Sophocles and the Athenian Democracy

download Sophocles and the Athenian Democracy

of 81

Transcript of Sophocles and the Athenian Democracy

  • 8/20/2019 Sophocles and the Athenian Democracy

    1/211

    SOPHOCLES ANDTHE TRAGEDY OF

    ATHENIAN

    DEMOCRACY

     JOSH BEER

    PRAEGER

  • 8/20/2019 Sophocles and the Athenian Democracy

    2/211

    Sophocles and the Tragedy

    of Athenian Democracy

  • 8/20/2019 Sophocles and the Athenian Democracy

    3/211

    Recent Titles in Lives of the Theatre

    Richard Wagner and Festival Theatre

    Simon Williams

    George Bernard Shaw and the Socialist Theatre

    Tracy C. Davis

    Christopher Marlowe and the Renaissance of Tragedy Douglas Cole

    Menander and the Making of Comedy

     J. Michael Walton and Peter D. Arnott 

    Sam Shepard and the American Theatre

     Leslie A. Wade

    Harold Pinter and the New British Theatre

     D. Keith Peacock 

    Voltaire and the Theatre of the Eighteenth Century

     Marvin Carlson

    Gower Champion: Dance and American Musical Theatre

     David Payne-Carter 

    Clifford Odets and American Political Theatre

    Christopher J. Herr 

    Michel Saint-Denis and the Shaping of the Modern Actor 

     Jane Baldwin

  • 8/20/2019 Sophocles and the Athenian Democracy

    4/211

    SOPHOCLES AND THETRAGEDY OF

    ATHENIAN

    DEMOCRACY

    JOSH BEER 

    Contributions in Drama and Theatre Studies, Number 105

    LIVES OF THE THEATRE

    SIMON WILLIAMS and CHRISTOPHER INNES, Series Advisers

  • 8/20/2019 Sophocles and the Athenian Democracy

    5/211

    Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication DataBeer, Josh

    Sophocles and the tragedy of Athenian democracy / Josh Beer.

     p. cm.—(Contributions in drama and theatre studies, ISSN 0163–3821 ; no. 105.

    Lives of the theatre)

    Includes bibliographical references and index.

    ISBN 0–313–28946–8 (alk. paper)

    1. Sophocles—Criticism and interpretation. 2. Political plays, Greek—History and

    criticism. 3. Sophocles—Homes and haunts—Greece—Athens. 4. Politics and

    literature—Greece—Athens. 5. Sophocles—Political and social views. 6. Mythology,

    Greek, in literature. 7. Theater—Greece—Athens. 8. Democracy in literature.

    9. Tragedy. I. Title. II. Contributions in drama and theatre studies ; no. 105.

    III. Contributions in drama and theatre studies. Lives of the theatre.

    PA4417.B37 2004

    882.01—dc28 2003060423

    British Library Cataloguing in Publication Data is available.

    Copyright © 2004 by Josh Beer 

    All rights reserved. No portion of this book may be

    reproduced, by any process or technique, without theexpress written consent of the publisher.

    Library of Congress Catalog Card Number: 2003060423

    ISBN: 0–313–28946–8

    ISSN: 0163–3821

    First published in 2004

    Praeger Publishers, 88 Post Road West, Westport, CT 06881

    An imprint of Greenwood Publishing Group, Inc.

    www.praeger.comPrinted in the United States of America

    The paper used in this book complies with the

    Permanent Paper Standard issued by the National

    Information Standards Organization (Z39.48–1984).

    10 9 8 7 6 5 4 3 2 1

  • 8/20/2019 Sophocles and the Athenian Democracy

    6/211

  • 8/20/2019 Sophocles and the Athenian Democracy

    7/211

  • 8/20/2019 Sophocles and the Athenian Democracy

    8/211

  • 8/20/2019 Sophocles and the Athenian Democracy

    9/211

    given time is set. Theatre itself can be seen to have a palpable effect on the

    social world around it, because it reflects the life of its time and helps to

    form that life by feeding it images, epitomes, and alternative versions of 

    itself. Hence, we hope that this series will also contribute to an under-standing of the broader social life of the period in which the theatre that is

    the subject of each volume was a part.

     Lives of the Theatre grew out of an idea that Josh Beer put to Christo-

     pher Innes and Peter Arnott. Sadly, Peter Arnott did not live to see the inau-

    guration of the series. Simon Williams kindly agreed to replace him as one

    of the series editors and has played a full part in its preparation. In com-

    memoration, the editors wish to acknowledge Peter’s own rich contributionto the life of the theatre.

    Josh Beer 

    Christopher Innes

    Simon Williams

    viii Series Foreword  

  • 8/20/2019 Sophocles and the Athenian Democracy

    10/211

    Acknowledgments

    I should like to thank Christopher Innes and Simon Williams, the coeditors

    of the Lives of the Theatre, for their unflagging patience as well as their 

    suggestions for improving this manuscript. I have used the Greek text of 

    Sophocles’ Plays and Fragments, edited and translated by Sir Hugh Lloyd-Jones in three volumes in the Loeb Classical Library edition of Sophocles

    (Cambridge, Mass., 1994–96). Except for one passage of Thucydides in

    chapter 8, where I have used the well-known translation of R. Crawley,

    first published in 1876, the translations in the book are my own. They are

    intended purely to be functional without any pretensions to literary merit.

    In chapter 7, I have incorporated some material I originally used in an arti-

    cle titled “The Riddle of the Sphinx and the Staging of Oedipus Rex,”

     Essays in Theatre 8 (1990): 105–20. I should like to thank the editors for  permission to use this material.

    I have a number of other acknowledgments. Three friends—Victor 

    Valentine, Steve Kupfer, and Bill McGrahan—kindly read parts of the

    manuscript and suggested improvements where they did not think my text

    was easily comprehensible to the general reader. Mrs. Catherine Andreadis,

    with great patience, helped to make the manuscript ready for the publisher.

    I also owe acknowledgments to the Office of the Dean of Arts and SocialSciences and the Office of the Dean of Graduate Studies at Carleton Uni-

    versity, Ottawa, Canada, as well as the Social Sciences and Humanities

    Research Council of Canada for subventions toward the research and pub-

    lication of this book.

    There is one other acknowledgment to be made of a different order.

    Before his death in 1990, Peter Arnott and I discussed matters related

    to Greek tragedy on many occasions. I still look at his marionette perfor-

  • 8/20/2019 Sophocles and the Athenian Democracy

    11/211

    mance of Euripides’ Bacchae on video to remind myself that the characters

    of Greek tragedies were masks, something admirably suggested by his

    marionettes. There is much in this book that I know Peter would have dis-

    agreed with, but it has been written in homage to someone who was a manof the theatre in every sense. Finally, I dedicate the book to Barnaby and 

    Carmel.

    [James Barrett’s Staged Narrative: Poetics and the Messenger in Greek 

    Tragedy, Berkeley, Calif. (2002), Pat Easterling and Edith Hall, eds., Greek 

    and Roman Actors: Aspects of an Ancient Profession, Cambridge (2002),

    and Rush Rehm’s The Play of Space: Spatial Transformation in Greek 

    Tragedy, Princeton, N.J. (2002), reached me after this book had gone to press. In conformity with The Lives of the Theatre series, I have not bur-

    dened the text with an overabundance of endnotes. My debts to many

    scholars are too numerous to acknowledge personally. I hope that the bib-

    liography serves as a token of my indebtedness.]

    x Acknowledgments

  • 8/20/2019 Sophocles and the Athenian Democracy

    12/211

    Introduction

    Although there are dissenters, there has been an increasing consensus that

    the Greek tragic theatre played an important role in the political life of 

    Athenian democracy in the fifth century. The way in which the theatre was

    funded and its institutional context within the life of Athenian democracy point to its public importance. Soon after the democratic reforms of Cleis-

    thenes at the end of the sixth century, the Athenians, at the beginning of the

    fifth century, immediately gave recognition to the theatre by erecting a

    large, permanent, public building for dramatic and choral performances on

    the southeast slope of the Acropolis. This space provided a larger gather-

    ing place for citizens to meet than did all other public places in Athens

    except the agora, which was not a building. The theatre itself could hold 

    considerably more people than could the area on the hill called the Pnyxwhere the ecclesia, the main political assembly of the Athenians, met.

    At first, only tragedies, satyr plays, and dithyrambs—which were orga-

    nized around the new tribes of the polis created by Cleisthenes’democratic

    reforms—were performed in this theatre. Comedy was introduced later, in

    486. Because the satyr play became subsidiary to tragedy, tragedy pro-

    vided the main dramatic fare. The emotional dangers inherent in tragedy

    were soon realized, for in the late 490s, the playwright Phrynichus put onhis Capture of Miletus, which so upset the Athenians that he was heavily

    fined and all future performances of the tragedy were banned. Tragedy as

    a theatrical art form intended for a large audience of citizens survived that

    crisis. It is difficult to imagine, however, that something as potentially sub-

    versive as tragedy—in which there is created an imaginary space within a

     public place, where different models of human behavior and conflict are

     presented for a mass audience to witness—would have been allowed to

  • 8/20/2019 Sophocles and the Athenian Democracy

    13/211

  • 8/20/2019 Sophocles and the Athenian Democracy

    14/211

    Chronology

    Date Sophocles Cultural Events Political Events

    c. 650?  Iliad and Odyssey

    594 Solon’s Reforms

    c. 546 Tyranny ofPisistratus begins

    c. 534 Traditional date of  

    first performance of 

    tragedy by Thespis

    527 Death of Pisistratus.

    Rule of Hippias and 

    Hipparchus begins

    525? Birth of Aeschylus

    514 Conspiracy of

    Harmodius and 

    Aristogiton.

