Science Stories: Selecting the Source Animal for …eprints.qut.edu.au/5977/1/5977.pdf ·...

18
Science Stories: Selecting the Source Animal for Xenotransplantation Peta S. Cook Centre for Social Change Research Queensland University of Technology Paper presented to the Social Change in the 21 st Century Conference Centre for Social Change Research Queensland University of Technology 27 th October 2006

Transcript of Science Stories: Selecting the Source Animal for …eprints.qut.edu.au/5977/1/5977.pdf ·...

Page 1: Science Stories: Selecting the Source Animal for …eprints.qut.edu.au/5977/1/5977.pdf · justifications of animal selection and use, changes the invisible role of animals to one

Science Stories: Selecting the Source Animal for Xenotransplantation

Peta S. Cook

Centre for Social Change Research Queensland University of Technology

Paper presented to the Social Change in the 21st Century Conference

Centre for Social Change Research

Queensland University of Technology

27th October 2006

Page 2: Science Stories: Selecting the Source Animal for …eprints.qut.edu.au/5977/1/5977.pdf · justifications of animal selection and use, changes the invisible role of animals to one

1

Science Stories: Selecting the Source Animal for

Xenotransplantation

Peta S. Cook

Centre for Social Change Research, Queensland University of Technology, Brisbane, Australia.

Abstract Xenotransplantation (animal-to-human transplantation) involves implanting, infusing or transplanting living animal tissues, cells or organs into a human recipient. The aim is to alleviate or eliminate human health conditions that prevent the individual from living the ‘good life’. Hence, xenotransplantation is constructed as a potential and needed solution to fixing ‘abnormal’ bodies. By crossing species barriers, however, this technology is not without its complexities and uncertainties. Importantly, xenotransplantation intimately intertwines animals and humans, which may challenge sacred boundaries such as animal/human, subject/object and us/them, while posing new questions about ontology. To deal with such complexities and potential hybridities, official science attempts to stabilise constructed knowledges of animals. This primarily targets knowledges on animals of interest as human organ sources, specifically nonhuman primates and pigs. Ironically, this approach also involves complicating our understandings of the concordance and discordance between nonhuman primates, pigs and humans. Utilising Irwin and Michael’s (2003) ethno-epistemic assemblages, I explore how official science selects an animal as an organ source for humans. By employing what I have called a comparative continuum, it is revealed how official science fashions animal identities on degrees of dissimilarities and similarities to humans, and how, through such negotiations, official science constructs its position of authority. This reveals how official science creates complex and sometimes contradictory truth-claims and stories about nonhuman primates and pigs. Keywords: xenotransplantation; animals; ethno-epistemic assemblage; hybrids; science and technology studies (STS) Contact Details: Peta S. Cook Centre for Social Change Research QUT Carseldine E block, Beams Road Carseldine QLD 4034 Email: [email protected]

Page 3: Science Stories: Selecting the Source Animal for …eprints.qut.edu.au/5977/1/5977.pdf · justifications of animal selection and use, changes the invisible role of animals to one

2

Introduction Human history is filled with imagery of monstrous, beastly couplings of humans and animals. Altering this imaginary to reality is xenotransplantation (animal-to-human transplantation), a techno-scientific and medical intervention that constructs new narrations of animal and human relationships. In everyday activities, however, humans are usually unaware of the important role animals play in creating and recreating what is understood as ‘human society’ and ‘human life’. The needed relation between humans and animals in xenotransplantation (XTP), and the subsequent scientific justifications of animal selection and use, changes the invisible role of animals to one of visibility. In this paper, I explore the stories told by official science about choosing an animal organ source, namely pigs over nonhuman primates (NHPs) for XTP. Official science can be understood as the science that is portrayed as reliable and factual. This science can be found in peer reviewed journals, books (which are often collections of peer reviewed journal articles or congratulatory praise), and popular scientific magazines (for example, Scientific American and New Scientist). Font type is used to distinguish the stories of official science from analysis, as this example demonstrates. To achieve this examination, Irwin and Michael’s (2003) ethno-epistemic assemblages are applied. The rather long-winded ‘ethno-epistemic assemblage’ is designed to explore how different techniques can be used to justify particular realities. In this particular case, the construction of scientific knowledge is a technique which is used to produce what is real, or the ‘facts’ about NHPs and pigs. This approach involves examining how “beliefs and notions emerge and stabilize in the process of collaboration or coordination” (Irwin and Michael 2003: 115), or simply put, how truth-claims are produced (the ‘epistemic’). In the case of choosing a source animal for XTP, particular stories provide common understandings and definitions, which coordinate and bind the scientific community together as an authoritative voice. As this paper explores, while this process aims to create a common narrative that decreases complexity of selecting a particular animal species to act as a human organ source, this process paradoxically occurs by increasing complexity. Consequently, sometimes contradictory understandings of species similarity and dissimilarity are used to justify the choice of source animal. Thus, this knowledge is always situated, contextual, contestable and reflexive (the ‘ethno’). To create a façade of stable stories and keep the assemblage in tact, truth-claims are continually reproduced (Irwin and Michael 2003: 119). In XTP therefore, the same stories on why pigs are chosen over NHPs as a source animal, keep reappearing. Such positioning is further justified with official science drawing upon discourses that go beyond science (heterogeneous discourses). This mixing up of boundaries involves blurring the social (in this case, the moral-ethical) and the natural (the practical). The ethno-epistemic assemblage is accordingly formed. To surmise, “the ethno-epistemic assemblage approach consists of a range of heterogeneous analytic concerns” (Irwin and Michael 2003: 139), which allows the exploration of “how such heterogeneous groupings might be characterized” (Irwin and Michael 2003: 113). At the risk of repetition, this paper explores how official science selects an animal organ source for XTP. Through such examinations, this paper also serves as an original contribution to science and technology studies, and the growing field of the sociology of animals. First, it is worth outlining what XTP is. Animal Choice - ‘Practical Stories’ From Greek, ‘xeno’ means foreign, strange or alien. Therefore, XTP traditionally refers to transplants that occur between different species. Recent definitions of XTP have

