Retórica a Herenio. Períodos - GOTOFF, H. C. (1973)

download Retórica a Herenio. Períodos - GOTOFF, H. C. (1973)

of 8

Transcript of Retórica a Herenio. Períodos - GOTOFF, H. C. (1973)

  • 8/10/2019 Retrica a Herenio. Perodos - GOTOFF, H. C. (1973)

    1/8

    Department of the Classics Harvard University

    The Concept of Periodicity in the Ad HerenniumAuthor(s): H. C. GotoffSource: Harvard Studies in Classical Philology, Vol. 77 (1973), pp. 217-223Published by: Department of the Classics, Harvard UniversityStable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/311070.

    Accessed: 02/09/2014 05:55

    Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at.http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

    .JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range ofcontent in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms

    of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].

    .

    Department of the Classics, Harvard Universityis collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend

    access toHarvard Studies in Classical Philology.

    http://www.jstor.org

    This content downloaded from 212.128.182.231 on Tue, 2 Sep 2014 05:55:47 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=dchuhttp://www.jstor.org/stable/311070?origin=JSTOR-pdfhttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/stable/311070?origin=JSTOR-pdfhttp://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=dchu
  • 8/10/2019 Retrica a Herenio. Perodos - GOTOFF, H. C. (1973)

    2/8

    THE

    CONCEPT OF PERIODICITY

    IN

    THE

    AD

    HERENNIUM

    H. C. GOTOFF

    MODERN

    scholars

    and

    critics seem

    to have

    a

    clear

    and

    fairly

    consistent

    notion of what

    periodic style

    entails.' It is a

    complex

    sentence in which both sense and syntax are held in suspension until

    the end

    of

    the construction when

    they

    are

    simultaneously

    resolved.

    The

    idea that

    the

    period

    is

    complete

    in

    itself and at

    every

    point

    anticipates

    its

    own

    conclusion

    goes

    back to

    Aristotle,

    Rhet.

    3.9.3-4: h

    '

    S'

    7rrEpd'ov

    AE'etw

    EJXOvUaT'

    cPX7p)

    Kal

    -rEAEUcvV aa'77rV

    KaO'

    5r7')i

    Kat

    1dEyaJos

    EVUOrVVO'7TT...V

    Sct SE'

    7r'v 7TEoSOV

    Kat

    a%

    (Lco coa

    He

    makes

    his case for this

    very

    strongly

    by

    his criticism of

    the

    articula-

    tion of

    the

    opening

    lines

    of

    Euripides'

    Meleager.2

    His

    point

    is

    that

    1

    See

    J.

    E.

    Sandys,

    M. Tulli

    Ciceronis ad M. Brutum

    Orator

    (Cambridge

    I885) 217, n. to 204, and G. M. Z. Grube, Thrasymachus, Theophrastus,

    and

    Dionysius

    AJP

    73

    (I952)

    253f

    n.

    4,

    among

    others

    for

    the articulation

    of

    the

    general

    view.

    The

    difficulties created

    by

    Aristotle

    are

    discussed

    by

    E. M.

    Cope,

    Introduction to

    the

    Rhetoric

    of

    Aristotle

    (London 1867)

    3o6f;

    J. Zehetmeier,

    Die

    Periodenlehre

    des

    Aristoteles,

    Philologus

    85

    (I930)

    192-208,

    255-284,

    414-436;

    W.

    Schmid,

    Ueber die

    Klassische

    Theorie

    und

    Praxis des

    Antiken

    Prosarhythmus,

    Hermes

    (Einzelschrift

    i2)

    1959,

    I12-I

    30;

    and L.

    P.