    Assassination of 

    Hipparchus

    510 Expulsion of

    Hippias and end of tyranny

    508–507 Cleisthenes’

    democratic reforms

    507–506? Reorganization of  

    City Dionysia?

  • 8/20/2019 Sophocles and the Athenian Democracy

    15/211

    c. 500 Construction of first

    theatre of Dionysus

    on southeast slope of 

    Acropolis. Aeschylus’dramatic career begins

    c. 499 “Ionian” revolt

     begins

    c. 498 Burning of Sardis

    c. 496 Birth of Sophocles

    c. 495 Birth of Pericles

    494 Persian capture of  Miletus

    c. 492? Production of Archonship of

    Phrynichus’ Capture Themistocles

    of Miletus

    490 Eretria sacked.

    Battle of Marathon

    487–486 Comedies introduced Archons appointed  at Dionysia by lot

    485 Death of Darius.

    Xerxes becomes

    Persian king

    484 First victory of  

    Aeschylus at Dionysia

    480 Persian invasion.

    Athens abandoned.

    Battles of 

    Thermopylae and 

    Salamis

    479 Battles of Plataea

    and Mycale. “Ioni-

    ans” revolt from

    Persia478–477 Formation of Con-

    federacy of Delos.

    Rise of Cimon at

    Athens

    476 Phrynichus’ Phoenician

    Women performed.

    Themistocles choregus

    xiv Chronology

  • 8/20/2019 Sophocles and the Athenian Democracy

    16/211

    472 Aeschylus wins tragic

     prize with Persians.

    Pericles choregus

    471? Ostracism of  Themistocles

    469 Birth of Socrates

    468 Sophocles’ first entry at

    Dionysia? Defeats

    Aeschylus

    467 Aeschylus victorious

    at Dionysia withTheban Trilogy, Laius,

    Oedipus, Seven

    against Thebes

    464 Revolt of Spartan

    helots

    463 Aeschylus’ victory Cimon goes to aid  

    with Suppliants? Spartans

    Sophocles winssecond prize

    463–461 Ephialtes’ demo-

    cratic reforms at

    Athens. Areopagus

    deprived of political

     powers. Athens

    allies herself with

    Argos. Ephialtesassassinated. Cimon

    ostracized. Influence

    of Pericles begins

    458 Aeschylus victorious

    with Oresteia

    456 Death of Aeschylus

    455 Euripides competes atDionysia for the

    first time

    454 Treasury of Confed-

    eracy of Delos

    moved to Athens

    451 Periclean citizenship

    law at Athens

    Chronology xv

  • 8/20/2019 Sophocles and the Athenian Democracy

    17/211

    449–440? Production of Ajax and Prize introduced Peace made

    of Trachiniae for lead tragic with Persia

    (dates unknown) actors

    447 Sophocles victorious Building of Parthenonat Dionysia begins

    (plays unknown)

    445 Birth of Aristophanes? Thirty Years’ Peace

     between Athens and 

    Sparta

    445–438? Production of Antigone

    (date of 441 is dubious).

    Wins first prize

    443–442 Treasurer of Athena Ostracism of  

    Thucydides (not the

    historian)

    441–440 Strategos with Pericles? Euripides’ first tragic Revolt of Samos

    victory (plays unknown)

    438 Sophocles wins victory  Alcestis, first extant

    at Dionysia play of Euripides(plays unknown)

    c. 435–425Oedipus Rex?

    (Production date

    unknown.) Second prize

    431 Sophocles wins second Production of Beginning of

     prize at Dionysia Euripides’ Medea Peloponnesian War 

    and  Philoctetes.

    Gains third prize.Victory of Euphorion,

    son of Aeschylus

    429? Birth of Plato

    428 Euripides wins first Revolt of Mytilene

     prize at Dionysia

    with Hippolytus

    427 Surrender of  

    Mytilene

    425  Acharnians, first

    extant comedy of 

    Aristophanes

    421 Truce in Pelopon-

    nesian War (Peace of 

     Nicias)

    c. 420? Euripides’ Electra

    xvi Chronology

  • 8/20/2019 Sophocles and the Athenian Democracy

    18/211

    416 Destruction of  

    Melos

    415 Trojan Women of Beginning of

    Euripides (second Sicilian expedition. prize) Alcibiades deserts to

    Sparta

    413 Disaster of Atheni-

    ans in Sicily

    413–412 Sophocles as Proboulos Euripides’ Helen Athenian allies

    revolt

    411 Sophocles’ Electra? Establishment of  Committee of 400.

    Later overthrown

    410 Democracy restored  

    409 Sophocles’ victory

    with Philoctetes

    408 Euripides’ Orestes

    407 Alcibiades returns to

    Athens

    407–406 Death of Euripides

    406 Death of Sophocles Battle of Arginusae

    (either 406 or 405) (generals tried on

     bloc)

    405 Posthumous Battle of

     production of Aegospotami

    Euripides’ Bacchae?Aristophanes’ Frogs,

    first prize at Lenaea

    405–404 Blockade of Athens

    404 Surrender of Athens

    to Spartan Lysander.

    Tyranny of Thirty

    set up

    403 Defeat of Thirty.

    Restoration of 

    democracy

    401 Posthumous victory

    of Sophocles’ Oedipus

    at Colonus

    399 Trial and death of  

    Socrates

    Chronology xvii

  • 8/20/2019 Sophocles and the Athenian Democracy

    19/211

  • 8/20/2019 Sophocles and the Athenian Democracy

    20/211

    Chapter 1

    Tragedy, Athens, and the

    Greek Cultural Mosaic

    What is commonly known as Greek tragedy is sometimes more precisely

    called Athenian or Attic tragedy, because tragedy as we usually understand 

    the term was an Athenian invention. The three major tragic playwrights

    were all Athenians who composed their plays, with few exceptions, for  production in Athens in the fifth century. The fifth century witnessed both

    the flowering of Athenian democracy and the rise and fall of the Athenian

    empire. However, even when their political power was at its height, the

    Athenians did not achieve complete mastery over the Greek world,

     because there were many poleis that never succumbed to their sway and 

    there was always the countervailing power of the Spartans and the Pelo-

     ponnesian League. The Athenian empire—which was founded on, and 

    largely maintained by, the strength of the Athenian fleet—was acquired inthe years following the unsuccessful Persian invasion of Greece in 481–79.

    This empire reached its peak in the middle decades of the century, but in

    431, the Athenians became embroiled with the Spartans and their allies in

    the long and exhausting Peloponnesian War that led finally to Athens’

    defeat and the loss of her empire in 404.

    The years between 479 and 404 are central to our study. All the surviv-

    ing tragedies, with the possible exception of  Rhesus —whose Euripideanauthorship is seriously debatable—fall within these years, as do the dra-

    matic careers of Sophocles and Euripides. Although Aeschylus’ dramatic

    career had begun earlier, in about 500, it seems more than simple chance

    that all his extant works were composed in the decades following the

    expulsion of the Persians. In fact, it could well be argued that the demo-

    cratic reforms that had been instituted by Cleisthenes at Athens in 508 and 

    the major role that the Athenians had played in the liberation of Greece

  • 8/20/2019 Sophocles and the Athenian Democracy

    21/211

    from the Persians served as the catalyst for the maturing of tragedy in the

    hands of Aeschylus and Sophocles. At the very least, it is symbolically

    significant that the plot of the earliest surviving tragedy, Aeschylus’ Per-

     sians, produced in 472, is centered on the actual historical events of thePersian invasion and enacts the tragedy of oriental despotism against the

     background of the Greeks’ struggle for freedom.

    Even though the Athenians failed to gain complete military and politi-

    cal dominance over the other Greeks in this period, their cultural superi-

    ority nevertheless became unrivaled—to such an extent that on many

    occasions, when we talk about the achievements of the Greeks in this era,

    we are really talking about the achievements of the Athenians. If we may believe the historian Thucydides (2.41), Pericles, the main architect of 

    Athens’ imperial policy and her most successful statesman, claimed that

    Athens was “the School of Greece.” In the visual and performing arts,

    history, philosophy, and science, Athens provided a unique cultural

    milieu. Even though not all of the most important writers, artists, and 

    thinkers of the era were Athenian, Athens provided the cultural center that

    they frequented.

    Most significant from our point of view is that by the middle of the fifthcentury, the City Dionysia, the main festival at which the tragedies and 

    comedies were performed in Athens, had become the major annual show-

    case for the demonstration of Athenian cultural achievements as well as

    Athenian wealth and power. Not only did it attract an Athenian audience in

    the thousands, but also visitors and dignitaries from many quarters of the

    Greek world. Although strictly speaking, unlike the Olympic games and a

    few other festivals, the Dionysia was not a Panhellenic festival, it never-

    theless assumed a Panhellenic significance. In the wake of its success, the-

    atres were to spread throughout the Greek world and come to hold a

    central place among the civic structures of many Greek poleis.

