Review 1 - ecology labfaculty.cs.tamu.edu/klappi/csce222-s12/review1.pdf · Review 1 Andreas...

39
Review 1 Andreas Klappenecker

Transcript of Review 1 - ecology labfaculty.cs.tamu.edu/klappi/csce222-s12/review1.pdf · Review 1 Andreas...

Page 1: Review 1 - ecology labfaculty.cs.tamu.edu/klappi/csce222-s12/review1.pdf · Review 1 Andreas Klappenecker. Summary Propositional Logic, Chapter 1 Predicate Logic, Chapter 1 Proofs,

Review 1Andreas Klappenecker

Page 2: Review 1 - ecology labfaculty.cs.tamu.edu/klappi/csce222-s12/review1.pdf · Review 1 Andreas Klappenecker. Summary Propositional Logic, Chapter 1 Predicate Logic, Chapter 1 Proofs,

Summary

Propositional Logic, Chapter 1

Predicate Logic, Chapter 1

Proofs, Chapter 1

Sets, Chapter 2

Functions, Chapter 2

Sequences and Sums, Chapter 2

Asymptotic Notations, Chapter 3

Time Complexity of Algorithms, Chapter 3

Page 3: Review 1 - ecology labfaculty.cs.tamu.edu/klappi/csce222-s12/review1.pdf · Review 1 Andreas Klappenecker. Summary Propositional Logic, Chapter 1 Predicate Logic, Chapter 1 Proofs,

Strategy for Exam Preparation

- Start studying now!

- Make sure you know your definitions!

- Do odd numbered exercises

(Solutions are in the Appendix)

- Review your quizzes

- Review your homework

Page 4: Review 1 - ecology labfaculty.cs.tamu.edu/klappi/csce222-s12/review1.pdf · Review 1 Andreas Klappenecker. Summary Propositional Logic, Chapter 1 Predicate Logic, Chapter 1 Proofs,

Logical Connectives - Summary

Let B={t,f}. Assign to each connective a function M: B->B

that determines its semantics. 4 The Semantics of Propositional Logic

Let B = {t, f} denote the set of truth values, where t and f represent trueand false, respectively. We associate to the logical connective ¬ the functionM¬ : B→ B given by

P M¬(P )f tt f

Thus, M¬(P ) is true if and only if P is false. This justifies the name negationfor this connective. The graph of the function M¬ given above is called thetruth table of the negation connective. Similarly, we associate to a connectiveX in the set {∧,∨,⊕,→,↔} a binary function MX : B × B → B. The truthtables of these connectives are as follows:

P Q M∧(P, Q) M∨(P,Q) M⊕(P, Q) M→(P, Q) M↔(P, Q)f f f f f t tf t f t t t ft f f t t f ft t t t f t t

You should very carefully inspect this table! It is critical that you memorizeand fully understand the meaning of each connective.

The semantics of the language Prop is given by assigning truth values toeach proposition in Prop. Clearly, an arbitrary assignment of truth values isnot interesting, since we would like everything to be consistent with the meaningof the connectives that we have just learned. For example, if the propositions aand b have been assigned the value t, then it is reasonable to insist that a ∧ bbe assigned the value t as well. Therefore, we will introduce the concept of avaluation, which models the semantics of Prop in an appropriate way.

A valuation v : Prop→ B is a function that assigns a truth value to eachproposition in Prop such thatV1. v�¬a� = M¬(v�a�)V2. v�(a ∧ b)� = M∧(v�a� , v�b�)V3. v�(a ∨ b)� = M∨(v�a� , v�b�)V4. v�(a⊕ b)� = M⊕(v�a� , v�b�)V5. v�(a→ b)� = M→(v�a� , v�b�)V6. v�(a↔ b)� = M↔(v�a� , v�b�)holds for all propositions a and b in Prop. The properties V1–V6 ensurethat the valuation respects the meaning of the connectives. We can restrict avaluation v to a subset of the set of proposition. If A and B are subsets ofProp such that A ⊆ B, and vA : A → B and vB : B → B are valuations, thenvB is called an extension of the valuation vA if and only if vB coincides withvA when restricted to A.

The consistency conditions V1-V6 are quite stringent, as the next theoremshows.

