Smith the Political Landscape (Pp 78-112)

37
8/12/2019 Smith the Political Landscape (Pp 78-112) http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/smith-the-political-landscape-pp-78-112 1/37 The Political Landscape Constellations of Authority in Early Complex Polities Adam T. Smith UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA PRESS Berkeley / Los Angeles / London

Transcript of Smith the Political Landscape (Pp 78-112)

Page 1: Smith the Political Landscape (Pp 78-112)

8/12/2019 Smith the Political Landscape (Pp 78-112)

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/smith-the-political-landscape-pp-78-112 1/37

The Political LandscapeConstellations of Authorityin Early Complex Polities

Adam T. Smith

UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA PRESS

Berkeley / Los Angeles / London

Page 2: Smith the Political Landscape (Pp 78-112)

8/12/2019 Smith the Political Landscape (Pp 78-112)

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/smith-the-political-landscape-pp-78-112 2/37

University of California PressBerkeley and Los Angeles, California

University of California Press, Ltd.London, England

© 2003 by The Regents of the University of California

Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data

Smith, Adam T. The political landscape : constellations of authority in early

complex polities / Adam T. Smith.p. cm.

Includes bibliographical references (p. ) and index.ISBN 0-520-23749-8 (cloth : alk. paper)—ISBN 0-520-23750-1

(pbk. : alk. paper)1. Political anthropology. 2. Landscape archaeology—Political

aspects. 3. Landscape assessment. I. Title.GN492.2 .S64 2003306.2—dc21 2003005058

Manufactured in the United States of America

12 11 10 09 08 07 06 05 04 0310 9 8 7 6 5 4 3 2 1

The paper used in this publication meets the minimum requirementsof ANSI/NISO Z39.48–1992 (R 1997) ( Permanence of Paper ).8

Page 3: Smith the Political Landscape (Pp 78-112)

8/12/2019 Smith the Political Landscape (Pp 78-112)

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/smith-the-political-landscape-pp-78-112 3/37

Contents

List of Illustrations ix

Acknowledgments xiii

Introduction: Surveying the Political Landscape 1

1. Sublimated Spaces 30

2. Archaeologies of Political Authority 78

3. Geopolitics 112

4. Polities 149

5. Regimes 184

6. Institutions 232Conclusion: Toward a Cartography of Political Landscapes 271

References Cited 283

Index 315

Page 4: Smith the Political Landscape (Pp 78-112)

8/12/2019 Smith the Political Landscape (Pp 78-112)

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/smith-the-political-landscape-pp-78-112 4/37

c h a p t e r 2

Archaeologies of Political Authority

The moment we utter the words “the state” a score of intellectual ghosts rise to obscure our vision.

John Dewey, The Public and Its Problems

It is not coincidental that the vision of modern political analysis came tobe obscured just as the spatial dimensions of human life were systemati-cally dismissed as elements of explanation, interpretation, and critique.Only at rare moments in twentieth-century thought—when the highly abstract theoretical position aªorded by the State (capitalized to reect its universalist ambition) has receded in the face of direct accounts of theproduction of relationships of authority—has political life been described in explicitly spatial terms. In perhaps the most important of these accounts,

Aleksandr Solzhenitsyn employed a geographic trope to describe “that amazing country of Gulag which, though scattered geographically, likean archipelago, was, in a psychological sense, fused into a continent” (1985: x). The signicance of this rich spatial metaphor for the penal apparatusof the Stalinist regime echoes beyond its literary eªectiveness. Solzhen-itsyn’s account suggests that political regimes must be understood in termsof the particular places that they carve out for themselves—that politicsnot only occupies land but also operates by and through landscapes. Fur-thermore, The Gulag Archipelagosuggests that these politically produced landscapes are not conceivable solely as problems of form. The success-ful operation of the Gulag lay not only in the direct experience of spacesoccupied by state power—a system of punishment and incarceration that

78

Page 5: Smith the Political Landscape (Pp 78-112)

8/12/2019 Smith the Political Landscape (Pp 78-112)

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/smith-the-political-landscape-pp-78-112 5/37

stretched from the cells of the Lubyanka in central Moscow to the work camps of Kolyma in Siberia—but also in the way these discontinuousspaces were articulated in the minds of those it ensnared into a coherent

landscape of authority. The lingering importance of Solzhenitsyn’s account to the way we con-ceptualize politics lies less in the descriptions of labor camps now aban-doned to the Siberian tundra than in his exposure of the State as an illu-sory object of political practice, analysis, and criticism—a pretension tocoherence placed on disparate and heterogeneous processes operatingacross a host of contiguous and noncontiguous places that together con-stitute political landscapes. The potency of the State as an idea arises fromits representation of politics as entirely removed from space and place;the State appears complete and immune to contestation precisely becauseit has no geography—there is no place one can go to argue with it. Dueto this lack of location built into the concept, the question “Where is theState?” though entirely reasonable, sounds quite peculiar. The only pos-sible answer to the question is that the State is both everywhere and nowhere. The State is everywhere in that it has been implicated in every aspect of our daily lives, from the production of culture and economy ona global scale to the creation of personal identities. But the State is also

nowhere. Although more than 180 political entities today are described as states, it is impossible to locate the State in the same way that we canobserve governments and visit nations. From this simultaneously invisi-ble and omnipresent conceptual location, the State provides an eªectivemask for political practices precisely because it obscures the inherently spa-tial operation of power (as an apparatus of domination) and legitimacy (as a representation of that apparatus). The State is thus a highly prob-lematic concept for investigations of politics and one that any attempt to

spatialize understandings of political life must directly confront.Since the mid-twentieth century, the study of early complex politieshas come to focus resolutely on the State. Political anthropology, the oneeld that has traditionally grappled with issues of political complexity be- yond the narrow sociohistorical window of the modern, has centered itsinvestigations of early complex polities on discrete political types set inuniversal histories. These accounts assemble various political formationsinto historical trajectories and thus render translucent the conditions un-der which polities coalesce, transform, and collapse (Adams 1966; Childe1950; Engels 1990; Johnson and Earle 1987; Morgan 1985; Sanderson 1995;Service 1975; Steward 1972;Yoªee 1993. At the proximal end of this de- velopmental sequence lies the State (Fried 1967; Harris 1979; Sanderson

A R C H A E O L O G I E S O F P O L I T I C A L A U T H O R I T Y 79

Page 6: Smith the Political Landscape (Pp 78-112)

8/12/2019 Smith the Political Landscape (Pp 78-112)

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/smith-the-political-landscape-pp-78-112 6/37

Page 7: Smith the Political Landscape (Pp 78-112)

8/12/2019 Smith the Political Landscape (Pp 78-112)

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/smith-the-political-landscape-pp-78-112 7/37

helped us to understand the societies we have studied and we considerthem of little scientic value” (1940: 4). Yet since that time, the study of early complex polities, a research project led by sociocultural anthropol-

ogists and archaeologists, has come to focus squarely on the State, thequintessential conceptual locus of modern political theory. Although usu-ally modied by the adjectives “early” or “archaic,” the State that ar-chaeologists assemble out of the ruins of places like the Maya lowlandsor the Nile valley is conceptually the same as that employed in social and political theory. What has placed the State at the center of studies of early complex polities is a presumed historical discontinuity that divides it fromprevious social formations. This social evolutionary rupture is usually phrased as a “leap” (Fried 1967: 236) to statehood and bears the impri-matur of V. Gordon Childe’s (1950) revolutionary model of the advent of urban societies (see chapter 5). This discontinuity is not simply envisioned as categorical—a consequence of drawing boundaries between types forpurely heuristic reasons. Rather, “the Great Divide,” to use Elman Ser- vice’s (1975) phrase, is understood as a real historical moment. Althoughit is quite reasonable that some cases of political formation do represent discontinuous, radical breaks in local history (one thinks of Cortés’s en-counter with the Aztec Empire as one such moment), the State concept

obscures the essential contingency of state formation projects. In carvingoª the State as a discontinuous social formation, it is reied as not simply an element of descriptive taxonomy but also a real historical phenome-non; explanation of the State is then free to drift into rival recipes in which various determinative prime movers inevitably and invariably produce ahistorical watershed. The State is thus intelligible only in recourse to “astyle of social understanding that allows us to explain ourselves and oursocieties only to the extent we imagine ourselves helpless puppets of so-

cial worlds we built or of the lawlike forces that have supposedly brought these worlds into being” (Unger 1997: 7). In placing the State at the heart of investigations of early complex polities, political analysis—the inves-tigation of the formation, administration, and transformation of civilrelationships—is replaced by a political cladistics in which typologicalclassication su‹ces as explanation.

the pr ist in e and the a rch aic

In setting out a critique of the State as it has come to be deployed in stud-ies of early complex polities, we should begin with a clear account of what is generally meant by the archaic, or early, State. Several scholars have ar-

A R C H A E O L O G I E S O F P O L I T I C A L A U T H O R I T Y 81

Page 8: Smith the Political Landscape (Pp 78-112)

8/12/2019 Smith the Political Landscape (Pp 78-112)

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/smith-the-political-landscape-pp-78-112 8/37

gued that the modiers “early” and “archaic” (treated as synonyms hence-forth) restrict the eld of study to those “pristine” or “primary” politicalformations where the State has arisen through entirely autochthonous

processes (Khazanov 1978: 77–78). The list of primary states traditionally includes six cases: southern Mesopotamia, Egypt, the Indus valley,1 north-ern China, Mesoamerica, and the Andes. The remaining complex politi-cal formations across the world over the past 5,000 years are classied assecondary States. The impetus to divide primary cases of State formationfrom secondary ones arises from a presumption that a true understand-ing of the origin of the State must lter out the “noise” created by exter-nal inuences. The implication is that, whereas cases of secondary for-mation were likely highly inuenced by neighboring preexisting stateseither through direct colonization or indirect eªects on the economy, theprimary cases oªer us an unsullied view on the most fundamental “primemovers” of political formation at work. The pristine State is thus theo-rized as arising in what Morton Fried termed a “political vacuum” (1967:231–32).