    For all of Athens’ distinctiveness, culturally the Athenians shared much

    in common with other Greeks. Tragedy provides a case in point. Although

    it was essentially an Athenian creation, the Athenian tragedians were the

    heirs of a larger Greek poetic tradition, in which no Athenian stands out

     prominently, with the exception of Solon, a sixth-century Athenian states-man. The themes of Solon’s political poetry undoubtedly had an influence

    on the moral discourse of tragedy, but it is archaic choral lyric, on the one

    hand, and archaic narrative poetry (especially the epics of Homer) on the

    other, that helped to shape the dramatic structure of tragedy as it came to

    exist in fifth-century Athens. Homer—used as shorthand for the two epic

     poems the Iliad and the Odyssey —was “the poet” whom no Greek polis

    could claim as uniquely its own. Whatever the origins of the Homeric

    2 Sophocles and the Tragedy of Athenian Democracy

  • 8/20/2019 Sophocles and the Athenian Democracy

    22/211

    epics, such was their towering influence that, in no small measure, they

    helped to forge the common cultural identity of the Greeks.

    At the same time, the other great cultural cum political institution that

    was essential in shaping the classical Greeks was the polis. Although anascent form of the polis is detectable in Homer, what is much more impor-

    tant for the poems is the conception of the heroes as individuals. The Athe-

    nian tragedians, especially Sophocles, were greatly influenced by the

    Homeric heroes in creating their dramatis personae. In Sophocles, however,

    unlike in Homer, the fate of these heroic figures has to be seen squarely

    from the point of view of the value structure of the classical polis, even

    when the polis does not form the immediate physical setting of the play.The larger background of tragedy, then, is the world of the Greek polis.

    Although the setting of most tragedies is mythical, because the plays are set

    in a legendary past, the concerns of tragedy arose from the moral, political,

    and religious issues of the contemporary polis. Myth was not simply a vehi-

    cle for preserving the memory of a legendary past, even if the memory of 

    that past had helped to form the consciousness of the Greeks. Rather, the

    myths were constantly subject to change and were a dynamic means whereby

    current concerns could be explored by the playwright and presented to theaudience for their scrutiny and examination or re-examination. Thus, it was

    open to a Sophocles or a Euripides to dramatize a myth that an Aeschylus

    had already dramatized and to re-present it from a radically different moral

    or political point of view. Myths did not admit of closure. Although the

    main narrative outlines of a particular myth may have been formed in the

     preceding archaic age, there was always the possibility of introducing

    important variations. Therefore, in spite of Sophocles’Oedipus Rex, Euripi-

    des, in his Phoenician Women, chose not to have Jocasta commit suicide on

    learning of her incestuous marriage with her son, but to have her live on. In

    Euripides’ lost Antigone, unlike Sophocles’ Antigone, it seems that Creon

    handed Antigone over to Haemon to kill, but he fell in love with her and 

    they had a child together. There could even be important extensions to the

    more commonly known versions to emphasize a specifically Athenian

    dimension such as in Aeschylus’ Eumenides and Sophocles’ Oedipus at 

    Colonus. In some cases, such as Euripides’ Orestes or  Iphigenia in Tauris,the plot seems to have been almost completely invented.

    What helped to give the treatment of the myths in tragedy a “political”

    dimension was the presence of the chorus. In Greek tragedy, the fate of the

    mythical characters was acted out against the sounding board of a chorus

    who both sang and danced. The chorus commonly comprised an individu-

    ally anonymous group that was representative of some part of the commu-

    nity, whether they were elders, sailors, women, or slaves. The distinction

    Tragedy, Athens, and the Greek Cultural Mosaic 3

  • 8/20/2019 Sophocles and the Athenian Democracy

    23/211

     between the actors proper, who portrayed the mythological characters, and 

    the members of the chorus became clearly differentiated in the fifth century.

    Whereas the actors became professionals, the chorus was always formed of 

    ordinary citizens, even if their training was rigorous and extensive. In a realsense, the chorus could be said to represent the polis “onstage.”1

    Because the individual poleis constituted the main foundation on which

    the political culture of classical Greece was built, Greece did not constitute

    a nation-state in a modern sense of the term, because there were more than

    a thousand individual poleis. Although the Greeks collectively called 

    themselves Hellenes, each polis aspired to be politically autonomous and 

    economically self-sufficient. Thus, a Greek citizen was an Athenian or aCorinthian first and foremost and only secondly a Hellene.

    By the standards of modern nation-states, the size of these poleis was

    tiny, consisting of no more than a few hundred or so people at one end of 

    the spectrum, to a few very large ones like Athens, which consisted of a

    few hundred thousand people. Although the figures are conjectural, the

    Athenian population in about 431 was probably somewhere between

    250,000 and 350,000 people. Even though Athens was a democracy, only

    about 15 percent of that number were citizens in the full sense of the word, because possibly as many as one-third of the population was slaves and 

    there was a large number of resident aliens (metics) who—whether born

    elsewhere or born in Athens of metic  parents—were not entitled to citi-

    zenship. In addition, women were always legally minors, subject to a male

    kurios (master), and had no direct access to political power. In fact, Athe-

    nian democracy has sometimes been described as a “men’s club.” There-

    fore, the size of the actual citizen population, even of a very large polis that

    had a democracy, was relatively small; however, size was of the essence of 

    the polis. Indeed, Aristotle was so preoccupied with the size of an ideal

     polis that, when discussing its constitution, he claimed: “In deciding ques-

    tions of justice and the allocation of offices by merit, citizens must know

    each other’s characters, since where this condition is not met, the election

    of political officials and judicial proceedings will go awry” ( Politics 7.4).

    For him, if a community consisted of too few people, it did not meet the

    requirements of a polis in being self-sufficient. However, if, like a nation,it consisted of too many people, although it might be self-sufficient, it

    would not be a polis, because its size would make it incapable of having a

    constitutional government.

    Reduced to its bare essence, a polis was a small, close-knit community

    of citizens ( politai, free adult males), even if they were dependent on oth-

    ers (e.g., women and slaves, etc.) for their existence and survival. More-

    over, although each polis occupied a certain territory (which is discussed 

    4 Sophocles and the Tragedy of Athenian Democracy

  • 8/20/2019 Sophocles and the Athenian Democracy

    24/211

     below), this was, in a sense, secondary. As Thucydides has the Athenian

    general, Nicias, say: “Men make a polis and not walls or ships” (7.77). If 

    the polis in essence was a community of citizens, these citizens were

     bound together by a complex of social, political, religious, and militaryties that were forged, in part, by local conditions and traditions. Potentially,

    there was no worse political evil for members of a polis than stasis (polit-

    ical strife), because there was no secure protection from death or slavery

     beyond the polis. To be apolis (without a polis) was a terrible fate. Stasis

    and exile are recurrent themes in tragedy. Therefore, it was in the interests

    of citizens to defend their polis at all costs and to be ready to die for it.

    Thus, citizen armies were the norm and the army—whether mustered onland or sea—was essentially nothing more than the polis under arms.

    Each polis was built at root on a collection of oikoi. The word oikos

    may be variously translated as “house,” “family,” or “household.” The

    oikos was not simply a “nuclear family,” but was also the primary eco-

    nomic unit on which the polis was built. It consisted of house and prop-

    erty, including slaves and domestic animals. The head of the oikos was the

    male kurios to whom everyone else was subordinate, and his prime

    responsibility was to preserve the economic and social interests of theoikos. Marriages were arranged between the male heads of different

    oikoi, without there being any “romantic” involvement between the bride

    and groom, primarily so that marriage might provide for the continuation

    of the husband’s oikos through the begetting of children. The oikos was a

    cooperative enterprise in which the interests of each individual were sub-

    ordinate to those of the larger whole, although the master had overriding

    authority. Wives were usually considerably younger than their husbands

    for, as Cynthia Patterson says, “The key determining factor in the struc-

    ture of the ancient Greek family—or, more properly, the ancient Greek 

    household—is clearly life expectancy.”2 How women may have regarded 

    these marital arrangements is a moot point, but in tragedy, marriage was

    often an arena of violent conflict.

    Because many aristocratic oikoi had their own traditions that predated 

    the emergence of the democratic polis, there was always the potential for 

    tension between the interests of members of an oikos and the polis, partic-ularly when the polis began to encroach upon things that had traditionally

     been the preserve of the oikos. In this world, what constituted dike (com-

    monly translated as “justice,” although the Greek word has an extensive

    range of meanings) was a matter of ongoing debate and forms a central

    issue of many tragedies.

    If the first duty of members of the oikos was to ensure its collective sur-

    vival, the oikoi collectively needed the polis for defense against hostile

    Tragedy, Athens, and the Greek Cultural Mosaic 5

  • 8/20/2019 Sophocles and the Athenian Democracy

    25/211

    intrusion. Thus, it was incumbent on the various oikoi to provide the polis

    with able-bodied soldiers. Even when a polis, like Athens, became a

    democracy and gave all its politai the freedom to have an equal share in the

    day-to-day government of the polis (as much as was reasonably possible),that freedom was premised on an active participation in what the polis

    required. The idea that an individual could simply opt out and do his own

    thing, without performing the minimum requirements of his duty as a cit-

    izen, was scarcely countenanced. Even Socrates fought in the Athenian

    army and served on the boule (the Council).