5

4 The Semantics of Propositional Logic

Let B = {t, f} denote the set of truth values, where t and f represent trueand false, respectively. We associate to the logical connective ¬ the functionM¬ : B→ B given by

P M¬(P )f tt f

Thus, M¬(P ) is true if and only if P is false. This justifies the name negationfor this connective. The graph of the function M¬ given above is called thetruth table of the negation connective. Similarly, we associate to a connectiveX in the set {∧,∨,⊕,→,↔} a binary function MX : B × B → B. The truthtables of these connectives are as follows:

P Q M∧(P, Q) M∨(P,Q) M⊕(P, Q) M→(P, Q) M↔(P, Q)f f f f f t tf t f t t t ft f f t t f ft t t t f t t

You should very carefully inspect this table! It is critical that you memorizeand fully understand the meaning of each connective.

The semantics of the language Prop is given by assigning truth values toeach proposition in Prop. Clearly, an arbitrary assignment of truth values isnot interesting, since we would like everything to be consistent with the meaningof the connectives that we have just learned. For example, if the propositions aand b have been assigned the value t, then it is reasonable to insist that a ∧ bbe assigned the value t as well. Therefore, we will introduce the concept of avaluation, which models the semantics of Prop in an appropriate way.

A valuation v : Prop→ B is a function that assigns a truth value to eachproposition in Prop such thatV1. v�¬a� = M¬(v�a�)V2. v�(a ∧ b)� = M∧(v�a� , v�b�)V3. v�(a ∨ b)� = M∨(v�a� , v�b�)V4. v�(a⊕ b)� = M⊕(v�a� , v�b�)V5. v�(a→ b)� = M→(v�a� , v�b�)V6. v�(a↔ b)� = M↔(v�a� , v�b�)holds for all propositions a and b in Prop. The properties V1–V6 ensurethat the valuation respects the meaning of the connectives. We can restrict avaluation v to a subset of the set of proposition. If A and B are subsets ofProp such that A ⊆ B, and vA : A → B and vB : B → B are valuations, thenvB is called an extension of the valuation vA if and only if vB coincides withvA when restricted to A.

The consistency conditions V1-V6 are quite stringent, as the next theoremshows.

5

Page 5: Review 1 - ecology labfaculty.cs.tamu.edu/klappi/csce222-s12/review1.pdf · Review 1 Andreas Klappenecker. Summary Propositional Logic, Chapter 1 Predicate Logic, Chapter 1 Proofs,

Alternative Summary

The immediate successors of a in the formation tree are labeled by subformulasof a of degree less than n; hence, these successors have a valuation assigned.Therefore, v has a unique extension to a using the consistency rules V1–V6.We can conclude that v is a valuation on the set of all proposition of degree nextending v0. Therefore, the claim follows by induction.

The key reason that the previous argument by induction works is that theformation tree is unique. If there would exist several different trees for a singleformula, then such a recursive definition of a valuation would be ambiguous,and the definition of the valuation v might not be well-defined.Remark. Perhaps you would like to see a more direct argument based on thegrammar rather than on the degree of the formulas. One can use structuralinduction, a generalization of induction to so-called freely generated recursivelydefined sets. For a proof of the existence of valuations using structural induc-tion, see [J.H. Gallier, Logic for Computer Science – Foundations of AutomaticTheorem Proving, John Wiley & Sons, 1987].

In this section, we have been a little bit pedantic by distinguishing the purelysyntactical form of a proposition such as (a → b) from its meaning M→(a, b).Of course, it is a good idea to clearly distinguish between syntax and semanticsuntil the semantics of the connectives is clearly understood. From now on, wewill abuse notation and freely interpret (a→ b) as the function M→(a, b).

Summary. Informally, we can summarize the meaning of the connectives asfollows:1) The and connective (a ∧ b) is true if and only if both a and b are true.2) The or connective (a ∨ b) is true if and only if at least one of a, b is true.3) The exclusive or (a⊕ b) is true if and only if precisely one of a, b is true.4) The implication (a → b) is false if and only if the premise a is true and the

conclusion b is false.5) The biconditional connective (a ↔ b) is true if and only if the truth values

of a and b are the same.An interpretation of a subset S of Prop is an assignment of truth values to allvariables that occur in the propositions contained in S. We showed that thereexist a unique valuation extending an interpretation of all propositions.

5 Tautologies and Satisfiability

In the previous two sections, we have introduced the language of propositionallogic and gave the propositions a meaning using valuations. In this section, wewill see propositional logic “at work”.

A proposition p is called a tautology if and only if v�p� = t for all valuationsv on Prop.