The assumption that the polities of northern China or the Andes weresomehow less inuenced by their neighbors than later formations, suchas Rome or Axum, deftly combines lingering romantic views of “civi-

lization” with modern evolutionary fantasies of the closed laboratory so-ciety. As romanticism, the idea of the pristine state insulates centers of “civilization” from surrounding “barbarian” groups, assuming that vec-tors of inuence could only radiate from centers of incipient complexity outward. Recent studies of culture ow between centers and peripheriessuggest that such one-way models of geopolitical inuence are highly du-bious (Hannerz 1992; Rosaldo 1989; Wolf 1982). The primary/secondary divide also assumes that later States, no matter what the immediate sources

of their formation, were modeled, either positively or negatively, on pre-existing ones. The romanticism of this view lies in the presumption that a historical memory of preceding political forms or a cosmopolitanismof neighboring organizational models is more signicant to political for-mation than immediate conditions. Although this assumption preservesthe integrity of the State as an analytic category—through the constant reiteration of a limited number of formal types (such as the territorial-state, the city-state, and so forth)—the degree of mimesis in second- and third-generation complex polities remains unassayed, and the processes

82 A R C H A E O L O G I E S O F P O L I T I C A L A U T H O R I T Y

1. However, see Possehl 1998 for an argument against including the Indus polities inthis list.

Page 9: Smith the Political Landscape (Pp 78-112)

8/12/2019 Smith the Political Landscape (Pp 78-112)

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/smith-the-political-landscape-pp-78-112 9/37

of secondary state formation is so woefully under-theorized as to cast doubt on the utility of the primary/secondary divide.

As social evolutionist fantasy, the concept of primary states presents

the possibility of a handful of historical cases where externalities aresu‹ciently well controlled such that conditions of study mimic the lab-oratory, hence the hermetic connotations of the adjective “pristine.” Toassume such hermetic conditions falsely demarcates early complex poli-ties as islands, isolated from the less developed world around them. Insuggesting that relations between polities constitute interference that needs to be screened out, the idea of the pristine verges on tautology be-cause it excludes from causation a priori the eªects of sociocultural ex-change. It is not surprising that, in the wake of the attack on social evo-lutionism waged in social theory and anthropology, new attention hasfocused on the regional to global ow of goods, technologies, ideas, and institutions. (See, for example, the considerable debate over a proposed Bronze Age world system in southwest Asia [Algaze 1993, 2001a; Frangi-pane 2001; Kohl 1978, 1989; Stein 1999, 2001].)

If archaic states are not intelligible as pristine cases of complex politi-cal formations, then what distinguishes them as a discrete class of objects?Several authors have proposed that “archaic” refers to political forms based

on preindustrial modes of production and so categorical distinction restson cleaving the concept from all that came after (that is, from the mod-ern state) rather than from all that came before (Marcus and Feinman 1998:3; Claessen and Skalnik 1978: 4–5). However, the separation of forms of political organization solely on the basis of economic modes of produc-tion leads to signicant problems in classication. Although the indus-trial revolution did not begin in earnest until the nineteenth century, therise of the modern state in Europe is generally located either in the rise

of absolutism or in its collapse.2

Either way, the historical gap betweenthe absolutist polities in Europe and the advent of industrial economies would seem to preclude founding the concept of the archaic on shifts inthe mode of production. (Indeed, one might well argue that industrial-ism is a product of the modern state, not its precondition.)

The di‹culty in clearly demarcating the archaic in conceptual termsin no way undermines the commonsense observation that certain for-mations arose before others and thus lend political life a temporal depth

A R C H A E O L O G I E S O F P O L I T I C A L A U T H O R I T Y 83

2. Gianfranco Poggi (1990: 42) refers to the absolutist state as “the rst major institu-tional embodiment of the modern state.” In contrast, Anthony Giddens (1985: 93) arguesthat the absolutist polity, despite its unique features “is still . . . a traditional [archaic] state.”

Page 10: Smith the Political Landscape (Pp 78-112)

8/12/2019 Smith the Political Landscape (Pp 78-112)

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/smith-the-political-landscape-pp-78-112 10/37

that can and should be investigated as historically situated processes. Inthis sense, the term “early” is preferred to the more evaluative term “ar-chaic” because the former may be reduced to simply a broad temporal

designation demarcating complex polities that “arose early in the history of their particular world region” (Marcus and Feinman 1998: 3). Usingthis sense of the term, H. J. M. Claessen (1978: 533) nds early states in various parts of the globe from the late fourth millennium b.c. (Sumerand Egypt) to the nineteenth century a.d. (Jimma [Ethiopia] and Kachari[Northeast India]). This is the sense of the term “early” to which I referin the phrase “early complex polities” (discussed at greater length below).

the conc eptual format ion of the sta te

Having arrived at some clarity with regard to the modier “archaic,” we are left with the much more di‹cult task of providing an account of the State. That we refer to the Greek polis,the Inka Empire, the Me-dieval European regnum, and the modern nation as all falling within theparameters of the State suggests that the term is necessarily broad and shallow in its denotation, rather than rich and deep. The State (or sta-tus, stato, état ) is a relatively recent focus for political description and

analysis. Discussions of political life in the ancient world tended to fo-cus directly on extant forms of association. For example, although clas-sical Greek sources often discussed the polis in general comparativeterms, this was an exceedingly particular category of objects, specic tothe communities of rst millennium b.c. Greece.3 For Aristotle (1988:I.ii), the polis arose through the accretion of several villages, giving it a distinctive geography composed out of a moderate to large town and a hinterland dotted with a number of smaller villages. Perfection of this

form of association depended on an ideal number of citizens distrib-uted across a territory that allowed for self-su‹ciency in production,preferably with access to the sea in order to allow for long-distance trade(ibid., VII.iv–vi). The polis thus produced, as part of its fundamentalnature, a unique landscape that was integral to the realization of its pur-pose, the good life.

Between the Aristotelian polis and the State looms a considerable con-

84 A R C H A E O L O G I E S O F P O L I T I C A L A U T H O R I T Y

3. Despite W. Weissleder’s (1978) attempt to read it as such, Aristotle’s polis is not theState in the contemporary sense of the word as used by social scientists. Indeed, asWeissleder himself remarks (ibid., 201), much of the insight Aristotle provides into politi-cal organization derives from the freedom of his thought from the state concept.

Page 11: Smith the Political Landscape (Pp 78-112)

8/12/2019 Smith the Political Landscape (Pp 78-112)

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/smith-the-political-landscape-pp-78-112 11/37

ceptual distance. Whereas the denition of the polis followed from itsfunction, the State cannot be dened by its ends. Although both con-ceptual objects share an understanding of political life that extends far be-

yond the apparatus of governance, the polis is specic and spatial, whereasthe State is general and universal; where political life in the polis emergesfrom relationshipsamong citizens, the state has come to describe an ab-solute phenomenon of political form.

An intellectual history of the State concept can be organized around four primary theoretical transformations. The rst centers on the deper-sonalization of the State in European political discourse. Between the thir-teenth and sixteenth centuries, the state was employed to denote a dis-tinctive quality of royalty—the status regis—so neatly encapsulated inLouis XIV’s perhaps apocryphal remark “l’état, c’est moi.”4 This sense of the term was employed through the seventeenth century both by de-fenders of divine right (such as Bossuet [1990: 69]) and by its critics (suchas Milton [1971: 365]).5 The extension of the state to refer not just to thequality of majesty but to the condition of the realm is known from Italy as early as the thirteenth century and from northern Europe by the early sixteenth century. In this broader sense, the state generally refers to the well-being of the political community as a whole and to the responsibil-

ity of magistrates to maintain a happy citizenry.6 This broader view of thestate is an important development because it removes the concept froman individual to encompass a geographic extent coterminous with the ter-ritory of the polity.

The second major intellectual transformation marking the emergenceof the modern conceptualization of the State was its generalization intoa category of political form. Use of the term “state” to describe a generaltype of political order can be found in a number of advice manuals for

princes that appeared in the sixteenth century. The most famous amongthese, Machiavelli’sThe Prince,opens with a broad categorical statement:“All the states, all the dominions that have had or now have authority overmen either have been or are republics or principalities” (1998: I.1–3). Thestate, for Machiavelli, describes the nature of the links that connect a rulerto a polity. Indeed, the substance of The Princeis advice on how a ruler

A R C H A E O L O G I E S O F P O L I T I C A L A U T H O R I T Y 85

4. On the implications of this remark for a theory of the State, see Manseld 1983: 849;Rowen 1961.

5. For a broader discussion of the state as a quality of rulers, see Dowdall 1923: 102.6. In the Italian traditions we can see this sense of “state” in Giovanni da Viterbo’s “Liber

de Regimine Civitatum” (1901: 230), among others. A similar use of the term can be found in Erasmus’s use of the term optimus reipublicae status(Skinner 1997: 5).