Page 4: Science Stories: Selecting the Source Animal for …eprints.qut.edu.au/5977/1/5977.pdf · justifications of animal selection and use, changes the invisible role of animals to one

3

become more specific. The Xenotransplantation Working Party of the National Health and Medical Research Council, Australia, (2003: 22, emphasis in original), define XTP as: “any procedure that involves transplantation, implantation or infusion into a human recipient of cells, tissues or organs from a nonhuman animal source”. The definition of XTP is now restricted to animal-to-human transplantation. In general, there are two types of xenotransplants or xenografts, as based on the evolutionary (phylogenetic) relationship of the two species; concordant and discordant. Concordant xenografts occur between closely-related species, such as NHPs (for example, baboons, chimpanzees, orang-utans and macaques), and humans. On the other hand, discordant xenografts occur between dissimilar or distantly-related species, such as pigs and humans (see Figure 1) (Hoffman 2000: 375; Bach 1998: 302). Figure 1 highlights the species which are of focus for official science in XTP. In addition, as indicated by the definitional stabilisation of XTP by the Xenotransplantation Working Party, XTP is a restricted technology that moves only in one direction. That is, while XTP could involve transplants between disparate animal species, in reality only humans can be xenograft recipients, while only animals can be the xenograft source or used as an experimental model. Wider asymmetrical social relationships between humans and animals are thereby reinforced by this construction. This binary structure is integral to current understandings of XTP, and acts as an intermediary that positively favours humans and negatively impacts animals.

TYPE BETWEEN EXAMPLE

Concordant Closely related/ similar species

Baboon to Human

Discordant Distantly related/ dissimilar species

Pig to Human

Figure 1 - Concordant and Discordant Xenotransplantation Compatibility? Returning to concordance and discordance, as phylogenetic difference between the host and donor species increases so does the severity of immunological rejection. When the host and donor share genetic similarities, host-to-recipient compatibility and graft acceptance is increased and immunological rejection is decreased. Consequently, concordance or discordance equates to levels of difficulty in achieving success when transplanting across species barriers, as influenced by the severity of immunological response. Species similarities make concordant xenograft survival easier to achieve and has lead to some limited success.

Page 5: Science Stories: Selecting the Source Animal for …eprints.qut.edu.au/5977/1/5977.pdf · justifications of animal selection and use, changes the invisible role of animals to one

4

Reemtsma et al. (1964) report a human recipient of a chimpanzee renal xenograft survived nine months post-xenotransplantation. More recently, Starzl et al. (1993) report a 70-day survival of a baboon-to-human liver xenograft. Based on this scientific experimental knowledge, NHPs seem the obvious choice as an organ source for successful XTP. NHPs, however, are constructed by official science to be inappropriate. Despite significant barriers to successful XTP, miniature pigs have generally been accepted as the most appropriate source animal. Therefore, official science employs practical (the natural) and moral-ethical (the social) truth-claims rather than quantitative, mathematical measures, to construct stories on why pigs have been chosen over NHPs. Practically and medically, the anatomy and physiology of the internal organs of pigs are moderately similar to humans. Differences between pigs, however, eliminate particular breeds. Domestic pigs are inappropriate, as they reach weights of up to 450 kilograms (Appel III, Alwayn and Cooper 2000: 219; Sachs 1994: 186). Miniature pigs reach maximum weights of between 100 to 135 kilograms, a size more consistent with adult humans (Appel III, Alwayn and Cooper 2000: 220; Sachs 1994: 186). At approximately thirty years, the life expectancy of adult porcine organs is comparable to humans (Magre, Takeuchi and Bartosch 2003: 313). Furthermore, piglets could be used for neonates and children (Perico, Benigni and Remuzzi 2002: 46; Cooper et al. 1991: 482). These initial justifications of using pigs as the source animal revolve around perceived physiological similarities to humans. These physiological discourses of official science align pigs and humans on what I have called the comparative continuum, where a degree of similarity, as based on physiology, is one of the desired outcomes (see Figure 2). It is worth taking a moment to explore the comparative continuum, as it is central to official science justifying the selection of pigs over NHPs. The Comparative Continuum The comparative continuum - or the diagrammatical form of the official scientific story on the increasing and decreasing degrees of desirability regarding using a particular animal as an organ source for XTP - relies upon boundary distinctions between humans and animals. These distinctions are vital. On the face of it, XTP seems to overcome such distinctions and create a hybrid body by merging humans and animals. Significantly, however, XTP can only exist if humans (official science) conceptualise - or tell the story of - animals being a resource (tool) that can be harvested and exploited for human use. Therefore, the value of animal life is assembled as different to the value of human life. The comparative continuum in itself only exists because the bodies of animals, or more specifically their body parts, are compared to the superior model of the human body. The perceived similarity or dissimilarity of animals to humans provides the intermediary for animal suitability or unsuitability as an organ source. This story thereby examines the angles of difference between particular animal species and humans to measure the suitability of a particular animal. The superiority of humans, however, means there will always be an angle of difference, as the value of human life is always beyond the reach of animals. Species equality can never be achieved. Therefore, despite any level of animal-human similarity, animals will not achieve equilibrium to humans on the comparative continuum, meaning the comparative continuum operates with an unbalanced equilibrium. It is therefore unsurprising that these stories are highly complex and problematic. For official science, these