    This “communitarian” notion of a person finding fulfilment in his duties

    to a larger entity, whether it be to the oikos or the polis, contrasts with thenotion of the individual we gain from Achilles, in the Iliad, who fought at

    Troy for his own personal glory and who, for later Greeks, became the par-

    adigm of aristocratic manhood. The contrast between the two conceptions

    of the individual—the Achillean and the communitarian—is one that helps

    to provide Sophoclean tragedy with many a fruitful tension. More gener-

    ally speaking, it is built into the structure of the tragedies with their indi-

    vidual protagonists and the collectivity of their chorus members.

    Let us briefly consider the polis as a territorial unit. Basically, the polisconsisted of an urban center with an agora, where trade could take place

    and political concerns could be discussed and resolved, and rural envi-

    rons, that were cultivated as much as possible because good, arable land 

    was at a premium. Although the territories of the Athenians and the Spar-

    tans were large by Greek standards, the territories of most poleis were

    restricted, whether because of the sea or nearby mountains or the territory

    of a neighboring polis. War was a common occurrence among neighbor-

    ing poleis and warfare was accepted as a fact of life. In the fifth century,

    Athens was at war on average every one year in two. The constant threat

    of war meant, of course, that although poleis valued their political inde-

     pendence, not all could survive alone without help; thus, many were

     joined together in alliances over which they might exercise a greater or 

    lesser degree of control.

    Although the Greeks were not politically united, there were certain

    important things shared in common that distinguished them in their ownminds from other peoples. In his Histories (8.144), Herodotus has some

    Athenian envoys state succinctly what these things are: their religion, their 

    racial kinship, their language, and their common way of life. Religion is a

    large topic that we shall have to treat separately and, for our purpose, what

    we have said about the polis can suffice for the moment about the Greek 

    “common way of life.” However, we should briefly state something about

    the Greeks’ “racial kinship” and “language.”

    6 Sophocles and the Tragedy of Athenian Democracy

  • 8/20/2019 Sophocles and the Athenian Democracy

    26/211

    The two topics are not wholly separable. Race, as we all know, is a

    loaded term. Although the Greeks regarded themselves as racially akin,

    Greek-speaking peoples had not all migrated into the central and southern

     parts of the Greek peninsula at the same time, but had settled there throughdifferent waves of migration between c. 2000 and c. 1000. Then, through

     pressures of one sort or another, many migrated overseas, inhabiting the

    littoral of a considerable part of the Mediterranean and the Black Sea. As

    a result, even though the Greeks spoke a mutually intelligible language,

    there were distinct tribal groupings among them. These tribal groupings

    were underscored by different dialects that can be clearly witnessed in dif-

    ferent types of poetry. We mentioned earlier that tragedy was heavilyindebted to archaic choral lyric, much of which was composed in Doric

    Greek, the dialect of the Spartans and Corinthians among others. Thus,

    Doric forms of Greek are found extensively in the choral parts of tragedy,

    even though the main tragic playwrights were Athenian whose local dia-

    lect was Attic, the dialect that predominates in the spoken parts of tragedy.

    The language of tragedy, therefore, was eclectic.

    A common language, in spite of dialectic variations, was an important

    factor in helping the Greeks to feel a sense of common ethnic identity and in separating Greeks from non-Greeks. In fact the Greek word that comes

    closest to expressing the modern notion of foreigner is the word bar-

    baros(oi), a word that may have originally suggested for the Greeks some-

    one who did not speak Greek. After the Persian Wars, however, the word 

    took on largely pejorative overtones with the implication that to be non-

    Greek was to be culturally inferior. Thus, the Persians were often collec-

    tively termed barbaroi. In this regard, tragedy not only reflected but no

    doubt helped to foster the cultural chauvinism of the Greeks. The term

    barbaros(oi) is found in Aeschylus’ Persians and is pervasive throughout

    the tragic corpus. Myth was harnessed in the interests of Greek or, more

     particularly, Athenian ideology. Thus, in the Homeric epics, we gain no

    sense that the Trojans are barbarians but—because, by the time of the Per-

    sian Wars, the area around Troy had become part of the Persian Empire— 

    we frequently find famous Trojans called barbarians.3

    Thus far, we have considered the polis almost wholly from a secular  point of view, but the citizens shared the polis with their gods, whose altars

    and shrines were visible everywhere. The Greek temple that, together with

    the oikos, forms the most frequent backdrop of the tragedies was the house

    of a god. It was not used, however, as a place of communal worship, like a

    Christian church; instead, it housed a statue of the god that served to

    acknowledge his or her presence. Much of the life of the polis was devoted 

    to religious rites and festivals. At Athens, more than a hundred days of the

    Tragedy, Athens, and the Greek Cultural Mosaic 7

  • 8/20/2019 Sophocles and the Athenian Democracy

    27/211

    year were given up to religious festivals of one sort or another. Both the

    tragedies and comedies were performed at religious festivals in honor of 

    Dionysus, who was honored at other festivals as well.

    Greek religion was polytheistic. The most well-known of these gods werethe twelve Olympians (Zeus, Apollo, etc.). In Homer, the presence of these

    anthropomorphic deities exerts a powerful influence on the actions of the

    heroes. According to Herodotus, it was the poets Homer and Hesiod who

    first “created theogonies for the Greeks by giving the gods their names and 

    defining their honors, powers and forms” (2.53). The poets, then, through

    their genealogies and stories of the gods, helped to forge for the Greeks a

    shared religious identity because—in the absence of an overriding religiousauthority, like the Christian Church, or a canonical religious text, like the

    Koran—the poets were often thought to provide insights into the ways of 

    the gods. However, even if their poetry could be conceived as being

    divinely inspired, the poets did not constitute a group of religious authori-

    ties in any formal sense. In fact, if we used the poets as our only source for 

    understanding Greek religion, we would gain a distorted view of it, because

    the poets—although they drew heavily, at times, on a common store of reli-

    gious experience—used the gods either for their own artistic purposes or asa means of presenting their own vision of human life and its problems. It is

    a contentious issue, for instance, to what extent we can use tragedy as evi-

    dence for understanding Greek religion as it was experienced in the daily

    life of the Greeks.4 All we can say positively is that, insofar as the tragedies

     present a Weltanshauung in which the human and the divine are inextrica-

     bly interrelated, they reflect—albeit in a refracted manner—a Greek view

    of the world. When we examine the life of the Greek polis, therefore, there

    is often no easy disjunction to be made between the secular and the divine

    or between politics and religion.

    Except at certain religious centers such as Delphi, where the priests of 

    Apollo presided over the administration of the oracle, there was no for-

    mally constituted class of priests who told the Greeks how to lead their 

    lives. The function of a priest, as the occasion demanded, could be fulfilled 

     by the head of an oikos, the general of the army, or the civic official who

    was in charge of the rites of a particular religious cult. For example, it wasthe 10 generals who, at the City Dionysia, poured libations to the god on

     behalf of the citizens. True, there were such people as soothsayers and ora-

    cle mongers who might read divine signs as manifested in sacrifices or in

    the sky, but these commanded no more authority than was credited to them

     by individuals or groups of individuals.

    In essence, Greek religion was not expressed by any overriding religious

    credo, but through a variety of religious observances (e.g., a sacrifice or a

    8 Sophocles and the Tragedy of Athenian Democracy

  • 8/20/2019 Sophocles and the Athenian Democracy

    28/211

     prayer, the construction of an altar or temple, or the holding of a festival)

    through which the power of a god was recognized. Because Greek religion

    did not constitute a closed system of belief, it was always possible to accept

    a new god. Thus, the Olympians were not the only gods; there were a hostof other deities, many of whom may have only been felt as vague presences

    and not conceived as anthropomorphic beings. In fact, the common Greek 

    terms for a god (theos and daemon) often imply simply some kind of power 

    immanent in human life, without the corollary that monotheistic religions

    commonly assume—that god is transcendent. Therefore, what we might

    regard as abstract ideas could be personified as gods: Poverty, Wealth, and 

    Persuasion, for example. Thus, although  Peitho (Persuasion) was some-times associated with Aphrodite, she had her own cultic status at Athens

    and could be worshipped either for her sexual power or, as we might expect

    in a democracy heavily dependent on the spoken word, as a political deity.5

    Because the day-to-day religion of the Greeks was mainly polis based,

    each polis had its own calendar, built around its own religious festivals and 

    cults. Several of these cults and festivals were agricultural in origin, because

    the economy of the Greeks was largely based on agriculture. Related to this,

    there were gods specifically connected with the earth, known as chthonicdeities. These gods could also be connected with the Underworld and the

    kingdom of Hades, whose name means “unseen,” so that their power could 

     be conceived as potentially sinister as well as beneficent.

    In each polis, the rites and festivals of the gods might take their own par-

    ticular form and, in every polis, some gods could assume a greater promi-

    nence than others. If, for example, Athena held a special place at Athens as

     Polias, guardian of the community, Hera assumed a similar position in

    Argos and Poseidon in Corinth. In the final analysis, it was the polis that

    determined how and what gods should be worshipped. Thus, the polis

     became the ultimate arbiter of what constituted eusebeia and  asebeia

    (what was correct or incorrect behavior toward the gods), words usually

    translated as “piety” or “reverence” and “impiety” or “irreverence,”

    respectively. Even if the evidence, in some instances, is unreliable, there

    are several cases recorded of people who were put on trial at Athens for 

    asebeia. Socrates, who was accused of “corrupting the young and notacknowledging the gods,” is the most famous.