Page 12: Smith the Political Landscape (Pp 78-112)

8/12/2019 Smith the Political Landscape (Pp 78-112)

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/smith-the-political-landscape-pp-78-112 12/37

can protect the naturally tenuous ties between himself and the principal-ity (as noted in Foucault 1979b: 8). Machiavelli’s sense of state is a gen-eral categorical one; his advice draws from observations of the histories

of comparable regimes and aspires to broad relevance. The state is thusgeneralized, divorced from the particularities of any specic polity and broadly descriptive of formal aspects of political order. It was this senseof the term that allowed Hobbes to place the concept at the center of anavowedly “scientic” exploration of public life. In the preface to De Cive,Hobbes codied the state as the focus of political science, dening thenascent discipline’s intellectual project as a “search into the rights of statesand duties of subjects” (1998: 32). But among Hobbes’s immediate suc-cessors, the state remained a secondary focus of investigation, overshad-owed by “nation” (as in Voltaire’s Letters Concerning the English Nation,)“government” (as in Locke’sTwo Treatises on Government,) and “law” (asin Montesqieu’s De l’Esprit des Lois)—concepts that emphasize the his-torical and geographic specicity of inquiry.

It is in Rousseau’s Discourse on the Origins of Inequalitythat the state(l’état civil)reappears at the center of analysis, and we nd it has under-gone a third conceptual transformation—reication, converted fromgeneral category into a real entity capable of instrumental activity.

Rousseau’s state is a real phenomenon of political life, an instrument used by the wealthy to protect inequality by eroding the liberty that is the nat-ural right of all humans. Moreover, the State is not only ceded instru-mentality but also lent a universal, evolutionary history.

This universalization of the concept is the fourth and last transforma-tion that presents us with a fully modern conception of the State (now warranting the capital “S”). Rousseau’s negative understanding of the uni- versal history of the State as a story of the fettering of natural human free-

doms percolates through subsequent writings on the subject, from Marx’sdescription of the State as a parasite on the economic order that must wither away upon the realization of communism to Freud’s argument that the restrictions placed on human expression by Civilization constitute aprime source of human neuroses (Marx 1986: 322; Freud 1961). In oppo-sition, Hegel forwarded a positive account of the State in history as thematerial realization of the human spirit: “In world history we are con-cerned only with those peoples that have formed states. For we must un-derstand that the State is the realization of freedom, i.e., of the absoluteend-goal [of world history], and that it exists for its own sake” (1988: 41).For Hegel, the State was the end of human history. Although profoundly Whiggish in its historiography, Hegel’s account of the State remains foun-

86 A R C H A E O L O G I E S O F P O L I T I C A L A U T H O R I T Y

Page 13: Smith the Political Landscape (Pp 78-112)

8/12/2019 Smith the Political Landscape (Pp 78-112)

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/smith-the-political-landscape-pp-78-112 13/37

dational to explorations of early complex polities within social evolu-tionary frameworks.

the sta te and archa eolog y

Given the close relationship between the historical development of mod-ern political systems and the conceptual development of the State, it isnot surprising that investigations of early complex polities were rather slow to adopt the concept. It is di‹cult to nd any substantive references tothe State in accounts of early complex polities prior to Lewis Henry Mor-gan’s evolutionary cultural anthropology. Although both Hegel and Rousseau had extended the State into historiography, as an object of metahistorical process, it was only within the increasingly systematic an-thropology of the late nineteenth century that the concept was deployed in a comparative study of political origins. Morgan established the stateas a particular subset of government, originating in Solon’s Athens and the Roman republic, founded on territorial diªerentiation and, more im-portant, on political rule centered on the protection of property and or-ganized by wealth (Morgan 1985: 338–40). Adhering rather closely to aMarxist conception, the State, according to Morgan, is simply govern-

ment by and for the propertied classes, a system that he suggests contin-ues through to “civilized society.” But the State was largely secondary toMorgan’s primary concern, a comparative study of the governmental in-stitutions that mark the evolution of civilization.

With the exception of Morgan, the concept of the State is largely absent from nineteenth-century explorations of ancient societies. “Civilization”—a portmanteau of social, cultural, and political characteristics—held greater sway well into the twentieth century. Unlike the State, civiliza-

tion is at its heart an evaluative term, a typological description of a soci-ety’s technological, artistic, and organization achievements. As Robert Braidwood, Robert Redeld, and the Oxford English Dictionaryall havemade clear, the term “civilization” implies at its core a particular moralorder, one more enlightened and rened than its dialectical antithesis, bar-barism (Braidwood 1964: 137; Redeld 1953: 54–60;Oxford English Dic-tionary Online, 2nd ed., 1989). It is the tension between civilization and the insatiable drive of barbarians to blot out its achievements, a dramatictheme rooted in Herodotus and updated by Gibbon, that lies at the heart of numerous late-nineteenth- and early-twentieth-century accounts of “therise of Civilization”: “Civilization, after having maintained itself for per-haps a thousand years in extreme southeastern Europe, was thus over-

A R C H A E O L O G I E S O F P O L I T I C A L A U T H O R I T Y 87

Page 14: Smith the Political Landscape (Pp 78-112)

8/12/2019 Smith the Political Landscape (Pp 78-112)

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/smith-the-political-landscape-pp-78-112 14/37

whelmed and blotted out by the northern Greek barbarians. . . . Underthe shadow of the great civilizations of the Orient, the rude Greek no-mads settled down among the wreckage of the Cretan and Mycenaean

palaces” (Breasted 1919: 206). Despite the well-intentioned eªorts of anumber of writers to rid the term of these evaluative implications by re-casting civilization as simply the cultural matrix surrounding the archaicState (Butzer 1980; Flannery 1972; Redman 1978; see also Scarre and Fa-gan 1997: 3–4), an inexpungible Victorian sensibility lies at the very heart of the concept and so is not easily purged (as the recent use of the termby Samuel Huntington [1993, 1996] to describe allegedly discrete and preternaturally opposed cultural blocs makes clear; see also the more sym-pathetic genealogy of the term in Van Buren and Richards 2000).

Politics, generally incidental to late-nineteenth- and early-twentieth-century studies that placed civilization at their conceptual center, was typ-ically explored under the more restricted subheading of “government.”Inquiries into governments of ancient polities have focused almost ex-clusively on elucidating the formal structures of institutions, as typied by Sylvanus Morley’s (1946: 57–59) account of ancient Maya govern-mental organization or Samuel Kramer’s (1963: 73–74) discussion of Sumerian government. In these accounts, government denotes a specic

apparatus for administering the public order, centered in a handful of discrete institutions. But government describes only one set of politicalrelationships—those securely located within discrete institutions—and thusincorporates only a single scale of political action. Beyond the govern-ment, but within the domain of politics, lie a host of other relationshipsconstituted on both more expansive (geopolitical relations, territorialsovereignty) and more rened (grassroots links to regimes, institutionalrivalries) scales of analysis.

The State began its migration into the center of studies of early com-plex polities in the writings of Childe, who contended that: “by 3000 b.c.

the archaeologist’s picture of Egypt, Mesopotamia, and the Indus valley no longer focuses attention on communities of simple farmers, but onStates embracing various professions and classes” (Childe 1936: 159, cap-italization in original). However, such uses of the universal sense of theState are rare in Childe’s writings. Largely due to his intellectual debt toMarx, Childe does not seem to have been particularly interested in thepolitical apparatuses of early complex polities except as they articulated with class orders dened by relations of production. Even the chapters of his books ostensibly focused on government move quickly to economy after very brief denitions of forms of leadership, such as monarchical,oligarchical, and republican (Childe 1946: chap. 10 is particularly notable

88 A R C H A E O L O G I E S O F P O L I T I C A L A U T H O R I T Y

Page 15: Smith the Political Landscape (Pp 78-112)

8/12/2019 Smith the Political Landscape (Pp 78-112)

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/smith-the-political-landscape-pp-78-112 15/37

in this respect). More often, Childe employed the term “state” in a purely classicatory sense (lowercase “s”), introducing the idea of a “civilized state” to encompass several forms of political organization that followed

the Urban Revolution (ibid., 155). It was in such hyphenated, categoricalforms that states entered the study of early complex societies: the ClassicMaya city-state, the Pharaonic regional-state of Old Kingdom Egypt, theChinese feudal-state of the Chou dynasty (Lattimore 1940: 391; Thomp-son 1954: 97–98). Through the mid-twentieth century, the State re-mained a marginal concept in the study of early complex polities and po-litical anthropology in general. In 1954, E. A. Hoebel summarized therather dim view many anthropologists held toward the State, dismissingit as conceptually unrened and analytically unproductive: “[W]here thereis political organization there is a state. If political organization is uni- versal, so then is the state” (1954: 376).

However, with the revival of cultural evolutionism in the 1950s, theState assumed central place in the study of early complex societies. Ad-mittedly, the rst-generation neo-evolutionists, most notably Leslie White(1949) and Julian Steward (1972 [1955]), were not particularly interested in the State. They were far more concerned with the operation of socialevolutionary forces within groups whose subsistence economies were

based on hunting and gathering or foraging. White preferred the term“civilization,” most likely because it emphasized the Victorian sources(and, some might add, spirit) of his theory in the writings of Morgan and E. B. Tylor; Steward also used “civilization” rather than “State,” but theformer was linked to the less inherently evaluative term “complex soci-ety.” It is with the second generation of neo-evolutionists that the Stateemerged as a central concept in investigations of early complex polities. The evolutionary typology advanced by Service (1962) placed the State

at the end of a unilineal sequence that passed from Band, to Tribe, to Chief-dom. Later variants on the sequence, such as those proposed by Fried (1967) and Marvin Harris (1977) oªered alternative terms for the rst threestages but preserved the State as the capstone of both unilinear and mul-tilinear metahistories.

