The Limits of Cladism- by David L. Hull Systematic Zoology, Vol. 28, No. 4 (Dec., 1979), pp....

download The Limits of Cladism- by David L. Hull Systematic Zoology, Vol. 28, No. 4 (Dec., 1979), pp. 416-440.

of 26

Transcript of The Limits of Cladism- by David L. Hull Systematic Zoology, Vol. 28, No. 4 (Dec., 1979), pp....

  • 8/10/2019 The Limits of Cladism- by David L. Hull Systematic Zoology, Vol. 28, No. 4 (Dec., 1979), pp. 416-440.

    1/26

    Society of Systematic iologists

    The Limits of CladismAuthor(s): David L. HullSource: Systematic Zoology, Vol. 28, No. 4 (Dec., 1979), pp. 416-440Published by: Taylor & Francis, Ltd.for the Society of Systematic BiologistsStable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/2412558.

    Accessed: 21/07/2014 17:05

    Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at.http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

    .JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of

    content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms

    of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].

    .

    Taylor & Francis, Ltd.and Society of Systematic Biologistsare collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve

    and extend access to Systematic Zoology.

    http://www.jstor.org

    This content downloaded from 142.51.1.212 on Mon, 21 Jul 2014 17:05:11 PMAll bj JSTOR T d C di i

    http://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=taylorfrancishttp://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=ssbiolhttp://www.jstor.org/stable/2412558?origin=JSTOR-pdfhttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/stable/2412558?origin=JSTOR-pdfhttp://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=ssbiolhttp://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=taylorfrancis
  • 8/10/2019 The Limits of Cladism- by David L. Hull Systematic Zoology, Vol. 28, No. 4 (Dec., 1979), pp. 416-440.

    2/26

    THE LIMITS OF CLADISM

    DAVID L. HULL

    Abstract

    Hull, David L. (Department of Philosophy,University f Wisconsin, Milwaukee, Wisconsin

    53201) 1979. The Limits of Cladism. Syst.

    Zool. 28:416-440.-The goal

    of cladistic

    systematics

    is to discern sister-grouprelations (cladistic relations) by

    the

    methods

    of

    cladistic analysis

    and to represent

    them

    explicitly

    and

    unambiguously

    in

    cladograms

    and

    cladistic classifica-

    tions. Cladists have selected

    cladistic relations to

    represent

    for wo

    reasons: cladistic relations

    can be

    discerned with reasonable

    certainty y

    the methods

    of

    cladistic

    analysis

    and

    theycan

    be represented

    with

    relative

    ease

    in

    cladograms

    and classifications. Cladists

    argue

    thatfea-

    tures

    of

    phylogeny

    other than cladistic relations cannot

    be

    discerned

    with

    sufficient ertainty

    to warrant ttempting o represent

    them

    in

    either

    cladograms

    or

    classifications

    and

    could

    not

    be

    represented

    if

    they

    could.

    I

    argue

    that

    a

    better alternative

    is

    to work

    toward

    improving

    methods of cladistic analysis (or else

    to supplement

    them with

    other methods) so thatsuch

    features ofphylogeny

    can be discerned

    and to devise methods of

    representation capable

    of

    representing them

    in

    both

    cladograms

    and classifications. However, cladograms and classi-

    fications cannot represent everything

    bout

    phylogeny.

    It is

    better

    to

    represent

    one or two

    aspects of phylogeny explicitly and unambiguously than nothing at all. [Cladism; classifica-

    tion; evolution; species.]

    Our classifications

    will come

    to

    be,

    as far

    s

    they

    can be

    so made, genealogies;

    and will then truly

    give what

    may

    be

    called the plan

    of creation.The

    rules for

    classifying

    will no doubt

    become sim-

    pler when

    we

    have a definite object

    in view

    (Darwin,

    1859:486).

    Charles

    Naudin's

    simile of tree and classifica-

    tion

    is like mine (and others), but

    he cannot,

    I

    think,have reflectedmuch on the subject, oth-

    erwise

    he would

    see that genealogy by

    itself

    does not give

    classification (Darwin,

    1899,

    2:42).

    One

    possible

    goal

    forbiological

    clas-

    sification

    s

    to represent

    hylogeny,

    o

    construct

    lassifications

    o

    that

    certain

    features

    f

    phylogeny

    an be

    read off

    n-

    equivocally.

    However,

    Darwin was quite

    correctwhen he noted thatgenealogy byitself does not give classification.Differ-

    ent

    taxonomists

    may

    select

    different s-

    pects

    of

    phylogeny

    to

    represent.

    One

    mightchoose

    order of branching,

    nother

    degree

    of divergence,

    another amount

    of

    diversity,

    nd

    so on. Whether or not

    the

    rules

    for classifying

    become simpler,

    as

    Darwin

    hoped they

    would,

    depends on

    the features

    of phylogeny

    which

    the tax-

    onomist

    chooses

    to

    represent

    nd the par-

    -ticular

    et

    of

    principles

    which

    he

    formu-

    lates to represent them. A classification

    which

    attempts

    o

    represent

    only

    one

    as

    pect of

    phylogeny

    s

    likely

    to be

    simpler

    than one

    which attempts

    o

    represent

    two

    simultaneously.

    Given any particular

    goal,

    the simplicity

    of the rules

    capable

    of accomplishing

    this goal depends

    both

    on the

    inherent

    limitations

    of

    the

    mode

    of representation

    nd the ingenuity

    of

    the

    taxonomist.For example, the traditional

    Linnaean

    hierarchy

    might

    lend itself

    to

    representing

    certain

    features

    of phylog-

    eny

    more readily

    than

    others,

    but nothing

    precludes

    a

    taxonomist

    from

    ntroducing

    additional

    representational

    devices to

    re-

    move these

    limitations.

    The end

    result

    s,

    of course,

    more

    complex

    rules for

    classi-

    fying.

    Systematists

    are thus

    forced

    to

    strike

    balance

    between

    how much

    they

    wish

    to

    represent

    and

    how complicated

    they are willing to make their principles

    of classification

    and

    resulting

    classifica-

    tions.

    In recent

    years a

    school

    of taxonomy

    has arisen

    whose members

    have serious-

    ly

    taken up

    the challenge

    of

    attempting

    to

    represent

    explicitly

    and

    unambiguous-

    ly

    something about

    phylogeny.

    The

    school

    is

    cladism,

    the

    aspect

    of phyloge-

    ny which

    the cladists

    have chosen

    to rep-

    resent

    is order

    of

    branching.

    The cladists

    have given two reasons forchoosing this

    416

    This content downloaded from 142.51.1.212 on Mon, 21 Jul 2014 17:05:11 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/10/2019 The Limits of Cladism- by David L. Hull Systematic Zoology, Vol. 28, No. 4 (Dec., 1979), pp. 416-440.

    3/26

    1979

    LIMITS OF

    CLADISM

    417

    particular

    eature

    f

    evolutionary

    evel-

    opment

    o

    represent. irst,

    he

    Linnaean

    hierarchy, s a list of indentednames,

    lends itselfmorenaturally o

    expressing

    discontinuous

    han continuous

    henom-

    ena. Whether r not evolution s gradual

    or saltative, hylogeny

    s

    largely matter

    of plitting

    nd

    divergence.

    A

    hierachy

    f

    discrete axa names s

    well-calculated o

    represent uccessive plitting.t is not s

    well-calculated

    o

    represent arying

    e-

    grees of divergence. econd, the

    cladists

    argue that

    rderof

    branching

    an

    be

    as-

    certained

    with ufficient

    ertaintyo war-

    rant he nclusion f such information

    n

    a

    classification

    while

    other aspects of

    phylogeny annot e. The methodwhich

    cladistshave

    devised

    to

    discover rder

    f

    branching

    s

    cladistic

    nalysis.

    Cladists

    argue that, y and large, ll

    a

    systematist

    as

    to

    go

    on is

    the

    traits f

    the

    specimens before him, whether

    these

    specimens represent

    extant

    or extinct

    forms.

    y studying

    is

    specimens, e

    can

    discover ested ets

    of haracters.

    nique

    derived

    characters istinguish mono-

    phyletic roupfrom ts nearest

    elatives;

    sharedderivedcharacters ombine hese

    monophyletic roups ntomore nclusive

    monophyleticroups.

    n

    this

    way

    the

    sys-

    tematist

    an ascertainnested sets ofsis-

    ter-groups. his method, o cladists ar-

    gue,

    cannotbe used

    to discern variety

    of

    other

    elations-speciation

    without he

    appearance

    of at

    least one unique

    de-

    rived character, reticulate evolution,

    multiple speciations, nd the

    ancestor-

    descendant relation-nor

    can

    any

    other

    method.

    Several questions rise at

    this

    uncture.

    If

    the

    Linnaean hierarchy annotrepre-

    sent

    certainfeatures

    fevolutionary

    e-

    velopmentverywell,

    is

    not that

    limi-

    tation f

    he Linnaean

    hierarchy?nstead

    of

    refusing

    o

    represent

    what

    particular

    system

    f

    representation

    as

    difficulty

    n

    representing, better lternative

    might

    be

    to

    abandon

    or

    improve

    hat

    ystem

    f

    representation.

    his is

    one avenue

    which

    the cladists hemselves ave taken Grif-

    fiths, 976; Hennig,1966; L0vtrup, 973;

    Nelson, 1972a,

    1973c;

    Patterson nd Ro-

    sen,

    1977;

    Wiley,1979).