    In addition, there were, of course, some festivals and religious centers

    that were Panhellenic, such as the festival at Olympia, where the famous

    games were held every four years, or the Oracle at Delphi. Because

     prophecies and oracles loom large in Greek tragedy—Sophoclean tragedy

     being a special case in point—we should briefly say a few things on the

    subject, without going into the complex issue of how and why oracles

    Tragedy, Athens, and the Greek Cultural Mosaic 9

  • 8/20/2019 Sophocles and the Athenian Democracy

    29/211

    (Delphi in particular) came to occupy such an important place in the Greek 

    world.

    In real life, oracles such as Delphi seem to have largely confined them-

    selves to giving advice or offering explanations in the face of disasters or what seemed inexplicable. As the spokesman of his father Zeus, Apollo,

    the chief god of Delphi, was felt to know the hidden meaning of events and 

    causes of things that were obscure to human beings. However, the gods

    were not believed to offer up their knowledge easily and thus oracular pro-

    nouncements often took the form of riddling statements and were open to

    different interpretations. Therefore, if an oracle seemed to be proved 

    wrong, that did not mean (for the believer in oracles) that Apollo was afalse prophet, but rather a wrong interpretation could well have been put

    on the oracular pronouncement. The Greeks were also aware that even if 

    Apollo spoke the truth, this did not mean that the priests at Delphi, who

     produced a written form of the oracle based on the utterances of an illiter-

    ate prophetess in a trance-like state, were infallible or could not be influ-

    enced. A not-uncommon charge against prophets and oracles was that they

    could be bribed. Confronted with an oracle, therefore, one always had to

    exercise caution. Moreover, there is no doubt that, although Delphi stillcommanded great influence in the fifth century and many still believed in

    oracles, in the wake of the “intellectual revolution” of the second half of 

    the century, there was a growing scepticism about the truth of oracles.

    When we turn to tragedy, we see that oracles and the prophets of the

    gods do not confine themselves to offering advice and explanations, but

    frequently predict the future. The classic example is Sophocles’ Oedipus

     Rex, in which the oracular pronouncements of Apollo at Delphi are central

    to the tragedy and prove all too true. Because of the truth of these oracles

    and their importance in the tragedy, it is not uncommon for it to be

    assumed that Sophocles was an upholder of the belief in oracles. However,

    it is also possible that Sophocles used oracles and prophecies in his

    tragedies primarily as an artistic device to serve the dramatic needs of his

     plot. We do not have to think that Shakespeare believed in witchcraft

     because he used the three witches to predict Macbeth’s future.

    There are three other aspects of Greek religion that should be mentioned  because they are relevant to understanding some aspects of Sophocles:

    hero-cults, the concept of “pollution,” and the unwritten laws that gov-

    erned the relationship between strangers. Unlike the gods, who were

    immortal, heroes were the famous dead, whether real or mythical. The

    Greeks did not really distinguish between the two, because the heroes of 

    myth were regarded as the legendary dead. The bones of a dead hero were

    thought to be endowed with special powers and a cult could grow up

    10 Sophocles and the Tragedy of Athenian Democracy

  • 8/20/2019 Sophocles and the Athenian Democracy

    30/211

    around his supposed grave. I say “supposed” purposely, because, in most

    instances, these graves were fictitious, but the shrines at which the heroes

    were worshipped were commonly treated as their actual tombs. Thus, it

    was quite possible for a hero to have a “tomb” in more than one place. Itwas thought that these heroes could be the workers of great benefit to a

    community but, if they were offended in some way or neglected, could also

    work harm. The exceptional power that heroes had manifested when they

    were alive was believed to continue after their death and that power was

    commonly believed to reside in the place where they were buried. The pos-

    session of a hero’s bones, therefore, was regarded as a matter of great

    importance.Two historical examples must suffice to illustrate this point. Once, when

    the Spartans were at odds with the Tegeans and were faring badly, they

    were informed by the Delphic oracle that they would only be successful in

    their struggle if they recovered the lost bones of Orestes (Herodotus

    1.67–68). Although the wording of the oracle was cryptic as to where these

     bones were to be found, eventually some bones were found that seemed to

    fit the oracle’s description, and Sparta became victorious. If Sparta had 

     been unsuccessful, the oracle might have replied that the captured boneswere not those of Orestes. Similarly, the Athenians were told by an oracle

    to recover the bones of their legendary king, Theseus, from the island of 

    Scyros (Plutarch Cimon 8). When the Athenian general Cimon went to

    Scyros, he reputedly discovered where the bones of Theseus were buried 

    and brought them back to Athens, where he was received with great honor.

    There was probably a personal political motive behind Cimon’s actions,

     but the important point is that this is no legendary event; it happened in the

    fifth century, within Sophocles’ own lifetime. Two of Sophocles’ tragedies,

     Ajax and Oedipus at Colonus, seem to foreshadow the heroization of the

     protagonist. Moreover, both Ajax and Oedipus came to be worshipped as

    heroes at Athens.

    Let us now turn to pollution, what the Greeks called miasma. The seri-

    ousness of a miasma varied, depending on the type of event that was felt to

    induce it. Thus, contact with childbirth and death could be construed as

    causing pollution in those directly involved. This pollution could becleansed through the observance of appropriate rituals. Much more seri-

    ous, however, was the type of pollution associated with such things as mur-

    der and acts of sacrilege. In these cases, the perpetrators, and even those

    who were associated with them, could be felt to have a moral stain that

    made them religiously impure and with whom contact of any kind could be

    extremely dangerous, affecting the whole family or community. Thus,

    the person(s) involved were, in a sense, “cursed.” In myth, Oedipus, the

    Tragedy, Athens, and the Greek Cultural Mosaic 11

  • 8/20/2019 Sophocles and the Athenian Democracy

    31/211

    subject of two of Sophocles’ surviving seven tragedies, is the most famous

    example.

    Lastly, we should mention the unwritten laws that governed the relation-

    ship between strangers. There are a number of references in Greek litera-ture to unwritten laws and there is some dispute as to what constituted 

    them, but the unwritten law governing the relationship between strangers

    was clearly one of them. In Greek, the word for a stranger (xenos) was the

    same word as for a “host” or a “guest,” because from earliest times—there

    are many examples in Homer—a traveler could be put up as a guest in a

    stranger’s home. Any violation of the code of correct behavior between

    host and guest was believed to be punishable by Zeus. Closely related isthe idea of Zeus as the god of suppliants. A suppliant could throw himself 

    on the mercy of a stranger, an enemy, or a god and ask for his protection.

    Because the suppliant was helpless and entrusted his life to the supplicated 

     person, it was a crime against Zeus to harm him. Several tragedies are built

    around the theme of suppliants and strangers.

    Fifth-century tragedy, then, drew inspiration widely from the common

    traditions of Greek culture, whether it was from language, poetry, myth,

    religion, or politics. Whatever the precise origins of tragedy, however, itwould not have blossomed and flourished in the way that it did without

    what transpired politically and culturally in Athens. It is in this sense that

    tragedy is a uniquely Athenian creation, so much so that it became an inte-

    gral part of the public life of Athenian democracy.

    The main structural framework of Athenian democracy was established 

     by Cleisthenes in c. 508. Outside of his political reforms and the general

     background to them, little is known about Cleisthenes except that he came

    from a famous aristocratic Athenian family, the Alcmaeonids, who had had 

    a curse put on them in the late seventh century and had, during the sixth

    century, suffered periods of exile. Toward the end of this period, they had 

     bribed the Delphic oracle to persuade the Spartans to intervene in Athe-

    nian affairs and drive out the Pisistratids, tyrants who had ruled Athens for 

    more than 30 years.

    During the sixth century, Athens had suffered times of great  stasis.

    Although in the early part of the century, Solon—the poet statesman—had  been appointed as a mediator to solve the severe economic problems of the

     poor and had instituted a number of important reforms, he had failed to put

    an end to the unrest. As a result, factions had re-emerged among aristo-

    cratic leaders until in c. 546, one Pisistratus finally established himself as

    tyrant at Athens.

    Tyranny was not an uncommon phenomenon among the Greeks. In fact,

    it was one of the three most common forms of government, the other two

    12 Sophocles and the Tragedy of Athenian Democracy

  • 8/20/2019 Sophocles and the Athenian Democracy

    32/211

     being oligarchy and democracy. Nor was tyranny always regarded in the

    same negative fashion as it is now considered. Originally, a tyrant was

    simply someone who had seized power unconstitutionally. Although the

    Spartans were generally opposed to tyrants, and tyranny became a pejora-tive term at Athens once the democracy had taken firm root, tyrants had 

    quite often overthrown oppressive regimes. Thus, tyrants could command 

    wide popular support, and their policies were, at times, enlightened.