The second-generation neo-evolutionary works of the 1960s and 1970sshould be credited with placing the issues posed by complex political for-mations and their development squarely on the agenda of anthropology and integrating comparative studies of early complex polities within thistheoretical domain. Several important volumes in political anthropology published from the 1960s through the mid-1980s are truly noteworthy accomplishments in that they integrate archaeological and ethnographictheorizations of the State into a well-developed program of research

A R C H A E O L O G I E S O F P O L I T I C A L A U T H O R I T Y 89

Page 16: Smith the Political Landscape (Pp 78-112)

8/12/2019 Smith the Political Landscape (Pp 78-112)

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/smith-the-political-landscape-pp-78-112 16/37

(Adams 1966; Claessen and Skalnik 1978; Claessen, Velde, and Smith 1985;Cohen and Service 1978). However, neo-evolutionist theory must also beblamed for compressing the rich array of ethnographic and archaeologi-

cal inquiries into various dimensions of complex societies, including law,government, and legitimacy, into just two canonical questions: What isthe early State, and where did it come from? Before moving to a critiqueof the State, we must also come to some agreement on these questions.

the a rch aic sta te def ine d

Attempts to dene the archaic State within political anthropology havebeen no less contentious than parallel attempts to pin down the State inpolitical sociology, Marxist studies, and political science.7 The prevailing working denitions have tended to cluster around four primary features:(1) radical social stratication preserved through (2) centralized institu-tions of governmental administration that (3) restrict access to and ap-portionment of resources through (4) the consistent threat of legitimateforce.

(1) Radical social stratication has resided at the heart of understand-ings of the state at least since Rousseau’s Discourse on Inequality.Strati-

cation generally arises out of diªerential access within a population tolimited resources that “sustain life,” such as food, shelter, and the bless-ings of the gods (Fried 1967: 186). Diªerential access produces an unevendistribution of wealth. Although there is no clear standard for when con-centration of wealth becomes so intense as to warrant the description “rad-ical,” archaeologists have long interpreted features such as large palacesor wealthy burials—features that highlight conspicuous consumption of goods—as su‹cient markers of a social privilege far exceeding more lim-

ited uctuations in resource distribution. Although stratication is a generally agreed upon feature of sociopo-litical complexity, there is disagreement over its causal role in the originsof the State. Both Fried and Igor Diakonoª accord stratication a centralrole as a “prime mover” in political evolution. Fried (1967: 230) arguesthat centralized government emerges inevitably out of social inequality in order to “defend the central order of stratication.” Diakonoª (1991:35–40), in a more subtle formulation, posits that unequal divisions of sur-pluses led to diªerentiation in relations of production and ultimately to

90 A R C H A E O L O G I E S O F P O L I T I C A L A U T H O R I T Y

7. One study recorded 145 distinct denitions of “the State” (Titus 1931: 45), a numberthat has only increased in the years since.

Page 17: Smith the Political Landscape (Pp 78-112)

8/12/2019 Smith the Political Landscape (Pp 78-112)

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/smith-the-political-landscape-pp-78-112 17/37

the exploitation of an enslaved population backed by institutionalized co-ercion. Service (1975: 297–303) disagrees with such “intra-societal conict”theories, arguing in a more contractarian vein that stratication is a col-

lateral result of the functional benets conferred by the State form. Ser- vice envisions a cost-benet origin to the State where acquiescence to theinequalities at the heart of the early State must have been exchanged forconcrete advantages, including defense from raiding parties (the State asprimordial protection racket) and fostering of long-distance trade.

(2) Centralized institutions of governmental administration preservethe uneven distribution of wealth, lending stability to the State. The eªec-tive autonomy of the government from the privileged social class is a mat-ter of great debate within the Marxist tradition. Some scholars have ar-gued that the governmental apparatus has no autonomy but is simply aninstrument of the dominant class. 8 This direct translation of social classinto political regime can be construed either narrowly, in terms of direct class control over the political agenda, or more broadly, in terms of classinterests that promote and maintain advantageous forms of governance.Others have argued that governmental institutions do have some auton-omy from class structures, but both are understood as two forms takenby the same process of domination. Friedrich Engels formulated an early

expression of this position:But now a society had come into being that by virtue of all its economic con-ditions of existence had to split up into freemen and slaves, into exploitingrich and exploited poor. . . . Such a society could only exist either in a state of continuous open struggle of these classes against one another or under the ruleof a third power which, while ostensibly standing above the conicting classes,suppressed their open conict and permitted a class struggle at most in theeconomic eld, in a so-called legal form. The gentile constitution had outlived itself. . . . Its place was taken by the state. (1990: 268)

More recently, Claus Oªe and Volker Ronge (1997: 60) have echoed En-gels’s description of the provisional autonomy of the State, describing it as an institutional form of political power that protects the common in-terests of various classes invested in reproduction of the existing order.

The central component of the State in these accounts is the way it man-ufactures sovereignty out of narrow sectional allegiances and interests.Sovereignty refers to “the idea that there is a nal and absolute author-

A R C H A E O L O G I E S O F P O L I T I C A L A U T H O R I T Y 91

8. See Bob Jessop’s (1990: 25–29, 88–91) outline of the varying conceptions of the Statein Marx’s writings and the neo-Marxist tradition. (See also Lukes 1974; Clegg 1989.)

Page 18: Smith the Political Landscape (Pp 78-112)

8/12/2019 Smith the Political Landscape (Pp 78-112)

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/smith-the-political-landscape-pp-78-112 18/37

ity in the political community” and is generally taken as a unique featureof the State, arising in the reconciliation of a ruling apparatus and the re-mainder of the civil community (Hinsley 1986: 1, 22–26). Sovereignty was

the implicit central feature of L. T. Hobhouse’s (1911: 126–39) conceptionof the State as he highlighted the subordination of districts to the centerand thus the creation of an institutionalized chain of command linkingruler to citizen (see also Hobhouse, Wheeler, and Ginsberg 1915). Sover-eignty may be considered in personal terms, as vested in a king, or moregenerally located throughout the institutions of the body politic (even toits ultimate dispersal in that most democratic of institutions, the “citi-zenry ”), but it is inherently limited geographically, circumscribed by theborders of the polity (though the inated rhetoric of regimes may dis-pute the boundedness of sovereign authority).

The establishment of sovereignty through class diªerentiation lies at the heart of Robert Carneiro’s (1970) account of the origin of the State.In Carneiro’s conict theory, the State arises out of population growththat stretches the capacities of agricultural production within a circum-scribed territory to their limits. Warfare intensies under these conditionsas competition for land leads to the subordination of defeated commu-nities. This subordination entails a loss of local autonomy, establishing

the sovereignty of the victor, now ruling as an arm of a privileged class,over the entire circumscribed territory.

(3) Institutions restrict access to and apportionment of resources by asserting various degrees of control over production, exchange, and con-sumption. Such controls may extend from policies of tribute extractionor taxation to direct governmental ownership of key means of produc-tion and distribution. These economic policies reinforce both the cen-trality of governmental institutions (encouraging the expansion of bu-

reaucracies described by Max Weber [1968]) and further concentration of wealth. However, they may also provide the basis for coalition buildingacross social strata.

Henry Wright and Gregory Johnson (1975) have emphasized the es-sentially bureaucratic nature of the State, arguing that it is best under-stood as a decision-making organization in which specialized adminis-trative institutions located in central places receive information from, and make decisions aªecting, lower institutional tiers distributed in a network of regional and district settlements. It is not surprising that, in develop-ing the most highly nuanced vision of the archaic State to emerge withinpolitical anthropology, Wright and Johnson’s approach does not t well within the reductionist historical vision of neo-evolutionism—the ques-

92 A R C H A E O L O G I E S O F P O L I T I C A L A U T H O R I T Y

Page 19: Smith the Political Landscape (Pp 78-112)

8/12/2019 Smith the Political Landscape (Pp 78-112)

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/smith-the-political-landscape-pp-78-112 19/37

tion as to why these systems of information exchange develop cannot beeasily articulated with a limited set of material determinants (see, how-ever, Wright 1978). Wright and Johnson’s model calls attention to the vast

networks of relationships that have been subsumed under the deceptively monolithic term, the State. These relationships link rulers to bureaucra-cies within institutional complexes that regulate the interconnections con-stitutive of the civil sphere.

(4) The consistent threat of legitimate force underlies the operationof the State as the capacity to compel adherence to the political order.Weber (1946: 77–78) was particularly emphatic in identifying “the mo-nopoly of the legitimate use of physical force” as the dening character-istic of the State (see also the denition of the State in MacIver 1926: 22).But at issue here is not so much the actual deployment of force as the cred-ibility of the threat. As Bob Jessop (1990: 342) has noted, though phys-ical coercion is generally theorized as the State’s ultimate instrument forcompelling obedience, it has numerous other methods that it can employ,and violence is rarely the tool of rst resort. What is critical to the Stateis not the possibility that political institutions monopolize all expressionsof violence, but rather that such outbursts must be considered legitimateonly in the hands of the institutionalized governmental authorities. We-

ber classies the possible sources of such legitimacy as arising from tra-dition (belief in the historical permanency of a regime), from aªect (anemotional commitment to the political order, often rooted in religioussources), from rational belief in the order’s absolute value, or from belief in the legality of the order’s establishment (Weber 1968: 11–12).

Stephen Sanderson (1995: 56) places a monopoly over the “means of violence” at the center of his denition of the State, suggesting that thesuccessful suppression of a rebellion denotes a fully realized monopoly

over the means of force, a power that distinguishes the State from previ-ous political formations along the evolutionary progression, such as theChiefdom. In addition to the arguments by Carneiro (1970) and Giddens(1985) that most States, ancient and modern, do not hold such a monopoly,Sanderson’s denition has the added drawback of precipitously reducingthe State to a synonym of repression.