    Do

    the evolu-

    tionary

    henomena

    which

    cladistic

    nal-

    ysis

    cannot

    discern

    actuallyexist?

    As

    I

    understand

    volution and

    evolutionary

    theory,

    wo

    of

    these

    phenomena

    learly

    occur (ancestorsgivingrise to descen-

    dants and

    reticulate

    evolution),

    one

    is

    quite

    ikely

    multiple

    peciation),

    nd the

    fourth

    s

    doubtful

    speciation

    without

    e-

    viation,

    although

    the

    unique

    derived

    character

    may

    be

    all but

    undetectable).

    s

    not

    the

    inability f cladistic

    analysisto

    discern

    the

    preceding

    phenomena,

    as-

    suming

    they

    take

    place,

    a

    limitation

    f

    the

    methods f

    cladistic

    nalysis?

    nstead

    of

    declining

    o

    deal with such

    phenom-

    ena because the methods of cladistic

    analysis cannot

    discern

    them,

    perhaps a

    better

    trategy

    ight e

    to

    attempt

    o

    m-

    prove

    upon

    the

    methods f

    ladistic

    nal-

    ysis

    or

    to

    supplement hem

    with

    other

    methods.

    The

    crucial

    question with

    re-

    spect to

    cladism,

    as

    I

    see

    it,

    is

    what is

    cladistic

    nalysis?

    What re

    its

    imits? s

    cladistic

    nalysis

    one

    way

    of

    scertaining

    phylogeny,

    he

    only

    way of

    ascertaining

    phylogeny,

    he

    only

    way

    of

    obtaining

    knowledge fanyphenomena?

    One fact

    bout

    cladism

    which

    compli-

    cates

    attempts o

    answer

    the

    preceding

    questions

    s that

    ladism,

    ike all

    scien-

    tific

    movements,

    s

    neither

    mmutable

    nor

    monolithic. t

    any one

    time,

    ladists

    can be

    found

    isagreeing

    with

    ach other

    about

    particular

    rinciples

    and

    conclu-

    sions.

    In

    addition,

    f

    one

    traces

    the

    de-

    velopment

    f

    cladism

    hrough

    ime,

    rom

    its

    inception

    in

    the

    works

    of

    Hennig

    (1950), through ts introductiono En-

    glish-speaking

    systematists

    Hennig,

    1965,

    1966;

    Brundin,

    1966;

    Nelson,

    1971a,

    1971b,

    1972a,

    1972b,

    1973a,

    1973b,

    1973c,

    1974)

    to

    the

    latest

    publi-

    cations

    of

    present-day

    ladists,

    signifi-

    cant

    changescan be

    discerned.

    he

    most

    significant

    hange whichhas

    taken

    place

    in

    cladism

    is

    a

    transition

    rom

    pecies

    being

    primary

    o

    characters

    being

    pri-

    mary.

    or

    Hennig

    1966,

    1975)

    and

    Brain-

    din (1972a), the basic unitsof cladistic

    analysis

    are

    species, characterized

    y

    at

    least

    one

    unique

    derived

    haracter.

    ow,

    This content downloaded from 142.51.1.212 on Mon, 21 Jul 2014 17:05:11 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/10/2019 The Limits of Cladism- by David L. Hull Systematic Zoology, Vol. 28, No. 4 (Dec., 1979), pp. 416-440.

    4/26

    418

    SYSTEMATIC

    ZOOLOGY

    VOL.

    28

    for a growing

    number

    of cladists, any

    monophyletic roup whichcan be char-

    acterizedby appropriate

    raits

    an func-

    tion in cladistic analysis,

    regardlessof

    whether

    hat

    group

    s

    more nclusive or

    less inclusive than traditionally-defined

    species. Cladistic classifications

    o not

    represent heorder fbranching

    f ister-

    groups,but the order of emergence of

    unique derived characters,

    whether or

    not the development f

    these characters

    happens to coincide with speciation

    events.

    t

    is

    not

    the

    emergenceof

    new

    species which

    s

    primary

    ut

    the

    emer-

    gence

    of new traits

    Tattersall

    nd

    El-

    dredge, 1977:207; Rosen,

    1978:176).

    In

    general, ladists seem to be moving o-

    ward the

    position

    hat he

    particulars

    f

    evolutionary evelopment

    re not rele-

    vant o cladism.

    t

    does notmatter heth-

    er

    speciation

    s

    sympatric

    r

    allopatric,

    saltativeor gradual,Darwinian or La-

    marckian,ust

    so

    long

    as

    it

    occurs

    nd

    is

    predominantlyivergentCracraft,

    974;

    Bonde, 1975; Rosen, 1978;

    andforthcom-

    ing works by Nelson and

    Platnick,El-

    dredge

    and

    Cracraft,

    nd

    others).

    The writingsof most cladists have

    been

    concernedwith

    developing

    meth-

    ods

    of

    ascertaining

    he

    cladistic elations

    between

    biological axa,

    ut

    Platnick

    nd

    Cameron

    1977)

    have shown thatthese

    same techniques

    can

    be

    used

    to

    discern

    the cladistic relations xhibitedby

    lan-

    guages

    and

    texts see

    also

    Kruskal, yen,

    and

    Black, 1971; Haigh,

    1971; and Nita,

    1971).

    n

    general

    ladistic nalysis an be

    used to

    discover

    the cladistic relations

    between any entitieswhichchange by

    means of modification

    hrough escent

    (Platnick, 979).

    As

    general

    s thisnotion

    of

    cladisticanalysis s,

    it still

    retains

    necessary emporal imension.

    ransfor-

    mation series must be established

    for

    characters,

    ot

    ust

    an

    abstract

    temporal

    transformation

    eries like the cardinal

    numbers r the

    periodic

    table, but

    a se-

    ries of ctualtransformations

    n

    time.For

    example,

    the vast

    majority

    f

    matter

    n

    theuniversehappens tobe hydrogen.n

    isolated pockets of the universe,more

    complex

    molecules have

    developed,

    but

    theyhave not developed by

    progressing

    up

    the periodic table, from

    ydrogen o

    helium, ithium,

    eryllium, tc.

    From the

    beginning,Gareth Nelson

    (1973c) seems to have been

    developing

    twonotions f cladistic nalysis imulta-

    neously, one limited to

    historically e-

    veloped patterns

    cladismwith a small

    'c'),

    the

    other more

    generalnotion p-

    plicable to all

    patternsCladism with a

    big C'). His

    method f

    component nal-

    ysis

    is

    a generalcalculus for

    discerning

    and

    representing

    atterns

    f

    ll sorts. or

    example,

    n a

    recent

    discussion,Nelson

    (1979:28) states that

    cladogram

    s

    an

    atemporal

    oncept

    ...

    a

    synapomorphy

    scheme. It remains o be seen whether

    all

    of

    the terms f cladistic

    nalysisfrom

    sister

    group to

    synapomorphy can

    be

    defined o that

    none of them neces-

    sarily resupposes

    temporal imension.

    Although think

    hat the principlesof

    cladistic

    nalysis

    an

    be

    extended

    o any

    system

    which

    genuinelyevolves (i.e.,

    changes through

    ime

    by means of

    mod-

    ification hrough

    descent), I

    will limit

    myself n this

    paper to phylogeny nd

    biological evolution. also will not ad-

    dress

    myself

    o

    Nelson's

    more general

    notion.

    Attemptingo discussthe princi-

    ples of cladistic

    nalysis s

    they pply to

    phylogeny s a

    sufficiently

    ifficultask

    without

    ttempting

    o

    present nterpre-

    tations f

    these

    principleswhich re also

    consistent

    with

    Nelson's more

    general

    program.

    METHODOLOGICAL

    PRINCIPLES

    AND

    OBJECTIONS

    In

    spite

    of

    certain bservations

    which

    cladists

    have made

    periodically

    boutthe

    evolutionary rocess,

    the

    principles

    of

    cladistic

    analysis

    do not concern

    evolu-

    tion

    but the

    goals

    of

    biological

    classifi-

    cation

    nd the means

    by

    which

    they

    an

    be realized.

    These

    principles

    re

    primar-

    ily

    methodological.

    s

    I

    see

    it,

    the

    goal

    of cladism

    s to

    represent

    ladistic

    rela-

    tions

    in

    both

    cladograms

    nd classifica-

    tions s explicitlynd unambiguouslys

    possible. Thus,

    cladistic

    methodology

    has two

    parts:

    ules for

    iscerning

    ladis-

    This content downloaded from 142.51.1.212 on Mon, 21 Jul 2014 17:05:11 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/10/2019 The Limits of Cladism- by David L. Hull Systematic Zoology, Vol. 28, No. 4 (Dec., 1979), pp. 416-440.

    5/26

    1979

    LIMITS OF CLADISM

    419

    tic

    relations nd

    rules for

    representing

    them

    in cladograms nd

    classifications.

    For example,

    Nelson raises

    two objec-

    tions o the

    ancestor-descendant

    elation:

    first,

    ancestral

    pecies cannot

    be iden-

    tified s such in thefossilrecord Nel-

    son,

    1973b:311),

    and

    second,

    they

    are

    also

    inexpressible

    in

    classifications

    (Nelson,

    1972a:227).