    Wilkinson,

    Golden

    Latin

    Artistry

    (Cambridge

    I963)

    167-170,

    among

    others. No

    one

    study

    has been

    definitive;

    various scholars have made

    suggestive

    contributions,

    such

    as

    Zehetmeier's

    relating

    periodicity

    to

    prose-rhythm

    under Aristotle's

    aesthetic

    heading

    of

    limit,

    or

    Schmid's

    understanding,

    however

    imperfect

    (see

    Wilkinson, ibid., I69n), of the racetrack metaphor. E. Norden, Antike Kunst-

    prosa

    (Leipzig; 5th

    ed.,

    Darmstadt

    1958)

    I

    42,

    and

    n.,

    dealing

    particularly

    with

    the ancient

    concept,

    maintained

    that

    periodicity

    is

    indivisible from

    prose-

    rhythm.

    In this

    he is followed

    by

    W. Schmid

    (ibid.),

    among

    others,

    and

    opposed

    by

    Grube

    (ibid.)

    254

    and

    n.

    There

    is need for a

    study

    of

    how and

    when the

    concept

    of

    periodicity

    developed

    from the

    more restricted

    ancient

    technique

    to

    what

    scholars from the

    Renaissance

    on

    picture

    it to

    be.

    I wish

    to

    thank Professor

    G.

    Kennedy

    for his

    reference

    to

    H.

    Lausberg,

    Handbuch

    der

    literarischen

    Rhetorik

    (Munich

    1962)

    vol.

    I,

    where Ad

    Herennium

    4.27

    is

    discussed

    in

    sections

    943

    and

    945.

    It

    seems to

    me that in

    returning

    periodos

    to a

    purely bipartite,

    Aristotelian

    sense,

    Lausberg,

    in

    section

    924f,

    ignores another meaning of the word and another kind of rhetorical sentence

    structure.

    2

    Aristotle

    quotes

    the first

    line

    only

    and

    attributes

    it

    to

    Sophocles.

    The

    scholiast

    to

    Ar.

    Frogs 1269,

    assigns

    it

    to the

    opening

    of

    the

    Meleager

    of

    Euripides.

    The

    This content downloaded from 212.128.182.231 on Tue, 2 Sep 2014 05:55:47 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/10/2019 Retrica a Herenio. Perodos - GOTOFF, H. C. (1973)

    3/8

    218

    H. C.

    Gotoff

    there

    is

    enough grammatical

    material

    in the first trimeter to be

    rendered

    as a

    complete

    unit,

    although

    the

    meaning

    would be distorted

    because

    the thought in fact continues grammatically into the next line. This is

    not the

    only

    somewhat

    surprising

    limitation of Aristotle's idea

    of

    a

    period.

    In his further

    remarks,

    he makes

    it

    quite

    clear,

    although

    scholars

    have not

    always

    acknowledged

    it,

    that

    by

    periodos

    he

    conceived

    of

    a

    unit of

    sentence

    structure far more restricted

    than

    the

    modern

    notion

    envisions.

    The definition he

    proposes

    can

    never

    have included

    the

    sophisticated

    architectonics

    of

    his

    contemporary

    Demosthenes,

    much

    less the writer

    whose name

    is

    most

    closely

    associated

    with the

    periodic

    style,

    Cicero.

    G. Kennedy maintained that, in considering periodos, Aristotle had

    in

    mind first and foremost the

    balanced, antithetical,

    essentially bipartite

    sentences that

    mark

    the

    style

    of

    Gorgias

    and

    later

    of

    Isocrates.3

    Aristotle

    is not consistent even

    in

    insisting

    that

    a

    period

    be

    bipartite,

    for he

    allows

    for

    a

    simple period

    -

    presumably,

    a

    sentence

    without subordina-

    tion

    in

    which sense

    and

    simple grammar

    are

    not

    resolved

    until the

    last

    word.4

    Nevertheless,

    there

    can

    be little

    doubt,

    pace

    Grube,5

    that

    when

    talking

    about

    complex periods,

    Aristotle

    understood

    the

    structure

    to

    be

    bipartite,

    i.e.

    composed

    of two cola

    (Rhet.

    3.9.5): KWAhov

    '

    a7rt

    Td

    T'rEpov

    d0PLov

    ra7;r.