Numerous other features have been prominent in denitions of theState, including administrative technologies (such as writing) and “eth-nic stratication.” (On the former, see excellent articles in Marcus 1992;Michalowski 1987; Postgate, Wang, and Wilkinson 1995; Rothman 1994;Schmandt-Besserat 1996. On the latter, see Thurnwald and Thurnwald 1935; rejected in Cohen 1978: 32.) Similarly, a number of other “prime

A R C H A E O L O G I E S O F P O L I T I C A L A U T H O R I T Y 93

Page 20: Smith the Political Landscape (Pp 78-112)

8/12/2019 Smith the Political Landscape (Pp 78-112)

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/smith-the-political-landscape-pp-78-112 20/37

movers” to State formation have been identied, including the manage-rial demands of irrigation and interpolity exchange (Polanyi, Arensberg,and Pearson 1957; Renfrew 1975; Wittfogel 1957). However, the denition

of the State discussed above pulls together enough of the main elementsto serve as a fair description of the concept and as a locus for critique.It should be made clear that the State concept, as presently constituted,

aspires to describe both a real phenomenon of political life and a generaltype of political organization. This is possible because of the essential unity attributed to the concept. The assumption of a phenomenal singularity underlying the diversity of political forms was defended in 1927 by Robert H. Lowie, who proposed that the State is a form of association whose expression in diverse global contexts is a result of the psychic unity of mankind.9 Although the psychological locus of Lowie’s unity postu-late was dismissed during the materialist turn in archaeology, it survivestoday rooted in a simplistic biology where it has been asserted that thelack of speciation among human groups provides the basis for a unied story of cultural transformation (Mann 1986: 34–35). In preserving a pos-tulated unity, a particular epistemological stance was also preserved that assumed diªering features of complex societies to be epiphenomenal, whereas shared features reected the “kernel” of the State. This is, of

course, a tautological enterprise; the shared classicatory features that arelabeled “the State” are also held up as proof of the State’s reality as a gen-eralizable social fact. However, it allows the State to have not only thestatus of heuristic category but also the ambition to describe a phenom-enon of political life that oªers a more encompassing and compelling locusfor political analysis than, for example, government and law—conceptsthat are marginalized as particular and epiphenomenal rather than uni- versal and explanatory. However, even as the State is transformed into a

real element of various public and private relationships, it becomes in-creasingly di‹cult to locate because, though the State has been given tem-porality, it has no place.

Against the State: An Archaeological CritiqueHaving developed a picture of the State and its deployment in theoriesof the evolution of early complex polities, I want now to discuss four pri-

94 A R C H A E O L O G I E S O F P O L I T I C A L A U T H O R I T Y

9. This psychological basis for presuming essential unity was later folded into a socialevolutionary approach in Krader 1968: 11–12.

Page 21: Smith the Political Landscape (Pp 78-112)

8/12/2019 Smith the Political Landscape (Pp 78-112)

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/smith-the-political-landscape-pp-78-112 21/37

mary reasons for abandoning the concept as the centerpiece for politicalanalyses of early complex polities. The rst reason centers on the deno-tational insecurity of the term.

denota t ion

The State, despite its centrality, is an entirely nebulous object of study without a clear referent. Fried began his landmarkThe Evolution of Polit-ical Society(1967) by bemoaning the horrors of denition and highlight-ing the pointlessness of it all if we cannot agree on common denotationsas tools of analysis. But Fried’s complaint was already quite dated in re-spect to the State. Bolingbroke decried the instability of any denition of the State in the eighteenth century, writing that “the state is become, un-der ancient and known forms, an undenable monster” (quoted in Skin-ner 1997: 19), and in the mid-twentieth century David Easton (1953: 107–8)led a functionalist assault on the concept’s lack of precision. Even We-ber’s oft-cited denition of the State as “a human community which (suc-cessfully) claims the monopoly of the legitimate use of physical force within a given territory” (1968: 78) quickly disappears from view, obscured by numerous qualications on the nature and deployment of force, the

variable forms of legitimacy, and the meaning of community that shift analysis away from the State and toward bureaucracy (see also Jessop 1990:343). In the most thorough recent examination of the State from a Marx-ist point of view, Jessop demurs on oªering a denition until his nal chap-ter and follows it with a long list of caveats. Pierre Bourdieu recently for-malized this tradition of denotational insecurity, arguing that the statemust be subject to “a sort of hyperbolic doubt . . . . For, when it comes tothe state, one never doubts enough” (1999: 54).

It might be objected that, though the multivocality of landscape wasapplauded in the previous chapter, I am here condemning the denotationalplurality of the State. In response I suggest that the diªerence betweenthe two cases lies in the analytical work that can be accomplished by therespective concepts. Whereas investigations of landscape have ourished as the meaning of the term has expanded, such conceptual fuzziness is ex-traordinarily problematic for accounts of the modern state. So much eªort has been spent over the past 30 years in trying to dene the archaic Statethat classicatory debates have sapped much of the eld’s theoretical en-ergy. The result has been an extended period when categorization and classication have substituted for analysis. For years the primary tensionin this endeavor was provided by a strangely vituperative dispute over the

A R C H A E O L O G I E S O F P O L I T I C A L A U T H O R I T Y 95

Page 22: Smith the Political Landscape (Pp 78-112)

8/12/2019 Smith the Political Landscape (Pp 78-112)

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/smith-the-political-landscape-pp-78-112 22/37

categorical and evolutionary division between the Chiefdom and the State(see, for example, Bawden 1989; Carneiro 1981; Earle 1987, 1991; Kirch1984; McGuire 1983; Wright 1994; Yoªee 1979, 1993). Generally lost in

this struggle was a concern for the actual dynamics of polities.Despite the often grand claims and bitter language, the intellectualstakes in these classicatory debates are extraordinarily low. That is, nogreat insight into the nature or origins of early polities could issue fromtheir resolution. Classication of polities as State or Chiefdom is singu-larly uninteresting because it speaks only to failures in our typologicalimagination, telling us little about the nature of politics in the past. Thesame shift in focus from what happens in ancient polities to the variabil-ity among and within types now threatens to engulf the analytical concept of the city-state. In a recent volume on the city-state as a “cross-culturalregularity,” Norman Yoªee argues that “we must resist elevating the [city-state] to an intellectual fetish. We must unpack the term city-state,tracethe variability within it, and explain the signicant divergences from it”(1997: 256). Despite the well-taken caution against fetishization, ratherthan reducing the city-state to a simple heuristic category, a creation of our own typological imagination, Yoªee goes on to position the concept as a real product of social evolution, a social form that lies at the termi-

nus of various trajectories of mounting social inequality: “In general, city-states evolve as collecting basins for the crystallization of long-termtrends toward stratication and social diªerentiation in a geographical re-gion” (ibid., 261). In taking the city-state as a real, singular, historically stable form of political association, this new social evolutionary programthreatens to merely reinstantiate the existing theoretical emphasis on cate-gorization in only slightly diªerent terms. The problem lies not in typol-ogy per se but rather in mistaking these analytical types as enduring spatial

forms with their own historical inevitability.

epistemology and i l lusion

A second argument for abandoning the State arises from epistemologicalsources. A growing number of critics have attacked the State’s pretensionto describe a coherent object of analysis, a real agent, or a site of politicalaction. Timothy P. Mitchell has argued that the State cannot be under-stood as an object, “a free-standing entity, whether an agent, instrument,organization or structure” (1991: 95). Rather, the state (lowercase “s”) canbe understood to emerge as “a set of powerful yet elusive methods of or-dering and representing social practice” (Mitchell in Bendix et al. 1992:

96 A R C H A E O L O G I E S O F P O L I T I C A L A U T H O R I T Y

Page 23: Smith the Political Landscape (Pp 78-112)

8/12/2019 Smith the Political Landscape (Pp 78-112)

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/smith-the-political-landscape-pp-78-112 23/37

1017). The goal of Mitchell’s Foucauldian critique is to break down theconceptual boundaries of the State that divide it, as an object of inquiry,from the larger social world. Without its conceptual discreteness, the State

merges into the broader eld of social practices such that investigation of the political is transformed into an investigation of “structural eªects”rather than structures, “of detailed processes of spatial organization, tem-poral arrangement, functional specication, and supervision and surveil-lance” (Mitchell 1991: 95). The state endures, in Mitchell’s analysis, only as a historically specic political formation, one unique in its current in-carnation, where the illusion of a separate political entity dictating policy for society holds profound consequences for action.

Philip Abrams has forwarded a similar critique in a more sociological vein that owes less to Foucault than to Marx. The State, Abrams argues,is not a real dimension of political life but, rather, represents a fetishiza-tion of twentieth-century political ideology as deep metahistorical struc-ture: “The state is at most a message of domination—an ideological arte-fact attributing unity, morality and independence to the disunited amoraland dependent workings of the practice of government” (1988: 81). TheState is thus reconsidered as a ction created through the mistakenreication of a classicatory type. The term unies and gives conceptual

coherence to what are in fact a large number of discrete political practices. The State, Abrams continues, is not the unied locus of political life that we have assumed but simply one of the many masks worn by authority in order to pretend to be universal, inevitable, and sewn in to the very deepest fabric of the way things are.10 As he concludes: “[T]he state isnot the reality which stands behind the mask of political practice. It is it-self the mask which prevents our seeing political practice as it is” (ibid.,81). What better guise could inequality, domination, and exploitation take

than to be represented as part of a metahistorical order that is simulta-neously everywhere and nowhere? The epistemological consequences of Mitchell’s and Abrams’s critiques

are quite staggering for the study of the archaic State. To the extent that they have attempted to detail the origins of the State, studies of early com-plex polities have been engaged in writing a profound backstory to cur-rent politics, one that universalizes and thus legitimizes current politicalsystems by rooting them in a far-oª antiquity connected to the present in an unbreakable chain of historical causation. By reading the State out

A R C H A E O L O G I E S O F P O L I T I C A L A U T H O R I T Y 97

10. For an extended discussion of critiques of the State as illusion, see Comaroª 1998.

Page 24: Smith the Political Landscape (Pp 78-112)

8/12/2019 Smith the Political Landscape (Pp 78-112)

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/smith-the-political-landscape-pp-78-112 24/37

Page 25: Smith the Political Landscape (Pp 78-112)

8/12/2019 Smith the Political Landscape (Pp 78-112)

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/smith-the-political-landscape-pp-78-112 25/37

litical views about our present state” (1975: 289) not only comes acrossas a tad disingenuous (the preceding paragraphs had ridiculed the Marx-ism of C. Wright Mills, leaving the equally problematic thought of Kings-

ley Davis unchallenged) but also somewhat undesirable; it was the am-plication of these debates in reference to ancient societies that made themrelevant to contemporary political discourse. In particular, the debateamong Marxist, liberal, and conservative writers over the role of classstratication in the emergence of the archaic State, though always cloaked in the folds of scientic argumentation, was a vital extension of the study of early complex polities into contemporary political discussions.