    One sourceof

    the confusion

    whichhas

    accompanied the

    controversyver clad-

    ism is the

    interpretationf

    their meth-

    odological

    principles

    s

    empirical

    eliefs

    aboutevolution. he claim that

    dichoto-

    mous

    speciationneveroccurs

    s an em-

    pirical

    claim to be

    tested by

    empirical

    means.The claim thatwe can neverdis-

    tinguish

    between dichotomous

    pecia-

    tion events and

    more complex

    sorts of

    speciation is a

    methodological claim

    about

    the limitsof our

    methodsof

    sci-

    entific

    nvestigation.

    inally,

    the

    claim

    thatmultiple

    peciation,

    f

    t

    occurs and

    if it can be

    discerned,

    annotbe

    repre-

    sented

    unambiguously

    in

    cladograms

    and/or

    lassifications

    s

    a comment

    bout

    the

    limitationsf

    these modes of repre-

    sentation. nce theprinciples fcladism

    are

    recognizedforwhat

    they re,

    meth-

    odologicalprinciples,

    he

    ogic

    of

    he cla-

    distic positionon

    a

    variety

    f ssues

    be-

    comes

    much

    clearer.

    Scientists re interested

    n

    truth,

    ot

    Absolute

    Truth,

    but truth

    nevertheless.

    Although

    hilosophershave

    yet to pro-

    duce

    a

    totally

    nproblematic

    nalysis

    of

    science as

    the

    pursuit

    of truth

    see, for

    example,Laudan,

    1977),

    think

    hat

    ci-

    entists re correct n the focus of their

    attention.

    cientists also

    present

    argu-

    mentsto buttress

    heir mpirical

    laims

    and

    try

    o make their

    rguments

    s

    good

    as

    possible.

    Unfortunately,

    cientists

    re

    rarely ble to

    present

    heir rguments

    n

    the

    unproblematic

    orms hus

    far ana-

    lyzed

    successfully by

    mathematicians

    and

    logicians.

    The

    reasoning

    which

    goes

    into the

    formulationnd

    testing f sci-

    entific

    heories

    s a

    good

    deal more

    om-

    plex and informal hanany explicitra-

    tional

    reconstructionas

    yet

    been

    able to

    capture.

    cientists

    re

    interested

    n

    both

    truthnd

    cogencyof argument,

    ut they

    are a

    good deal more

    nterested

    n

    truth

    than

    n

    cogency fargument.f

    a line of

    reasoningwhich

    ed to a

    particular on-

    clusion turns out

    to be

    somewhat ess

    thanperfect,treallydoes notmatter ll

    that

    much, ust so long

    as the

    conclusion

    depicts

    reality

    with

    greater

    idelity

    han

    previous

    ttempts.

    Scientists ave

    limited

    patience when

    it

    comes to discussing

    rguments. hat

    patience s even more

    imitedwhen the

    argumentsre

    methodological. s

    strange

    as

    it

    may sound

    coming

    from

    philoso-

    pher,

    am

    highly ceptical of

    methodo-

    logical principles

    nd

    prescriptions,

    s-

    peciallywhenthey represented n the

    midst

    fscientific

    isputes.They tendto

    be

    suspiciously

    elf-serving,esigned

    to

    put one's opponentsat a

    disadvantage

    while

    shoring p

    one's

    own

    position.

    n-

    variably the advocates of a

    particular

    methodology an know

    what

    they

    need

    to

    knowwhile their

    pponents an never

    hope

    to know what

    theyneed

    to know.

    For example,

    hepheneticists

    laim that

    we can

    analyze

    traits

    nto

    unit

    haracters,

    butwe can neverhope to establishgen-

    uine,

    evolutionary

    ransformationeries

    among

    haracters. one too

    surprisingly,

    the

    pheneticists

    eed toknow

    he former

    but

    not the

    latter.

    Only

    the

    cladists and

    evolutionists

    eed

    to know

    the unknow-

    able.

    Similarly,

    he cladists

    laim

    that

    we

    can establish

    transformation

    eries with

    sufficient

    ertainty

    o warrant he role

    which

    they

    play

    in

    cladistic

    ystematics

    but that

    ancestor-descendant

    elations

    are unknowable.As luck would have it,

    cladistsneed to

    knowthe former ut not

    the

    atter. nly the

    evolutionists eed to

    knowthe

    unknowable.

    As

    cynical as the

    precedingremarks

    may

    ound,

    think

    heyhave some valid-

    ity.

    t is

    no

    accident that ll

    four f the

    phenomenawhich

    he cladists laim can-

    not be

    known,

    annotbe

    discerned by

    the traditional

    eans

    ofcladistic

    nalysis

    and

    cause

    problems

    for he

    explicit

    nd

    unambiguous representation f sister-

    group relations

    n

    both

    cladograms nd

    classifications.

    t is

    also

    no

    accidentthat

    This content downloaded from 142.51.1.212 on Mon, 21 Jul 2014 17:05:11 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/10/2019 The Limits of Cladism- by David L. Hull Systematic Zoology, Vol. 28, No. 4 (Dec., 1979), pp. 416-440.

    6/26

    420

    SYSTEMATIC

    ZOOLOGY VOL. 28

    one of the

    phenomena

    which cladists

    claim cannot

    be

    known

    (the

    ancestor-de-

    scendant relation) plays

    a central

    role

    in

    the research program of their chief

    ri-

    vals-the evolutionists. I do not mean

    to

    imply that the preceding remarks apply

    uniquely to the

    cladists. They apply to

    scientists

    n

    general.

    If

    I

    were

    investigat-

    ing the pheneticists or the

    evolutionists,

    comparable

    observations would

    apply

    as

    readily to them. These are the sorts of

    games

    which scientists

    (not

    to mention

    philosophers)

    play with each other.

    In

    general,

    I think

    t

    is

    very bad strat-

    egy

    for

    proponents

    of a

    particularscien-

    tific research program to stake their fu-

    ture on epistemological considerations,

    especially

    on

    our

    inability

    to

    know some-

    thing. Phenomena

    which

    scientists

    in

    one

    age

    claim

    can

    never

    be

    known often

    become common

    knowledge

    at a

    later

    date.

    The

    history

    of science

    is

    littered

    with

    the bodies

    of

    scientists who

    staked

    the success of their movements on

    what

    we can never know.

    I

    agree

    with

    Einstein

    (1949:684),

    who,

    in

    response to philo-

    sophical criticismsof his

    work, stated:

    Science without

    epistemology

    is-insofar as it

    is

    thinkable

    at

    all-primitive

    and

    muddled.

    How-

    ever,

    no

    sooner has the

    epistemologist,

    who

    is

    seeking

    a clear

    system, fought

    his

    way

    through

    to

    such

    a

    system,

    han

    he

    is

    inclined to

    interpret

    the

    thought-content

    f science

    in

    the sense

    of his

    system

    and

    to

    reject

    whatever does not fit

    nto

    his

    system.

    The

    scientist,however,

    cannot afford

    to

    carry

    his

    striving

    for

    epistemological system-

    atic that far.

    I

    hardly want

    to argue against

    meth-

    odological rigor n science, but I also do

    not want to see scientificprogress

    sacri-

    ficed to

    it.

    Invariably methodological rig-

    or is a

    retrospective

    exercise, carried on

    long after

    ll

    the

    Nobel prizes have been

    won.

    From the

    point of view of current

    methodologies, scientists will, as

    Ein-

    stein

    (1949:684) noted, appear to

    the

    systematic epistemologist as a type

    of

    unscrupulous opportunist. Instead

    of

    cladists

    insisting

    that

    certain aspects of

    phylogeny can never be known and

    could

    not be

    represented cladistically

    if

    they could be known,

    wiser strategy

    would be

    to

    attempt

    o devise methods f

    analysiscapable

    of discerning hese fea-

    tures of evolutionary

    evelopment

    nd

    representational

    echniquessufficiento

    representhem. n thispaper, have at-

    tempted o

    produce an internal riticism

    of

    cladism;

    that

    s,

    I have

    accepted

    the

    goals

    of cladism

    and

    have

    set

    myself

    he

    task of decidingwhich

    methodological

    principles

    re central

    o the

    undertaking,

    which

    peripheral,

    nd which could

    be

    modified

    r abandoned without oss

    and

    possibly

    with

    ome

    gain.

    CLADOGRAMS,

    PHYLOGENETIC TREES,

    AND EVOLUTIONARY SCENARIOS

    A curious featureof scientific

    evel-

    opment

    s

    the

    frequency

    with

    which a

    new movement

    s named

    by its oppo-

    nents. ocial

    Darwinists o morewanted

    to be called

    Social

    Darwinists han

    clad-

    ists have

    wanted to be called cladists.

    Twentyyears

    ago, JulianHuxley 1958)

    coined

    the terms

    clade

    and

    grade

    to

    distinguish

    etweengroups

    f

    organisms

    with common enetic rigin

    nd

    groups

    distinguished y differentevels of or-

    ganization.

    Later Mayr (1965:81)

    and

    Camin and

    Sokal

    (1965:312)

    introduced

    the term

    cladogram o refer o

    a

    dia-

    gram depicting

    the

    branching

    of the

    phylogenetic

    reewithout espect

    o rates

    of

    divergence Mayr,

    1978:85). Finally,

    Mayr 1969:70)

    invented he term clad-

    ism as a substitute or phylogenetic

    ys-

    tematics, he name preferred

    y Hennig

    and

    his

    followers.