A proposition p is a tautology if and only if p evaluates to t under eachinterpretation of the variables in p. If the proposition p contains n variables,then we have to check all 2n possible interpretations of p.

7

Page 6: Review 1 - ecology labfaculty.cs.tamu.edu/klappi/csce222-s12/review1.pdf · Review 1 Andreas Klappenecker. Summary Propositional Logic, Chapter 1 Predicate Logic, Chapter 1 Proofs,

Conditional

Perhaps the most important logical connective is the conditional, also known as implication:

p -> q

The statement asserts that q holds on the condition that p holds. We call p the hypothesis or premise, and q the conclusion or consequence. Typical usage in proofs:

“If p, then q”; “p implies q”; “q only if p”; “q when p”; “q follows from p”

“p is sufficient for q”; “a sufficient condition for q is p”; “a necessary condition for p is q”; “q is necessary for p”

Page 7: Review 1 - ecology labfaculty.cs.tamu.edu/klappi/csce222-s12/review1.pdf · Review 1 Andreas Klappenecker. Summary Propositional Logic, Chapter 1 Predicate Logic, Chapter 1 Proofs,

Predicates

A function P from a set D to the set Prop of propositions is called a predicate. The set D is called the domain of P. E: Z->{t,f} with E(x)= x is an even integer, E(6) is true;

O: Z->{t,f} with O(x)= x is an odd integer; O(6) is false.

Page 8: Review 1 - ecology labfaculty.cs.tamu.edu/klappi/csce222-s12/review1.pdf · Review 1 Andreas Klappenecker. Summary Propositional Logic, Chapter 1 Predicate Logic, Chapter 1 Proofs,

Logical Equivalence

Two statements involving quantifiers and predicates are logically equivalent if and only if they have the same truth values no matter which predicates are substituted into these statements and which domain is used.

We write A ≡ B for logically equivalent A and B.

You use logical equivalences to derive more convenient forms statements.

Example: De Morgan’s laws.

Page 9: Review 1 - ecology labfaculty.cs.tamu.edu/klappi/csce222-s12/review1.pdf · Review 1 Andreas Klappenecker. Summary Propositional Logic, Chapter 1 Predicate Logic, Chapter 1 Proofs,

De Morgan’s Laws

¬∀xP (x) ≡ ∃x¬P (x)

¬∃xP (x) ≡ ∀x¬P (x)

¬(p ∧ q) ≡ ¬p ∨ ¬q

¬(p ∨ q) ≡ ¬p ∧ ¬q

Page 10: Review 1 - ecology labfaculty.cs.tamu.edu/klappi/csce222-s12/review1.pdf · Review 1 Andreas Klappenecker. Summary Propositional Logic, Chapter 1 Predicate Logic, Chapter 1 Proofs,

Valid Arguments

An argument in propositional logic is a sequence of propositions that end with a proposition called conclusion. The argument is called valid if the conclusion follows from the preceding statements (called premises).

In other words, in a valid argument it is impossible that all premises are true but the conclusion is false.

Page 11: Review 1 - ecology labfaculty.cs.tamu.edu/klappi/csce222-s12/review1.pdf · Review 1 Andreas Klappenecker. Summary Propositional Logic, Chapter 1 Predicate Logic, Chapter 1 Proofs,

Modus Ponens

The tautology (p ⋀ (p->q)) -> q is the basis for the rule of inference called “modus ponens”.

p

p -> q

-------

∴ q

Page 12: Review 1 - ecology labfaculty.cs.tamu.edu/klappi/csce222-s12/review1.pdf · Review 1 Andreas Klappenecker. Summary Propositional Logic, Chapter 1 Predicate Logic, Chapter 1 Proofs,

Modus Tollens

¬q

p -> q

------

∴¬ p

“The University will not close on Wednesday.”

“If it snows on Wednesday, then the University will close.”

Therefore, “It will not snow on Wednesday”

Page 13: Review 1 - ecology labfaculty.cs.tamu.edu/klappi/csce222-s12/review1.pdf · Review 1 Andreas Klappenecker. Summary Propositional Logic, Chapter 1 Predicate Logic, Chapter 1 Proofs,

Simplification

p ⋀ q

------

p

Page 14: Review 1 - ecology labfaculty.cs.tamu.edu/klappi/csce222-s12/review1.pdf · Review 1 Andreas Klappenecker. Summary Propositional Logic, Chapter 1 Predicate Logic, Chapter 1 Proofs,