Page 6: Science Stories: Selecting the Source Animal for …eprints.qut.edu.au/5977/1/5977.pdf · justifications of animal selection and use, changes the invisible role of animals to one

5

hierarchical oppositions between humans and animals are considered ‘natural’, thus rendering the stories of similarity, dissimilarity and angles of difference, fixed, indisputable, unquestionable and unchallengeable. The comparative continuum is provided throughout this paper as a summary of official science’s key points on selecting an animal organ source. Significantly, it also demonstrates how official science builds the construction of an animal being suitable or unsuitable as based on predetermined criteria. Obviously, criterion is established and determined by official science, and operates as a mechanism to enforce and reinforce their position of authority in the decision-making process. Through the comparative continuum, it will be demonstrated how the truth-claims of official science involve an increasing complexity, rather than simplicity.

Figure 2 - The Comparative Continuum (Pigs - Part 1) Incompatibility? At this initial stage, the comparative continuum (see Figure 2) reveals the phylogenetic difference between pigs and humans has a negative impact on the appropriateness of using pigs as an organ source. This is offset by desirable physiological similarities. Simultaneously, physiological similarities do not necessarily mean a porcine organ will function effectively or efficiently in a human environment. Expected and unexpected functional deficiencies of porcine organs may have problematic and harmful affects to the human recipient. For example, while both the heart and lungs of pigs are

Page 7: Science Stories: Selecting the Source Animal for …eprints.qut.edu.au/5977/1/5977.pdf · justifications of animal selection and use, changes the invisible role of animals to one

6

horizontally aligned, these organs are upright in humans. Xenografting these porcine organs would change their anatomical positioning. It is unknown whether pig organs can cope with the different physiological demands, such as an adequacy to pump blood vertically to the brain (Weiss 1998: 932). Other problems could manifest in the pulmonary circulation between the heart and lungs, which is important for the body’s respiration and blood oxygenation (Morris 1997: 257; Sherwood 1993: 259). Thus, while pigs and humans share physiological compatibilities, there remain stories which tell of physiological incompatibilities (see Figure 2). Physiological similarity is disrupted by these dissimilarities, posing problems for reducing the angle of difference, or providing a coherent story, on the comparative continuum. These potential problems do not circumvent pigs as the source animal of choice. In contrast, while the close phylogenetic relationship and physiological similarity of NHPs, particularly chimpanzees to humans increases xenograft success, this desirable similarity is overridden by undesirability. The close relationship between NHPs and humans could increase the likelihood of cross-species viral transmission, as viral pathogens between the two species are comparable. Many nonhuman primate viruses have been known to infect humans, such as the simian immunodeficiency virus, herpes B virus, Ebola virus, monkey pox, Marburg virus and simian foamy virus (Boneva and Folks 2004: 505; Wolfe et al. 2004: 2094; Allan 1998: 89-92; Palmer, Soulsby and Simpson 1998: 353, 387, 417-418; Allan 1996: 18-19). Discrepancies in size also exist between NHPs and humans, with baboons only reaching approximate weights of between 10 to 30 kilograms (Chiche et al. 1993: 1418). As a result, baboon organs are generally too small for adult humans (Appel III, Alwayn and Cooper 2000: 219; French et al. 1998: 684-685), and may not function or cope with human physiological demands. For example, Hardy et al. (1964: 120) found a chimpanzee’s heart cannot manage human circulatory needs. While the comparative continuum achieves favourable similarity between humans and NHPs on phylogenetic and physiological deliberations, this alignment is now recounted as too close (pathogenity) and too dissimilar (organ size and function) (see Figure 3). This is despite the previously mentioned favourable history of using NHPs as an organ source. The implication is that phylogenetic differences between pigs and humans may reduce or protect against possible pathogenic transfer. Pig/human phylogenetic discordance is favourable for virology, though conflicts with the desire of phylogenetic concordance for immunology. The result is a comparative continuum that continues to favour pigs as an organ source.

Page 8: Science Stories: Selecting the Source Animal for …eprints.qut.edu.au/5977/1/5977.pdf · justifications of animal selection and use, changes the invisible role of animals to one

7

Figure 3 - The Comparative Continuum (Nonhuman Primates - Part 1) A history of domesticity and extensive knowledge of pigs is believed to reduce infectious risk (Weiss 2004: 284), as human proximity to pigs has not resulted in any major infections (Daar and Phil 1997: 976).