    Pisistratus is a case in point. The evidence suggests that his rule was

    moderate and popular. As much as possible, Pisistratus sought to preserve

    the political system that Solon had introduced. He took measures to pro-

    tect the livelihood of the poor; he expanded Athens’ economic base bydeveloping foreign trade; he introduced a vigorous building program and 

    tried to create a greater sense of unity among the people of Attica, by

    introducing new religious cults or expanding pre-existing ones—the

    Dionysia and the Panathenaia, the main festival in honor of Athena, being

    two signal examples. Before the time of the Pisistratids, Athens had been

    something of a cultural backwater. All this changed under their rule: poets

    and artists were invited to Athens; Athenian sculpture gained greater dis-

    tinction; Attic black-figure vase-painting began to rival the more famousware of Corinth; and the poems of Homer were written down (the first

    written version of them that we know of), and provision was made for their 

    recitation at the Panathenaia by rhapsodes, whose highly histrionic perfor-

    mances must have had an important influence on the art of acting. Finally,

    Thespis produced his one-actor tragedies. In short, the Pisistratids did 

    much to lay the foundation of later Athenian success.

    Pisistratus died in 527, but his policies were continued by his sons, Hip-

     pias and Hipparchus. When, however, Hipparchus was assassinated in 514

     by Harmodius and Aristogiton—probably because of a homosexual lovers’

    quarrel—the rule of his brother turned oppressive and the popularity of the

    tyranny waned. Later, Hipparchus’ two assassins were made “heroes” as

    the liberators of the Athenians. Such are the myths of history.

    In 510, Hippias was driven out of Athens with the help of the Spartans. In

    the power struggle that ensued, ultimately Cleisthenes, the Alcmaeonid,

    emerged victorious. However, in order to win, Cleisthenes had to enlist thehelp of the Athenian demos, the common people, who, until this time, had 

    had little say in governing the polis. Traditionally, Athenian society was

    divided between aristoi (members of aristocratic oikoi), and the demos. The

    main political power had resided with the Areopagus, which had originally

     been a wholly aristocratic council, but whose membership had been opened 

    up to the very wealthy by Solon. The Athenians were also divided into four 

    tribes, in which the influence of the aristoi would have been paramount.

    Tragedy, Athens, and the Greek Cultural Mosaic 13

  • 8/20/2019 Sophocles and the Athenian Democracy

    33/211

    We cannot be sure what Cleisthenes’ultimate intentions were in institut-

    ing his reforms, but these reforms completely redrew the political map of 

    Attica and laid the basis for Athenian democracy, although Athens was not

    to become a radical democracy for about another half century. Cleisthenesdid not abolish the Areopagus that still commanded extensive power, and 

    the aristoi still provided leadership, because one still needed wealth— 

    most of which was based on inherited land—to hold certain high offices

    for which there was no financial remuneration. In order to break the stran-

    glehold of the old tribal divisions, Cleisthenes created 10 new tribes, based 

    on artificial divisions. For this purpose, Attica was divided into three geo-

    graphical areas: urban, coastal, and nonurban inland. Each of these threeareas was further divided into 10 subdivisions, making 30 in all. In the

    future, each new tribe was to be composed of three trittyes (thirds), one

    drawn from an urban, another from a coastal, and another from an inland 

    area. He also created a new council for the 10 tribes. This boule had 500

    members, 50 appointed by lot from each of the 10 new tribes. Every mem-

     ber served on the boule for a year, and no citizen could serve on it more

    than twice in a lifetime. The main function of the boule was to draft

    motions and to prepare the agenda for the ecclesia, which was the assem- bly of all the citizens, whose will was to be sovereign and who had the

    responsibility for passing laws and making all major political decisions.

    The main executive officers of the polis, however, were the nine archons

    (leaders or rulers), who were in charge of religious, legal, and military

    affairs. In order to become one, a property qualification had to be fulfilled.

    Under Cleisthenes, these officials were elected for a year and, on comple-

    tion of their term of office, became members of the Areopagus, the tradi-

    tional aristocratic council. However, in 487, appointment by lot replaced 

    election as the means of choosing these archons and thus their political

     power was seriously diminished. From that time on, the strategia became

    the most powerful political office. Each of the new tribes elected, annually,

    a  strategos (a general), creating a board of 10. Warfare was one area in

    which the Athenians could not rely on mere chance.

    Cleisthenes’ reforms were far reaching. Because the boule consisted of 

    500 annually appointed members who could only serve twice in a lifetime,given the small size of the citizen population, this meant that, within a rel-

    atively short time, a significant percentage of the citizenry would have held 

    an important executive position within the polis. Furthermore, since the

    ecclesia (the sovereign assembly of the Athenians) was open to all citizens

    to vote on whatever motion was brought before it, Athens became a direct,

    rather than a representative, democracy, and thus there was no true dis-

    tinction between rulers and the ruled. The citizens were the government.

    14 Sophocles and the Tragedy of Athenian Democracy

  • 8/20/2019 Sophocles and the Athenian Democracy

    34/211

    The Athenians were the polis. Finally, in breaking the old aristocratic tribal

    divisions, Cleisthenes joined together people of different regional, eco-

    nomic, and political interests. Because the organization of space helps in

     profound ways to shape people’s perception of reality, Cleisthenes’redrawing of the spatial divisions of the Athenians radically affected the

    way in which they came to view their polis.

    Cleisthenes’ reforms were also to have a significant influence on the

    organization of the Athenian theatre, because—however it had been orga-

    nized before, whether on a rural or urban basis—the Dionysia, the festival

    at which the tragedies were performed, was at least partially reorganized,

    taking into account Cleisthenes’ new tribal divisions. All 10 new tribeswere required to submit, every year, two dithyrambic choruses, one adult

    male and one boys’, each consisting of 50 members, for competition at the

    Dionysia. If we can believe Aristotle ( Poetics 49a), the dithyramb was

    important in the origins of tragedy. Be that as it may, what is of interest is

    its cultural significance in the new democratic polis. In the archaic era,

    choral performances tended to be of aristocratic provenance. The dithy-

    rambs at Athens, however, were choral performances in honor of Dionysus

    (a popular god), that were designed to cement the new divisions of thedemocratic polis. The training of these dithyrambic choruses lasted the

     better part of a year and, during the period of their training, the adult males

    were released from military service. Because there were a thousand per-

    formers, altogether, in these dithyrambs—500 adult males and 500 boys— 

    this meant that most likely, as in the case of service on the boule, a large

     percentage of the citizens at the theatre had also acted as performers at one

    time or another. Athletics and mousike (not simply music, but song, dance,

    and poetry) formed the basis of traditional Athenian education. Given the

    rigorous training that the performers underwent, participation in a dithy-

    rambic chorus was not simply a musical experience but also hard physical

    training. Among other things, it trained the members of the chorus how to

    function as a coordinated group. As such, it must have been an excellent

     preparation, in the case of the boys’ choruses, for military service, not the

    least because at Athens, in the army, the citizens served in tribal divisions.

    As Athenaeus reports Socrates to have written: “Those who honor the gods best in choruses are the finest in war” (14.628). Did the Athenians march

    into battle with musical accompaniment? It is possible, but we do not

    know. In any case, the dithyrambic choruses based on Cleisthenes’ new

    tribes served as an important form of training and education in Athens’

    new democracy.

    One final point should be made. The performances of the dithyrambs

    took the form of a competition, with prizes for the winning choruses. The

    Tragedy, Athens, and the Greek Cultural Mosaic 15

  • 8/20/2019 Sophocles and the Athenian Democracy

    35/211

    competitive aspect no doubt helped to cement loyalty to the new tribes.

    Because the theatre held some 15,000 spectators, the atmosphere at times

    must have been more like that of a major sporting event than that of a mod-

    ern theatre. Competition was a vital part of the Greek way of life, becauseso many aspects of it took the form of an agon (contest): war was an agon,

    the Olympic games were agons, law cases were agons, several of the reli-

    gious festivals contained agons. The life of a democratic polis like Athens

    was both a cooperative and a competitive enterprise. When the playwrights

     presented their tragedies and comedies, they, too, were engaged in an agon

    for a prize with their fellow tragedians and comedians, respectively. The

    winners took all, the losers received nothing. Greek culture has been vari-ously called a “song culture” and a “performance culture”; it was also, in

    large measure, a “competition culture.”6 This competitive spirit was instru-

    mental in the Greek invention of politics. The fifth-century theatre that

    came to hold such a central place in the life of Athenian democracy was

    one manifestation of their zest for the political life.

    In summary, tragedy was both a Greek and an Athenian creation.

    Although it drew much of its lifeblood from the rich wellsprings of Greek 

    culture, only after it had taken firm root in Athenian soil did it fully mature.Through the use of muthos (word as story), it fed the Athenians with

    images of alternative versions of life and its problems and thus made a

    vital contribution to the logos (word as discourse) of the democratic polis.

    NOTES

    1. On this point, see especially S. Goldhill’s reply, “Collectivity and Other-

    ness—The Authority of the Tragic Chorus,” 244–256, to J. Gould’s “Tragedy and Collective Experience,” in Tragedy and the Tragic, ed. M. Silk (Oxford, 1996),

    217–43.

    2. C. Patterson, The Family in Greek History (Cambridge, Mass., 1998), 43.

    3. See E. Hall,  Inventing the Barbarian: Greek Self-Definition through

    Tragedy (Oxford, 1989). As she writes: “To an archaic Greek Priam was a king,

    Hector a hero, Memnon the son of Dawn, and Medea a sorceress; to the fifth cen-

    tury theatre-goer, an essential aspect of such figures’ identities was that they were

     barbarians” (54).4. On this question, see C. Souvrinou-Inwood, “Tragedy and Religion: Con-

    structs and Readings,” in Greek Tragedy and the Historian, ed. C. Pelling (Oxford,

    1997), 161–86.