    Gradually

    he cladists

    themselves ave cometo use theterm o

    refer o

    themselves, lbeit

    grudgingly.

    Whether

    he

    Hennigian

    school

    of

    sys-

    tematics

    s

    called

    phylogenetic

    r cla-

    distic

    s

    not

    very mportant,

    ut the

    pre-

    cise nature

    f

    cladograms

    s

    they

    unction

    in

    cladistic

    nalysis

    s.

    In

    fact,

    ncertain-

    ty ver

    what

    t s

    that ladograms

    re

    sup-

    posed

    to

    depict

    and how

    they

    are

    sup-

    posed

    to depict

    it

    has been

    the

    chief

    source

    of confusion

    n

    the

    controversy

    overcladism.Like all terms,hemeaning

    of

    cladogram

    has

    changed

    through

    he

    This content downloaded from 142.51.1.212 on Mon, 21 Jul 2014 17:05:11 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/10/2019 The Limits of Cladism- by David L. Hull Systematic Zoology, Vol. 28, No. 4 (Dec., 1979), pp. 416-440.

    7/26

    1979

    LIMITS OF

    CLADISM

    421

    years.

    t

    no longermeansto cladistswhat

    Mayr,

    Camin

    and

    Sokal

    proposed. The

    meanings

    of cladism and

    cladistic

    analysis

    have

    changed

    accordingly.

    n

    an

    attempt o

    reduce the

    confusion verthe meaning of cladogram, cladists

    have introduced he

    distinction

    etween

    cladograms,

    hylogeneticrees,

    nd evo-

    lutionarycenarios.'

    Once again,

    he par-

    ticular erms

    sed tomark hese

    distinc-

    tions are

    not important;he

    distinctions

    themselves

    re.

    It

    is

    also truethat the

    cladists

    have devised

    these distinctions

    for

    their

    own

    purposes. Others

    might

    want o

    draw

    ther

    istinctions

    rto draw

    these distinctions

    differently.

    n

    anycase, all three ppellationsrefer o rep-

    resentations,ot o the

    phenomena

    eing

    represented. Cladogram nd

    tree re-

    fer

    o two

    sorts

    f

    diagrams, hile scen-

    ario refersto a

    historical narrative

    couched

    n

    ordinary iological

    anguage.

    Phylogenetic rees

    re designedto de-

    pict

    phylogenetic evelopment,

    ndicat-

    ing which

    taxa are extinct, hich

    extant,

    which

    gave

    rise to

    which,degrees

    of

    di-

    vergence, nd so on. As

    diagrams

    hey

    do

    not include discussions ofthe methods

    used to construct

    hem,

    he natural

    ro-

    cesses which

    produced

    the

    phenomena

    theydepict,

    nd

    a

    variety

    f

    other onsid-

    erations

    f

    equal importance.

    tree

    s a

    diagram,

    ot an

    entire

    axonomicmono-

    graph.

    All

    sorts f

    conventions ave been

    devised to

    represent hylogeny

    n a dia-

    grammatic

    orm; or xample,

    ines

    usu-

    ally represent

    ineages,

    forks

    epresent

    speciation

    vents,

    he

    slant nd

    length

    f

    a line reflect herapiditywithwhichdi-

    vergence ookplace, and

    the termination

    of line

    indicates xtinction.

    ther

    ech-

    niques of

    representation ave

    also been

    used on

    occasion; for xample,

    dots

    in-

    dicating uestionable

    connections,

    ines

    of

    varying

    hicknesses

    eflecting

    elative

    1

    The

    distinction

    between

    cladograms,trees,

    and

    scenarios

    discussed

    in

    Tattersall

    nd

    Eldredge

    (1977)

    was takenfrom manuscriptbyGarethNelson. See

    Mayr

    (1978)

    for early

    definitionsof

    such

    terms as

    i'cladogram

    .

    phenogram, and

    phylogram.

    numbers

    of

    organisms,

    and so

    on. How-

    ever,

    as a

    diagram

    in

    two-dimensional

    space, a

    tree can

    include

    only

    so much

    information

    efore

    a point of

    diminishing

    returns ets in. Eventually attempts o in-

    clude additional

    sorts of

    information

    e-

    sult in

    the

    loss

    of

    nformation. f

    trees are

    supposed to

    be

    systems of

    information

    storage

    and

    retrieval, the

    information

    must be

    retrievable.

    Scenarios, as

    cladists

    use the

    term,

    re

    not

    diagrams.

    They

    are

    historical

    narra-

    tives

    which

    attemptto

    describe not

    only

    which

    groups

    gave

    rise

    to

    which

    (the

    sort

    of

    information

    contained

    in

    trees)

    but

    also the ecological changes and evolu-

    tionary

    forces

    which

    actually

    produced

    the

    adaptations

    which

    characterize the

    organisms

    discussed.

    Romer's

    (1955:57)

    story of the role which

    the

    drying up

    of

    ponds and streams

    played

    in

    the

    transi-

    tion

    from the

    crossopterygians

    to early

    amphibians is

    by now

    a

    classic

    example

    of an

    evolutionary

    scenario.

    Because

    scenarios

    are

    presented

    in

    ordinary

    an-

    guage-supplemented

    with a host

    of

    technical biological terms-the phenom-ena which scenarios can

    describe are

    lim-

    ited

    only by

    the

    limitations

    of

    language.

    Hennig's early

    cladograms

    (Hennig,

    1950:103;

    1966:59, 71)

    give every

    ap-

    pearance

    of

    being

    highly stylized

    trees.

    The

    circles

    arrayed along

    the top of

    the

    diagram

    apparently

    represent extant

    species,

    while

    those

    at

    the

    nodes

    repre-

    sent

    extinct, ommon

    ancestors

    (see

    Fig.

    la).

    At

    one

    stage

    in

    the

    development

    of

    the cladogram, Nelson (1972b, 1973b) ar-

    gued that the

    circles at

    the

    nodes

    did

    not

    represent

    real common

    ancestors

    but

    hypothetical

    ancestors.

    The

    term is

    problematic.

    All

    taxa that

    ever

    existed

    are

    equally

    real.

    Only

    our

    ability

    to

    discern

    them varies.

    We

    can

    usually discern

    ex-

    tant

    species with

    greater

    certainty

    than

    extinct

    forms,

    but the

    postulation of

    any

    taxon,

    whether

    extant or

    extinct,

    nvolves

    highly

    complex

    inferences and

    requires

    evidence

    which is

    frequently quite dif-ficult to obtain.

    (Recall

    the

    objections

    which

    pheneticists

    raised to

    the

    biologi-

    This content downloaded from 142.51.1.212 on Mon, 21 Jul 2014 17:05:11 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/10/2019 The Limits of Cladism- by David L. Hull Systematic Zoology, Vol. 28, No. 4 (Dec., 1979), pp. 416-440.

    8/26

    422

    SYSTEMATIC

    ZOOLOGY

    VOL. 28

    A

    B C

    FIG.

    1.-The

    evolution of the cladogram. (a) A

    cladogram

    in

    which the darkened circles

    at the ter-

    mini represent

    extant

    species,

    while those at the

    nodes represent

    ommon

    ancestors. b) A cladogram

    in which

    the darkened circles at the

    termini rep-

    resent species,

    both extantand extinct,

    while the

    circles at the nodes represent hypothetical

    com-

    mon ancestors,

    i.e., morphotypes. c)

    A cladogram

    in which the darkened

    circles at the termini rep-

    resent species, both extant

    and extinct,while the

    nodes represent

    speciation events

    and/or

    he emer-

    gence of unique derived

    characters.

    cal

    species

    concept

    even when

    it is

    ap-

    plied to extant

    forms.)

    f

    extinctforms

    re

    hypothetical

    because

    of their inferen-

    tial basis, then so

    are extant

    forms.The

    difference

    between

    extant

    and

    extinct

    species

    is

    not between observation

    and

    inference, but between

    inferences of

    varying degrees of

    certainty.

    Another

    nterpretation f hypothetical

    ancestor

    is that he

    circles

    which

    appear

    at the nodes of cladograms are not sup-

    posed

    to

    be taxa

    at

    all

    but

    morpho-

    types,

    rational constructs characterized

    by

    the

    defining

    traitsof the taxa

    listed at

    the termini

    of the

    cladogram

    and

    no

    oth-

    ers.

    As Platnick

    1977c:356)

    observes,

    the

    nodes

    of cladograms

    representonly

    in-

    ferred

    species (or,

    more accurately, only

    minimum sets of synapomorphic

    charac-

    ters).

    In this sense, hypothetical

    ances-

    tors are

    hypothetical,

    but they are not

    ancestors. They are not even taxa (see

    Fig. lb).

    In

    present-day

    cladograms,

    all

    taxa,

    whether

    extinct or extant, appear

    along

    the top

    of the

    cladogram.

    Clado-

    grams

    would

    be much

    less

    misleading

    if

    they

    included nothing

    at the nodes (see

    Fig. ic).

    If

    the nodes

    in

    a cladogram

    do

    not rep-

    resent real taxa

    (ancestral

    or

    otherwise),

    what do the

    lines and

    forks

    n

    cladograms

    represent?