In view of the close association of humans and pigs, and attempts at transplantation and accidental contamination of humans, especially butchers, with pig blood, if there was a severe danger, one would have expected it to have made its appearance, but this is not the case. (Calne 2005: 6)

This official science story reduces apprehensions of infectivity, though there have been cases of pig-to-human infection and subsequent human-to-human transfer. Pigs can act as a vector for spreading animal viruses to humans. Cases include the Nipah virus, which originated in fruit bats (Weiss 2004: 285), and avian respiratory diseases (Fishman and Patience 2004: 1387; Palmer, Soulsby and Simpson 1998: 365). The Comparative Continuum These discourses reveal the comparative continuum to be increasingly complex. Namely, to continue the movement towards reducing angles of difference and to provide a cohesive story for selecting pigs as a human organ source, the

Page 9: Science Stories: Selecting the Source Animal for …eprints.qut.edu.au/5977/1/5977.pdf · justifications of animal selection and use, changes the invisible role of animals to one

8

considerations of similarity alter to considerations of dissimilarity. A complex combination of similarity and dissimilarity, as based on parameters and understandings defined by official science, can both increase and decrease the suitability of using a particular species and breed for XTP. This means stories on physiological similarity, dissimilarity, and phylogenetic disparity, can all occur simultaneously and yet not compromise choosing pigs (see Figure 4). In the case of NHPs, narratives of similarity and dissimilarity are used to increase the angles of difference on the comparative continuum, and therefore eliminate NHPs as the organ source.

Figure 4 - The Comparative Continuum (Pigs - Part 2) Animal Choice - ‘Moral-Ethical Stories’ Truth-claims on phylogenetic and physiological function are not the only practical concerns of official science. Practicalities also arise from morals and ethics. Moral-ethical stories focus upon species characteristics, or ‘species-being’, and their correlation with XTP requirements. In regards to NHPs, their ontology is seen as unfeasible. NHPs reach sexual maturity between three to five years of age, and reach full grown adult size at nine years. In addition, the duration of pregnancy lasts six months with typically singular births (Cooper and Lanza 2000: 47-48). These offspring require intensive parental care and extensive socialisation with other NHPs for behavioural development (Hammer et al. 1998: 7; Weiss 1998: 931), and exercise (Fishman 1997:

Page 10: Science Stories: Selecting the Source Animal for …eprints.qut.edu.au/5977/1/5977.pdf · justifications of animal selection and use, changes the invisible role of animals to one

9

S43). The cost of breeding and maintaining NHPs is difficult, economically prohibitive and time consuming, as based on their long maturation and species needs. Thus, the need to create large colonies of captive NHPs for XTP is resource intensive. At the present time, NHPs are not available in large numbers for scientific and medical applications (Boneva and Folks 2004: 505; Tibell and Lundgren 2002: 20). It is also put forward that animals used for XTP would need to be bred and kept in specific pathogen free (SPF) environments. These barren, biosecure settings are designed to eliminate, prevent, or minimise infection and disease in order to produce germ-free (gnotobiotic) animals. Once again, this conflicts with the ontology of NHPs. To guarantee a SPF environment, animals need to be delivered by hysterectomy and/or caesarean section, and reared in isolation with little or no social contact. While it might be possible to breed NHPs in SPF conditions to minimise infectious risk, some pathogens are persistent and latent, and therefore difficult to eliminate (Boneva and Folks 2004: 505; Weiss 2004: 284). Although SPF nonhuman primate colonies exist, these are small in number with rudimentary husbandry methods (Boneva, Folks and Chapman 2001: 3). Furthermore, the complex needs of NHPs would be difficult to achieve in SPF conditions. Breeding and raising NHPs in isolation for XTP is thereby considered logistically complex and unethical. In the requirements of XTP, the species characteristics of pigs are viewed as ethically permissible. The species needs of pigs are also believed to be adequately catered for in SPF colonies and environments. Pigs produce large litters of three to sixteen piglets after a pregnancy of approximately four months. After reaching sexual maturity at four to nine months, pigs have a regular mating cycle of three weeks (Cooper and Lanza 2000: 47, 50; Dorling et al. 1997: 868; Sachs 1994: 187). As pigs are already used and studied extensively in scientific and medical experimentation, large numbers are currently available for use. Furthermore, their short gestation and large litter production would allow herds with desirable characteristics to be created relatively quickly. Herd production of suitable pigs might include pigs that are selectively bred (Sachs 1994: 187-188), and/or genetically engineered to reduce xenograft rejection (Boneva and Folks 2004: 506; Cooper and Lanza 2000: 51). Pigs have minimal space requirements, are easily fed, and can be separated from their mother immediately after birth and reared in SPF facilities (Weiss 1998: 931; Cooper et al. 1991: 481). The widespread use and knowledge of pigs indicates husbandry methods are well developed and in active use, including the monitoring of SPF colonies and gnotobiotic pigs (Boneva, Folks and Chapman 2001: 4; Cooper et al. 1991: 482). As evidenced, the story of pigs told by official science is one involving ease of raising and breeding in large numbers. This is reinforced with pigs being easy to maintain, and logistically and economically feasible. As compared to NHPs, the ontology of pigs, as told by official science, designates them as an appropriate source animal. The species characteristics of NHPs, however, are not considered feasible to permit them as a source animal, though they were considered permissible in the past (for example, see Starzl et al. 1993; Bailey et al. 1985; Barnard, Wolpowitz and Losman 1977; Hardy et al. 1964; Hitchcock et al. 1964; Reemtsma et al. 1964; Starzl et al. 1964; Voronoff