    5. On  Peitho and a discussion of persuasion in Greek tragedy, see R. G. A.

    Buxton, Persuasion in Greek Tragedy (Cambridge, 1982).

    6. See J. Herington, Poetry into Drama: Early Tragedy and the Greek Poetic

    Tradition (Berkeley, Calif., 1985), 3–5, on song culture; and R. Rehm, Greek 

    16 Sophocles and the Tragedy of Athenian Democracy

  • 8/20/2019 Sophocles and the Athenian Democracy

    36/211

    Tragic Theatre (London, 1992), 3–11, on performance culture. Jacob Burckhardt

    was the first to emphasize the importance of competition for Greek culture. See,

    for example, his History of Greek Culture, trans. P. Hilty (New York, 1963), 133;

    see also, A. W. Gouldner, Enter Plato: Classical Greece and the Origins of Social Theory (New York, 1965), 41–77.

    Tragedy, Athens, and the Greek Cultural Mosaic 17

  • 8/20/2019 Sophocles and the Athenian Democracy

    37/211

  • 8/20/2019 Sophocles and the Athenian Democracy

    38/211

    Chapter 2

    Sophocles: Dramatic Beginnings

    Sophocles was born c. 496 into the world of the emerging Athenian

    democracy. He died in 406–405, shortly before the Athenians were finally

    defeated in the Peloponnesian War that brought about the end of their 

    empire in 404. His life thus spanned most of the century that witnessed Athens’ greatest achievements. Although the biographical information on

    Sophocles is scanty and largely unreliable,1 we can nevertheless set his life

    against the political and cultural background of the time. What reliable

    evidence we have indicates that Sophocles, unlike Aeschylus and Euripi-

    des, had a political as well as a dramatic career.

    Sophocles, the son of Sophillus, was born at Colonus, an Attic deme

    about a mile and a quarter northwest of Athens. A number of anecdotes

    speak of his musical and athletic achievements in his youth. Whether trueor not, Sophocles must have enjoyed the traditional fare of Athenian edu-

    cation of the time, which, as previously described, was comprised of 

    mousike and physical training. At the time, Athens was no bookish culture.

    Poetry was taught orally and committed to memory.

    Sophocles’ early years were scarcely a time of political stability. We

    should not assume that, with Cleisthenes’ reforms, Athens made a simple

    and smooth transition from tyranny to democracy. The possibility ofHippias’ restoration, through the intervention of outside forces, was

    always a threat and only receded once the Persians had been soundly

    defeated. Moreover, various aristocratic leaders must have vied for power,

    not necessarily with any democratic ends in mind. In the 480s, there were

    a number of ostracisms, a peculiarly Athenian practice whereby a promi-

    nent politician could be banished from Athens for 10 years through a pub-

    lic vote in the assembly. Whether this institution was established by

  • 8/20/2019 Sophocles and the Athenian Democracy

    39/211

    Cleisthenes himself or was introduced a little later, it was instituted as a

    safeguard against tyranny and as a means of avoiding stasis among polit-

    ical leaders.

    What must have lent charge to the air of instability was the growingmenace of Persia. In 499, the Athenians had embarked on a risky foreign

    venture that was to have grave consequences. In that year, some of the

    Greeks of Asia Minor who, in the sixth century, had become subject to

    Persian domination, revolted and appealed to other Greeks for help. Only

    Athens and Eretria responded by sending an expeditionary force of ships.

    Although this force soon withdrew, in the meantime it burnt the Persian

    city of Sardis. The “Ionian revolt” continued to 494, before it was finallyquelled by the Persians. However, Darius, the Persian king, had not taken

    kindly to the Athenian and Eretrian intervention and launched a punitive

    expedition against them in 490.

    At the time, the Persian Empire was vast and expansionist in its designs,

    something to be feared by mainland and Aegean island Greeks, who

    resided in all too close a proximity. The Athenians, in view of their actions,

    had special reason to fear the Persians, and the measure of their fear may

    well be gauged by the reception of a tragedy by Phrynichus, an early Athe-nian tragic playwright whose works have not survived. The collapse of the

    Ionian revolt came when the Persians sacked the city of Miletus, on the

    island of Lesbos, in 494. Sometime shortly afterward—possibly 492— 

    Phrynichus produced his tragedy centered on the sacking of Miletus.

    According to Herodotus (6.21), the Athenian audience was so affected by

    it that they burst into tears. Phrynichus was fined a thousand drachmas,

    and a ban was put on any further production of the tragedy. Although

    Sophocles himself would probably have been too young to have seen

    Phrynichus’ Capture of Miletus, this play may possibly, as we shall con-

    sider below, have had an important influence on the direction of tragedy

    and thus on Sophocles himself.

    Athens survived the Persian assault when it came, although Eretria was

    not so lucky. When a Persian force landed on the plain of Marathon on the

    east coast of Attica, the Athenians drove them back to their ships. The

    Athenians then had to beat a hasty retreat the 30 miles back overland toAthens to prevent the Persians from anticipating their arrival by sailing

    around the south coast of Attica and taking Athens in their absence. When

    the Persian fleet arrived and found the Athenians waiting for them, they

    sailed home. Apart from a small contingent of troops who had come to

    help from the neighboring polis of Plataea, the Athenians had stood alone

    against the might of Persia and had won. Later, these Marathon veterans— 

    among them, Aeschylus—became the stuff of legend.

    20 Sophocles and the Tragedy of Athenian Democracy

  • 8/20/2019 Sophocles and the Athenian Democracy

    40/211

    The Persian threat, however, was by no means over. In the following

    decade, the Persians planned a full-scale conquest of Greece. If the Greeks

    were to have any chance of resisting the Persian menace, it was imperative

    that they overcome their customary differences and unite in some kind of concerted military effort. Some Greeks, such as the Thebans, sensing the

    futility of resistance, submitted to the Persian invaders without a fight, but

    those who decided to resist combined under the leadership of Sparta, the

    strongest military power in Greece, to oppose the Persians. For the sake of 

    unity, the Athenians acquiesced in the Spartans taking overall command.

     Nevertheless, the Athenians provided by far the largest number of ships.

    Thanks to the strategy and leadership of their general, Themistocles, whoearlier had persuaded them to invest their resources in building a fleet, the

    Athenians were to play a crucial role in helping to defeat the invaders.

    When the Persians actually invaded in 481, it was a combined land and 

    sea operation. After some initial encounters, notably at Thermopylae and 

    Artemisium, the Greek fleet met the Persians in the narrows of the Saronic

    Gulf between the island of Salamis and the mainland, in 480. Although the

    Athenians played the decisive role in the naval victory of Salamis, victory

    did not come without serious cost, because the Athenians, after transport-ing their women and children to safety, abandoned their city to the Per-

    sians. After the defeat, Xerxes—who had succeeded his father, Darius, to

    the Persian throne—fled back to Persia, but left a large land army under his

    general, Mardonius, to continue the war. Mardonius retreated north for the

    winter before advancing south again in the following year. Once more the

    Athenians were forced to abandon their city; but Mardonius was no more

    successful than the Persian fleet had been. In 479, the Greek and Persian

    land forces met near Plataea, and the Persians were resoundingly defeated,

    thanks in large measure to the Spartans, although the Athenians acquitted 

    themselves with honor. Mardonius himself was killed. Meanwhile, the

    Greek fleet had crossed the Aegean sea, landed at Mycale, and burnt the

    remnants of the Persian fleet, thus paving the way for the liberation of

    the Greeks under Persian control.

    If these Greeks were to gain and maintain their freedom, they needed 

    leadership. When the Spartans proved unsuited for the task, they turnedto the Athenians who, in spite of the destruction of their city, willingly

    accepted the offer. Thus, in 478, the Delian Confederacy was formed. Each

    member contributed ships or made a monetary contribution assessed 

    according to its size and power. From then on, Athens was to become the

    most dynamic power in the Greek world. Here lay the origins of her empire.

    The psychological and cultural effects of the Persian Wars on the Athe-

    nians and other Greeks were enormous. Nothing less than the Greek way

    Sophocles: Dramatic Beginnings 21

  • 8/20/2019 Sophocles and the Athenian Democracy

    41/211

    of life had been at stake. We have to gain an insight into these psychologi-

    cal and cultural effects largely from the art and literature of the subsequent

    era, because the main historical sources are tantalizingly sparse. Hero-

    dotus ends his history with the repulse of the Persians and Thucydides onlygives a brief sketch of the period between the Persian and Peloponnesian

    wars. However, there can be no doubt that the Persian Wars provided a

    major watershed in Greek culture. Conventionally, art historians use the

    term “Archaic” to describe the period before the Persian Wars, and “Clas-

    sical” to describe the one that came after. Although such a demarcation is,

    to some extent, more one of convenience than of absolute precision, there

    was a beginning of a new era in sculpture, architecture, and vase painting.As J. J. Pollitt expressed it:

    Archaic Greek art had never lost touch with the artistic traditions of the

    ancient Near East from which it had borrowed certain schemes of composi-

    tion and a good many decorative details. . . . After 480/79 B.C. the Orient was

    increasingly viewed as barbarous and contemptible; and Archaic art, which

    had been fostered in many cases by Greek tyrants who had been on good 

    terms with the oriental monarchs and had set themselves up in power some-what on the oriental model, was tainted by these associations.2

    The fact that tragedy was affected by the new Zeitgeist can scarcely be

    doubted, but quite how it was affected is not easy to determine because

    evidence of what tragedy was like between the first performance of a one-

    actor tragedy by Thespis in c. 534 and Aeschylus’ Persians in 472 (the ear-

    liest surviving play) is confusing and meager. There are three types of 

    information, however, that we can look at in slightly more detail: what

    Aristotle says in the Poetics; what we know of Phrynichus’ tragedies; and,

    lastly, the fragments of the lost plays of Aeschylus that can, in part, be sup-

     plemented by his post-Persian Wars, extant tragedies.