    This is not the place to try to reach a

    definition of colon

    that

    would

    satisfy every

    use

    of

    it

    by

    Greek

    and

    Latin

    writers;

    for,

    like

    many

    of the words we

    are

    pleased

    to think

    of

    second

    verse is

    found

    in

    several

    sources,

    among

    them Dem. De

    Eloc.

    58.

    Aristotle's

    objection

    is

    too

    severe;

    the

    standard

    applied

    here would

    render

    much of

    classical

    composition

    open

    to the

    charge

    of

    poor

    and

    confusing

    con-

    struction. Demetrius cites the

    lines to how

    actors'

    interjections

    can miscast

    the

    emphasis

    of a

    statement. The lines as

    they appear

    in

    Demetrius,

    with

    the

    added,

    artificial

    pause

    created

    by

    the

    expletives,

    argue

    Aristotle's

    point

    ratherbetter than the single line he himself cites:

    KaAVL)sv~Lev

    E

    yaYac

    EAo7TELcX

    OoVdo'

    EP

    aVT7TrdpO~Lot 7TrES ' E4ova' 4Et?VLova

    at,

    at-

    3

    George

    Kennedy,

    Aristotleon the

    Period,

    HSCP

    63

    (1958) 283ff.

    4

    Presumably any

    sentence without

    subordinationthat

    suspends

    the verb

    until the end

    would

    come under the

    heading

    of

    eA*

    eptloSos.

    Attempts

    to

    reconcile

    the

    simple period

    with the

    statement that the

    period

    consists of

    two

    cola

    have

    not,

    unsurprisingly,

    been

    successful.

    '

    Grube,

    A

    Greek

    Critic:

    Demetrius

    Toronto

    1961)

    35

    n.

    41,

    suggests

    the

    possibilitythat

    7ra-vldh

    oes not referbackto replo8o0s,ut ratherto the trimeter

    quoted

    from

    the

    Meleager.

    Demetrius

    34

    did

    not so

    understand

    Aristotle,

    nor

    would this

    rendering

    make

    sense.

    This content downloaded from 212.128.182.231 on Tue, 2 Sep 2014 05:55:47 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/10/2019 Retrica a Herenio. Perodos - GOTOFF, H. C. (1973)

    4/8

    Periodicity

    in the Ad Herennium

    219

    as

    technical

    terms

    in Classical

    treatises,

    its use

    by

    the ancient

    authorities

    was not consistent.6

    It seems to

    me that we

    can

    extract more out

    of

    Aristotle's definition without doing violence to his intent or to the

    Greek,

    if

    we

    allow colon

    to

    refer

    to

    a

    unit

    larger

    than a clause

    in

    the

    modern sense

    of the

    word. We

    think of

    a

    clause

    as a

    single

    verbal

    notion

    containing

    a

    finite

    verb,

    an

    accusative-and-infinitive

    construc-

    tion,

    or the like. What

    Aristotle

    was

    referring

    to,

    I

    think,

    was a

    sentence

    the structure of which

    could be reduced

    to a

    pair

    of

    discrete

    units,

    e.g. protasis-apodosis,

    relative clause-main clause

    (with

    an

    explicit

    antecedent

    if

    the

    main clause should

    precede),

    when

    -clause-

    then -

    clause, etc.,

    whether

    or

    not

    either or

    both units contained

    a

    subordi-

    nate element. Each of these discrete units was to Aristotle a colon.

    This

    view,

    perhaps,

    makes sense of

    the

    metaphor

    of the race

    track

    in

    which the runner would

    start

    out,

    say,

    on a

    dorcEp-clause,

    round

    the

    post,

    and

    return

    with

    the

    0'vrwos-clause.

    Thus,

    even

    a

    highly

    complex

    sentence

    like

    Dem.

    Aristocr.

    99,

    quoted

    by

    Demetr.

    De

    Eloc.