Page 11: Science Stories: Selecting the Source Animal for …eprints.qut.edu.au/5977/1/5977.pdf · justifications of animal selection and use, changes the invisible role of animals to one

10

1925). With these deliberations, the selection of pigs can be partially viewed in light of economic rationalism. That is, the fast reproduction of pigs and existing husbandry practices allows larger numbers of suitable organs, tissues or cells for humans in need. Hence, the product can be produced relatively quickly, easily and cheaply. Furthermore, the short gestation and regular mating cycle of pigs means pigs (the machinery), can maintain an efficient turn over of product (their cells, tissues or organs), and reach the consumer quickly. The entitlement of the (human) consumer to acquire an (animal) product on demand is met (see Figure 5). A concern with animal welfare, however, would consider the environment that pigs will be and are kept in, and how this complements or deviates from what would be their behaviours and experiences in a ‘natural’ environment. The need for pig health and development could be limited or impossible in a SPF environment.

Figure 5 - The Comparative Continuum (Pigs - Part 3) Animal Bodies and Species-being Stories that compare the bodies of NHPs and pigs to humans - a comparison that is never reversed by official science - have now been deserted. Namely, stories that tell of the animal body in relation to its own species-being, as defined and understood by official science, are now revealed. This shift of focus should not suggest the animal body is now examined in its own right and exclusively of humans. Rather the animal, in this case the pig, is still viewed with relevance to human usage. In this way, species characteristics can be understood as the way humans already use a particular species, which permits further exploitation of animals in XTP. For example:

Page 12: Science Stories: Selecting the Source Animal for …eprints.qut.edu.au/5977/1/5977.pdf · justifications of animal selection and use, changes the invisible role of animals to one

11

The risk of controversy with regard to the use of animals as organ donors for man would be greatly minimized if the animal were already being killed in large numbers on a daily basis to provide food for human consumption. (Cooper et al. 1991: 481) Arguably, because society allows the use of animals for food, the use of animals as a source of organs or tissues is morally acceptable. (Samstein and Platt 2001: 189) The widespread societal acceptance of the use of pigs for food and other products presages a broad social acceptance of their use for medical purposes. (Boneva, Folks and Chapman 2001: 4)

In such official scientific truth-making of species-being, pigs are narrated as dispensable and easy to replace as a ‘renewable’ source. The sacrifice of one pig can quickly and easily be replaced by another pig. As ‘a pig is a pig is a pig’, pigs are not viewed as a species with complex relationships and interdependency. The sacrifice of one pig means little, as they are portrayed as an individualistic species with little awareness of the world around them. The possibility of close relationships between pigs and species characteristics with which humans can identity with, is rendered impossible in such narrations. Once again, humans (official science) control how animals are viewed, understood, and constructed in particular ways that suit human purposes (or exploitations). As previously mentioned, to supply ‘safe’ xenotransplants, certain requirements or restrictions are placed on the choice of animal and animal housing. Part of this consideration connects to species needs. For NHPs, highly dependent and complex social arrangements and the potential of immunological compatibilities that increase infectious risk, render them an unsuitable organ source for humans. These practical reasons are heightened by moral-ethical reasoning. Environmental concerns also preclude the use of some species. Some Great Apes such as chimpanzees, bonobos (pygmy chimpanzees), orang-utans, gorillas and various forms of gibbon, are endangered (Cooper and Lanza 2000: 45; Daar and Phil 1997: 975). XTP would place pressure on species survival. Furthermore, gathering male baboons from wild tribes “would destroy the social life of a baboon gang and lead to their extinction within a short time” (Hammer et al. 1998: 7). These stories, which aid to eliminate NHPs in their entirety, are interesting given that some NHPs are not endangered. This suggests that while environmental concerns might preclude certain species as an organ source, other stories might be the real source of nonhuman primate exclusion as a whole (see Figure 6). Should our closely related relatives be used as a “tissue and organ farm” (Weiss 1998: 931)? NHPs, particularly chimpanzees, display a physical appearance and intellectual, emotional and social nature that are analogous to humans (Takeuchi, Magre and Patience 2005: 324; Magre, Takeuchi and Bartosch 2003: 313; French et

Page 13: Science Stories: Selecting the Source Animal for …eprints.qut.edu.au/5977/1/5977.pdf · justifications of animal selection and use, changes the invisible role of animals to one

12

al. 1998: 685). These ‘human-like qualities’ facilitate feelings of kinship, affording NHPs some limited human rights (Daar and Phil 1997: 976).

