism’, in Hall, J.A. (ed.) The

State of the Nation: Ernest Gellner and the Theory of Nationalism. Cambridge: Cambridge

University Press, 272�306.

Carens, J. (1987) ‘Aliens and citizens’, Review of Politics, 49(2): 251�73.

Carens, J. (2002) ‘Citizenship and civil society: what rights for residents?’, in Hansen, R. and Weil, P.

(eds) Dual Nationality, Social Rights and Federal Citizenship in the US and Europe: The

Reinvention of Citizenship. Oxford: Berghahn, 100�20.

Carens, J. (2010) ‘Live-in domestics, seasonal workers, and others hard to locate on the map of

democracy’, in Fishkin, J. and Goodin, R. (eds) Population and Political Theory. Oxford:

Blackwell, 206�34.

Chin, R. (2009) The Guest Worker Program in Postwar Germany. Cambridge and New York:

Cambridge University Press.

Crumley, B. (2008) ‘Will France impose a ban on the burqa?’, Time, 19 July, online at: http//www.

time.com.

Erlanger, S. (2009) ‘Burqa furor scrambles French politics’, New York Times, 31 August.

Faist, T. (2000) The Volume and Dynamics of International Migration and Transnational Social

Spaces. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

856 F.B. Adamson, T. Triadafilopoulos & A.R. Zolberg

Page 15: The Limits of the Liberal State, Migration Identity and Belonging in Europe

Fekete, L. (2006) ‘Enlightened fundamentalism? Immigration, feminism and the Right’, Race and

Class, 48(2): 1�22.

Freeman., G.P. (1995a) ‘Modes of immigration politics in liberal democratic states’, International

Migration Review, 29(4): 881�901.

Freeman, G.P. (1995b) ‘Modes of immigration politics in liberal democratic states: rejoinder’,

International Migration Review, 29(4): 909�13.

Gilroy, P. (2000) Against Race: Imagining Political Culture Beyond the Color Line. Cambridge:

Belknap Press.

Givens, T.E. (2005) Voting Radical Right in Western Europe. Cambridge and New York: Cambridge

University Press.

Gourevitch, P. (1978) ‘The second image reversed: international sources of domestic politics’,

International Organization, 32(4): 881�912.

Greenfeld, L. (1992) Nationalism: Five Roads to Modernity. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University

Press.

Guild, E., Groenenduk, K. and Carrera, S. (2009) Illiberal Liberal States: Immigration, Citizenship

and Integration in the EU. Farnham: Ashgate.

Guiraudon, V. and Joppke, C. (2001) ‘Controlling a new migration world’, in Guiraudon, V. and

Joppke, C. (eds) Controlling a New Migration World. New York: Routledge, 1�28.

Guiraudon, V. and Lahav, G. (2000) ‘Comparative perspectives on migration control: away from the

border and outside the state’, in Andrea, P. and Snyder, T. (eds) The Wall Around the West:

State Borders and Migration Controls in North America and Europe. New York: Rowman and

Littlefield, 55�80.

Hammar, T. (1990) Democracy and the Nation State: Aliens, Denizens and Citizens in a World of

International Migration. Aldershot: Avebury.

Hampshire, J. (2009) ‘Disembedding liberalism? Immigration politics and security in Britain since

9/11’, in Freeman, G., Givens, T. and Leal, D. (eds) Immigration Policy and Security: US,

European and Commonwealth Perspectives. New York: Palgrave Macmillan, 109�29.

Hansen, R. (2009) ‘The poverty of postnationalism: citizenship, immigration, and the new Europe’,

Theory and Society, 38(1): 1�24.

Hansen, R. and Koehler, J. (2006) ‘Issue definition, political discourse and the politics of nationality

reform in France and Germany’, European Journal of Political Research, 44(5): 623�44.

Hansen, R and Weil, P. (2001) Towards a European Nationality: Citizenship, Immigration and

Nationality Law in the EU. New York: Palgrave Macmillan.

Hollifield, J.F. (1992) Immigrants, Markets, and States: The Political Economy of Postwar Europe.

Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

Howard, M.M. (2009) The Politics of Citizenship in Europe. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Huntington, S.P. (1996) The Clash of Civilizations and the Remaking of World Order. New York:

Simon and Schuster.

Jacobson, D. (1996) Rights Across Borders: Immigration and the Decline of Citizenship. Baltimore:

Johns Hopkins University Press.