It is di‹cult to see how such a debate might inform critical thought re-garding the current situation of the world. If Lenin’s remarks in 1919 mark the emergence of the State as the pivotal concept of critical political his-toriography, then the concept’s fall might appropriately be located in com-ments made by Mikhail Gorbachev at the United Nations 70 years later:“We [the Soviet Union] are, of course, far from claiming to be in posses-sion of the ultimate truth” he declared, implicitly deating Marxist claimsto superior knowledge of human political history and mechanics (quoted in Nelson 2000: 4). In today’s post–Cold War world, very little hangs inthe balance in competing conceptualizations of the State. Some might fairly

argue that contemporary arguments between defenders of the welfare stateand advocates of neo-liberalism are substantially invested in opposed un-derstandings of the State. However, I would argue that these are conictsover policies and practices within rival visions of liberal governance, not over competing claims on the essence of the State. That is, their diªerencesare not, by and large, predicated on competing theories of history but onmore or less technocratic accounts of proper governance.

Events have clearly outpaced the intellectual apparatus through which

the study of early complex polities can be deployed to allow the past toprovide illumination on the present. The myriad conicts that now gripthe world reveal not the practical irrelevance of the nation-state, as someauthors have argued, but rather the conceptual obsolescence of the Stateconcept itself as the orienting object of political research. Althoughclearly great political struggles are ongoing, can debate over the natureor origins of the State shed any illumination on conicts in southeasternEurope or the rapidly increasing chasm between rich and poor in West-ern democracies? I think it unlikely. The very features that made the Statecompelling for Cold War rivalries—the eschatological view of history rooted in remote antiquity—make it appear pious and impractical today.What seems more clear today than ever before is that politics is less about

A R C H A E O L O G I E S O F P O L I T I C A L A U T H O R I T Y 99

Page 26: Smith the Political Landscape (Pp 78-112)

8/12/2019 Smith the Political Landscape (Pp 78-112)

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/smith-the-political-landscape-pp-78-112 26/37

rival metahistorical vision than it is about rivalries over historically situ-ated landscapes.

ontology and space

A nal di‹culty in building political analysis on the State is ontologicaland centers on the aspatial nature of the concept. Though argued from thepoint of view of landscape in chapter 1, the exclusion of space from Statetheory is also objectionable from a political perspective. A spatial critiqueof the State has been forwarded in a number of disparate arenas. ImmanuelWallerstein’s World Systems theory reinvigorates a geographic under-standing of politics by according central analytical position to relationshipsestablished in space between economically intertwined places (Wallerstein1974; see also Johnston 1982: chap. 4; Taylor 1997). In Wallerstein’s account of the modern World System, the rise of European (later American) in-dustrial capitalism was predicated on the creation of a set of economic re-lationships between the centers of industrial production—the factories and mills of Europe that transformed raw materials into nished products—and the peripheral regions that served as sources of raw materials and mar-kets for re-export of nished products. The particular signicance of the

World System lies in the instrumentality accorded to geographic position. The relationships established between center, semiperiphery, and periph-ery are central to formation of political regimes and political economiesbecause it was relations across space—and the transportation technologiesthat facilitated them—that enabled Europe to build itself on the produc-tion of goods from raw materials dispersed around the globe.

It is important to note that, as originally conceived, the World Systemnot only described a particular set of places but was also set in a very

specic time: the development of capitalist economies since a. d.

1500. Attempts by archaeologists and historians (and indeed by Wallerstein him-self ) to read a World System back in time, into the era of early complexpolities, tend to obscure what is most interesting about the model (Al-gaze 1993; Blanton and Feinman 1984; Champion 1989; Eckhardt 1995;Frank 1993; Kohl 1989; Stein 1999; Wallerstein 1995). The explanatory power of the World System model lies in its condent intersplicing of vari-ation across both space and time. To move it out of the modern age re-quires the crystallization of the complexities of its geography into rigid generalities (as evidenced by the way archaeologists tend to unceremo-niously dump the semiperiphery from the model with little discussion or justication). Hence the World System taken outside of the modern con-

100 A R C H A E O L O G I E S O F P O L I T I C A L A U T H O R I T Y

Page 27: Smith the Political Landscape (Pp 78-112)

8/12/2019 Smith the Political Landscape (Pp 78-112)

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/smith-the-political-landscape-pp-78-112 27/37

text generally depends on reestablishing an absolute spatial ontology founded on a limited set of highly crystallized geographic positions. Thelesson to be drawn from Wallerstein’s model is that considerable ex-

planatory power and interpretive elegance can arise from accounting forsocial, political, and economic complexity in terms of the spatial rela-tionships they produced. These relationships, as Gil Stein (1999: 6–7) haspointed out in his thoughtful critique of the use of World Systems mod-els to describe fourth millennium b.c. southwest Asia, are exceedingly heterogeneous depending on both local and regional conditions.

Asecond prominent source of spatial critiques of the State can be traced to several studies of modern urbanism penned in the 1970s and 1980s. Withroots in David Harvey’s Social Justice and the City(1973) as well as HenriLefebvre’s La Production de l ’Espace(1991), the uorescence of this criti-cism of the State through the lter of the city can be found in ManuelCastells’s seminal study,The City and the Grassroots:“Therefore spatialforms, at least on our planet, will be produced by human action, as areall other objects, and will express and perform the interests of the domi-nant class according to a given mode of production” (1983: 311). The key terms in Castells’s declaration are “express and perform.” Spatial dimen-sions of political life not only reect aspects of structure but are also in-

strumental in producing power and legitimacy. This account of politicalspace—a vision ultimately quite close to that oªered by Solzhenitsyn—has been powerfully developed in a number of geographic and architec-tural studies, from Mike Davis’s (1990) searing indictment of Los Ange-les urban development as a tool of political exclusion and domination toSharon Zukin’s (1991) nuanced exploration of the interplay of spatial pro-duction, political institutions, and social fantasies in the creation of thepostmodern American landscape.

Within this tradition of political criticism, the State is maddening inits lack of place, obscuring the intense everyday political concern with or-dering landscapes. In practical terms, the lack of any location for the Statemakes political action almost impossible. In rallying against the State, where must one strike? In coming to the defense of the State, where doesone rally? On the most fundamental level, the State fails to adequately ap-prehend political life because of its a priori demotion of space to the sta-tus of epiphenomena. The central reason for this dismissal is that the Stateis built on both an absolute ontology of space and an absolute ontology of politics. Civil society rests in a limited repertoire of possible forms that arise and transform in predictable (or at least retrodictive) ways becausethey follow a rather limited set of rules. But, like space, politics arises in

A R C H A E O L O G I E S O F P O L I T I C A L A U T H O R I T Y 101

Page 28: Smith the Political Landscape (Pp 78-112)

8/12/2019 Smith the Political Landscape (Pp 78-112)

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/smith-the-political-landscape-pp-78-112 28/37

relationships between groups and individuals, not full grown from arepertoire of types. This relational account of politics begs numerousquestions—what is the nature of civil ties? what kinds of groups or sub-

jects should be thought of as agents within the political sphere? what socio-cultural links parallel political relationships? These issues, I suggest, pro- vide far richer foci for investigations of early complex polities than debatesover typological assignments.13 A relational conception of political lifemust therefore be built not on the rigid absolutism of the State but onauthority, an umbrella term for a set of concepts that emphasize the inter-section of space and time in political practice.

What Was Political Authority?I have argued above against a particular concept of the State, one that vests all political action and explanatory power in a universalized set of structurally discrete formations. But where does the dismissal of the (ar-chaic) State, as a real object of inquiry, leave archaeological and histori-cal analyses of political life? What conceptual apparatus can we build tore-center analysis on what polities do rather than what type they resem-

ble? If we throw out the State as the central object of study, studies of early complex polities must confront two separate problems that have tra-ditionally been conated. The rst problem is to identify the class of ob- jects under examination and dene the heuristic bases on which they areceded a degree of analytical discreteness. The second problem is to iden-tify a productive conceptual locus for investigations of the political. That is, what conceptual foundation can provide a basis for understanding therelationships that constitute the political sphere of action?

ear ly complex pol i t ies

The rst problem is typological and thus of limited theoretical conse-quence. The rejection of the archaic State leaves us with the much moregrounded, and consequently less grand, term “early complex polities” asa provisional description of the objects of comparative inquiry into the

102 A R C H A E O L O G I E S O F P O L I T I C A L A U T H O R I T Y

13. It is important to note that, even if we abandon the State as the conceptual locus fordetailing politics in early complex polities, an imperative remains to account for the con-cept’s modern ideological construction and its rhetorical hegemony. This work, unfortu-nately, extends well beyond the limits of the present discussion.