    Two answers

    have been

    given

    to this question, which may or may not

    'be reducible

    to the

    same

    answer.

    A fork

    in

    a cladogram can

    representeither

    a

    spe-

    ciation vent

    the splittingfone

    species

    intotwo),

    or the emergence f an

    evolu-

    tionary

    ovelty a unique derived

    char-

    acter),

    or both.

    If

    the

    emergence

    of a

    unique derived character

    ccurs

    always

    and onlyat speciation, hen the twoan-

    swers lways oincide.

    f

    not,not. imilar

    observations

    old for he term cladistic

    relation.

    t

    can refer

    o order f splitting

    of taxa,

    or to order fappearance

    of evo-

    lutionaryovelties, r

    both.The decision

    hinges

    on how operational

    ne wishes

    to

    make cladistic nalysis.Since

    specia-

    tion events

    re inferred y

    means

    of

    the

    appearance

    of evolutionary

    novelties,

    one

    inferential

    tep

    can be eliminated

    y

    talking nly bouttheemergence fevo-

    lutionarynovelties

    and not speciation

    events.

    CERTAINTY

    AND LEGITIMATE DOUBT

    One reason

    for he

    cladists' ntroducing

    the

    distinction between

    cladograms,

    trees, and

    scenarios

    was

    to clarify

    he

    technical

    ense

    in

    which heywere

    using

    the term

    cladogram.

    Too manypeople

    were misinterpretingladograms

    s bi-

    zarre, ighly tylized rees.A secondrea-

    son was

    to establish

    he

    ogical

    and

    epis-

    temological

    priority

    f

    cladograms

    ver

    trees nd

    of reesover

    cenarios.

    As clad-

    ists define

    hese terms, n inclusion

    re-

    lation

    xists etweenthem.

    cenarios

    n-

    clide

    all

    the information

    ontained

    in

    trees,

    and more besides. Trees

    include

    all

    the

    nformationontained

    ladograms,

    and more

    besides.

    Thus, any knowledge

    required

    for

    cladogram

    s

    required

    for

    a tree, nd anyknowledge equiredfor

    tree

    is

    required

    for

    scenario,

    but not

    vice versa.

    Thus,

    cladograms

    re more

    certain

    han

    rees,

    nd treesmore ertain

    than

    scenarios.

    As harmless

    s the dis-

    tinction

    etween cladograms, rees,

    nd

    scenariosmay

    seem on

    the

    surface,

    t

    re-

    sults

    n

    cladistic

    nalysisbeing

    in

    some

    sense

    basic

    to

    all

    evolutionary

    tudies.

    The relations

    et outabove do

    obtain

    between

    cladograms,

    rees,

    and scenar-

    ios-as the cladists definethese terms.

    That is one reason why non-cladists

    might refer

    therdefinitions. ut even

    This content downloaded from 142.51.1.212 on Mon, 21 Jul 2014 17:05:11 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/10/2019 The Limits of Cladism- by David L. Hull Systematic Zoology, Vol. 28, No. 4 (Dec., 1979), pp. 416-440.

    9/26

    1979

    LIMITS OF

    CLADISM

    423

    if

    one were to accept the cladists'

    defi-

    nitions, ertain onclusionswhich

    clad-

    istshave claimedfollow rom he

    preced-

    ing ine ofreasoning o not.For

    example,

    in claiming hat trees should always

    be

    based on cladograms nd that cenarios

    should follow rom rees,

    Tattersall nd

    Eldredge (1977:205)

    are confusing ogi-

    cal and

    epistemological

    rder

    with tem-

    poral order.The

    conclusion

    to

    an argu-

    ment

    follows ogically

    rom

    ts

    premises.

    That does not mean

    that

    people

    must

    think f the premisesfirst nd only

    then

    thinkof the conclusion.Sense

    data are

    epistemologically

    rior

    o

    all

    knowledge,

    but that

    does

    not mean

    that

    scientists

    should beginevery cientifictudywith

    an

    extensive

    nvestigation

    f their own

    sense data.

    f scientists ad actually ro-

    ceeded

    in

    this

    fashion,

    we would

    still

    be

    awaiting Ptolemaic

    astronomy, ot to

    mention

    elativityheory.

    he

    inferences

    which

    take

    place

    in

    the

    actual

    course of

    scientificnvestigations

    re

    very ntricate

    and

    frequently

    feed

    back

    upon each oth-

    er, as Tattersall nd Eldredge 1977:205)

    note.

    n

    retrospect,

    here s considerable

    pointtounravelinghese nferencesnd

    setting hem ut

    n

    some ogically

    oher-

    ent

    fashion,

    ut the insistence

    hat

    sci-

    en-tists

    must

    always begin

    at

    the

    begin-

    ning and proceed step by step

    according

    to some sort f ogical or epistemological

    order would

    stop

    science

    dead

    in its

    tracks.2

    Cladists

    also

    make

    much

    of

    the

    differ-

    ences

    in

    certainty

    etween

    cladograms,

    trees,

    and

    scenarios.

    n

    actual practice,

    scientistswanderfromne level ofanal-

    ysis to

    another

    n

    the course of their

    n-

    vestigations.

    As a result knowledge ac-

    2The pheneticists

    presented similar arguments

    for the

    epistemological

    priority

    f

    phenetic

    classi-

    fications.

    According to

    the

    pheneticists, the only

    place at which systematists

    an legitimately begin

    is

    phenetic characters nd

    the construction f

    pure-

    ly phenetic

    classifications. Once such

    a phenetic

    classification

    is

    erected,

    then a systematistcould

    put various interpretations on his classifications

    and

    possibly produce

    one or more special pur-

    pose

    classifications; see e.g., Sneath

    and Sokal

    (1973).

    quisition

    s a

    process of

    both

    reciprocal

    illumination

    Hennig,

    1950;

    Ross,

    1974)

    and

    reciprocal

    lundering.

    etting

    ne

    element

    right

    elps

    improve

    ur

    under-

    standing fthe

    other

    lements, ut

    errors

    feed throughhe systemust as readily.

    Although ladists

    might

    well

    admit

    that

    knowledge

    acquisition

    in

    general

    is

    a

    process

    of

    reciprocal

    llumination,

    hey

    also

    tend

    to be

    so

    sceptical

    oftrees

    and

    scenariosthat

    hey

    see all

    the

    illumina-

    tion

    going in

    a

    single

    direction-from

    cladogramsto

    trees and

    scenarios. At

    times

    ladists eem

    to

    argue

    hatnot

    only

    should

    evolutionary

    tudies

    begin with

    cladogramsbut

    also

    they should

    end

    there as well. Cladistic relations are

    knowable;

    verything

    lse

    about

    phylog-

    eny

    s

    unknowable.

    For

    example,

    Platnick

    1977d:439) ar-

    gues

    that

    he

    onlyway

    that

    hylogenetic

    trees an

    be tested

    s

    by the

    same

    means

    used

    to

    test

    cladograms,

    by

    evaluation

    in

    the

    lightof

    newly

    discovered

    harac-

    ters.

    Any

    hree axa

    can

    be

    ordered

    nto

    22

    different

    rees.

    omeof

    hese

    rees an

    be

    rejected

    by

    discovering

    ppropriate

    characters,.e., the appropriate utapo-

    morphies

    and

    synapomorphies.

    Other

    trees

    can

    be

    rejected

    only by

    claiming

    that

    no

    autapomorphies

    xistfor

    he rel-

    evant

    taxa.

    Since

    the most hat

    system-

    atist

    an

    legitimately

    laim

    s that

    he has

    yet

    to

    detect uch

    autapomorphies,

    e is

    not

    ustified n

    rejecting

    hese

    trees.Plat-

    nick

    1977d:440) concludes

    that

    phylo-

    genetic

    rees

    re

    not estable

    y character

    distributionsnd

    thus hat

    cientific

    hy-

    logenyreconstructions not possible at

    the evel

    of

    phylogenetic

    rees nd must

    be

    restrictedo

    the evel of

    cladograms.

    But

    the

    same

    sort

    f

    rgumentan be

    pre-

    sented

    against

    he

    cladists.

    They

    do

    not

    need

    to

    know

    ancestor-descendantela-

    tions,

    ut

    they

    do

    need

    to establish

    rans-

    formation

    eries nd

    to

    determine he

    po-

    larity

    f

    these

    series.

    They do

    need to

    individuate

    haracters nd

    decide which

    are

    autapomorphic,

    ynapomorphic,

    tc.

    For instance, synapomorphies an be

    used to

    test

    cladograms

    f

    they re

    syn-

    apomorphies,

    ut

    no one

    has

    yetto

    sug-

    This content downloaded from 142.51.1.212 on Mon, 21 Jul 2014 17:05:11 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/10/2019 The Limits of Cladism- by David L. Hull Systematic Zoology, Vol. 28, No. 4 (Dec., 1979), pp. 416-440.

    10/26

    424 SYSTEMATIC ZOOLOGY VOL. 28

    gest any infallible means

    for

    deciding

    whether

    r

    not a trait s

    actually syn-

    apomorphy.

    he same can

    be said

    for

    such relations s

    thepolarity

    f transfor-

    mation

    eries. In fact,

    Tattersall

    nd El-

    dredge 1977:206)state, In practice t s

    hard, even

    impossible, to

    marshal a

    strong,ogical

    argument or

    given

    po-

    larity

    formany

    characters

    n a given

    group. The

    sortof

    argument

    rom eg-

    ative

    evidence

    which the

    cladists

    use

    againstothers t

    the evel of taxa

    can be

    used

    againstthem

    at the

    level of

    traits.