Formal Argument

¬p ∧ qr → p¬r → ss → t

∴ t

Argument

1) ¬p ∧ q Hypothesis

2) ¬p Simplification of 1)

3) r → p Hypothesis

4) ¬r Modus tollens using 2) and 3)

5) ¬r → s Hyposthesis

6) s Modus ponens using 4), 5)

7) s → t Hypothesis

8) t Modus ponens using 6), 7)

Page 15: Review 1 - ecology labfaculty.cs.tamu.edu/klappi/csce222-s12/review1.pdf · Review 1 Andreas Klappenecker. Summary Propositional Logic, Chapter 1 Predicate Logic, Chapter 1 Proofs,

Sets, Functions, Summations

Page 16: Review 1 - ecology labfaculty.cs.tamu.edu/klappi/csce222-s12/review1.pdf · Review 1 Andreas Klappenecker. Summary Propositional Logic, Chapter 1 Predicate Logic, Chapter 1 Proofs,

Set Builder Notation

The set builder notation describes all elements as a subset of a set having a certain property.

Q = { p/q ∈ R | p ∈ Z, q ∈ Z, and q≠ 0 }

[a,b] = { x ∈ R | a <= x <= b }

[a,b) = { x ∈ R | a <= x < b }

(a,b] = { x ∈ R | a < x <= b }

(a,b) = { x ∈ R | a < x < b }

16

Page 17: Review 1 - ecology labfaculty.cs.tamu.edu/klappi/csce222-s12/review1.pdf · Review 1 Andreas Klappenecker. Summary Propositional Logic, Chapter 1 Predicate Logic, Chapter 1 Proofs,

Equality of Sets

Two sets A and B are called equal if and only if they have the same elements.

A = B if and only if ∀x(x ∈ A ⟷ x ∈ B)

[To prove A=B, it is sufficient to show that both ∀x(x ∈ A ⟶ x ∈ B) and ∀x(x ∈ B ⟶ x ∈ A) hold. Why? ]

17

Page 18: Review 1 - ecology labfaculty.cs.tamu.edu/klappi/csce222-s12/review1.pdf · Review 1 Andreas Klappenecker. Summary Propositional Logic, Chapter 1 Predicate Logic, Chapter 1 Proofs,

Subset

A set A is a subset of B, written A ⊆ B, if and only if every element of A is an element of B.

Thus, A ⊆ B if and only if ∀x(x ∈ A ⟶ x ∈ B)

18

Page 19: Review 1 - ecology labfaculty.cs.tamu.edu/klappi/csce222-s12/review1.pdf · Review 1 Andreas Klappenecker. Summary Propositional Logic, Chapter 1 Predicate Logic, Chapter 1 Proofs,

Cardinality of a Set

Let S be a set with a finite number of elements. We say that the set has cardinality n if and only if S contains n elements. We write |S| to denote the cardinality of the set.

For example, |∅| = 0.

19

Page 20: Review 1 - ecology labfaculty.cs.tamu.edu/klappi/csce222-s12/review1.pdf · Review 1 Andreas Klappenecker. Summary Propositional Logic, Chapter 1 Predicate Logic, Chapter 1 Proofs,

Power Sets

Given a set S, the power set P(S) of S is the set of all subsets of S.

Example: P( {1} ) = { ∅, {1} }

P( {1,2} ) = { ∅, {1}, {2}, {1,2} }

P(∅) = { ∅ } since every set contains the empty set as a subset, even the empty set.

P({∅}) = {∅, {∅}}.

20

Page 21: Review 1 - ecology labfaculty.cs.tamu.edu/klappi/csce222-s12/review1.pdf · Review 1 Andreas Klappenecker. Summary Propositional Logic, Chapter 1 Predicate Logic, Chapter 1 Proofs,

Cartesian Products

Let A and B be sets. The Cartesian product of A and B, denote AxB, is the set of all pairs (a,b) with a ∈A and b∈B.