    In an elusive passage of the  Poetics (49a 9–21), Aristotle summarizes

    the evolution of tragedy. He informs us that tragedy arose as a form of 

    improvisation on the part of the leaders of the dithyramb and only gradu-

    ally grew as improvements were made, but in the process it underwent sev-eral changes until it found its natural form. Aeschylus added a second 

    actor, reduced the choral component, and made the spoken part the most

    important. Sophocles added a third actor and  skenographia. Moreover, it

    was only at a late date that tragedy became serious, after abandoning short

     plots and ridiculous language through changing from the “satyr-like.”

    Although I will not go into tragedy’s possible relationship with the

    dithyramb, if Aristotle is reliable, tragedy began as a form of improvisation

    22 Sophocles and the Tragedy of Athenian Democracy

  • 8/20/2019 Sophocles and the Athenian Democracy

    42/211

    and did not become serious until quite late. It is an interesting point that, at

    least by some time in Aeschylus’ dramatic career, each tragic playwright at

    the City Dionysia was required to produce four plays for performance on a

    single day: three tragedies and a satyr play. When this number became fixed cannot be ascertained but, presumably, it was not fixed when Thespis first

     began producing tragedies. If, as Aristotle suggests, the plots of the tragedies

    were slight and the language ridiculous, then we have to assume that the ear-

    liest tragedians produced a series of lighthearted, rather sketch-like perfor-

    mances with a single actor and chorus. At some later point, perhaps when

    tragedy became more serious, four became the established number of plays

    for a tragedian to produce—three tragedies and a satyr play as an afterpiece,which may have preserved the spirit of the original performances.

    When did the change take place in the tone of tragedy from nonserious

    to serious? Virtually nothing is known about the tone of the tragedies of 

    Thespis and his immediate successors until Phrynichus—and what is

    known about Phrynichus is very limited. Aristophanes attests to the para-

    mount importance of the choral element in his plays, something we would 

    naturally suspect, because he only used one actor. He is also said to have

     been the first to introduce female characters. However, it is only when wecome to his Capture of Miletus in c. 492 that we have the first evidence of 

    a tragedy that treated a serious subject in a serious manner. Phrynichus’

    tragedy created a storm of protest, and his play was banned in perpetuity,

    its subject matter being too close to home. The Capture of Miletus, how-

    ever, may have been the first attempt to have a tragedy make a politically

    meaningful statement. Was it Phrynichus who was instrumental in chang-

    ing the tone of tragedy from less to more serious and was his Capture of 

     Miletus a harbinger of later developments, once the Athenians had weath-

    ered the Persian threat and were buoyed up by a new spirit of confidence?

    We do not know, but it remains a tantalizing possibility. What we do know

    is that Phrynichus did not abandon historical subjects, because he pro-

    duced his Phoenician Women in 476 with the backing of no less a person

    than Themistocles, who served as choregus. This tragedy, like Aeschylus’

     Persians later in 472, dealt with the defeat of the Persians. Furthermore, it

    is quite possible that Themistocles was the archon who had given Phryn-ichus permission to produce his Capture of Miletus.3 Although we know

    that Phrynichus also produced tragedies on mythological themes, we do

    not know how he treated these myths.

    If we wish to speculate about what tragedy was like in the early part of 

    the fifth century, we have to turn to the fragments of the lost plays of 

    Aeschylus, a rather unsatisfactory source, admittedly. Aeschylus was born

    in 525 under the Athens of the tyrants. He began his dramatic career c. 500

    Sophocles: Dramatic Beginnings 23

  • 8/20/2019 Sophocles and the Athenian Democracy

    43/211

    after the democratic reforms of Cleisthenes, but he had to wait about 15

    years before he won his first victory at the City Dionysia in 484. From then

    on, however, he was victorious on 13 occasions and, after his death in 456,

    he was granted the signal honor of having anyone who wanted to, restagehis plays. Although we commonly associate tragedy with the heroic figures

    of legendary places like Argos, Troy, and Thebes—places that do indeed 

    form the backdrop of some of his late plays that survive—the extant frag-

    ments reveal a rather different view of his dramatic imagination. As J. Her-

    ington once expressed it:

    Such now familiar heroic themes occupied scarcely a quarter of Aeschylus’dramatic output as it originally stood. The titles and fragments of the

    remaining three-quarters open up a wild mythological landscape that seems

    to be bounded by no horizons of space, time, or credibility—a very ancient

    landscape, which few later European dramatists, or even Attic dramatists,

    were ever to explore again on the stage.4

    Although none survive, in later times, Aeschylus was recognized as the

    greatest writer of satyr plays. Even in his late surviving tragedies there can be seen clear evidence of a world of archaic imagination both in his lan-

    guage and in the grotesque appearance of some of his stage characters. In

     Eumenides, the last play of his famous Oresteia trilogy, side by side with

    Orestes, a figure from heroic myth, and the Olympian gods Apollo and 

    Athena, stands the chorus of Furies. So appalling is their appearance that

    the priestess of Apollo, on seeing them, is reduced to crawling on all fours

    out of terror. The Furies are described as having snakes in their hair, snort-

    ing with foul breath, and letting flow a dreadful ooze from their mouths.

    First compared with Gorgons and then with Harpies, they feed on human

     blood and are the ghoulish daughters of Night. Only when we turn to

    Sophocles’ surviving tragedies do the protagonists of heroic myth come

    more firmly into their own.

    Sophocles is said to have learned his tragic art from Aeschylus ( Life 4).

    According to Plutarch (de Profectu in Virtute 7), he divided his own works

    into three stylistic periods, in the first of which he adopted the high-flownstyle of Aeschylus. Although we have no way of proving this claim, we can

    detect Aeschylean echoes in much of his work.5 However, the younger 

     playwright may equally well have had an important influence on the older 

    one, because all of Aeschylus’ datable, surviving tragedies except the Per-

     sians were first produced after Sophocles’ dramatic career had begun.

    Unlike Aeschylus’ dramatic career, Sophocles’ was highly successful

    from the beginning and was to remain so throughout his life. Out of the

    24 Sophocles and the Tragedy of Athenian Democracy

  • 8/20/2019 Sophocles and the Athenian Democracy

    44/211

    123 plays that he most likely composed—there are some variations in the

    figures in our sources—he was the victor in the tragic competition at least

    18 times and possibly as many as 24. This success was unprecedented.

    Moreover, he never placed lower than second. According to Plutarch(Cimon 8), Sophocles was the victor with his first productions at the City

    Dionysia in 468, defeating Aeschylus. Although this, in fact, may not have

     been his first appearance at the festival,6 the rivalry between the supporters

    of the two playwrights on this occasion was so great that the 10 generals

    had to be called in to serve as the 10 judges. The following year, however,

    Aeschylus came back and was victorious with his Theban trilogy, of which

    there survives the last tragedy, Seven against Thebes. Moreover, we knowthat Aeschylus defeated Sophocles with his Danaid trilogy, of which Sup-

     pliants is extant.

    These last two mentioned tragedies of Aeschylus, together with the Per-

     sians of 472, only require two actors, whereas Aeschylus’ last trilogy,

    Oresteia, first produced in 458, and Prometheus Bound  —if indeed it is by

    Aeschylus, because its Aeschylean authorship is disputed 7 —require three

    actors. Furthermore, the two-actor tragedies do not seem to require a clearly

    defined  skene (backdrop), because their action takes place in a rather gen-eralized dramatic space, whereas in Oresteia, there is a clearly defined 

     skene, which in the first two parts of the trilogy represents the accursed 

    House of Atreus. As we have seen earlier, Aristotle ( Poetics 49a 9–21)

    claimed that the two innovations that Sophocles brought to tragedy—the

    introduction of the third actor and skenographia —carried tragedy to a more

    fully evolved form. If Aristotle’s testimony is reliable, it is possible that

    Sophocles introduced both of these innovations sometime toward the end of 

    Aeschylus’ dramatic career, before the first production of Oresteia in 458.

    Let us first look at the three-actor rule. Greek tragedy never used more

    than three actors, who divided up all the speaking roles between them-

    selves, even if this meant—as in the case of Sophocles’ Oedipus at 

    Colonus at least—a particular role had to be shared by more than one

    actor. This doubling of parts was facilitated by the use of masks, which is

    discussed in the next chapter. Even though Aeschylus adopted the third 

    actor in his last plays, the manner in which he used his actors is, in manyways, different from that of Sophocles. To talk about character interaction

    at all in much Aeschylean tragedy is misleading, because dramatic mood