    Of

    course,

    their

    pponents

    lso

    must n-

    dividuate nd

    categorize raits.

    hus, the

    cladists'

    position s

    refuted t

    only

    one

    level of analysis,while the positionof

    their

    opponents s

    refuted t

    two.

    Put

    more

    directly, uch

    arguments efute o

    positions

    whatsoever.

    The

    cladists

    have weakened

    the force

    of

    their

    rguments

    y

    presenting

    hem

    n

    a

    needlessly dichotomous

    ashion.The

    only

    thing

    hat

    hey

    need to

    know

    o pro-

    duce

    cladograms

    re cladistic

    relations,

    and

    they re

    knowable.Others

    who wish

    to produce

    trees

    need to

    know much

    more; e.g., ancestor-descendantrela-

    tions,

    the

    existence of

    multiple specia-

    tion and

    reticulate

    volution, tc. These

    phenomena re

    totally

    nknowable. he

    cladists

    need not

    present

    such an ex-

    treme

    and

    suspiciously

    elf-serving)o-

    sition. Estimations

    f

    cladistic

    relations

    are

    inferences

    nd

    as such

    carrywith

    them he

    possibility ferror.

    owever, t

    is certainly

    ruethat

    everything

    hich

    the cladists

    need to know

    the

    evolution-

    istsalso need toknow,whiletheevolu-

    tionists

    need to

    know more besides.

    These additional

    phenomena

    lso

    carry

    with

    them

    certain

    egree

    of

    uncertain-

    ty.

    Hence,

    evolutionary lassifications

    are

    bound to be

    moreuncertain

    han

    la-

    distic

    classifications. he

    question re-

    mains

    whether

    ll

    evolutionary

    henom-

    ena

    other han

    cladisticrelations

    re so

    uncertain hat

    o

    attempt

    houldbe made

    to

    include

    informationbout

    them n a

    classification.n thesucceeding ections

    of this

    paper,

    I

    will

    investigate

    arious

    phenomenawhich

    cladists

    rgue cannot

    be

    known or

    at

    least

    cannot

    be known

    with

    ufficient

    ertainty)

    o

    see

    why hey

    are so

    difficult

    o discern. s it

    that

    hey

    cannotbe

    known, r

    that

    hey

    annotbe

    knownby

    means of

    cladistic

    nalysis?

    s

    therenowaytoacquireknowledge f he

    world

    other than

    by

    cladistic

    analysis?

    The

    pointof

    his

    ection s,

    however, hat

    the

    difference

    n

    our

    ability o ascertain

    cladistic

    elations nd

    other

    volutionary

    phenomena s

    one of

    degree,not

    kind.

    Differences

    r1

    degree of

    certainty re

    neither

    eryneat

    nor

    esthetically.

    leas-

    ing,but

    theyare

    the

    most

    thatcladists

    can

    justifiably

    laim. What

    they

    ose

    in

    elegance

    and

    simplicity,

    hey gain

    in

    plausibility.

    Certain

    ladists,

    n

    more

    recent

    publi-

    cations,

    eem

    to be

    moving

    n

    precisely

    this

    direction. For

    example,

    Eldredge

    (1979:169)

    states hat,

    ontraryo

    hisear-

    lier

    opinions:

    I

    no

    longer

    oppose the

    construction

    f

    phyloge-

    netic trees

    outright,or

    for

    that

    matter,

    scenar-

    ios (which

    are,

    after

    ll,

    the

    most

    fun),

    but

    mere-

    ly point

    out

    that,

    in

    moving

    through the

    more

    complex

    levels,

    we

    inevitably

    become further e-

    moved from he original data base in adding as-

    sumptions

    and ad

    hoc

    (and

    largely

    untestable)

    hypotheses.

    As

    long as we

    understand

    precisely

    what

    we are

    doing

    at each

    step

    in

    the

    analysis,

    which includes

    having

    an

    adequate

    grasp

    of the

    probability

    that

    we are

    wrong

    and

    of what the

    assumptions are what we have

    added

    along

    the

    way,

    there no

    longer

    seems to me

    any

    reason

    for

    anyone to

    tell anyone

    else what

    notto

    do.

    Although hoseworkers

    ngaged

    n

    the

    production f

    trees and

    scenarios

    might

    differwith Eldredge on the situationbeingas extreme s he makes touttobe,

    they oo

    are aware

    ofthe

    difficulties.

    or

    example,

    Lucchese

    (1978:716)

    concludes

    a

    paper on the

    evolution

    f sex

    chromo-

    somes

    with

    he

    followingemarks:

    ...

    for

    n

    individual

    to

    profess

    n

    insight

    nto

    the

    biological

    changes

    that

    have

    occurred

    through

    time

    remains

    an

    act of faith

    of

    considerable mag-

    nitude.

    [Yet,

    within]

    the

    limitationsust

    set forth,

    the

    purpose

    of

    this

    article

    has been

    to

    spin a rel-

    ativelyreasonable evolutionarytale in the hope

    of

    expanding

    the

    current

    perception of a

    highly

    significant

    xample

    of genetic

    regulation

    in eu-

    karyotes.

    This content downloaded from 142.51.1.212 on Mon, 21 Jul 2014 17:05:11 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/10/2019 The Limits of Cladism- by David L. Hull Systematic Zoology, Vol. 28, No. 4 (Dec., 1979), pp. 416-440.

    11/26

    1979

    LIMITS

    OF CLADISM

    425

    THE

    PRINCIPLE

    OF

    DICHOTOMY

    Few

    principles

    attributed

    to cladistic

    taxonomists

    have caused

    more

    conster-

    nation and

    confusion

    than the claim

    that

    all cladogramsand classificationsmust be

    strictly

    dichotomous.

    When cladism

    was

    first

    ntroduced

    to English-speaking

    sys-

    tematists,

    cladists

    and anti-cladists

    alike

    agreed

    that the principle

    of

    dichotomy

    was

    essential

    to

    the

    philosophy

    of

    Hen-

    nig and

    Brundin

    (Nelson,

    1971a:373;

    see

    also

    Darlington,

    1970:3;

    Mayr,

    1974:

    100;

    Bonde,

    1975:302;

    Platnick,

    1977d:438).

    Although

    Cracraft

    1974:79)

    agrees

    that phylogenetic

    classification

    sensu Hennig and Brundin would appear

    to require

    the

    assumption

    of dichotomous

    branching,

    cladistic

    classification

    in

    a

    more

    general

    sense

    does

    not necessitate

    dichotomous

    branching,

    and the exact

    pattern

    f branching

    s determined

    by

    the

    manner

    in

    which

    shared

    derived

    charac-

    ter-states

    cluster

    taxonomic

    units. The

    question

    remains

    why

    the principle

    of

    dichotomy

    has seemed

    so central

    to most

    cladists

    and continues

    to seem

    so to

    some.

    Although

    no

    cladist

    has ever

    main-

    tained

    that the

    principle

    of

    dichotomy

    s

    an empirical

    claim

    about the

    speciation

    process,

    few

    cladists

    have

    been

    able

    to

    resist the

    temptation

    to justify

    t

    by ref-

    erence to empirical

    considerations.

    For

    example,

    Hennig (1966:210,

    211) begins

    by stating

    hatdichotomy

    s

    primarily

    no

    more than

    a methodological

    principle

    and then goes

    on

    to

    add,

    A

    priori

    it is

    very improbable that a stem species ac-

    tually

    disintegrates

    nto several

    daughter

    species

    at once.

    Cracraft

    1974:79)

    in-

    terrupts

    the

    discussion quoted

    above

    with the

    remark

    that the

    principle

    of

    di-

    chotomy

    can

    be

    justified

    on

    theoretical

    grounds

    not

    associated

    with classifica-

    tion.

    Bonde

    (1975:302)

    agrees.

    Although

    dichotomy

    s

    a

    methodological

    principle,

    in nature

    speciations

    are probably

    near-

    ly

    always

    dichotomous.

    Whether multiple speciation seems

    possible

    or

    impossible

    depends

    on

    the

    unit

    of

    time one

    selects to

    define

    simul-

    taneous.

    As

    Hennig

    (1966:211)

    notes,

    the

    issue

    of dichotomous

    speciation

    can

    be trivialized

    by defining

    simulta-

    neous

    too

    narrowly.

    If

    it

    is defined

    in

    terms

    of split

    seconds,

    then

    multiple

    spe-

    ciation is impossible. Conversely, if si-

    multaneous

    is

    defined

    too

    broadly,

    everything

    an be

    made to occur

    at

    the

    same

    time.

    The question

    of

    dichoto-

    mous speciation

    can

    be

    made significant

    only

    by

    the specification

    of a unit of

    time

    which

    makes

    sense

    in

    the context of

    the

    evolutionary

    process.

    In the absence

    of

    such

    a unit,

    the notion

    of

    simultaneity

    can

    be

    expanded

    or contracted

    t will

    and

    the

    issue

    decided

    by

    fiat

    see

    Cracraft,

    1974:74).

    Whether

    multiple speciation

    as an em-

    pirical

    phenomenon

    seems plausible

    or

    implausible

    depends

    on

    the

    model

    (or

    models)

    of

    speciation

    which one

    holds.