AxB = { (a,b) | a ∈A ⋀ b∈B }

21

Page 22: Review 1 - ecology labfaculty.cs.tamu.edu/klappi/csce222-s12/review1.pdf · Review 1 Andreas Klappenecker. Summary Propositional Logic, Chapter 1 Predicate Logic, Chapter 1 Proofs,

Set Operations

Give two sets A and B. You should know

- the union of A and B

- the intersection of A and B

- the set difference between A and B

- the complement of A

22

Page 23: Review 1 - ecology labfaculty.cs.tamu.edu/klappi/csce222-s12/review1.pdf · Review 1 Andreas Klappenecker. Summary Propositional Logic, Chapter 1 Predicate Logic, Chapter 1 Proofs,

De Morgan Laws

A ∩B = A ∪B

Proof :

A ∩B = {x | x �∈ A ∩B} by definition of complement

= {x | ¬(x ∈ A ∩B)}= {x | ¬(x ∈ A ∧ x ∈ B)} by definition of intersection

= {x | ¬(x ∈ A) ∨ ¬(x ∈ B)} de Morgan’s law from logic

= {x | (x �∈ A) ∨ (x �∈ B)} by definition of �∈= {x | x ∈ A ∨ x ∈ B} by definition of complement

= {x | x ∈ A ∪B} by definition of union

= A ∪B

23

Page 24: Review 1 - ecology labfaculty.cs.tamu.edu/klappi/csce222-s12/review1.pdf · Review 1 Andreas Klappenecker. Summary Propositional Logic, Chapter 1 Predicate Logic, Chapter 1 Proofs,

Terminology

Let f: A -> B be a function.

We call

- A the domain of f and

- B the codomain of f.

The range of f is the set

f(A) = { f(a) | a in A }

24

Page 25: Review 1 - ecology labfaculty.cs.tamu.edu/klappi/csce222-s12/review1.pdf · Review 1 Andreas Klappenecker. Summary Propositional Logic, Chapter 1 Predicate Logic, Chapter 1 Proofs,

Functions

Let A and B be sets. Consider a function f: A-> B.

- When is f surjective?

- When is f injective?

- When is f bijective?

25

Page 26: Review 1 - ecology labfaculty.cs.tamu.edu/klappi/csce222-s12/review1.pdf · Review 1 Andreas Klappenecker. Summary Propositional Logic, Chapter 1 Predicate Logic, Chapter 1 Proofs,

Floor Function

The floor function ⎣⎦: R -> Z assigns to a real

number x the largest integer <= x.

⎣3.2⎦= 3

⎣-3.2⎦= -4

⎣3.99⎦= 3

26

Page 27: Review 1 - ecology labfaculty.cs.tamu.edu/klappi/csce222-s12/review1.pdf · Review 1 Andreas Klappenecker. Summary Propositional Logic, Chapter 1 Predicate Logic, Chapter 1 Proofs,

Ceiling Function

The ceiling function ⎡⎤: R -> Z assigns to a real

number x the smallest integer >= x.

⎡3.2⎤= 4

⎡-3.2⎤= -3

⎡0.5⎤= 1

27

Page 28: Review 1 - ecology labfaculty.cs.tamu.edu/klappi/csce222-s12/review1.pdf · Review 1 Andreas Klappenecker. Summary Propositional Logic, Chapter 1 Predicate Logic, Chapter 1 Proofs,

Basic Facts

We have⎣x⎦= n if and only if n <= x < n+1.

We have⎡x⎤=n if and only if n-1< x <= n.

We have⎣x⎦= n if and only if x-1 < n <= x.

We have⎡x⎤=n if and only if x<= n < x+1.

28

Page 29: Review 1 - ecology labfaculty.cs.tamu.edu/klappi/csce222-s12/review1.pdf · Review 1 Andreas Klappenecker. Summary Propositional Logic, Chapter 1 Predicate Logic, Chapter 1 Proofs,

Example

29

Prove or disprove:

��

�x�� = �√x�

Page 30: Review 1 - ecology labfaculty.cs.tamu.edu/klappi/csce222-s12/review1.pdf · Review 1 Andreas Klappenecker. Summary Propositional Logic, Chapter 1 Predicate Logic, Chapter 1 Proofs,

Example 3

30

Let m = ���x��

Hence, m ≤��x� < m+ 1

Thus, m2 ≤ �x� < (m+ 1)2

It follows that m2 ≤ x < (m+ 1)2

Therefore, m ≤√x < m+ 1

Thus, we can conclude that m = �√x�

This proves our claim.

Page 31: Review 1 - ecology labfaculty.cs.tamu.edu/klappi/csce222-s12/review1.pdf · Review 1 Andreas Klappenecker. Summary Propositional Logic, Chapter 1 Predicate Logic, Chapter 1 Proofs,

Geometric SeriesIf a and r �= 0 are real numbers, then

n�

j=0

arj =

�arn+1−a

r−1 if r �= 1

(n+ 1)a if r = 1

Proof:The case r = 1 holds, since arj = a for each of then+ 1 terms of the sum.