    31:

    WUor7T

    yyap EZ

    7L6-KEWCWV

    E(XAW,

    OvTows

    X

    cr

    vfv

    acogS,

    'AAosog0

    YPwEL...

    or

    the

    several

    examples

    of

    antithesis

    quoted

    by

    Aristotle

    himself

    at

    3.9,7,

    from

    Isoc.,

    Panegyr. 35f

    come under

    his definition

    of a

    period.

    On the other

    hand,

    sentences like Thuc.

    2.102,

    cited

    by

    Dem.

    45:

    yAEp XEAPOs oc PA V EKH'I

    ov opovs &(XJoAoXasK11

    A

    ypt.cwv

    EV

    XEtItLWV

    Ur-pa7-Er;E

    at;

    or

    even

    Demosth.

    Lept.

    init.

    (Dem.

    Io):

    CtaA&yra

    tl0g

    EWVEKC

    01)V0OLVEK

    TU7LV/pEY

    77

    StEL

    AEOUO7'L

    V VOXLOV

    LT(

    KaM701

    7TAtL0'0

    LVEK(

    oo

    XTplov

    p1)oXdy o

    70Uo70Vro'

    v '

    E

    e

    ,

    vrvEpetv

    re

    not.

    The fact is that

    in

    Aristotle's

    mind

    the

    period

    is

    closely

    related

    to the

    enthymeme,

    and the

    enthymeme

    is

    constructed

    as

    a

    two-

    6

    I

    have not seen A.

    DuMesnil,

    Begriff

    der

    drei

    Kunstformen

    des Rede:

    Komma,

    Kolon,

    Periode,

    nach der

    Lehre der Alten

    in

    Zum

    zweihundertjahrigen

    Jubildum

    des

    k6nigl.

    Friedrichs-Gymnas

    (Frankfort

    1894)

    32-I21,

    cited

    by Caplan,

    Ad

    Herennium

    Libri IV de

    Ratione Dicendi

    (Harvard

    University

    Press

    1954)

    294

    n. b.

    I am

    not,

    however,

    hopeful

    that

    order

    can have

    been

    created from a

    situa-

    tion in

    which

    a

    prepositional phrase

    can be

    called a

    colon

    (Demetr.

    io

    on

    Dem.

    Lept.

    init.)

    or an

    independent

    predicate

    be

    called

    a

    comma

    (ibid.

    9,

    yviot oaTEvL-rv,

    t

    al.).

    Similarly,

    the

    opening

    sentence of Herodotus can be cited

    as

    an

    example

    of

    unperiodicity

    by

    Aristotle

    (Rhet.

    3.9.2)

    and

    of

    periodicity

    by

    Demetrius

    (I7).

    This content downloaded from 212.128.182.231 on Tue, 2 Sep 2014 05:55:47 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/10/2019 Retrica a Herenio. Perodos - GOTOFF, H. C. (1973)

    5/8

    220

    H. C.

    Gotoff

    part

    parallelism

    or

    antithesis.'

    Thus,

    each

    of

    the two basic units

    of

    the

    period

    is a

    colon,

    as Aristotle

    insists;

    within this framework

    the

    structure

    may

    be

    strictly

    antithetical or otherwise divided.8

    Thus,

    while

    agreeing basically

    with

    Kennedy,

    I

    find that

    Aristotle's

    analysis

    can

    accommodate a

    larger

    number

    of

    periods

    in our

    sense

    than

    Kennedy suggests.

    Not,

    unfortunately,

    that

    complete consistency

    can

    be

    derived

    from

    Aristotle's

    account;

    the

    notion

    of the

    simple period

    cannot be

    incorporated

    into this

    system.

    But,

    leaving

    that

    aside,

    the

    present

    explanation

    is

    supported

    by

    the ease

    with

    which Aristotle

    moves to his

    discussion

    of the

    Gorgianic

    figures

    at

    Rhet.

    3.9.9.