    If

    speciation

    is viewed

    as the

    gradual

    split-

    ting

    and

    divergence

    of

    large

    segments

    of

    a species,

    as Hennig (1966:210)

    main-

    tains,

    then

    multiple

    speciation

    looks

    less

    likely

    than

    if it is

    viewed

    as

    a

    process

    in

    which

    small,

    peripheral

    populations

    be-

    come isolated and develop into separate

    species,

    as

    Wiley (1978:22)

    supposes.

    But, as

    the cladists

    have reminded

    us

    often

    enough,

    dichotomy

    is

    a

    methodo-

    logical

    principle.

    If

    speciation

    were

    al-

    ways

    dichotomous,

    this fact

    about

    evor

    lution

    would

    certainly

    lend support

    to

    dichotomy

    s

    a methodological

    principle,

    but

    good

    reasons might

    exist

    for

    produc-

    ing exclusively

    dichotomous

    cladograms

    and

    classifications

    even

    if

    speciation

    is

    not always dichotomous.

    Cladists

    have

    presented

    two sorts

    of

    justification

    for

    their preference

    for the

    principle

    of

    dichotomy:

    our inability

    to

    distinguish

    dichotomous

    speciation

    from

    more

    complex

    sorts

    of speciation

    and our

    inability

    to

    represent

    unequivocally

    more

    complex

    sorts

    of speciation

    in

    cladograms

    and classifications.

    If

    one

    limits

    oneself

    ust to

    traditionally-defined

    traits

    e.g.,

    presence

    of

    various sorts

    of

    appendages, dentitions,etc.) and if one

    assumes

    that these

    traits have

    been

    ap-

    propriately

    individuated

    and identified,

    This content downloaded from 142.51.1.212 on Mon, 21 Jul 2014 17:05:11 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/10/2019 The Limits of Cladism- by David L. Hull Systematic Zoology, Vol. 28, No. 4 (Dec., 1979), pp. 416-440.

    12/26

    426

    SYSTEMATIC ZOOLOGY

    VOL.

    28

    then he argument hichthe

    cladistsput

    forth

    s

    reasonably traightforward.

    f a

    cladist

    tarts ith

    nytwo pecies

    chosen

    at random nd compares third

    pecies

    to them, wo ofthese species

    will be cla-

    disticallymore closely relatedto each

    other

    than

    either

    is

    to the remaining

    species.

    If

    the cladist continues o add

    species to his study ne at a time,he will

    produce a consistently dichotomous

    cladogram

    ntil

    ne oftwothings ccurs:

    either he happens upon

    a

    genuine

    in-

    stance of multiple peciation

    or else he

    is unable to resolve this complex situa-

    tion nto he ppropriateequence

    of uc-

    cessive dichotomies.

    ecause dichotomy

    is the simplesthypothesis,t should al-

    ways

    be

    preferred,

    vidence

    permitting.

    But as the cladists see it, giventhe sort

    of

    data available to the

    systematist

    nd

    the resolvingpower of his methods of

    analysis, e

    will

    always

    end

    up

    wherehe

    begins-with

    doubt

    or

    with

    dichotomy.

    Never is

    a

    systematistustified

    n

    con-

    cluding

    that

    speciation

    vent

    s

    genu-

    inely trichotomous ecause he is never

    justified

    n

    dismissing hepossibilityhat

    an apparent richotomys really pair of

    unresolveddichotomies.

    If

    the preceding

    s a fair

    haracteriza-

    tion of the cladists'argument,

    t has

    two

    weaknesses.

    First,

    he cladists re

    selec-

    tive

    in

    acknowledging ossible

    sources

    of error.After

    ll,

    a

    systematist

    annot

    guarantee

    hat trait

    which

    he considers

    to be unique and derived actually is.

    There

    is

    always the possibility

    hathe

    is

    dividing singlegroup

    nto woor ump-

    ing two groups nto one. Ifa trichotomy

    represents ither genuine richotomyr

    two unresolveddichotomies, hen a

    di-

    chotomy

    could

    just

    as

    well

    represent

    either

    genuinedichotomy,

    lumped

    ri-

    chotomy,

    r a

    single ineage

    dividedmis-

    takenly nto

    two. When

    a

    systematist

    claims that

    particular peciation

    vent

    is trichotomous,e maybe mistaken, ut

    he

    may

    lso

    be

    mistaken

    n

    claiming

    hat

    it s dichotomous. uring heearly tages

    of nvestigation,oubtsaboutthe actual

    cladistic elationswhichcharacterize he

    groups under study are legitimate.

    Many

    trichotomies re very likely to

    be resolv-

    able into

    dichotomies

    after

    urther tudy,

    many of the groups treated as

    single may

    have to be split

    into two or

    more groups,

    and vice versa. However, as the groups

    are studied

    more exhaustively, the legit-

    imacy of continued doubt decreases.

    If

    after xhaustive study,three

    species con-

    tinue to appear

    to be related

    trichoto-

    mously, the claim

    that they mightactual-

    ly be related by a pair of dichotomies

    begins to ring rather

    hollow. Descartes

    has shown where that sort of

    mindless

    scepticism

    leads.

    If

    a

    systematist

    an be-

    come

    reasonably certain

    that

    he

    has

    cor-

    rectly discerned a genuine dichotomy,

    see no

    reason why

    he

    cannot also

    attain

    that same

    level of certainty

    n the iden-

    tification of

    trichotomies-even

    using

    just the

    traditional methods of cladistic

    analysis.

    But

    systematists re not

    limited

    just to the study

    of ordinary taxonomic

    traits.There

    is

    no reason fornot

    using the

    methods of

    cladistic analysis on other

    sorts of evidence, e.g.,

    the

    data

    of histor-

    ical biogeography.

    As Platnick and Nel-

    son (1978: 10) remark:

    Trichotomous

    cladograms are of no signifi-

    cance

    as tests

    or

    as initial

    hypotheses)

    unless

    the

    cladograms

    for

    all available

    test

    groups

    are

    tri-

    chotomous,

    in

    which case we

    may

    suspect

    that

    an event disconnected

    an area

    into

    three smaller

    areas

    simultaneously. Testing

    this

    hypothesis by

    biotic relationships

    seems

    impossible (because

    we have no

    way

    of

    distinguishing

    those clado-

    grams reflecting

    ctual trichotomiesfrom those

    reflecting

    only our

    failure

    to

    find the relevant

    synapomorphies

    that would

    resolve

    a dichoto-

    mous cladogram),but it should be subject to in-

    dependent testing by

    data

    from

    historical

    geolo-

    gy,

    which

    can

    either be

    in

    accordance

    with such

    a

    synchronoustripartite

    isconnection of

    the

    to-

    tal area or not.

    If

    multiple

    speciation can occur

    in na-

    ture and

    if n

    certain circumstances

    t can

    be

    discerned,

    then cladists would be

    wise to devise

    methods of

    representing

    multiple speciation

    in

    their cladograms

    and

    classifications.One theme

    which the

    cladists repeatedlyvoice is thatanything

    represented

    in

    a

    cladogram

    and

    classifi-

    This content downloaded from 142.51.1.212 on Mon, 21 Jul 2014 17:05:11 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/10/2019 The Limits of Cladism- by David L. Hull Systematic Zoology, Vol. 28, No. 4 (Dec., 1979), pp. 416-440.

    13/26

    1979

    LIMITS OF CLADISM

    427

    cation should be

    represented xplicitly

    andunambiguously.fcladistswere will-

    ing to arguethat richotomouspeciation

    never took place, then trichotomiesn

    cladograms

    would not be

    ambiguous.

    They would always represent pair of

    unresolveddichotomies.

    s

    things tand

    now, they are ambiguous,representing

    either

    genuine richotomyr

    else a

    pair

    of unresolveddichotomies.

    Whether

    r

    not cladists

    think

    hat nstances

    f

    mul-

    tiple speciation can be discerned, the

    adoptionof such

    an

    ambiguousmode of

    representation eems counter-produc-

    tive. A better lternative ould be to re-

    serve

    trichotomies or representing

    ri-

    chotomouspeciation vents hewaythat

    dichotomies are used to representdi-

    chotomous

    peciationevents,epistemo-

    logical doubts o one side, and to devise

    another

    way

    of

    indicating ncomplete

    knowledge.For example,

    f

    systematist

    is reasonably ure that two species are

    each other's

    losest relatives,

    e can

    in-

    dicate

    this

    by

    a

    dichotomy.

    f

    he thinks

    --they ight

    e but

    s

    not ure,

    he can

    con-

    nect them

    y dots.

    Similar emarks

    pply

    to trichotomiessee Fig. 2). No system f

    representation

    an

    represent verything,

    but

    if

    doubt

    s

    importantnoughtorep-

    resent

    in

    a

    cladogram,

    t

    is

    important

    enough

    to

    represent nequivocally.