The case r �= 1 holds, since

(r − 1)�n

j=0 arj =

n�

j=0

arj+1 −n�

j=0

arj

=n+1�

j=1

arj −n�

j=0

arj

= arn+1 − aand dividing by (r − 1) yields the claim.

Extremely useful!

Page 32: Review 1 - ecology labfaculty.cs.tamu.edu/klappi/csce222-s12/review1.pdf · Review 1 Andreas Klappenecker. Summary Propositional Logic, Chapter 1 Predicate Logic, Chapter 1 Proofs,

Sum of First n Positive Integers .

For all n ≥ 1, we haven�

k=1

k = n(n+ 1)/2

We prove this by induction.Basis step: For n = 1, we have

1�

k=1

k = 1 = 1(1 + 1)/2.

Extremely useful!

Page 33: Review 1 - ecology labfaculty.cs.tamu.edu/klappi/csce222-s12/review1.pdf · Review 1 Andreas Klappenecker. Summary Propositional Logic, Chapter 1 Predicate Logic, Chapter 1 Proofs,

Sum of the First n Positive Integers

Induction Hypothesis: We assume that the claim

holds for n− 1.

Induction Step: Assuming the Induction Hypoth-

esis, we will show that the claim holds for n.

�nk=1 k = n+

�n−1k=1 k

= 2n/2 + (n− 1)n/2 by Induction Hypothesis

=2n+n2−n

2

=n(n+1)

2

Therefore, the claim follows by induction on n.

Page 34: Review 1 - ecology labfaculty.cs.tamu.edu/klappi/csce222-s12/review1.pdf · Review 1 Andreas Klappenecker. Summary Propositional Logic, Chapter 1 Predicate Logic, Chapter 1 Proofs,

Infinite Geometric Series

Let x be a real number such that |x| < 1. Then

∞�

k=0

xk =1

1− x.

Page 35: Review 1 - ecology labfaculty.cs.tamu.edu/klappi/csce222-s12/review1.pdf · Review 1 Andreas Klappenecker. Summary Propositional Logic, Chapter 1 Predicate Logic, Chapter 1 Proofs,

Infinite Geometric Series

Since the sum of a geometric series satisfies

n�

k=0

xk =xn+1 − 1

x− 1,

we have

∞�

k=0

xk = limn→∞

n�

k=0

xk = limn→∞

xn+1 − 1

x− 1

As limn→∞ xn+1 = 0, we get

∞�

k=0

xk =−1

x− 1=

1

1− x.

Page 36: Review 1 - ecology labfaculty.cs.tamu.edu/klappi/csce222-s12/review1.pdf · Review 1 Andreas Klappenecker. Summary Propositional Logic, Chapter 1 Predicate Logic, Chapter 1 Proofs,

Asymptotic Notations

Page 37: Review 1 - ecology labfaculty.cs.tamu.edu/klappi/csce222-s12/review1.pdf · Review 1 Andreas Klappenecker. Summary Propositional Logic, Chapter 1 Predicate Logic, Chapter 1 Proofs,

Big Oh Notation

Let f,g: N -> R be functions from the natural numbers to the set of real numbers.

We write f ∈ O(g) if and only if there exists some real number n0 and a positive real constant U such that |f(n)| <= U|g(n)| for all n satisfying n >= n0

Page 38: Review 1 - ecology labfaculty.cs.tamu.edu/klappi/csce222-s12/review1.pdf · Review 1 Andreas Klappenecker. Summary Propositional Logic, Chapter 1 Predicate Logic, Chapter 1 Proofs,

Big Ω

We define f(n) = Ω(g(n)) if and only if there exists a constant L and a natural number n0 such that

L |g(n)| <= |f(n)|

holds for all n >= n0.

In other words, f(n) = Ω(g(n)) if and only if g(n) = O(f(n)).

Page 39: Review 1 - ecology labfaculty.cs.tamu.edu/klappi/csce222-s12/review1.pdf · Review 1 Andreas Klappenecker. Summary Propositional Logic, Chapter 1 Predicate Logic, Chapter 1 Proofs,

Big Θ

We define f(n) = Θ(g(n)) if and only if there exist constants L and U and a natural number n0 such that

L|g(n)| <= |f(n)| <= U|g(n)|

holds for all n >= n0.

In other words, f(n) = Θ(g(n)) if and only if

f(n) = Ω(g(n)) and f(n) = O(g(n)).