Figure 6 - The Comparative Continuum (Nonhuman Primates - Part 2) As such, it is not simply species preservation that precludes NHPs. Rather, NHPs are seemingly too closely related to humans to be used as source animals. This includes an awareness and development of complex relationships. This allows moral concerns usually afforded only to humans to be extended to NHPs. As a result, phylogenetic concordance to humans allows the status and value of NHPs to be elevated above other animals, including pigs. Humanisation? The “humanization of primates” (Fung, Rao and Starzl 1997: 957) in XTP is inappropriate and subjects them to too much suffering. Therefore, using NHPs as an organ source is socially unacceptable and unethical. Ironically, the story of ‘humanisation’ and NHPs plays upon both similarity and difference to humans. As the comparative continuum (see Figure 6) demonstrates, a close phylogenetic relationship and shared species characteristics to humans renders NHPs as an unsuitable source animal. At the same time, this fear of ‘humanising’ NHPs preserves important differentiations between humans and NHPs. This occurs by

Page 14: Science Stories: Selecting the Source Animal for …eprints.qut.edu.au/5977/1/5977.pdf · justifications of animal selection and use, changes the invisible role of animals to one

13

retaining a clear physical separation between ‘us’ and ‘them’. They can be close to humans, but not too close. In regards to pigs, this dyad is reversed. Once again, as the comparative continuum highlights (see Figure 5), the distant phylogenetic relationship, a perceived difference of species-being and a (scientific) comfort with ‘humanising’ pigs, simultaneously breaks down and maintains the human/pig divide. Namely, because pigs are different (‘them’), they can be used. At the same time, this use and stories of species similarity break down the differences between ‘us’ and ‘them’. Exploitation of pigs by humans, however, maintains pigs as ‘them’. Hence, standards are fluid and flexible, and are applied differently to NHPs and pigs. Despite these truth-claims: The pig-to-nonhuman primate (baboon) model is generally accepted as a preclinical experimental assessment for human clinical trials (Lambrigts, Sachs and Cooper 1998: 547). Therefore, the discomfort of using NHPs as an organ source does not preclude exploiting NHPs for human use. The story of using NHPs as an experimental model is differentiated from the story of using NHPs as an organ source. That is, this ‘humanisation’ of NHPs as a preclinical model operating in place of a human (or as a ‘pseudo human’), is contextually different to the discomfort of ‘humanising’ NHPs as an organ source. Thus, while phylogenetic similarity has been narrated as undesirable, it now becomes desirable as a preclinical ‘tool’ to ensure human safety. In the complexity of the comparative continuum, phylogenetics is also applied on virological and moral-ethical grounds to justify not using NHPs as an organ source. The differentiation of ‘they can stand in for us but they cannot be inside of us’, preserves and complicates the similarity/ dissimilarity dyad. In the comparative continuum, pigs as an organ source are narrated as ethically unproblematic. Unlike NHPs, pigs display marked differences to humans in appearance and behaviour. By lacking qualities reminiscent of humans, the story of pigs is one of dissimilarity. The consequence is pigs apparently share less cognitive and emotional capacities with humans. The intrinsic value of pigs is resultantly diminished. Sentience becomes redundant as the reduction of intrinsic value implies pigs do not suffer in XTP: “[…] pigs […] are not sentient animals” (Fung, Rao and Starzl 1997: 956). The ethics of animal use, however, is abstracted and framed from the biases of official science. If the animal product needs to be kept and bred in certain conditions that will meet the needs of the human, then human truths of species-being are used to frame and narrate animal well-being. With all these stories and truth-claims from official science, the final comparative continuum features a complex narrative of species similarity and dissimilarity. The story is by no means simplistic or straightforward. To summarise, pigs are portrayed as more desirable than NHPs as an organ source for humans, as based on an overall reduced degree of species difference. Through this construction by official science, the story of heterogeneous discourses becomes the truth (see Figure 7):

Page 15: Science Stories: Selecting the Source Animal for …eprints.qut.edu.au/5977/1/5977.pdf · justifications of animal selection and use, changes the invisible role of animals to one

14

Figure 7 – The Final Comparative Continuum (Pigs, Nonhuman Primates and Pigs/Nonhuman Primates)

Conclusion In choosing a source animal for XTP, official science attempts to create common understandings and reduce complexities by binding official scientific truth-claims. In such stories, we witness how humans become the measurement for all being. The comparative continuum, which reveals how official science selects a source animal for XTP, emphasises how the boundary distinctions between animals and humans are integral to the technology. In this fashion, NHPs and pigs are compared to humans on parameters defined and limited by official science. This assemblage of truths plays on complex constructions of species similarity and dissimilarity to justify pigs as the source animal of choice. In the process, the sentience and intelligence of animals are reduced or downplayed. Furthermore, by appealing on moral-ethical grounds, practical reasoning, and constructions of ‘humanisation’, official science blurs discursive boundaries. Consequently, science merges the social and the natural together to create scientific truths. Notably, the reverse comparison – humans to animals – is not possible due to ‘natural’ and ‘indisputable’ differentials in species value. What we also witnessing is how official science constructs itself as the bearer of privileged knowledge. On deciding which animal is the most suitable for XTP use, official science places itself in a position of trust. Furthermore, this decision should be viewed as right and just, as evidenced by complex negotiations of truth. Hence, the decision on animal source can only be made by those who have or are perceived to have specialist knowledge and insight. This means selecting an animal as based upon

Page 16: Science Stories: Selecting the Source Animal for …eprints.qut.edu.au/5977/1/5977.pdf · justifications of animal selection and use, changes the invisible role of animals to one