    Similar

    emarks re equally applicable

    to classifications. or example, Nelson

    (1973c) distinguishes

    etween

    the

    two

    sorts

    f

    representationommonly

    sed

    in

    the Linnaean

    hierarchy-subordination

    and

    sequencing-and

    shows

    how

    com-

    binationsof these two conventions an

    represent variety f evolutionary he-

    nomena including trichotomouspecia-

    tion. More

    recently,Wiley (1979)

    has

    suggested using

    sedis mutabilis when-

    ever the order

    of

    isting

    axa

    n

    a

    classi-

    fication

    means

    nothing.

    n

    addition o the

    difficulties hich he

    recognition

    f

    mul-

    tiple speciation

    aises

    for

    ladograms

    nd

    classifications,

    t

    also

    poses problems

    for

    theproperdefinition f monophylynd

    related terms (Wiley, 1977; Platnick,

    1977c).

    A B 7

    c

    FIG.

    2.-The ambiguitybetween genuine trichot-

    omies and unresolved

    dichotomies. (a) A clado-

    gram which represents

    unambiguously a pair of

    successive dichotomies;

    epistemological doubts, if

    any, are not indicated.

    (b) A cladogram which is

    commonly used to represent a pair of unresolved

    dichotomies, a genuine trichotomy, ommon ances-

    try nd reticulate evolution.

    (c)

    A

    cladogram which

    indicates doubt about the

    actual relations between

    the species indicated.

    Such cladograms might in

    time resolve to (a) a pair

    of dichotomies or (b) a

    genuine trichotomy.

    ommon ancestry and reticu-

    late evolution must be

    represented in some other

    but equally unambiguous fashion.

    ANCESTOR-DESCENDANT

    RELATIONS

    Although some disagreement exists

    over the

    occurrence of

    multiple specia-

    tion, everyone

    agrees thatcertain species

    which

    once existed no

    longer

    exist and

    that some of these

    species gave rise to

    Recent species. The

    cladists' complaints

    about the

    ancestor-descendant relation

    cannot possibly be interpreted s empir-

    ical. They are clearly methodological.

    Once again the distinctionmust be made

    between difficulties n

    discerning

    ances-

    tor-descendant relations and

    difficulties

    in representing them.

    Farris (1976:272)

    acknowledges

    this

    distinction when

    he

    presents two reasons fornot treatingfos-

    sil

    species

    as

    ancestral

    to later species:

    First, there

    is

    no obvious way of using a

    classi-

    fication

    to

    represent ancestor-descendant

    rela-

    tionships.A taxonomic ierarchy ith tswell-

    nested axa s naturally

    uitedonly o the repre-

    sentation

    f sister-groupelationships.econd

    while

    ister-group

    elationships ay

    more

    r ess

    readilybe established hroughhedetection f

    apomorphous

    imilarities, ncestor-descendant

    relationships aynot

    be so established.

    A

    second

    distinction

    of

    equal impor-

    tance

    is between the

    recognition

    of

    ex-

    tinct

    species

    as

    species

    and

    deciding

    which

    species gave

    rise to which.

    Those

    cladists who are willing to recognize ex-

    tinct

    species

    as

    species

    while

    maintain-

    This content downloaded from 142.51.1.212 on Mon, 21 Jul 2014 17:05:11 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/10/2019 The Limits of Cladism- by David L. Hull Systematic Zoology, Vol. 28, No. 4 (Dec., 1979), pp. 416-440.

    14/26

    428

    SYSTEMATIC

    ZOOLOGY VOL. 28

    ing that he

    ancestor-descendantelation

    is unknowable

    re put

    in

    the

    positionof

    explaininghow we can

    knowthe former

    but

    notthe atter

    Engelmann

    nd

    Wiley,

    1977).

    Those cladistswho

    arguethat

    nei-

    ther s knowable re spared hisdilemma

    but

    are faced

    with the

    problem

    of

    what

    to do with

    fossils.L0vtrup

    1973) argues

    that

    xtinctpecies are so

    poorlyknown

    that hey hould

    be totally xcluded

    from

    classifications. rowson

    1970) sees the

    differences

    n

    our

    ability

    o

    recognize x-

    tinct nd extant

    orms o be

    sufficiently

    great

    hat hey

    houldbe included

    n

    sep-

    arate classifications.

    elson

    (1972a:230)

    reasons

    hat ossilgroups

    houldbe fitted

    intoclassifications hich lso contain e-

    cent

    groups

    but

    distinguished

    y

    some

    convention.

    Finally, Rosen

    (1978:176)

    agrees that extant and

    extinct forms

    should be

    distinguishedbut that

    they

    shouldbe

    treated

    s

    the same sorts

    fen-

    tities-groups

    distinguished y

    unique

    derived

    characters.

    n

    this

    section

    will

    deal

    first

    with difficultiesn

    discerning

    species

    and

    ancestor-descendant

    ela-

    tionsand then

    withproblemsof

    repre-

    sentation.

    Hennig

    (1966, 1975)

    and

    Brundin

    (1972b) maintain

    that

    the biological

    species

    concept

    s

    central

    o

    phylogenet-

    ic systematics.rom

    the

    beginning,

    rit-

    ics of

    thebiological

    pecies concepthave

    argued

    that t is

    not

    sufficiently

    opera-

    tional even

    for

    xtant

    pecies.

    Perhaps

    it is

    possible to

    ascertainwhich

    organ-

    isms actually

    have mated with

    one

    another

    o producefertile

    ffspring

    nd

    whichorganisms annotmate witheach

    other nd/or

    roduce

    fertile

    ffspring,

    ut

    it

    is impossible

    to discoverwhich

    could

    have done so but did

    not.

    When the

    species

    under

    investigation

    re

    extinct,

    so

    the critics

    rgue,

    nothing

    an be

    dis-

    covered

    directly

    bout their

    reeding

    e-

    lations.

    t

    is

    certainly

    rue that

    the bio-

    logical species

    concept

    is

    not very

    operational,

    ut

    as

    I

    have

    argued

    else-

    where,

    no

    theoretically ignificant

    on-

    cept n science s (Hull, 1968, 1970).The

    interesting uestion

    is whether

    iologi-

    cal

    species

    can be

    discerned often

    enough and with sufficientertainty o

    justify ystematists'ttemptingo repre-

    sent hem

    n

    their

    lassifications.

    n

    even

    more fundamental uestion is whether

    biological species

    are

    sufficientlympor-

    tantto the evolutionary rocess to war-

    rant he attention hey re given. But in

    any case, the existence nd extent f bi-

    ological species are almost always in-

    ferred

    ndirectly

    rom

    haracter istribu-

    tions. Hence, mistakes will be made.

    When these species are extinct,mistakes

    are even

    more ikely

    and

    our abilityto

    correct hem ven more imited.No one

    could possibly laim that

    ll

    pterodactyls

    belonged

    to

    a

    single species,

    but

    finer

    distinctionsrehighly roblematic.

    Thus, those cladists who continue to

    maintain hatbiological species are the

    ultimate nits

    n

    their nvestigationsre

    forced

    o admit hat heir

    ladogramsnd

    classificationsmightbe mistaken.They

    mighthave lumped several species into

    one

    or divided a

    single species

    into

    two

    or more

    pecies.

    For extinct

    orms,

    hese

    mistakes re difficult,

    f

    not impossible,

    to remedy. ladistswho have abandoned

    the biological pecies concept re spared

    this problem. They are not classifying

    species

    but are

    grouping rganisms

    c-

    cording

    to

    the

    possession

    of

    particular

    traits.The

    only

    doubt associated with

    such an

    exercise

    is

    whether

    he

    organ-

    isms actuallyhave the trait ttributed o

    them,whether r not

    t s

    actually

    trait

    and

    not several,

    and

    whether

    t

    has

    the

    distribution

    ttributedo

    t.

    The

    question

    remainswhether

    t is

    any easier to indi-

    viduate raits han t s to ndividuatehe-

    oretically ignificant

    axa.The two

    seem

    both

    conceptually

    nd

    inferentiallyery

    closely connected.

    If

    extinct pecies cannot e recognized

    as

    genuinegroups

    f

    some

    sort, hey

    an-

    not be recognized

    s

    sistergroups.

    But

    assuming

    hat

    extinct orms

    an

    be rec-

    ognized

    as extinct

    pecies

    or

    as

    extinct

    groupsdelimited y

    a

    particularrait,

    an

    ancestor-descendant

    elations

    between

    extinct and extant forms lso be dis-

    cerned?Cladists

    re

    all butunanimous

    n

    claiming

    that

    they

    cannot.

    As

    Nelson

    This content downloaded from 142.51.1.212 on Mon, 21 Jul 2014 17:05:11 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/10/2019 The Limits of Cladism- by David L. Hull Systematic Zoology, Vol. 28, No. 4 (Dec., 1979), pp. 416-440.

    15/26

    1979

    LIMITS

    OF

    CLADISM

    429

    (1973b:311) states, Indeed,

    I

    have as-

    sumed that ancestral species cannot be

    identified s such in the fossil record, and

    I have pointed out that this assumption

    is fundamental to Hennig's phylogenetic

    systematics. Two considerations seem

    central to the

    cladists'

    claim

    that

    ances-

    tor-descendantrelations are unknowable.

    First, any distribution of characters

    which would

    imply

    that one

    taxon

    was

    ancestral to

    another

    would equally imply

    that one was the sister group of the other,

    and no other way

    exists for

    deciding

    ancestor

    relations.

    Second, given

    the

    vast

    number of species which

    must have ex-

    isted from he beginning of time and the

    relatively few which have left records, it

    seems very unlikely

    that

    very many

    ac-

    tual common ancestors have been discov-

    ered.

    I

    find the second argument more