Page 29: Smith the Political Landscape (Pp 78-112)

8/12/2019 Smith the Political Landscape (Pp 78-112)

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/smith-the-political-landscape-pp-78-112 29/37

historical roots of contemporary modes of political action.14 Where thearchaic State was amorphous and di‹cult to dene, the early complexpolity, though not unproblematic in itself (as I discuss in the last chap-

ter), is clear in its terms yet exible in its connotation—an advantage be-cause there is little likelihood that much debate will be stirred over whether particular formations can be described as early complex polities. The intellectual stakes involved in such a designation are simply far toolow. It is important to emphasize that political complexity—a means of referencing certain sociological features such as inequality or centralized organs of governance—does not equate with cultural complexity, whichtends to center on an evaluative positioning of social groups along broad trajectories of social development.

The modier “early” refers to a temporal horizon relative to local his-tories of political transformation. What distinguishes early complexpolities from more recent formations is not a profound historical dividebut merely a methodological shift. The study of early complex polities is vested as profoundly in archaeology as it is in history and epigraphy. Therelative primacy (or at least equality) of the material culture record sets“early polities” apart from later formations where the historical record tends to swamp archaeological studies.15 This by no means restricts the

eld to nonliterate societies; the historical records of, for example, Meso-potamia, the Classic Maya, or the early Chinese dynasties are only intel-ligible in connection with the archaeological contexts of their discovery.Furthermore, these documents tend to be so restricted in their concernsthat they cannot provide su‹cient bases for understanding social life with-out archaeological research. As a result, early complex polities demand aunique epistemological stance that makes use of the extant archaeologi-cal and textual records even as they are historically continuous with more

modern formations in which studies of material culture play an important,if somewhat diªerent, part. The term “complex” typically refers to a very general set of sociocultural

features, such as inequality in access to resources, variability in social roles,diªerentiation of decision-making bodies, permanence of institutions, and

A R C H A E O L O G I E S O F P O L I T I C A L A U T H O R I T Y 103

14. A number of other archaeologists have also eschewed “the State” in favor of varia-tions on “early complex polity.” Olivier de Montmollin (1989) adopts the synonymous term“ancient complex polities” in his study of the late/terminal Classic period in the Rosario Valley of Mexico.

15. This does not imply a diminution in the importance of archaeological knowledge tounderstanding more intensely textual eras. Rather, I am simply pointing to an epistemo-logical shift that necessarily follows the incorporation of a wealth of written sources.

Page 30: Smith the Political Landscape (Pp 78-112)

8/12/2019 Smith the Political Landscape (Pp 78-112)

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/smith-the-political-landscape-pp-78-112 30/37

the distribution and ow of symbols, meanings, and practices (Blau 1977;Hannerz 1992; McGuire 1983; Tainter 1988: 23–31). In contrast to the State,a noun with pretensions to represent real structures, “complex” is an ad-

jective describing the relativeextent, heterogeneity, and diªerentiation of sociocultural formations. However, I do not wish to suggest that com-plexity is an entirely unproblematic category. As Randall McGuire (1996)has cogently argued, the term can obscure the operation of a wide rangeof social phenomena by reducing them to a rather narrow set of socialoperations—a problem most manifest in the strident reductionism of theso-called “complexity ” theorists of the Santa Fe Institute (see also Gumer-man and Gell-Mann 1994; Waldrop 1992). Moreover, complexity doesnot entirely satisfy as a value-neutral adjective for diªerentiating qualita-tively diªerent objects of anthropological analysis. For this reason, theterm has undergone what Yoªee refers to as “complexity ination” as evensocial communities from the Paleolithic have come to be described as“complex” (personal communication). However, this need not be a prob-lem so long as we are clear about what dimension of complexity providesthe focus for any given study.

A number of political scientists, anthropologists, and sociologists havestrongly contested eªorts, such as those made by Michael Mann, to carve

out a structurally discrete political sphere (Bourdieu 1999; Corrigan and Sayer 1985; Mitchell 1991). Politics intrudes far too profoundly on econ-omy, culture, and social life to be conned within a well-bounded insti-tutional position. However, we can describe the political in terms of prac-tical relationships that are strongly shaped by public forms of civil action.I suggest that four relationships in particular must lie at the heart of how we conceptualize politics:

·interpolity ties, or geopolitical relationships;· relations between regimes and subjects that forge the polity;

· ties among power elites and their links to grassroots social groups (suchas kin groups, occupational associations) that constitute politicalregimes; and

· relationships among governmental institutions.

All four of these sets of relationships can be described as strongly politi-cal in that they have immediate and profound eªects on the life of thepolity. These relationships by no means exhaust the political, but they arecentral to it. Thus, the political here describes a exible set of public re-

104 A R C H A E O L O G I E S O F P O L I T I C A L A U T H O R I T Y

Page 31: Smith the Political Landscape (Pp 78-112)

8/12/2019 Smith the Political Landscape (Pp 78-112)

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/smith-the-political-landscape-pp-78-112 31/37

lationships that organize practices of domination, governance, and legit-imation. In other words, what is at issue in an examination of politics inearly complex polities is the constitution of authority.

on authori ty

Authority is a neglected concept not only in the study of ancient societiesbut in modern ones as well. A prominent reason for this lacuna is the po-litical theory of Hannah Arendt (1958), who forcefully argued that au-thority rst entered political life during the Roman era only to disappearagain during the twentieth century. Arendt’s argument has been reiter-ated in conservative intellectual circles since the 1960s as an indictment of leftist assaults on then-dominant institutions. As a result of Arendt’shistorical positioning of the concept, authority was dened as of little con-cern to political analyses of either modern or ancient polities. Arendt’sargument was that authority is only possessed by a regime that faithfully transmits the principles of a society ’s foundation through succeeding gen-erations. In the case of Rome, the authority of the living derived fromthe sacred roots of the founders transmitted from Aeneas and Romulusto successive generations of elders institutionalized in the Senate.

The most immediate objection to Arendt’s account of authority is sit-uational. The context of Arendt’s writing is important to elucidating thehistorical peculiarity of her position. As Bruce Lincoln (1994) has out-lined at some length, Arendt’s argument arose out of two sources. Ingrouping both Nazi Germany and Stalinist Russia under the general cat-egory of totalitarian regimes, Arendt’s seminal workThe Origins of To-talitarianism (1951) was profoundly invested in connecting communism with the dangers of fascism that had mobilized the United States in World

War II. This intellectual position, supported in part, we now know, by covert monies from U.S. governmental organizations including the Cen-tral Intelligence Agency, attempted to rebut an analytic position forwarded by Theodor Adorno and other members of the Frankfurt School. Ador-no’s research in the United States had suggested that many traits of the“authoritarian personality” that led the German population to embracefascism were highly prevalent among Americans as well. Such a focus onauthoritarianism threatened to shade the sociological and moral dividebetween the Soviet Union and the West at a time when various groupsclustered around the anticommunist banner sought to portray the con-trast in stark terms. Today, it is di‹cult to share Arendt’s concern that au-thority be so conceptually reduced.

A R C H A E O L O G I E S O F P O L I T I C A L A U T H O R I T Y 105

Page 32: Smith the Political Landscape (Pp 78-112)

8/12/2019 Smith the Political Landscape (Pp 78-112)

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/smith-the-political-landscape-pp-78-112 32/37

This brings us to a second objection to Arendt’s account of authority.In his analysis of authority, Weber outlined three basic forms—traditional,charismatic, and rational-legal—that could be diªerentiated on the basis

of “the kind of claim to legitimacy typically made by each” (1947: 324).Rational-legal authority rests on a belief in the legality of rules rooted ina general condence in the procedural validity by which they were en-acted. Charismatic authority arises in the devotion of a population to the“specic and exceptional sanctity” of an individual and the rightness of any social order ordained by him or her. Traditional authority is grounded in the belief that the present order rests on a sanctied politicoculturalhistory. It is clear that Arendt wanted to exclude the rst two forms and limit authority to the traditional. This move is unconvincing, however,because Arendt never considers how tradition, charisma, and rational-legalforms of authority might grow out of and into each other over time. Thetransition from the Roman republic to the empire under the Caesars canbe seen as just such an elision of tradition and charisma.

The rigidity of Arendt’s sense of the term is largely due to her de-scription of authority as an entity to be possessed. As Lincoln has per-suasively argued, authority is not an entity but, rather, is best described “in relational terms as the eªect of a posited, perceived, or institutionally

ascribed asymmetry between speaker and audience” (1994: 4). As a re-sult, authority is not an obsolete element of political life but is, and hasalways been, a fundamental element of civil discourse. Lincoln’s eruditeanalysis of authority in contexts ranging from the Homeric Assembly tocontemporary environmental protests indicates that the relations consti-tuting authority emerge primarily in linguistic performance. Authority,he argues, “lies in the capacity to produce consequential speech” (ibid.).What is said, Lincoln notes, has little consequence. What is central to au-

thority is the eªect produced by speech. Authoritative speech reassuresthe doubtful, wins over the ambivalent, and defuses the opposition. Although claiming precedence for the operation of authority through

language, Lincoln notes the importance of nonverbal dimensions of hu-man intercourse, including landscapes, material culture, gesture, and cos-tume. But he dismisses these as gimmicks—the smoke and mirrors that help “bamboozle” an audience but are ultimately secondary to the show carried out in language (ibid., 5). David Bell goes even further than Lin-coln, arguing a neo-Aristotelian position that “politics is talk” (1975: 10).If politics were indeed only talk, it would be rather di‹cult to make senseof a wide range of contemporary political activities from taxation and warto the protest march and sit-in. In such elds of explicitly political prac-

106 A R C H A E O L O G I E S O F P O L I T I C A L A U T H O R I T Y

Page 33: Smith the Political Landscape (Pp 78-112)

8/12/2019 Smith the Political Landscape (Pp 78-112)

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/smith-the-political-landscape-pp-78-112 33/37

tice, talk is rather beside the point if not practically impossible. Politicscertainly involves speech, but it would also seem to be, in a more en-compassing sense, about human action and movement, and hence about

landscape. There are good reasons to think that language is only one part of thelarger constitution of authority through practice. Let me use the follow-ing example. A judge in a court of law is said to have authority in that court. Outside of that place, though possessed of considerable status (sug-gesting a great deal of transitivity between status and authority), a judge’sspeech is not authoritative because he or she cannot simply condemnpassersby to jail sentences. Likewise, another individual who sits on thebench and pronounces judgments is at best recognized to be a fool and at worst a usurper. Either way, such pronouncements are not legitimateand thus not authoritative. The relationship between people and placesis quite clearly an important constituent of authority.