    Gorgias

    is

    identified

    with

    antithesis and other

    figures

    that arise

    from and

    support

    two-part balance. In this treatment, Aristotle seems to be following

    Theodectes, who,

    we

    are

    told, listed,

    in

    the

    context

    of

    antithesis,

    parison,

    and

    homoeoteleuton most of

    the

    beginnings

    of

    periods.9

    He

    was

    thus

    considering

    in

    close

    conjunction

    periodicity

    and the

    Gorgianic

    figures.

    It

    cannot be said that

    later writers on

    the

    subject

    of

    prose composition

    were

    prevented

    entirely by

    the

    Aristotelian

    view

    from

    proceeding

    to

    a

    more

    complex

    definition of

    the

    period

    -

    a

    definition that

    could embrace

    the

    constructions of

    Demosthenes

    and

    Cicero.

    Nevertheless,

    the

    limitation was a pervasive one. Dionysius of Halicarnassus uses the

    word

    periodos

    without

    definition,

    sometimes to

    mean

    little more

    than

    we do

    by

    sentence. 10o

    When he

    speaks

    of

    periodic

    style,

    moreover,

    he

    gives

    no

    indication

    of

    whether

    he has

    in

    mind

    the

    bipartite

    con-

    structions

    predicated

    on

    Gorgianic parallelism

    and

    antithesis,

    or

    the

    freer-flowing,

    more

    complex

    periods

    of

    Demosthenes or Cicero.

    In

    7

    Aristotle,

    Rhet.

    3.9.8,

    cf.

    2.9.

    In

    the

    first cited

    passage

    Aristotle states

    his

    preference

    for

    antithetical

    periods

    of the

    Isocratean sort.

    8

    Arist., Rhet.

    3.9-7.

    Although

    Aristotle

    favors the

    AEe'S

    &aV7TKELLEVrq,

    here

    is

    nothing

    about the

    AELSe

    8tqpv-qtt7

    intrinsically

    incompatible

    with a

    bipartite

    framework

    as

    defined

    in our

    discussion.

    9

    In

    3.9.9,

    Aristotle

    moves

    from the

    antithetical

    period

    to a

    discussion of

    parisosis,

    isocolon,

    and

    paromoiosis

    (homoeoteleuton).

    At

    the

    end of the

    section

    he

    says

    at

    8'

    pcXal

    'V

    7rEpLOdSWV

    XE8Ov

    v

    70~S

    OEO8EK7ELOL9~

    'OjIPrqV7.raL.

    f

    my

    interpretation

    of

    Aristotle's

    meaning

    is

    correct,

    this

    list

    may

    have

    included

    elements

    both

    syntactic

    (relative

    pronouns,

    conjunctions,

    etc.)

    and

    rhetorical

    (i.e.

    tdv,

    o

    ~dto'vov)

    hat

    anticipate

    a

    second unit

    to

    resolve

    them.

    aperar

    for

    apxalc

    is,

    therefore,

    an

    unnecessary

    change.

    10

    For

    example,

    Dionysius

    usually

    introduces

    a

    sentence with

    the

    word

    AEl7

    rqe

    v

    .'8 8

    17

    Coam-VLK7.V

    AExLV

    bu-aV-7Vt

    TiVi

    7ThOeE

    sAAO

    KOL07EF(aV

    OuTCS

    fo4LCthLa7LK7eV

    i-iv

    q

    &TtV

    v...

    (De

    Comp.xviii), but in ix he uses

    7rEpIo8oS

    purely

    for

    the sake of

    variety:

    KCUo~'it

    r'7v

    HAcV7-WVLK77V

    EKE7qV

    TEpLOSOV,

    V

    EV

    TrO

    L

    rrO

    0v-Vp

    bpdEL,

    49

    OUK

    V

    (Xal

    7MparrA7IpO~irTL

    AEeES~J

    VK

    cwVytKXCq0,

    7rpoUrqpavLurOL...