Jacobson, D. and Ruffer, G.B. (2003) ‘Courts across borders: the implications of judicial agency for

human rights and democracy’, Human Rights Quarterly, 25(1): 74�93.

Joppke, C. (1999) Immigration and the Nation-State: The United States, Germany, and Great Britain.

New York: Oxford University Press.

Joppke, C. (2005a) Selecting By Origin: Ethnic Migration in the Liberal State. Cambridge: Harvard

University Press.

Joppke, C. (2005b) ‘The retreat of multiculturalism in the liberal state’, British Journal of Sociology,

55(2): 237�57.

Joppke, C. (2007a) ‘Transformation of immigrant integration: civic integration and antidiscrimina-

tion in the Netherlands, France and Germany’, World Politics, 59(2): 243�73.

Journal of Ethnic and Migration Studies 857

Page 16: The Limits of the Liberal State, Migration Identity and Belonging in Europe

Joppke, C. (2007b) ‘Beyond national models: civic integration policies for immigrants in Western

Europe’, West European Politics, 30(1): 1�22.

Joppke, C. (2009) Veil: Mirror of Identity. Oxford: Polity Press.

Joppke, C. (2010) Citizenship and Immigration. Cambridge: Polity Press.

King, D. (2000) Making Americans: Immigration, Race, and the Origins of the Diverse Democracy.

Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

Koenig, M. (2005) ‘Incorporating Muslim migrants in Western nation-states: a comparison of the

United Kingdom, France, and Germany’, Journal of International Migration and Integration,

6(2): 219�34.

Koenig, M. (2007) ‘Europeanising the governance of religious diversity: an institutionalist account

of Muslim struggles for public recognition’, Journal of Ethnic and Migration Studies, 33(6):

911�32.

Korteweg, A. and Yurdakul, G. (2009) ‘Gender, Islam and immigrant integration: boundary drawing

on honour killing in the Netherlands and Germany’, Ethnic and Racial Studies, 32(2): 218�38.

Kostakopoulou, D. (2010) ‘Matters of control: integration tests, naturalisation reform and

probationary citizenship in the United Kingdom’, Journal of Ethnic and Migration Studies,

36(5): 829�46.

Kymlicka, W. (2001) Politics in the Vernacular: Nationalism, Multiculturalism, and Citizenship.

Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Laborde, C. (2002) ‘Secular philosophy and Muslim headscarves in schools’, Journal of Political

Philosophy, 13(3): 305�29.

Lamont, M. and Molnar, V. (2002) ‘The study of boundaries in the social sciences’, Annual Review of

Sociology, 28: 167�95.

Laurence, J. (2006) ‘Managing transnational Islam: Muslims and the state in Western Europe’,

in Parsons, T. and Smeeding, C. (eds) Immigration and the Transformation of Europe.

Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 251�73.

McCarthy, T. (2009) Race, Empire and the Idea of Human Development. Cambridge: Cambridge

University Press.

Mehta, U. (1990) ‘Liberal strategies of exclusion’, Politics and Society, 18(4): 427�54.

Mehta, U. (1999) Liberalism and Empire: A Study in Nineteenth-Century British Liberal Thought.

Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

Messina, A. (2007) The Logics and Politics of Post-WWII Migration to Europe. Cambridge:

Cambridge University Press.

Mill, J.S. (1859) On Liberty. London: Penguin.

Minkenberg, M. (2001) ‘The radical right in public office: agenda-setting and policy effects’, West

European Politics, 24(4): 1�22.

Minkenberg, M. (2002) ‘The new radical right in the political process: interaction effects in France

and Germany’, in Schain, M., Zolberg, A.R. and Hossay, P. (eds) Shadows Over Europe: The

Development and Impact of the Extreme Right Wing in Western Europe. Basingstoke: Palgrave,

245�68.

Prantl, H. (2006) ‘Baden-Wurttemberg: ‘‘Alle Muslime sind verdachtig’’’, Suddeutsche Zeitung,

29 January.

Pritchett, L. (2008) ‘The future of migration: irresistible forces meet immovable ideas’, in Zedillo

Ponce de Leon, E. (ed.) The Future of Globalization: Explorations in Light of Recent Turbulence.

New York: Routledge, 358�83.