15

complex perceptions of similarities and dissimilarities cannot be made by the public. At the same time, official science cannot rely on science truth alone and must engage with the social. Mixing these discursive boundaries provides the opportunity for heterogeneous groupings to expand. The process serves to increase the complexity of choosing a source animal, rather than reduce it. The primary problem with using animals in XTP is “one of the parties being discussed does not participate in the debate, and we are restricted to evaluating Homo sapiens’ own moral sensibilities, principles, and values” (Daar and Phil 1997: 976, emphasis in original). Moreover, the desperation of patients does not empower medicine and clinicians to deliver solutions (ends) regardless of the method (means) (Arundell and McKenzie 1997: 66). Along with the exclusion of public voices, these truths indicate further narratives in the ethno-epistemic assemblage that demand exploring. For this reason, it feels somewhat premature to provide a conclusion. Indeed, potential further heterogeneous groupings only serve to raise questions and other potential narratives. Far from creating consistent truths and providing closure, official science’s narrative reveals further uncertainties and questions. These include, amongst others: what do the public think? How do they view animal use and animal value in XTP? How are their views (stories) different or similar to official science? Do the public perceive NHPs and pigs with a different truth? How do intermediaries function in these heterogeneous assemblages? As such, while science uses heterogeneous discourses to construct its truth-claims, it will be interesting to see how the public may – or may not – use the same tactics to construct their own truth-claims. Will these complement or differ from the stories told by official science? I plan to explore these questions in the future. References Allan, J.S. (1996) 'Xenotransplantation at a crossroads: Prevention versus progress',

Nature Medicine, 2 (1), Jan: 18-21. ___________. (1998) 'The Risk of Using Baboons as Transplant Donors: Exogenous

and Endogenous Viruses' in Fishman, J., Sachs, D. and Shaikh, R. (eds.) Xenotransplantation: Scientific Frontiers and Public Policy (Annals of the New York Academy of Sciences), 862, New York: The New York Academy of Sciences, 87-99.

Appel III, J.Z., Alwayn, I.P.J. and Cooper, D.K.C. (2000) 'Xenotransplantation: the challenges to current psychosocial attitudes', Progress in Transplantation, 10 (4), Dec: 217-225.

Arundell, M.A. and McKenzie, I.F.C. (1997) 'The acceptability of pig organ xenografts to patients awaiting a transplant', Xenotransplantation, 4: 62-66.

Bach, F.H. (1998) 'Xenotransplantation: Problems and Prospects', Annual Review of Medicine, 49: 301-310.

Bailey, L.L., Nehlsen-Cannarella, S.L., Concepcion, W. and Jolley, W.B. (1985) 'Baboon-to-Human Cardiac Xenotransplantation in a Neonate', Journal of the American Medical Association, 254 (23), Dec 20: 3321-3329.

Barnard, C.N., Wolpowitz, A. and Losman, J.G. (1977) 'Heterotopic Cardiac Transplantation with a Xenograft for Assistance of the Left Heart in Cardiogenic Shock after Cardiopulmonary Bypass', South African Medical Journal, 52, Dec 17: 1035-1038.

Boneva, R.S. and Folks, T.M. (2004) 'Xenotransplantation and risks of zoonotic infections', Annals of Medicine, 36 (7): 504-517.

Boneva, R.S., Folks, T.M. and Chapman, L.E. (2001) 'Infectious Disease Issues in Xenotransplantation', Clinical Microbiology Reviews, 14 (1): 1-14.

Page 17: Science Stories: Selecting the Source Animal for …eprints.qut.edu.au/5977/1/5977.pdf · justifications of animal selection and use, changes the invisible role of animals to one

16

Calne, R. (2005) 'Xenografting - the future of transplantation, and always will be?' Xenotransplantation, 12 (1), Jan: 5-6.

Chiche, L., Adam, R., Caillat-Zucman, S., Castaing, D., Bach, J.F. and Bismuth, H. (1993) 'Xenotransplantation: Baboons as Potential Liver Donors?' Transplantation, 55 (6): 1418-1421.

Cooper, D.K.C. and Lanza, R.P. (2000) Xeno: The promise of transplanting animal organs into humans, Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Cooper, D.K.C., Ye, Y., Rolf Jr., L.L. and Zuhdi, N. (1991) 'The Pig as Potential Organ Donor for Man' in Cooper, D.K.C., Kemp, E., Reemtsma, K. and White, D.J.G. (eds.) The transplantation of organs and tissues between species, 1st edition, Berlin: Springer, 481-500.

Daar, A.S. and Phil, D. (1997) 'Ethics of Xenotransplantation: Animal Issues, Consent, and Likely Transformation of Transplant Ethics', World Journal of Surgery, 21 (9), Nov/Dec: 975-982.

Dorling, A., Riesbeck, K., Warrens, A. and Lechler, R. (1997) 'Clinical xenotransplantation of solid organs', The Lancet, 349 (9055): 867-871.

Fishman, J.A. (1997) 'Xenosis and xenotransplantation: Addressing the infectious risks posed by an emerging technology', Kidney International, 51 (Suppl. 58): S41-S45.

Fishman, J.A. and Patience, C. (2004) 'Xenotransplantation: Infectious Risk Revisited', American Journal of Transplantation, 4: 1383-1390.

French, A.J., Greenstein, J.L., Loveland, B.E. and Mountford, P.S. (1998) 'Current and future prospects for xenotransplantation', Reproduction, Fertility and Development, 10 (8): 683-696.