The speech of the judge cannot, I think, be said to create authority,because that must already exist if his words are to be distinguished fromthose of the usurper. Indeed, the words exchanged in a courtroom areonly signicant if the authority of the proceedings has alreadybeen es-tablished, before the rst word is uttered. This throws our analysis of the

roots of authority back on the space of the court itself. As the example of the usurper shows, authority cannot be said to inhere in space itself but rather in the relationship between the place and the actors. The constitu-tion of authority therefore hangs on the production of place as it organ-izes and conditions the actors who will practice through, rather than sim-ply within, specic landscapes. Authority is constituted in the court through the production of its space providing an arena in which speechby designated actors can already be constituted as authoritative. Author-

ity is thus not a favored child of language but an eªect of relationshipsassembled and reproduced in the much broader realm of political prac-tice, in which landscape plays a central role before the rst authoritative word is uttered. As a result, we should look for authority not simply inthe relatively rareed realm of a handful of literary texts but on the ground,in the archaeological record.

A large number of human relationships may be described as authori-tative: parent-child, teacher-student, boss-worker, and the like. Ethnog-raphers have detailed the constitution of and challenges to authority incontexts as disparate as the cadres of rural China and the punks of Brix-ton (Emery 1986; Siu 1986). But the analytical importance of explicitly political authority lies in its presumptive claim to be the authority of last

A R C H A E O L O G I E S O F P O L I T I C A L A U T H O R I T Y 107

Page 34: Smith the Political Landscape (Pp 78-112)

8/12/2019 Smith the Political Landscape (Pp 78-112)

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/smith-the-political-landscape-pp-78-112 34/37

resort, able to exert its commands within all other such relations and thusrecongure them, if only momentarily, in the public realm. Political au-thorities can come to the defense of children against parents and work-

ers against bosses. The central question for the study of early complex poli-ties is thus not the origin and evolution of an essentialized totality that we call the State but an inquiry into how, in varying sociocultural for-mations, an authoritative political apparatus came to gain varying degreesof ascendancy over all other social relations.16 This is what we should mean when we refer to states, if the concept is to have any utility: those poli-ties where a public apparatus holds the legitimate power to intercede inother asymmetric relationships in order to mark itself as the authority of last resort.

Authority can thus be located in the conuence of interests that pro-mote fundamental practical asymmetries and embrace the paramountcy of the resultant apparatus as inherent to the proper order of things. 17 At the center of this understanding of authority rest two fundamental rela-tional processes: the power to direct others, and the recognition of thelegitimacy of these commands. Studies of political organization in an-thropology have resolutely moved to consider the concept of power inethnographic and archaeological contexts under the inuence of theorists

such as Mann (1986), Michel Foucault (1979a), Steven Lukes (1974), and Nicos Poulantzas (1973). Indeed, the concept has become so ubiquitousthat it has, in many cases, come to exhaust analysis of processes of polit-ical formation (Haas 1982). For the purposes of this study, power is not just the ability of one (individual, class, regime, polity) to realize its (po-litical, economic, social) interests at the expense of another (individual,class, regime, polity) but, more profoundly, the capacity to constituteinterests and determine their signicance within the management of

existing conditions. As important as power relations are, they are only one aspect of au-thority. As Weber argued, power may ultimately be exerted in similar waysin varying forms of authority; it is the bases of legitimacy that diªeren-tiates them. By legitimacy I refer to the ability of a regime to synchronizepractices that perpetuate the existing political order within a discursiveframework that generates the allegiance of subjects. This description coin-

108 A R C H A E O L O G I E S O F P O L I T I C A L A U T H O R I T Y

16. See Shamgar-Handelman and Handelman 1986 for a study of how educational in-stitutions in Israel try to set the nation-state (rather than familial structures) at the apex of authority.

17. See also the denition of authority oªered in Ferguson and Mansbach 1996: 35.

Page 35: Smith the Political Landscape (Pp 78-112)

8/12/2019 Smith the Political Landscape (Pp 78-112)

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/smith-the-political-landscape-pp-78-112 35/37

cides generally with Antonio Gramsci’s (1971: 182) description of the third moment in the historical relation of social forces in which the interestspursued by a regime are perceived by subjects to coincide with their own

interests. Such a view of legitimacy also generally accords with John Bainesand Norman Yoªee’s (2000: 15) denition of the term as “the institu-tionalization of people’s acceptance of, involvement in, and contributiontowards order,” although I would place particular emphasis on the reso-lution of the oppositional nature of power through a redenition of theinterests of subject groups.

Both power and legitimacy are necessary to constitute authority. A legitimate government in exile holds no power and thus cannot be said to be in authority; conversely, a regime without legitimacy, based solely on domination, may be described as piratical or extortionist, but not authoritative. In discussing the constitution of political authority, I amreferring to the process by which relations of political power emerge within a framework of legitimate governance. This process of constitu-tion is productive in that it emerges, as Giddens (1984) has outlined, inthe reexive interrelations between historically situated agents and exist-ing structures.

Space and Reproduction: The Temporality of Political Landscapes

Landscape envelopes both the spatial and the temporal. Although the fol-lowing studies emphasize the intertwined historicity and spatiality of po-litical production and reproduction, it is worthwhile to briey outline here just how one might formally theorize the temporality of landscape. That

is, if authority is an eªect of spatialized practices, then we must pose thequestion as to how authority waxes, wanes, and reproduces over time.What is it that generates the need for regular reproduction of authority once it is understood as practice closely linked to the production of space?We can identify four primary sources of emergent gaps between author-ity and landscape that generate a demand for constant reproduction (as well as providing potential locales of strong critique). The rst and most important arises from the constellatory nature of the political landscape. As Solzhenitsyn suggested in Gulag Archipelago,the pretensions of re-gimes to geographic universality—to an immanent presence—is an illu-sion cloaking what is at best an archipelagic landscape created in practicesof governance and oversight of varying intensity and sustainability. Thus,

A R C H A E O L O G I E S O F P O L I T I C A L A U T H O R I T Y 109

Page 36: Smith the Political Landscape (Pp 78-112)

8/12/2019 Smith the Political Landscape (Pp 78-112)

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/smith-the-political-landscape-pp-78-112 36/37

the political landscape’s inevitable incompleteness sustains a relentlesseªort to ll in absent positions and re-map the imagination of the polity.

A second source of the need for reproduction arises from the unique

nature of the built environment as an artifact. The political landscape asa material instrument in the constitution of authority emerges as not only incomplete but also highly inadequate. Once something is built, it im-mediately begins to age at a rate wholly incommensurable with the en-durance of various policies and strategies for rule. Thus political author-ity exists in constant tension with the very landscape that generates and sustains its rule.

A third drive to political reproduction arises in the incomplete rela-tionship between land and landscape. Environmental transformationssuch as major droughts and shifts in river courses can have a profound impact on political orders, necessitating wholesale transformations in land-scapes, both physical and representational. As Davis cogently argues in Ecology of Fear (1998), it is not the environmental catastrophes that con-stantly strike modern Los Angeles per se that provoke shifts in relation-ships between political regimes and constituencies. Rather, it is the imag-ination of these landscapes on which eªective political coalitions are built.

A fourth source of the need for reproduction arises from the fractured

nature of authority. Where the State presents us with a rather singular to-talized view of the political, authority is more broadly distributed in a wide array of relationships. Landscapes are produced in many diªerent spheres of authority (for example, families build houses, corporate groupsconstruct settlements, rulers establish cities). As a result, the landscapeemerges as a palimpsest of relations of authority. This plurality in pro-duction creates potential for signicant instability in the relationship be-tween practice and landscape. Political authority presents itself as the arena

of spatial production of the last resort. Zoning laws, for example, revealthe ability of the political apparatus to intrude itself into the spatiality of other authority relations. However, this control over landscape produc-tion is never complete and often unsustainable. Hence, political landscapesare constantly shifting in response to factors far beyond immediate po-litical relationships.

In attending to the production and reproduction of authority in spaceand over time, politics begin to emerge within a set of intertwined rela-tionships. The chapters that follow address the spatial constitution of political authority within four distinct sets of historically conditioned re-lationships: the landscapes of geopolitics established in interpolity rela-tionships; the territorial landscapes of the polity forged in ties between

110 A R C H A E O L O G I E S O F P O L I T I C A L A U T H O R I T Y

Page 37: Smith the Political Landscape (Pp 78-112)

8/12/2019 Smith the Political Landscape (Pp 78-112)

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/smith-the-political-landscape-pp-78-112 37/37

regimes and subjects; the settlement-centered landscapes of regimesforged within intra-elite ties and links to grassroots coalitions; and thearchitectural landscapes of institutions. In disarticulating each of these re-

lationships, I do not mean to suggest that each is independent of the other.On the contrary, by treating them as components of a broad vision of thepractical constitution of authority, the following chapters argue for abroadly encompassing account of political landscapes.

A R C H A E O L O G I E S O F P O L I T I C A L A U T H O R I T Y 111