Razack, S. (2008) Casting Out: The Eviction of Muslims from Western Law and Politics. Toronto:

University of Toronto Press.

Ruhs, M. and Martin, P. (2008) ‘Numbers vs. rights: trade-offs and guest worker programs’,

International Migration Review, 42(1): 249�65.

Schmidtke, O. and Ozcurumez, S. (2008) Of States, Rights, and Social Closure: Governing Migration

and Citizenship. New York: Palgrave Macmillan.

858 F.B. Adamson, T. Triadafilopoulos & A.R. Zolberg

Page 17: The Limits of the Liberal State, Migration Identity and Belonging in Europe

Soysal, Y.N. (1994) Limits of Citizenship: Migrants and Postnational Membership in Europe. Chicago:

University of Chicago Press.

Stolcke, V. (1999) ‘New rhetorics of exclusion in Europe’, International Social Science Journal,

51(159): 25�35.

Tamir, Y. (1995) Liberal Nationalism. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

Tavan, G. (2005) The Long, Slow Death of White Australia. Melbourne: Scribe.

Tebble, A. (2006) ‘Exclusion for democracy’, Political Theory, 34(4): 463�87.

Thielemann, E. (2008) ‘Towards a Common European asylum policy: forced migration, collective

security and burden-sharing’, in Freeman, G. and Givens, T. (eds) Immigration After 9/11.

New York: Palgrave, 167�86.

Torpey, J. (2000) ‘States and the regulation of migration in the twentieth-century North Atlantic

world’, in Andreas, P. and Snider, T. (eds) The Wall Around the West: State Borders and

Immigration Controls in North America and Europe. Lanham: Rowman and Littlefield, 31�54.

Triadafilopoulos, T. (2010) ‘Global norms, domestic institutions and the transformation of

immigration policy in Canada and the United States’, Review of International Studies, 36(1):

169�93.

Tsoukala, A. (2005) ‘Looking at migrants as enemies’, in Bigo, D. and Guild, E. (eds) Controlling

Frontiers: Free Movement Into and Within Europe. Aldershot: Ashgate, 161�92.

Weil, P. (2001) ‘Access to citizenship: a comparison of twenty-five nationality laws’, in Aleinikoff,

T.A. and Klusmeyer, D. (eds) Citizenship Today: Global Perspectives and Practices.

Washington: Carnegie Endowment for International Peace, 17�35.

Wimmer, A. and Glick Schiller, N. (2002) ‘Methodological nationalism and beyond: nation-state

building, migration and the social sciences’, Global Networks, 2(4): 301�34.

Wimmer, A. and Glick Schiller, N. (2003) ‘Methodological nationalism, the social sciences and the

study of migration: an essay in historical epistemology’, International Migration Review,

37(3): 576�610.

Yack, B. (1996) ‘The myth of the civic nation’, Critical Review, 10(2): 193�212.

Young, S.P. (2002) Beyond Rawls: An Analysis of the Concept of Political Liberalism. Lanham:

University of Maryland Press.

Zaslove, A. (2008) ‘Community, exclusion, and a populist political economy: the radical right as an

anti-globalization movement’, Comparative European Politics, 6(2): 169�90.

Zolberg, A.R. (1997) ‘The great wall against China: responses to the first immigration crisis’, in

Lucassen, J. and Lucassen, L. (eds) Migration, Migration History, History: Old Paradigms and

New Perspectives. New York: Peter Lang, 291�315.

Zolberg, A.R. (2006) A Nation by Design: Immigration Policy in the Fashioning of America.

Cambridge: Harvard University Press and New York: Russell Sage Foundation.

Zolberg, A.R. (2010) ‘Why not the whole world? Ethical dilemmas of immigration policy’.

Barcelona: Pompeu Fabra University, paper prepared for a conference on the ‘Ethics of

International Migration Management’, 31 May.

Zolberg, A.R. and Long, L.W. (1999) ‘Why Islam is like Spanish: cultural incorporation in Europe

and the United States’, Politics and Society, 27(1): 5�38.

Journal of Ethnic and Migration Studies 859

Page 18: The Limits of the Liberal State, Migration Identity and Belonging in Europe

Copyright of Journal of Ethnic & Migration Studies is the property of Routledge and its content may not be

copied or emailed to multiple sites or posted to a listserv without the copyright holder's express written

permission. However, users may print, download, or email articles for individual use.