    This content downloaded from 212.128.182.231 on Tue, 2 Sep 2014 05:55:47 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/10/2019 Retrica a Herenio. Perodos - GOTOFF, H. C. (1973)

    6/8

    Periodicity

    in

    the Ad Herennium

    221

    Lys.

    8,

    he

    appears

    to

    judge

    periodicity

    to be

    a

    highly

    artificial

    technique

    that

    militates

    against

    verisimilitude,

    perhaps suggesting

    the

    very

    formal and artificial Gorgianic figures.

    Demetrius,

    on

    the

    other

    hand,

    is

    quite

    specific

    both

    in

    acknowledging

    his

    debt

    to Aristotle's discussion

    in

    Rhet.

    3.9,

    and

    in

    his

    determination

    to

    expand

    the

    compass

    of

    the

    period

    to include

    suitable

    constructions

    of

    three

    or

    four

    members.11

    His

    first

    example

    of a

    period,

    that from

    Demosth.

    Lept.

    init.,

    cited

    above,

    is

    of a

    type

    not

    included

    by

    Aristotle,

    since

    it

    cannot

    be

    reduced

    to two units.

    Further,

    his subdivision

    into

    rhetorical, narrative,

    and

    conversational

    periods

    reveals

    an

    inclusiveness

    that

    practically

    makes the

    word

    periodos

    useless

    as a

    critical

    term.12

    Nevertheless, in

    22f,

    he singles out for special notice the kind of period

    that is constructed

    from

    antithetical

    and

    parallel

    members. There

    follows

    a discussion

    of

    antithesis,

    isocolon,

    and

    homoeoteleuton,

    the

    Gorgianic

    figures.

    After

    this nod to

    Aristotle,

    it

    cannot

    be

    coincidental

    that he

    next

    distinguishes

    between the

    enthymeme

    and

    syllogism

    (32).

    He

    may

    be

    correcting

    Aristotle,

    but he is

    certainly

    at that

    point

    involved

    in

    the

    Aristotelian

    conception

    of the

    period

    as a

    basically

    bipartite

    structure.

    The

    relationship

    of the

    concept

    of

    periodicity

    to

    the

    Gorgianic

    figures in the rhetorical works of Cicero deserves full treatment else-

    where.

    It

    may

    suffice here

    to

    say

    that nowhere

    in

    his

    discussion of

    composition

    does Cicero reveal

    an

    awareness

    of

    that

    complex

    periodicity

    that

    distinguishes

    his

    style

    and

    that of

    Demosthenes

    from

    the

    bipartite,

    often

    antithetical,

    and

    frequently

    redundant

    structure associated with

    Gorgias

    and

    Isocrates.13

    What

    may,

    I

    think,

    be established

    fairly

    succinctly

    is

    the

    strong

    Aristotelian flavor

    of the

    discussion of

    periodicity

    in

    the

    ad Herennium.

    In

    4.27,

    we are told:

    continuatio

    est

    densa et continens

    frequentatio

    verborumcum absolutione sententiarum, translated by H. Caplan as, A

    Period

    is

    a

    close-packed

    and

    uninterrupted

    group

    of words

    embracing

    a

    complete

    thought. 14

    This

    definition is

    compatible

    with

    the

    modern

    11

    Demetr. De Eloc.

    I6.

    It

    is

    indicative of

    the

    problems

    involved

    with

    treating

    the ancient critical treatises as

    technical works

    that,

    after

    setting

    two to four

    cola as

    the limits of a

    period,

    Demetrius introduces the

    monocolon in the

    next

    paragraph.

    12

    Demetrius all but

    acknowledges

    this

    in

    De Eloc.

    21.

    13

    See,

    for

    example,

    the

    discussions

    in

    Orator

    38-38

    and

    219-220. Quint,

    9.3.74,

    credits Cicero's restraint

    in

    the use of Isocratean

    periods.

    See, also,

    n. 18 below.