Fung, J., Rao, A. and Starzl, T. (1997) 'Clinical Trials and Projected Future of Liver Xenotransplantation', World Journal of Surgery, 21 (9), Nov/Dec: 956-961.

Hammer, C., Linke, R., Wagner, F. and Diefenbeck, M. (1998) 'Organs from Animals for Man', International Archives of Allergy and Immunology, 116 (1): 5-21.

Hardy, J.D., Chavez, C.M., Kurrus, F.D., Neely, W.A., Eraslan, S., Turner, M.D., Fabian, L.W. and Labecki, T.D. (1964) 'Heart Transplantation in Man', Journal of the American Medical Association, 188 (13), Jun 29: 114-122.

Hitchcock, C.R., Kiser, J.C., Telander, R.L. and Seljeskog, E.L. (1964) 'Baboon Renal Grafts', Journal of the American Medical Association, 189 (12), Sept 21: 158-161.

Hoffman, T.J. (2000) 'Organ Donor Laws in the U.S. and the U.K.: The Need for Reform and the Promise of Xenotransplantation', Indiana International and Comparative Law Review, 10 (2): 339-386.

Irwin, A. and Michael, M. (2003) Science, Social Theory and Public Knowledge, Maidenhead: Open University Press.

Lambrigts, D., Sachs, D. and Cooper, D.K.C. (1998) 'Discordant Organ Xenotransplantation in Primates', Transplantation, 66 (5), Sept 15: 547-561.

Magre, S., Takeuchi, Y. and Bartosch, B. (2003) 'Xenotransplantation and pig endogenous retroviruses', Reviews in Medical Virology, 13: 311-329.

Morris, K. (1997) 'No early rejection of animal organs in UK', The Lancet, 349: 257. Palmer, S.R., Soulsby, L. and Simpson, D.I.H. (eds.) (1998) Zoonoses: Biology,

Clinical Practice, and Public Health Control, Oxford: Oxford University Press. Perico, N., Benigni, A. and Remuzzi, G. (2002) 'Xenotransplantation in the 21st

Century', Blood Purification, 20 (1): 45-54. Reemtsma, K., McCracken, B.H., Schlegel, J.U., Pearl, M.A., Pearce, C.W., DeWitt,

C.W., Smith, P.E., Hewitt, R.L., Flinner, R.L. and Creech, O. (1964) 'Renal Heterotransplantation in Man', Annals of Surgery, 160 (3), Sept: 384-410.

Sachs, D.H. (1994) 'The pig as a potential xenograft donor', Veterinary Immunology and Immunopathology, 43 (1-3): 185-191.

Samstein, B. and Platt, J.L. (2001) 'Physiologic and Immunologic Hurdles to Xenotransplantation', Journal of the American Society of Nephrology, 12 (1): 182-193.

Sherwood, L. (1993) Human Physiology: From Cells to Systems, 2nd edition, Minneapolis: West Publishing Company.

Page 18: Science Stories: Selecting the Source Animal for …eprints.qut.edu.au/5977/1/5977.pdf · justifications of animal selection and use, changes the invisible role of animals to one

17

Starzl, T.E., Fung, J., Tzakis, A., Todo, S., Demetris, A.J., Marino, I.R., Doyle, H., Zeevi, A., Warty, V., Michaels, M., Kusne, S., Rudert, W.A. and Trucco, M. (1993) 'Baboon-to-human liver transplantation', The Lancet, 341 (8837), Jan 9: 65-71.

Starzl, T.E., Marchioro, T.L., Peters, G.N., Kirkpatrick, C.H., Wilson, W.E.C., Porter, K.A., Rifkind, D., Ogden, D.A., Hitchcock, C.R. and Waddell, W.R. (1964) 'Renal Heterotransplantation from Baboon to Man: Experience with 6 Cases', Transplantation, 2 (6): 752-776.

Takeuchi, Y., Magre, S. and Patience, C. (2005) 'The potential hazards of xenotransplantation: an overview', Revue Scientifique et technique - Office international des épizooties, 24 (1): 323-334.

Tibell, A. and Lundgren, T. (2002) 'Xenotransplantation - Clinical Activities and Regulatory Development', Acta veterinaria Scandinavica, 99 (Suppl.): 19-23.

Voronoff, S. (1925) Rejuvenation by Grafting, (trans. by Fred F. Imianitoff), London: Allen and Unwin.

Weiss, R.A. (1998) 'Science, medicine, and the future: Xenotransplantation', British Medical Journal, 317, Oct 3: 931-934.

___________. (2004) 'Circe, Cassandra, and the Trojan Pigs: Xenotransplantation', Proceedings of the American Philosophical Association, 148 (3), Sept: 281-295.

Wolfe, N.D., Prosser, A.T., Carr, J.K., Tamoufe, U., Mpoudi-Ngole, E., Torimiro, J.N., LeBreton, M., McCutchan, F.E., Birx, D.L. and Burke, D.S. (2004) 'Exposure to Nonhuman Primates in Rural Cameroon', Emerging Infectious Diseases, 10 (12), Dec: 2094-2099.

Xenotransplantation Working Party. (2003) Animal-to-Human Transplantation Research: How Should Australian Proceed? , Canberra: Commonwealth of Australia.