    14

    H.

    Caplan,

    Ad

    Herennium

    ...

    297.

    The textual

    problem

    in the first

    line

    is

    of no

    consequence

    to

    this

    discussion.

    This content downloaded from 212.128.182.231 on Tue, 2 Sep 2014 05:55:47 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/10/2019 Retrica a Herenio. Perodos - GOTOFF, H. C. (1973)

    7/8

  • 8/10/2019 Retrica a Herenio. Perodos - GOTOFF, H. C. (1973)

    8/8

    Periodicity

    in the Ad Herennium

    223

    contrarium

    ?)

    or

    in

    the form of

    a

    consequence

    (Ev

    &KoAovOL'a

    crxWatr

    =

    conclusio

    ?).16

    It would seem, then, that the author of the Ad Herennium was

    following

    in

    his discussion of continuatio

    a

    view of

    periodicity

    as

    old

    as

    Theodectes

    and one

    enunciated

    by

    Aristotle

    - a

    view that

    pervaded

    the works

    or

    influenced

    the attitudes

    of

    rhetorical

    writers

    down

    to

    Cicero

    and

    Quintilian

    on the Latin side. Cicero

    may

    have

    accepted

    this

    view

    uncritically

    from

    tradition,

    or he

    may

    have

    limited

    himself

    intentionally

    by

    tradition to

    make

    a

    point

    about

    his

    style

    that was

    only

    partially

    literary.1

    The

    fact

    is

    that,

    following

    the

    account that is

    found

    in

    Aristotle,

    Cicero,

    in

    treating

    periodicity,

    describes

    a

    structure that

    is more readily found in Isocrates than in Demosthenes or himself.

    This is

    part

    of the

    explanation

    of

    why posterity

    has

    identified

    him

    with

    Isocrates

    far

    more

    closely

    than an

    analysis

    of

    their

    styles

    would

    justify.18

    HARVARD

    UNIVERSITY

    16

    I

    am not

    suggesting

    that

    these are

    equivalent

    technical

    terms

    in

    the

    Ad.

    Her.,

    or

    elsewhere.

    In

    fact,

    see

    Quint.

    5.10.2,

    where

    enthymeme

    is

    defined as a

    conclu-

    sion from antithesis

    (or

    contrarium).

    The

    similarity

    of the

    discussion in

    Demetrius

    and the Ad

    Her. is

    patent

    in

    general

    terms.

    17

    This requires full discussion. I plan to deal elsewhere, at

    greater length,

    with the

    contradiction

    between

    theory

    and

    practice

    in

    Cicero's

    rhetorical

    treatises. It

    may

    be

    suggested

    briefly

    here that

    in his

    treatment of

    periodicity,

    no less

    than of

    rhythm

    -

    two areas in which

    his

    contribution to

    prose

    style

    was

    most

    original

    -

    Cicero is at

    great pains

    to

    insist

    upon

    and

    identify

    himself

    with a

    tradition,

    even

    when he

    does not

    -

    as with

    that of

    the

    Gorgianic

    figures

    -

    in the main

    follow that

    tradition.

    18

    E.

    Laughton,

    Cicero

    and the Greek

    Orators,

    AJP

    82

    (1961) 27-49,

    shows

    masterfully

    that

    the

    periodic

    constructions

    of Isocrates and

    Demosthenes

    are

    very

    different and that

    Cicero has a

    fondness

    for

    the latter

    type.

    The article

    may suggest

    that

    Cicero

    eschewed

    two-part

    constructions and

    Isocratean

    parallelism. This is not the case by any means; but the formal balance, thrice

    repeated,

    of

    the first

    sentence of

    the

    pro

    Archia,

    often

    cited

    as

    an

    example

    of

    Ciceronian

    periodity,

    is hard

    to

    parallel

    elsewhere in the

    corpus.

    This content downloaded from 212.128.182.231 on Tue, 2 Sep 2014 05:55:47 AM

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp