Re-thinking and Re-balancing Rules and Routines

download Re-thinking and Re-balancing Rules and Routines

of 32

Transcript of Re-thinking and Re-balancing Rules and Routines

  • 7/28/2019 Re-thinking and Re-balancing Rules and Routines

    1/32

    RE-THINKING AND RE-BALANCING RULES AND

    ROUTINES: A FRAMEWORK ON

    INSTITUIONALISATION PROCESSESS IN

    MANAGEMENT ACCOUNTING

    Joo Oliveira, Faculdade de Economia da Universidade do Porto (FEP.UP, Portugal)

    Martin Quinn, Dublin City University Business School (DCU, Ireland)

    Interdisciplinary Perspectives On Accounting Conference 2012

    Cardiff, 11th 13th July 2012.

    First draft, please do not quote without authors permission

    Authors contact details:

    Joo Oliveira,[email protected]

    Martin Quinn,[email protected]

    1

    mailto:[email protected]:[email protected]:[email protected]:[email protected]:[email protected]:[email protected]
  • 7/28/2019 Re-thinking and Re-balancing Rules and Routines

    2/32

    Abstract

    This paper addresses the ongoing debate about rules and routines in institutional theory, in

    particular the debate building on Burns and Scapens (2000). Their seminal contribution was

    used as one initial springboard to inform our interpretations of the processes of management

    accounting change in two case studies. However, we both separately encountered some

    vulnerability in Burns and Scapens (2000) conceptualisations of rules and routines.

    Oliveiras (2010) case highlighted how rules, accepted and enacted by organisational actors,

    were crucial to a far reaching change process. The case adopted a wide conception of rules,

    beyond merely formal rules. Instead, the case drew on Cleggs (1989) concepts of rules of

    meaning and rules of membership, therefore emphasising the conception of rules as

    internalised and a part of actors cognitive structures. In turn, Quinns (2011, 2010) case led

    to focusing on routines. Formalised (i.e. written) management accounting rules were found

    to be less prevalent, with routines seemingly portraying structural and more formalised

    properties. A broader conceptualisation of routines was deemed to be required, leading to

    Feldman and Pentlands (2003) two dimensions of routines - the ostensive and the

    performative. This allowed explaining the apparent lack of any formalised, documented

    rules: in their absence, routines could portray a structural quality, i.e. a guiding and referring

    function for actions (Quinn 2010, pp. 167-181).

    Bringing together our two strands of research, we realised both rules and routines play a part

    in the formation of potentially institutionalised management accounting practices. We

    integrated our conceptualisations on rules and routines to build a distinctive, more detailed

    framework on the interactions of rules and routines, when compared to Burns and Scapens

    (2000). We thus propose a framework which explains how rules (as internal cognitive

    structures) and routine dimensions (ostensive and performative) interact to first embody a

    management accounting practice, which in turn may be repeated and, eventually, may become

    a routine. We thus draw a distinction between repeated practices and routines. The framework

    also considers a material dimension of rules (Volkoff et al, 2007) which, together with the

    notion of rules as internal cognitive structures, makes a case for the importance of rules in the

    formation of repeated practices, routines and institutionalised practices.

    2

  • 7/28/2019 Re-thinking and Re-balancing Rules and Routines

    3/32

    1. Introduction

    We both set out on the road to our doctoral thesis five or six years ago now. We were (and

    are) both interested in studying change and stability in management accounting and we both

    included Burns and Scapens (2000) (hereafter B&S) among our theoretical perspectives.

    However, we began to realise that we needed to think more about the concepts contained

    within B&S. That is not to say that we disagree with B&S, but we both found some further

    conceptualisation on the nature of rules and routines was necessary to interpret the empirical

    data presented from both our cases.

    Our sense-making guided us in different directions. Oliveira (2010) studied a long-term

    process of organisational change. Whereas formal rules were also at stake, the most

    interesting insights concerned rules of meaning and membership (Clegg, 1989), as

    internalised and/or enacted in practice. As such, Oliveiras study analysed in particular the

    rules component of B&S framework, although adopting a different conceptualisation of

    rules (the way things should be done) from that put forward by B&S. On the other hand,

    Quinn (2011, 2010) studied an information systems change project. Initially conceptualising

    rules as formalised and written, he realised such rules were scarce in his case study. So, he

    tended to focus more on routines as per the B&S framework (the way things are done),promoting a more detailed conceptualisation of routines compared to that proposed by B&S.

    Based on joint reflection, our perhaps excessively one-sided focus on rules (Oliveira, 2010) or

    routines (Quinn, 2011) does not do justice to the process of what B&S refer to as the

    routinization of management accounting practices. Here, we propose that both rules and

    routines play an important role in the bringing about of institutions (i.e. taken-for-granted

    ways of doing things). B&S do not detail the very nature of rules and routines, nor do they

    explore their interactions in detail. Work by Clegg (1989), Coad & Herbert (2009), Morgen

    and Olsen (2011), Reynaud (2005) and Stones (2005) have provided some further theoretical

    clarity on the nature of rules; and work by Feldman & Pentland (2003), Pentland & Feldman

    (2008) and Volkoff et al.(2007) has provided some further theoretical clarity around routines

    (see also Quinn, 2011). We attempt to bring the contributions from this work to our

    understanding of B&S, offering a different model of the process leading to the

    institutionalisation of management accounting practices. Based on our respective studies and

    more recent theoretical perspectives as outlined above, in this paper we attempt to re-think

    3

  • 7/28/2019 Re-thinking and Re-balancing Rules and Routines

    4/32

    and re-balance rule and routines in the process of institutionalising management practices. To

    this end, the developed framework explores the interactions of rules and routines in the

    bringing about of repeated practices in the first instance, and ultimately routines. The

    framework (see Section 5) highlights the importance of rules, which we conceive as accepted

    cognitive structures, in the formation of repeated practices (and routines). It also explores how

    material factors such as technology are encompassed within the process of routine formation.

    The rest of the paper is structured as follows. Section Two provides a brief overview of B&S

    framework. Section Three develops our conceptualisations on rules, briefly drawing from

    Oliveiras (2010) case. Section Four likewise develops our conceptualisations on routines,

    also briefly drawing from Quinns case. Finally, Section Five brings together

    conceptualisations from our cases and some further literature, to offer a potentially useful

    framework for management accounting researchers. Section Six concludes the paper with

    some final remarks.

    2. Rules and Routines in Burns and Scapens (2000)

    The conceptual framework proposed by B&S depicts a process of how management

    accounting practices can become taken-for-granted. Their concepts are now briefly describedto set a context for remainder of this paper. The B&S framework portrays management

    accounting as a routine and potentially institutionalised organisational practice (2000, p. 5).

    Hamilton defined an institution as a way of thought or action of some prevalence and

    permanence, which is embedded in the habits of a group or the customs of a people (1932, p.

    34, as cited in B&S). Premised on this definition, an organisation could be said to exhibit

    characteristics of an institutional nature. That is, organisational behaviour (such as

    management accounting) generally portrays some consistency, and in some instances

    behaviour can become a permanent feature. A starting assumption of the B&S framework is

    that management accounting can be interpreted drawing on concepts such as rules and

    routines. B&S defined routines as the way things are done (2000, p. 5), which can be

    contrasted with rules, the ways things should be done (2000, p. 6). They also recognise a

    link between institutions and actors, proposing that institutions define relations between social

    groups and group members. This explains the two realms of institution and action

    encompassed by B&S. These realms represent an on-going cumulative process of change

    through time (2000, p.9). The B&S framework somewhat arbitrarily starts at the point of

    4

  • 7/28/2019 Re-thinking and Re-balancing Rules and Routines

    5/32

    encoding new ideals in rules and routines. This is typically influenced by existing routines

    as these incorporate existing institutional values. Actors act out rules and routines over time,

    which eventually may become institutionalised practices. The B&S framework outlines in

    particular the importance of existing institutional factors such as rules and routines. The B&S

    framework also suggests routines can become institutionalised. Such institutionalised routines

    may, or may not, be in line with rules (see Lukka (2007) for an example). Institutionalised

    routines imply a deeply embedded set of assumptions on how things are done and are a

    potential source of inertia, continuity and inflexibility (Becker, 2004; Feldman and Pentland,

    2003).

    Thus, in summary the B&S framework proposes that a study of management accounting

    change requires an understanding of, first, the historical and institutional context of existing

    rules and routines and, second, the processes by which new rules and routines can become

    embedded and taken-for-granted. This paper by and large supports the general process as

    proposed by B&S. That is to say, the interaction of rules and routines is important to interpret

    how management accounting practices can remain stable, or how these same practices,

    although taken-for-granted, can also change. Where this paper differs is in both the

    conceptualisation of rules and routines and the interactions between them. The next section

    explores, proposes and justifies alternative conceptualisation of rules, stemming from the

    Oliveira (2010) RuleCo case. Then, Section Four takes similar steps as regards

    conceptualisations of routines, drawing from the Quinn (2010) RoutineCo case. Finally,

    Section Five brings together our conceptualisations of both phenomena, proposing a more

    detailed framework of their interactions in the potential institutionalisation of management

    accounting practices.

    5

  • 7/28/2019 Re-thinking and Re-balancing Rules and Routines

    6/32

    3. Theoretical development and empirical insights from the

    RuleCo case study

    3.1. Setting the scene at RuleCo

    The insights presented in this section emerged during a three year case study of a large

    European manufacturing company (Oliveira, 2010), called RuleCo for the purposes of this

    paper. This paper only provides a summary of some key points of the case study, to support

    the theoretical developments. This case study was motivated by the suggestion in the

    literature that such systems have the potential to drive management accounting change

    (Scapens and Jazayeri, 2003). So, this case study aimed at studying management accounting

    changes subsequent to the implementation of an Enterprise Resource Planning (ERP) system,

    based on a company that had embarked on a long and yet on-going process of ERP

    implementation.

    Institutional theory was initially adopted as lenses to explore management accounting change

    and stability. However, power issues emerged during the case study. Formally powerful

    central actors had been confronted with important limitations in the past, but which at the

    time of the case study had been largely overcome. It was apparent that these limitations could

    be construed as lack of power. However, institutional theory provided little guidance in

    explaining power (and lack of power), in spite of some efforts and calls for research in this

    literature (Burns, 2000; Ribeiro and Scapens, 2006; Seo and Creed, 2002; Siti-Nabiha and

    Scapens, 2005). This required researching literature on power and Cleggs (1989) framework

    of Circuits of Power was found to adequately explain the empirical setting.

    Exploring Cleggs conceptions of power is beyond the scope of this paper (see Oliveira, 2010and 2011 for a synthesis of the framework and a proposal for its development). Here, the two

    types of structures setting the standing conditions in which organisational action is produced

    are particularly relevant. These structures are materialconditions (related with techniques of

    discipline and production) and prevalent rules of practice (rules of meaning and membership).

    The following subsections analyse these two types of structures in OIE and in Cleggs

    framework, and how they were incorporated in the analysis of the RuleCo case.

    6

  • 7/28/2019 Re-thinking and Re-balancing Rules and Routines

    7/32

    3.2. Rules in OIE

    Within the old institutional economics literature, which we have primarily drawn uponi,

    conceptualisations of rules different from B&Ss were helpful to interpret the empirical

    insights about prevailing rules of practice. In the scarce discussion of B&S specifically on

    rules, the main emerging dimension concerns their formal / informal nature. In particular, in

    B&S rules tended to be associated with formal rules e.g., as codified in a procedure manual.

    However, as Hodgson (2006, p. 18) argued, the term formal has been differently associated

    with notions such as legal, written, explicit, codifiable. In addition, the contextualisation

    and operationalization of formal rules always depends on non-legal rules and inexplicit

    norms and, importantly, there is not clear distinction between the formal and the informal.

    The notion of prevailing rules of practice goes beyond formal / informal dimensions.

    Instead, it emphasises rules acceptance and enactment by organizational actors. Within

    institutional theory, rules thus conceived are included in what Coad and Herbert (2009)

    described as internal structures, within the agent (p. 179, emphasis added) (also, Busco,

    2009). These internal structures are cognitive representations, internal to the agent, providing

    orientations for action and decisive in influencing the way the external structures constrain the

    agent and the agents perceptions. Rules are connected sets of precepts (Englund and

    Gerdin, 2008 p. 1129) and create dispositions among actors to behave in certain ways. Becker

    (1998) also adopted this concept of rule as a cognitive representation to replace the abstract

    (rather than action) level of routines. This corresponds to what Burns (2009) described (as

    regards habits, routines and other rule-like structures), as embed[ding] themselves within

    peoples minds and cognitive armoury (Burns, 2009, p. 18). In a nutshell, what is at stake is

    becoming a rule to that particular agent.

    Consistently with such views, for eminent OIE theorist Geoffrey Hodgson (2006, p. 3) a rule

    is broadly understood as a socially transmitted and customary normative injunction or

    immanently normative disposition, that in circumstances X do Y (p. 3). Prevailing rules (and,

    indeed, institutions themselves) are subsequently enacted in, and therefore shape, actors and

    organizational practices. At stake is the reconstitutive downward causation mechanism that

    OIE attributes to institutions, acting to some degree upon individual habits of thought and

    action (p. 7). The crucial aspect in this conceptualisation lies in rules becoming an internal

    structure to the actor. If laws or declarations are neither customary nor embodied in

    7

  • 7/28/2019 Re-thinking and Re-balancing Rules and Routines

    8/32

    individual dispositions, thenformal or notthey have insignificant effects. They are mere

    declarations or proclamations, rather than effective social rules (Hodgson, 2006, p. 18). The

    key is therefore, as stated above, becoming a rule to particular actors - rather than being

    externally defined or proposed, in whatever form, but without having become accepted.

    3.3. Rules and material conditions in Clegg (1989)

    Cleggs framework also dealt with the issue of actors dispositions deriving from prevalent

    rules of practice, conceptualising rules in a broader way than merely formal rules. Clegg

    (1989) identified two types of rules: rules of membership and rules of meaning. Rules of

    membership refer to what actors believe to be appropriate behaviours. The desire to adopt

    appropriate behaviours is considered to derive from the actors status of members of certain

    groups and, in particular, from the actors ambitions to be accepted, retained and promoted

    members in those groups (Munro, 1999). Membership must be achieved, since it is

    provisional, rather than reified. In turn, rules ofmeaningrefer to the ways actors make sense

    of the world, events, the others and themselves. Therefore, rules of meaning shape the way

    actors knowledge is constructed.

    Rules of meaning and membership are related. In particular, rules of membership indicating

    to actors which behaviours are appropriate may include, and require, the endorsement of

    certain rules of meaning. For example, a rule of membership may indicate that the production

    of accounting reports should be oriented towards organisation-wide (rather than locally-

    specific) decision-making. Underlying such rules of membership, rules of meaning must be

    endorsed by accountants producing accounting information, orienting how they should

    interpret the business transactions they will record in the accounting system.

    Likewise, different conceptions about a particular business transaction (different rules of

    meaning) may reflect different rules of membership. In fact, a particular conception may

    address the interests of certain actors, rather than other actors. Hence, the rule of meaning is

    underpinned by a rule of membership, regarding whose interests the actor should consider as

    objectives to be attained.

    8

  • 7/28/2019 Re-thinking and Re-balancing Rules and Routines

    9/32

    Finally, for Clegg (1989, p. 201) rules are indexical, because they can never provide for their

    own interpretation. Indexicality occurs regarding the context of interpreters, i.e., the agents;

    and indexicality occurs regarding the context of interpretation, i.e., the actual situation in

    which the rule is interpreted and potentially enacted. Rules indexicality thus creates

    considerable leeway for divergence in the interpretation and enactment of rules.

    3.4. Rules and material conditions at RuleCo

    An in-depth analysis of the case is beyond the scope of this paper, so this section will only

    provide some relevant insights for the discussion held here. A key reason for difficulties of

    RuleCos central actors (roughly referring to managers at RuleCos headquarters) resided in

    the rules that local actors accepted and enacted in their daily activities, in accounting and

    other areas such as production. More than formal rules were at stake and could be considered

    prevalent rules of practice. Typical rules at stake within the accounting area concerned, e.g.,

    how to organize the charts of accounts, how to classify business transactions within the

    adopted chart of accounts, the timings to report to the headquarters, what accounting control

    mechanisms should be adopted (e.g., reconciliations), etc.. Although some formal rules

    defined by central actors were accepted and enacted by local actors, there were also other

    types of rules influencing local practices.

    In daily organizational activities, local actors could be confronted with conflicting rules,

    reflecting local and central conflicting objectives and interests. Traditionally, prevalent rules

    of membership of local actors at RuleCo were oriented to the local level the plant or the

    subsidiary-, rather than the organization as a whole. Likewise, locally relevant rules of

    meaning were often preferred over others addressing the interests of central actors. Local

    practices were often the enactment of locally-oriented accepted rules of practice, as

    highlighted by a Corporate Centre manager:

    each one () [at a local level gave] total and absolute priority to the

    countrys reporting, and not the internal group reporting.

    In turn, material conditions had an important role in the initial lack, and subsequent rise, of

    central actors power. Without going into details, at RuleCo, historically, available techniques

    were particularly limited to promote acceptance and enactment of centrally-oriented rules of

    9

  • 7/28/2019 Re-thinking and Re-balancing Rules and Routines

    10/32

    practice. However, three key technological and organizational innovations (techniques in a

    broad sense) were introduced by central actors: the introduction of the financial accounting

    module of SAP; the relocation of the Corporate Centre; the creation of a Shared Services

    Centre. These three innovations were crucial in attaining the objectives of particular actors by

    changing prevalent rules of practice, particularly as internalised by local actors.

    The telegraphic empirical account above does not fully convey the insights supporting the

    theoretical choice of adopting a wider conception of rules and, in particular, emphasising their

    dimension of internal cognitive structures, orienting actors practices. However, the above

    suffices to highlight that rules and material conditions were important structures to introduce

    practices and fix them within that organisation setting. This insight was useful to develop our

    framework, by bringing these two elements thus conceptualised into our account of the

    routinisation and institutionalisation of practices

    4. Theoretical development and empirical insights from the

    RoutineCo case.

    4.1 Setting the scene at RoutineCo

    The genesis of the concepts proposed in this section stem from an eighteen month

    longitudinal case study of a corrugated container1 company (see Quinn, 2010). This case

    study set out to interpret why management accounting practices within the industry had

    remained apparently stable despite the increased use of information systems like ERP systems

    and other large-scale information systems. As with Oliveira (2010), precise details of the case

    are not given here and this case also set out using B&S as a starting point.

    The case company referred to above is called RoutineCo for the purposes of this paper. At the

    time of the study, RoutineCo was installing additional software2 to help increase its ability to

    work more like an integrated group, rather than a collection of separate companies. While no

    change to management accounting practices was planned, the nature of the software and its

    associated change project implied change to management accounting can accompany

    information systems change (Scapens and Jazayeri, 2003).

    1 Cardboard boxes in common speech.2 The software was integrated with an existing ERP system.

    10

  • 7/28/2019 Re-thinking and Re-balancing Rules and Routines

    11/32

    During initial visits to RoutineCo, it emerged that little in the way of management accounting

    rules were present. Or, more precisely, using a working understanding of what B&S

    implied by the term rules, there were no rules in management accounting. At this point in

    the research at Routine Co, rules were being interpreted as written or documented, which

    transpired later could be a mis-understanding (see also Section 3.1 above, where Oliveira

    (2010) interprets B&S rules). Based on this premise, this presented a potential issue if

    formalised documented rules did not exist, how could B&S be used in the RoutineCo case to

    interpret change and/or stability in management accounting practices? As the research

    continued, the nature of management accounting practices at RoutineCo were revealed as

    more routine- than rule-like, with almost no written procedures or manuals in evidence as

    guide to practices. It was also apparent that management accounting routines were tightly

    inter-woven with other organisational routines (e.g. performance-related pay, legal (financial)

    accounting) and, thus, it seemed change to management accounting practices was quite

    unlikely. Nonetheless, some change to management accounting practices was found, albeit

    emergent and grounded in existing routines (see Quinn, 2010 for more detail). On example

    was the introduction of a performance measurement called the Contribution Factor (CoFa),

    which was derived from a previous contribution margin measure.

    The CoFa actually became formalised and written, and was used by managers at the case sites

    visited. In fact, the CoFa as it became formalised, written and taken-for-granted, was one of

    very few (written) management accounting rules found at RoutineCo. But, rules had been

    misinterpreted as being written, or had they? If rules, assumed as written, did not exist, where

    then did management accountants get guidance from? As shown by the CoFa example, this

    new management accounting routine (c.f. B&S how things are done) existed prior to it

    being formalised as a (written) rule. B&S seem to propose that rules may be in existence

    prior to routines, but evidence at RoutineCo seemed to show that routines may in fact be in

    existence prior to any (written) formalisation of management accounting practices. In such a

    scenario, were existing management accounting routines (i.e. the contribution margin, which

    was not formalised in any way) themselves a source of guidance for actors rather than rules?

    However, following the logic of B&S, routines are actions, not structures. And management

    accountants do engage in purposeful, structured, guided practices (action).With such

    questions presenting from the evidence at RoutineCo, some further conceptualisation on the

    nature of routines and rules was needed. So, what began as a misunderstanding (on the

    interpretation of rules) actually became a key focus in the analysis of the findings at

    11

  • 7/28/2019 Re-thinking and Re-balancing Rules and Routines

    12/32

    RoutineCo. The next sub-section begins to address the issues poised by the RoutineCo,

    namely: 1) can management accounting routines represent both structure and action?; and 2)

    what are management accounting rules? Although Section Three has already provided details

    on rules in line with the interpretation of RuleCo, the interpretation of rules in the RoutineCo

    case differs in some respects.

    4.2 Ostensive and performative routines

    During the course of the research at RoutineCo, the concept of a routine as defined by Burns

    and Scapens (2000) was found to require some conceptual development. A number of

    scholars in recent years have recognised the duality of routines, or put another way, that a

    routine does not represent just behaviour. Winter distinguished between a routine in

    operation at a particular site and a routine per se- the abstract activity pattern (1995, pp.

    169-170). Similarly, Feldman and Pentland state that organisational routines consist of two

    aspects or dimensions, namely: (1) the ostensive dimension; and, (2) the performative

    dimension (2003, p. 101). According to Feldman and Pentland, the ostensive dimension of a

    routine may have a significant tacit component which moulds the perception of what the

    routine is, may be codified as a standard procedure and may exist as a taken-for-granted

    norm (2003, p. 101). Pentland and Feldman describe the ostensive aspect as abstract,

    cognitive regularities and expectations that enable participants to guide, account for and refer

    to specific performances of a routine (2008, p. 286). The latter part of this quote suggests

    that an actors perception of the ostensive aspect is subjective, which is supported by Feldman

    and Pentland where they note the ostensive incorporates the subjective understandings of

    diverse participants (2003, p. 101). The performative dimension of a routine is the specific

    action(s) taken by people [] when engaged in an organisational routine (Feldman and

    Pentland, 2003, p. 102) at specific times, in specific places (Pentland and Feldman, 2008, p.

    286). Thus, Feldman and Pentland (2003)3 also distinguish between the abstract concepts of a

    routineper se and associated behaviour (see also Hodgson (2008, 2006)).

    Hodgson (2008) defines routines thus: routines are not behaviour; they are stored capacities

    or capabilities (2008, p. 19). This suggests that routines are separate from action. Hodgson

    does, however, state that routines depend upon a structured group of individuals, each with

    habits of a particular kind (2008, p. 22). This, in a similar way to Feldman and Pentland3 See also, subsequent papers by Pentland and Feldman (2008, 2005).

    12

  • 7/28/2019 Re-thinking and Re-balancing Rules and Routines

    13/32

    (2003), highlights a duality of routines. Finally, Burns (2009), in a similar vein to Hodgson

    (2008), proposes routines as dispositions, which separates routines as a concept from

    behaviour.

    The above mentioned literature suggests there is both a structure and action aspect to

    routines. B&S, while depicting both structure (the institutions) and actions, do not make any

    distinction between a structural and an action component of a routine. In the accounting

    literature, Englund and Gerdin (2008) argue:

    [] we need notions both to describe the situated and recurrent management

    accounting practices as such, and to denote the non-situated modalities that inform

    those management accounting practices (p. 1130).

    Englund and Gerdin (2008) refer to conceptual disparity (p. 1131) in management

    accounting research, where some writers view management accounting as modalities (i.e.

    structures) which are drawn on to reproduce practices, whereas others view management

    accounting as recurrent practices (i.e. actions). They further argue that to combine both

    conceptualisations in the same study may be ontologically problematic, suggesting that there

    is a risk of social structure and action becoming conflated (p. 1131).

    Given the above literature on routines which provides some further conceptualisations on

    organisational (and management accounting) routines, and the nature of the data unveiled in

    the RoutineCo case (i.e. few written rules), it is proposed here to adopt the notion of duality in

    management accounting routines. Given the apparent lesser importance of rules in

    management accounting at RoutineCo, proposing routines as having a structural component

    which guides action is potentially more suited to analysis of the data. Adopting this approach

    avoids any conceptual disparity on the nature of routines (Burns, 2009; Johannson and

    Siverbo, 2009; Englund and Gerdin, 2008) by making a clear distinction between the tacit

    dimension of a routine and the action dimension. In other words, it argued here that routines

    are best described as having ostensive and performative dimensions as per Feldman and

    Pentland (2003). A clear distinction between these two dimensions (as defined earlier) allows

    a researcher to interpret how and why in the apparent absence of rules (as at RoutineCo),

    aspects of routines changed or remained inert. In turn, this dual-dimension interpretation ofroutines provides potentially improved explanations on the process of institutionalisation of

    13

  • 7/28/2019 Re-thinking and Re-balancing Rules and Routines

    14/32

    management accounting practices as outlined by B&S. This is because it provides a method to

    utilise B&S in organisations where formalised rules may not exist e.g. small business.

    However, rules are an important component of B&S and, as highlighted by Oliveira (2010),

    are important in a management accounting context as evidenced at RuleCo. The

    conceptualisation of routines described above does not exclude rules from process of

    institutionalisation of management accounting practices. Feldman and Pentland (2003) and

    Pentland and Feldman (2008) describe rules as artefacts of routines. If rules are

    conceptualised as artefacts of routines, then by definition routines would have a tendency to

    exist before rules. This point is reflected on in the next section.

    The conceptualisation of routines proposed here, alongside Oliveiras (2010) earlier depiction

    of the importance of rules, raises a number of discussion points which are explored in the next

    section. We bring together our respective notions of rules and routines as noted here and

    Section 3 to derive a framework which will begin to address the complex interactions of rules

    and routines in a management accounting practices setting.

    5. DISCUSSION

    5.1. Making a case for rules within institutional theory

    Among the various components of B&Ss framework, routines, next to institutions, have been

    the main focus of attention by researchers. The findings by the Carnegie School (see a review

    in Hodgson, 1988) that behaviour is not entirely deliberative, conscious and intentional, and

    in particular that individuals adopt satisficing (rather than maximising) strategies (March and

    Simon, 1958), downgraded the emphasis in the precise calculation of consequences.

    Alternatively, they placed rule following in centre stage and, particularly, routinised rule

    following - even if mere rules of thumb are involved, rather than maximising ones

    (DiMaggio and Powell, 1991; Hodgson, 2008; Scapens, 1994).

    The previous two sections highlighted the empirical importance of both rules and routines and

    refined conceptualisations to capture the complexity of both phenomena. However, it should

    be noted that the emphasis on routinised rule following still leads to the issue of knowing

    what the followed rules are and highlights that there are still rules involved. As suggested in

    14

  • 7/28/2019 Re-thinking and Re-balancing Rules and Routines

    15/32

    Section 3, conceptualising rules merely as a set of formal rules only partially captures the

    relations between rules and routines. Alternatively, an expanded conception of rules

    encompasses the notion of formal rules but places a distinctive emphasis on rules as an

    internal structure of agents. This conception emphasises the cognitive dimension of rules -

    rules as accepted by agents, which may then be enacted by agents in their activities. In

    addition, it also makes a case for rules to regain a centre stage in institutional research, next to

    the current emphasis on routines and institutions.

    Oliveira (2010) argued that rules, in the broad conceptualisation discussed in Section 3, are

    implicated in all recent conceptions of routines reviewed by Becker (2004), Quinn (2011,

    2010) and Volkoff et al. (2007): the dispositional, ostensive, performative and material

    dimensions of routines. Each dimension is analysed next. In the first conception, restricting

    routines to generative dispositions, orienting agents, Johansson and Siverbo (2009)

    highlighted that routines can be expressed as rules (p. 148). This is in line with the view of

    (accepted) rules as part of agents internal structures, also influencing agents dispositions

    towards actions.

    In the second conception, the ostensive dimension of routines also has underlying rules, given

    its guiding properties. Indeed, the characteristic of guiding behaviour is shared by both rules

    and the ostensive dimension of routines. As Quinn (2010, p. 295) noted, [i]t could be argued

    that the ostensive aspect of a routine is similar to an informal (undocumented) rule a

    conception which is included in a broader conceptualisation of rule. As regards the third

    dimension, performative routines (i.e., the action dimension of routines as behaviour), the

    underlying rule being enacted (albeit in a routinised way) should not be ignored; as mentioned

    above, this perspective concerns programmatic rule-basedbehaviours.

    Fourth, and finally, Volkoffet al.s (2007) discussion on the materialdimension of routines

    actually concerns the multiple rules underlying routines being hard-coded in information

    technology. Although Volkoffet al. do not mention rules in their paper, their definition that

    [o]rganizational routines are embedded in the ES [Enterprise System] in the form of system-

    executed transactions - sets of explicitly defined steps that require specific data inputs to

    automatically generate specific outcomes (p. 839) reveals that they are referring to rules

    intended to define transactions and their sequence.

    15

  • 7/28/2019 Re-thinking and Re-balancing Rules and Routines

    16/32

    It therefore seems to be impossible to expunge rules out of the debate on routines, routinised

    rule following, and routinised action. Routinely producing a monthly variance statement (an

    example of a routine in B&S) is the enactment of an accepted rule stating that such a report

    should be produced every month even if potentially mostly unconscious. The above analysis

    highlighted the importance of rules, in as much as they underlie routines. The next subsection

    discusses another issue of crucial importance: rules influence behaviour even when, and

    particularly when, there are no routines.

    5.2. Rules when there are no routines filling a gap of routine-based frameworks

    5.2.1 Recurrence: necessary for the existence of routines

    The concepts of routines and rules are not synonymous, in spite of the linkages highlighted

    above. Indeed, one of the crucial differences is derived precisely from a key characteristic of

    routines: recurrence. As Becker (2004) noted, based on a wide literature review (see also

    Quinn, 2011), [t]he only commonality amongst [the various definitions of routines] is that

    they have to do something with repetition or regularity (p. 664, emphasis in the original) (see

    also Pentland, 2011). Indeed, recurrence of behaviours is required both to create a routine and

    to maintain it (Feldman and Pentland, 2003). Previous recurrence of behaviours is required so

    that one can evoke the concept of routine in the first place indeed, in any of the alternative

    concepts, even those which are not within the realm of action. Realistically, one would be

    hard pressed to call something happening only once a routine (Becker, 2004, p. 646).

    Additionally, even after being constituted (in whatever ontological form), a routine needs

    recurrent performance to be sustained. As Feldman and Pentland (2003) argued, without on-

    going performance of a routine, the performative dimension disappears and even the

    ostensive definition, though it maystillexist, becomes meaningless (Feldman and Pentland,

    2003, p. 108) and may diminish over time, or even disappear (Quinn, 2010, p. 296).

    The requirement of recurrence, or repeated occurrence, clearly restricts the field of

    application of the concept of routine. If an action has never been repeated or even performed,

    no routine exists. Likewise, if a routine ceases to be performed, even its ostensive dimension

    may diminish or disappear (Feldman and Pentland, 2003; Quinn, 2011). However, repeated

    occurrence is a striking difference between routines and rules, as discussed next.

    16

  • 7/28/2019 Re-thinking and Re-balancing Rules and Routines

    17/32

    5.2.2 Recurrence: but not necessary for the existence ofrules

    Unlike routines, rules do not necessarily derive from, and so do not necessarily require,

    repeated occurrence of behaviours. Actors may draw on specific rules for a number of other

    reasons, other than due to routines. One approach draws on a Parsonian account of human

    behaviour, which deeply influenced OIE. This approach emphasises the individuals

    evaluative judgment based on wider values, norms and attitudes, largely a result from the

    commitment derived from socialisation. Rules are, above all, morally accepted. In an

    alternative approach, Ribeiro (2003) drew attention to a more calculative perspective of

    human behaviour, in which individuals may enact certain rules according to strategic

    purposes, rather than genuine internalisation and moral acceptance of those rules (see alsoBoland, 1996). This possibility of calculative order, nonetheless, provides an account of

    behaviour different from the downward causation from institutions (putatively embedding

    shared values) upon individuals, suggested by the Parsonian account endorsed by B&S.

    It is acknowledged that it is plausible, as B&S suggest, that repeated behaviours may create

    (ostensive) routines - which may be conceptualised as rules, as below in this section and

    then eventually even be codified as (formal) rules (see also Quinn, 2011). However, they did

    not claim explanatory exclusivity, and did not claim that all rules which individuals draw

    upon in their social life derive from previous behaviours.

    Therefore, unlike routines, rules do not derive necessarily from past behaviour. A rule may be

    a part of an individuals internal structure without the underlying prescribed action having

    ever been performed. This does not mean, of course, that past behaviour ( any past behaviour,

    and particularly past and recurrent behaviour) may not leave its mark on actors and their rules.

    The importance of past actions is, for example, reflected in the related notion of path-

    dependency (e.g., Becker, 2004; Burns, 2000; B&S; Coad and Cullen, 2006; Coad and

    Herbert, 2009; Modell et al., 2007; Nelson and Winter, 1982; Powell, 1991). Indeed, as we

    explore later, how routines and rules (as agents internal structures) may evolve in a

    cumulative interaction to bring about routinized behaviour, and ultimately institutions, is

    worthy of more detailed study.

    17

  • 7/28/2019 Re-thinking and Re-balancing Rules and Routines

    18/32

    5.2.3 Rules when recurrent actions do not develop intoroutines

    Finally, it should be noted that past behaviour does not necessarily translate into the

    development of routines. This applies to all conceptions of routines. In a conception of routine

    as a recurrent behavioural pattern, past behaviour may not be as sufficiently recurrent as to

    qualify as a pattern (the degree of empirical recurrence required for such qualification is,

    clearly, not amenable to an easy quantification). In the conceptions of routine as a cognitive

    representation or a disposition, the emergence of such cognitive representations or

    dispositions is also not guaranteed to occur after (any given number of) reiterations of past

    behaviour.

    Although the cognitive revolution highlighted that much behaviour is routinised (Cyert and

    March, 1963; DiMaggio and Powell, 1991; Hodgson, 1988; March and Simon, 1958), some

    authors are cautious about not exaggerating their claims about the extent of routinisation.

    Routines () comprise programmatic, rules-based behaviour () grounded in repeatedly

    following such rules. () The above is not to say, however, that all accounting becomes

    routinised (), but that there is potential for routinisation () to occur (Burns, 2000, also

    cited by Yazdifaret al., 2008).

    The current literature emphasis on routines may leave researchers with an inadequate

    conceptual toolkit to account for empirical situations in which actors cognitive structures

    orient their actions, but in which routines have not consolidated, or have not consolidated yet.

    As noted above, routines may not emerge at alland surely do not emerge immediately after

    an action is first performed. Conceptual frameworks in the literature to date have neglected

    these insights. The next section will present a framework which addresses these gaps, by

    providing a greater emphasis to rules and identifying characteristics which distinguish

    between routines and merely repeated practices.

    18

  • 7/28/2019 Re-thinking and Re-balancing Rules and Routines

    19/32

    5.3. Towards a conceptualisation of interactionsbetween rules and routines.

    5.3.1 A framework on interactions of rules and routines

    Rules are an important, and arguably an essential, component of understanding potentially

    institutionalised management accounting practices. The relationship between routines (in their

    varying conceptual guises) and rules seem a tightly bound and conceptually inseparable one.

    However routines may not emerge, as repetition is an essential component of routines (Becker

    2004, 2008; Feldman and Pentland, 2003), and rules do not necessarily derive from past

    behaviour. This is where rules may provide researchers with a potential starting point in the

    analysis of organizational (and management accounting) practices. Once routines emerge

    however, they are a fundamental building block and arguably the primary means by which

    organizations accomplish much of what they do (Feldman and Pentland, 2003, p.94).

    In Figure 1, we attempt to answer this which comes first, rules or routines question, in a

    processual account bringing together the concepts of rules and routines outlined earlier

    19

  • 7/28/2019 Re-thinking and Re-balancing Rules and Routines

    20/32

    Material realm Actionrealm Psychologicalrealm

    Rules(cognitivestructures)

    Practices

    Technologicaldevices

    Repeatedpractices

    Performative routine Ostensiveroutine

    Institutionalised practices

    Figure 1 a detailed conceptualisation of the interactions of rules and routines.

    Figure 1 depicts three realms material, action and psychological which encompass the

    ontology of the elements which we argue ultimately lead to institutionalised practices. The

    material realm encompasses rules (as eventual routines) that are engrained within

    technological devices such as enterprise resource planning software and other similar

    technologies. The action realm encompasses the actual acting out of practices by actors. The

    psychological element encompasses cognitive understandings of how practices are to be

    performed. Each three realms work together to help us interpret how management accountingpractices (and other organisational practices) can become routinized, or indeed not. Before

    elaborating on Figure 1, it should be noted that all three realms presented in Figure 1 are

    assumed to represent actions at a collective or group level within organisations.

    The conception of rules depicted in Figure 1 refers to rules as internal cognitive structures i.e.

    rules which have been accepted by organisational members4. In the material realm, accounting

    software typically includes encoded rules as described by Oliveira (2010) and Volkoff et al.

    4 The introduction and acceptance of rules in a particular social context (e.g. an organisation) is itself a worthyresearch topic (see Oliveira, 2011A, 2010), but beyond the scope this paper.

    20

  • 7/28/2019 Re-thinking and Re-balancing Rules and Routines

    21/32

    (2007) (see earlier). These encoded rules have been selected by organisational members

    according to the cognitive rules they had accepted and considered desirable5. Together,

    cognitive and material rules are structures which inform new practices. Most organisational

    practices are repeatedly performed (supported by technological devices), and eventually gain

    a routinized nature. This routinized nature encompasses performative routines (actions) and

    ostensive routines (Feldman and Pentland, 2003), with the latter representing a rule reinforced

    by routinization. Ultimately, if both routine dimensions are sustained, in time, they may

    assume a taken-for-granted status within the organisation and become institutionalised

    practices. A more detailed analysis of the framework, supported by a fictitious example,

    follows.

    5 Technology is not infinitely flexible to accommodate whatever rules human actors may wish (Volkoff et al,

    2007). However, we argue that parameterisation capacities of contemporary software such as ERPs providesignificant flexibility to embed most rules envisaged by organisational actors, through the selection amongst themultiple alternatives offered by the software.

    21

  • 7/28/2019 Re-thinking and Re-balancing Rules and Routines

    22/32

    5.3.2. Exploring the framework

    To illustrate the conceptualisations within Figure 1, suppose the following fictitious example,

    which although fictitious, is typical of how we observed many practices evolve at our

    respective case studies (see Oliveira, 2010; Quinn, 2010). Let us assume an organisation is

    adopting a new management accounting system, which includes some form of enterprise

    software (such as an ERP). Managers may consider, for example, that more frequent and

    detailed variance reporting improves control and that this is desirable6. The rule at stake is

    we must produce a twice-monthly, detailed variance report7, which is a rule of membership

    that is expected to bring and sustain successful organisational membership for these

    managers. In turn, this rule of membership requires rules of meaning, such as a conception

    about a good report (it should be detailed) and good reporting (it should be frequent and

    detailed) (see Section 3). According to the orientation for action provided by this accepted

    rule, managers will attempt to shape the information system in order to embed this rule in it,

    through parameterisation (or eventually customisation) of the software. Accepted rules and

    encoded rules represent respectively the circuits of social and system integration (Clegg,

    1989). At this stage, standing conditions at the psychological and material realms have been

    set, which both enable and constraint possibilities of action.

    Within this structural context of accepted and encoded rules, the organisational practice of

    producing the variance report takes place. Through rules enactment, the first report is issued

    and, subsequently, it happens on a twice-monthly basis. At the time when a practice is first

    performed, it is premature to suggest that a routine is already in place (cf. van der Steen,

    2011), since the fundamental characteristic of routines is repetition (Becker, 2004). As the

    report is repeatedly produced, according to the accepted and encoded rules, the practice may

    achieve a routine status. As argued, repetition is a necessary, but not sufficient characteristic

    to grant routine status to a practice. Hence, the separation of both concepts in our framework.

    6 We acknowledge that this unitary view of organisations, endorsing the managerial perspective, overlooks

    diversity within organisations. The crude simplification of a unitary view, common to other synthetic

    institutional frameworks such as B&S, merely intends to focus the discussion on the concepts and relationsbetween rules and routines. See Oliveira (2011A) for a related approach explicitly accounting for intra-

    organisational diversity.7

    This rule by nature requires repetition, since it specifies frequency of report production. However, a similarrational would apply to a rule such as depreciation should be not be part of product costs, yet repeatedpractices would emerge as this rule is continuously enacted in on-going product costing decisions.

    22

  • 7/28/2019 Re-thinking and Re-balancing Rules and Routines

    23/32

    The degree of necessary repetition (as regards the length, quantity or intensity of repetition)

    for a routine to emerge is not fully debated here. Repetition is inherently a time-related

    concept but most likely in a non-linear way. For example, a new once a year management

    accounting task might not be regarded as routine for a number of years, whereas a task

    performed multiple times per month may be considered a routine in a much shorter

    timeframe. In other cases, the decisive perspective of repetition can be spatial, even more than

    time or the number of repetition (see Quattrone and Hopper, 2005 on the importance of time

    and space dimensions). E.g., the extent to which a practice is repeated throughout a company

    may promote that such practice gains a routine status more quickly. The literature has not

    provided a definitive answer on when a merely repeated practice becomes a routine and

    probably can never do so.

    Alternatively, we tentatively suggest characteristics of routines, to allow researchers to

    recognise one when they see it. We argue that characteristics like inertia (Becker, 2004; van

    der Steen, 2009), automaticity and tacitness (Lorenz, 2000) are required to classify a repeated

    practice as a routine. Inertia can be conceptualised as routine rigidity (Gilbert, 2005), referring

    to how routines preserve the underlying logic of an organisation, creating a virtuous circle

    which supports the routine. As noted by van der Steen (2009), inertia in routines manifests

    itself through limited change in behaviour. Looking at it another way, as noted by Feldman

    and Pentland (2003) and Pentland and Feldman (2008) (performative) routines can fade away

    over time if not enacted, thereby loosing inertial properties. Inertia of routines is thus similar

    to inertia of physical objects, resisting to change its state of: 1) rest, since a routine does not

    get constituted immediately; and 2) motion, since a routine tends to remain stable in time.

    Inertial tendency to remain in motion is strongly influenced by some automaticity in

    performative routines. Automaticity refers to the ability to undertake tasks in an almost

    unconscious fashion, as typical of ones everyday habits. Finally, tacitness implies an

    unspoken and inferred way of doing things8. Thus, characteristics such as inertia,

    automaticity and tacitness have a sedimentary effect (Clegg, 1989), whereby repeated

    practices evolve into a settled routine.

    Our framework also includes the interdependence between the performative and the ostensive

    dimensions of routines. As argued above in this section, the acting out of the routine (the

    8 Notions such as tacitness and automaticity align with the Carnegie school findings whereby behaviour is notentirely deliberative, conscious and intentional, as noted earlier.

    23

  • 7/28/2019 Re-thinking and Re-balancing Rules and Routines

    24/32

    performative routine) is essential for the ostensive dimension to emerge and be sustained. In

    time, without action, routines may become meaningless, diminish and even dissipate 9. In turn,

    ostensive routines provide the idea of a routine and hence influence how it is performed

    (Feldman and Pentland, 2003).

    Some points on the framework presented in Figure 1 are worthy of mention. First, the

    framework adopts some simplifying assumptions. The framework starts with the assumption

    that rules have been accepted by organisation members. As already acknowledged, we do not

    examine how acceptance of rules occurs. As our framework emphasises routines and

    routinization, it has by definition a collective focus. However, to fully explore the nature of

    rules and their origin in an organisational context (e.g. an external or internal source, an

    individual or collective initiative) is beyond the scope of our framework and worthy of further

    study. Also, whether what we term cognitive rules are derived from formal or informal rules

    (Hodgson, 2006), or whether they have a constitutive or regulative nature (Searle, 2005) is not

    debated here, as such notions do not detract from the fact that the rules (in our framework)

    have been accepted by organisational members. As we depict in Figure 1, rules, as accepted

    cognitive structures, underpin (with material rules) the formation of repeated practices.

    Second, for the purposes of illustration and explanation, Figure 1 depicts a scenario where a

    single instance of institutional practices is (potentially) formed. However, dynamically,

    institutions are the basis of the downward causality underlying OIE, a stabilising

    mechanism that the current framework accommodates (and could be represented by a

    downward arrow from institutions to rules). But institutionalised practices can change based

    on, for example, exogenous factors such as technological change or economic shocks (see

    also B&S). Thus, the process depicted in Figure 1 is on-going and dynamic, but may require

    an exogenous shock to re-start, i.e. for new rules to become accepted. In an alternative,

    relevant contribution, Seo and Creed (2002) have proposed change triggers from within

    institutional theory itself, i.e., dispensing totally exogenous forces. Seo and Creeds proposal

    is based on the heterogeneity and interconnectedness of multiple institutional areas. Emerging

    perceptions of institutional contradictions function as triggers, leading actors to re-evaluate

    their own institutional arrangements and, consequently, their accepted rules. Again, a detailed

    analysis or application of Seo and Creeds ideas to the proposed framework is beyond the

    scope of the paper, but the two frameworks are tentatively compatible, with Seo and Creed9 Although, as shown by Birnholtz et al.2007 dormant routines can be re-enacted.

    24

  • 7/28/2019 Re-thinking and Re-balancing Rules and Routines

    25/32

    offering other detailed processual mechanisms and a particular attention for diversity. Finally,

    we are not suggesting that the process depicted within our framework will necessarily unfold.

    For example, it may not be possible to embed accepted rules into technological devices as the

    generic rules available for selection within technologies such as ERP software may match the

    requirements of the organisation. Or, as already mentioned, a repeated practice may not

    evolve into a settled routine.

    Third, we depict institutionalised practices as being underpinned by action and psychological

    realms, but not the material realm. While encoded rules, in the material realm, are a

    component in the formation of repeated practices and routines as depicted, they are not an

    essential component of routines per se and, inherently, of institutions. Nevertheless, the

    importance of material conditions (e.g., software) in management accounting is amply

    documented (e.g., Volkoff et al., 2007; Dechow and Mourtisen, 2005), justifying the inclusion

    of material rules in the framework.

    Fourth, based on the interactions and processes depicted in Figure 1, we propose that an

    ostensive routine - a rule enacted over and over again and that achieved a routine nature - is in

    fact an empirically strengthenedrule. At least two factors contribute to this greater strength.

    The first contributing factor relates directly with the conception that an ostensive routine is a

    rule, thus providing guidance for actions. This guidance means that an ostensive routine has

    dispositional properties, representing a propensity to act (Burns, 2009; Hodgson, 2008) in

    similar ways to the (repeated) actions which built and sedimented to form that same ostensive

    routine. The second contributing factor to think of an ostensive rule as an empirically

    strengthened rule is that its previous enactment allows to somewhat reduce the uncertainty

    caused by the inherent indexicality of rules (Clegg, 1989; Oliveira, 2010). As discussed in

    section 3, indexicality of rules is related with processes of interpretation: regarding the

    context of interpreters, i.e., organisational members; and regarding the context of

    interpretation, i.e., the actual situation in which the rule is interpreted and potentially enacted.

    A first (and then repeated) enactment of a rule to particular circumstances is arguably an

    important step to increase clarity around the rule. Its enactment implied the interpretation of

    the rule by organisational actors, in their particular context; and it implied the interpretation of

    the particular empirical context at stake. Although both contexts (of the interpreters and of the

    empirical context) are likely to change, the performance of these two interpretations may

    promote the emergence of a kind ofpsychologicaljurisprudence for the future interpretation

    25

  • 7/28/2019 Re-thinking and Re-balancing Rules and Routines

    26/32

    (and enactment) of the rule by organisational members, thus potentially further strengthening

    the rule as a orienting, cognitive structure. However, it should also be highlighted that the

    interpretation and enactment of rules in particular circumstances also creates an opportunity to

    clarifications and even changes to rules rules as accepted by actors, and even rules as

    externally available, regardless of their formal or informal nature.

    Overall, this empirical strengthening of rules is likely to contribute to a greater resilience of

    those rules. As Modell et al. (2007) noted, B&S mainly ascribe resilience (e.g., of

    institutionalised controls) to organisational routines. Our proposal that ostensive routines

    provide greater strength and resilience to those rules is in line with B&Ss ascription, but

    suggests a more detailed account of underlying processes.

    6. Concluding comments

    The preceding sections have outlined our respective case studies and a framework which has

    been informed by both our empirical findings and recent literature on organisational routines

    in particular. As mentioned briefly in the introduction, we both set out on our research

    projects using B&S as a backdrop to help us understand change and/or stability in

    management accounting practices resulting from large-scale information systems change.

    However, as outlined in Sections 3 and 4, our outcomes in terms of interpreting and

    understanding our empirical data differed somewhat, in particular in relation to the relative

    importance of rules and routines in our respective studies. These differing outcomes prompted

    us to critically evaluate the nature of rules and routines and the part played by both in the

    bringing about of institutionalised management accounting practices the outcome of which

    is the proposed framework.

    Our framework offers several potential contributions to the furtherance of research in

    management accounting routines andrules. Recent literature has tended to concentrate less on

    rules. We adopted a wider conception of rules and focused on the dimension of rules as

    internal cognitive structures, orienting action. As conveyed in Figure 1, rules are an essential

    component in the ultimate formation of routines and should remain a focus of management

    accounting research. To this end, we encourage further research into how rules becomeaccepted in organisations. Fruitful lines of research here may include exploring how the

    26

  • 7/28/2019 Re-thinking and Re-balancing Rules and Routines

    27/32

    material realm may also affect rules acceptance (and not only rules enactment) and

    introducing intra-organisational diversity, as in Oliveira (2011A). We also encourage further

    empirical research on the distinction between repeated practices and routines, and on the

    factors which may sediment repeated practices into becoming routines. Finally, we also

    encourage empirical research on how processes we described may not unfold, become

    interrupted or divert from their original direction, problematising the virtuous cycle

    underpinning our synthetic framework and thus bringing a more realistic view of

    organisations.

    27

  • 7/28/2019 Re-thinking and Re-balancing Rules and Routines

    28/32

    References

    Becker, M. (ed.) 2008, Handbook of Organisational Routines, Edward Elgar, Cheltenham.

    Becker, M. 2004, "Organisational routines: a review of the literature", Industrial and Corporate

    Change, vol. 13, no. 4, pp. 643-677.

    Becker, M. C. 1998, Routines revisited: A contribution to an Evolutionary Theory of recurrent action

    patterns. Paper presented at the EAEPE Conference, Lisbon.

    Birnholtz, J., Cohen, M., Hoch, S. 2007, Organizational Character: On the Regeneration of Camp

    Poplar Grove, Organization Science, vol. 18, no. 2, pp. 315-332.

    Boland, R. J. 1996. Why shared meanings have no place in structuration theory: A reply to Scapens

    and Macintosh. Accounting, Organizations and Society, vol. 21, no.7-8, pp. 691-697.

    Burns, J. 2009, Addressing definitional ambiguity: management accounting routines as propensities

    to act, British Accounting Association, Annual Conference, Dundee, April 21-23, 2009.

    Burns, J. 2000, The dynamics of accounting change - Inter-play between new practices, routines,

    institutions, power and politics, Accounting, Auditing & Accountability Journal, vol. 13,

    no. 5, 566-596.

    Burns, J., & Scapens, R. W. 2000, Conceptualizing management accounting change: an

    institutional framework, Management Accounting Research, vol. 11, no. 1, pp. 3-25.

    Busco, C. 2009, Giddens' structuration theory and its implications for management accounting

    research, Journal of Management and Governance, vol. 13, no 3, pp. 249-260.

    Clegg, S. R., 1989, Frameworks of Power, London: Sage.

    Clegg, S. R., Courpasson, D., & Philips, N. 2006, Power and Organizations. London: Sage

    Publications.

    Coad, A. & Cullen, J. 2006, Inter-organisational cost management: towards an evolutionary

    perspective, Management Accounting Research, vol. 17, pp. 342-369.

    Coad, A. & Herbert, I. 2009, Back to the future: New potential for structuration theory in

    management accounting research?, Management Accounting Research, vol. 20, no 3, pp.

    177-192.

    Cyert, R. M., & March, J. G. 1963, A behavioral theory of the firm. Englewood Cliffs: Prentice-Hall.

    DiMaggio, P. & Powell, W. (eds) 1991, The New Institutionalism in Organizational Analysis,

    University of Chicago Press, Chicago.

    Englund, H. & Gerdin, J. 2008, "Structuration theory and mediating concepts: pitfalls and implications

    for management accounting research", Critical Perspectives on Accounting, vol. 19, pp.

    1122-1134.

    Feldman, M. S., & Pentland, B. T. 2003. Reconceptualising organizational routines as a source of

    flexibility and change, Administrative Science Quarterly, vol. 48, no. 1, 94118.

    Giddens, A. 1984, The Constitution of Society, Polity Press, Cambridge

    28

  • 7/28/2019 Re-thinking and Re-balancing Rules and Routines

    29/32

    Gilbert, C. (2005), Unbundling the structure of inertia: resource versus routine rigidity,Academy of

    Management Journal, Vol. 48 No. 5, pp. 741-63.

    Hamilton, W. 1932, "Institution" in Encyclopedia of the Social Sciences, eds. E. Seigman & A.

    Johnson, 8th ed., Macmillan, New York.

    Hamilton, W. 1919, "The institutional approach to economic theory", American Economic Review,

    vol. 9, no. 1 - Supplement, Papers and Proceedings of the Thirty-First Annual Meeting of

    the American Economic Association, pp. 309-318.

    Hodgson, G. 2008, "The concept of a routine" in Handbook of organisational Routines, ed. M. Becker,

    Edward Elgar, UK, pp. 15-28.

    Hodgson, G. 2006, "What are institutions?", Journal of Economic Issues, vol. XL, no. 1, pp. 1-25.

    Hodgson, G. 1988, Economics and institutions: a manifesto for a modern institutional economics.

    Cambridge: Polity Press.

    Humphrey, C. & Scapens, R. 1996, "Methodological Themes: Theories and case studies of

    organizational accounting practices: limitation or liberation?", Accounting, Auditing and

    Accountability Journal, vol. 9, no. 4, pp. 86-106.

    Johansson, T. & Siverbo, S. 2009, "Why is research on management accounting change not explicitly

    evolutionary? Taking the next step in the conceptualisation of management accounting

    change", Management Accounting Research, vol. 20, no. 2, pp. 146-162.

    Lorenz, E. 2000, Organisational routines in the light of old evolutionary economics: Bringing

    politics back into the study of organisational learning, European Journal of Economic and

    Social Systems, vol. 14 no. 2, pp. 191-207.

    Lukka, K. 2007, "Management accounting change and stability: loosely coupled rules and routines in

    action", Management Accounting Research, vol. 18, pp. 76-101.

    March, J. G., & Simon, H. A. 1958, Organizations. New York: Wiley.

    Modell, S., Jacobs, K., & Wiesel, F. 2007, A process (re)turn?: Path dependencies, institutions and

    performance management in Swedish central government. Management Accounting

    Research, 18(4), 453-475.

    Morgen, J, Olsen W. 2011, Conceptual issues in institutional economics; clarifying the fluidity of

    rules, Journal of Institutional Economics, vol. 7, no. 3, pp. 425-454.

    Munro, R. J. B. 1999,. Power and Discretion: Membership work in the time of technology,

    Organization, vol. 6, no. 3, 429-450.

    Nelson, R. & Winter, S. 1982, An Evolutionary Theory of Economic Change, Harvard College,

    Boston.

    Oliveira, J. 2011, Power and organizational change: developing theories of power and research

    avenues for institutional theory, 4th Workshop on Management Accounting as Social and

    Organizational Practice (MASOP), HEC Paris.

    Oliveira, J. 2011A, Bringing power, interests and rules to OIE: a model of rule-based action, 8th

    ENROAC Conference, Lisbon

    29

  • 7/28/2019 Re-thinking and Re-balancing Rules and Routines

    30/32

    Oliveira, J. 2010, Power and organizational change: a case study. Unpublished PhD, University of

    Dundee, Dundee.

    Pentland, B., (2011), The foundation is solid, if you know where to look: comment on Felin and

    Foss,Journal of Institutional Economics, vol. 7, no. 2, pp. 279 -293.

    Pentland, B. T., & Feldman, M. S. 2008,. Issues in field studies of organizational change, In M.

    Becker (Ed.), Handbook of Organisational Routines (pp. 281-300), Cheltenham: Edward

    Elgar.

    Powell, W. W. 1991, Expanding the scope of institutional analysis. In W. W. Powell & P. J. DiMaggio

    (Eds.), The New Institutionalism in Organizational Analysis (pp. 183-203). Chicago: The

    University of Chicago Press.

    Quattrone, P., Hopper, T. (2005). A Time-Space Odyssey: Management Control Systems in

    Multinational Organisations,Accounting, Organizations and Society, 30, 7-8: 735-764.

    Quinn, M. 2011, Routines in management accounting: some further exploration, Journal of

    Accounting and Organizational Change, vol. 7, no.4, pp. 337-357.

    Quinn, M. J. 2010, Continuity and change in management accounting - evidence from the corrugated

    container sector. Unpublished PhD, University of Dundee, Dundee.

    Reynaud, B, 2005, The void at the heart of rules: routines in the context of rule-following. The case

    of the Paris Metro workshop,Industrial and Corporate Change. vol. 14, no. 5, pp. 847-871.

    Ribeiro, J. 2003, Institutionalism, Power and Resistance to Management Accounting -a Case Study.

    Unpublished PhD, University of Manchester, Manchester.

    Ribeiro, J. & Scapens, R. 2006, "Institutional theories in management accounting change:

    contributions, issues and paths for development", Qualitative Research in Accounting &

    Management, vol. 3, no. 2, pp. 94-11.

    Scapens, R. 1994, "Never mind the gap: towards an institutional perspective on management

    accounting practice", Management Accounting Research, vol. 5, pp. 301-321.

    Scapens, R. & Jazayeri, M. 2003, "ERP systems and management accounting change: opportunities or

    impacts? A research note", European Accounting Review, vol. 12, no. 1, pp. 201-233.

    Searle, J. (2005), "What is an institution?", Journal of Institutional Economics, vol. 1, no. 1, pp. 1-22.

    Seo, M.-G., & Creed, W. E. D. 2002, Institutional contradictions, praxis, and institutional change: a

    dialectical perspective, Academy of Management Review ,vol. 27, no. 2, pp. 222-247.

    Siti-Nabiha, A. K., & Scapens, R. 2005, Stability and change: an institutionalist study of management

    accounting change, Accounting, Auditing & Accountability Journal, vol. 18, no. 1, pp. 44-

    73.

    Stones, R. 2005, Structuration Theory, Palgrave, London.

    Van der Steen, M. (2011), The emergence and change of management accounting routines

    Accounting, Auditing and Accountability Journal, vol.24, no. 4, pp. 502-547.

    30

  • 7/28/2019 Re-thinking and Re-balancing Rules and Routines

    31/32

    Van der Steen, M. (2009), Inertia and Management Accounting change,Accounting, Auditing and

    Accountability Journal, vol.22, no. 5, pp. 736-761.

    Volkoff, O., Strong, D. M., & Elmes, M. B. 2007, Technological Embeddedness and Organizational

    Change. Organization Science, vol. 18, no. 5, pp. 832-848.

    Winter, S. 1995, "Four rs of profitability: rents, resources, routines and replication" in Resource-based

    and evolutionary theories of the firm: Towards a synthesis, ed. C. Montgomery, Kluwer,

    Boston, pp. 147-178.

    Wittgenstein, L. 1953,Philosophical Investigations, Blackwell Publishing, UK.

    Yazdifar, H., Zaman, M., Tsamenyi, M., & Askarany, D. 2008, Management accounting change in a

    subsidiary organization. Critical Perspectives on Accounting, vol. 19, no.3, pp. 404-430.

    31

  • 7/28/2019 Re-thinking and Re-balancing Rules and Routines

    32/32

    i It should be noted that other eminent scholars such as Giddens (1984) and Wittgenstein (1953) have also discussedrules and rule following behaviour. However, such works do not provide clarity of what exactly a rule is. Given

    our starting point of B&S, and somewhat more detailed attempts in associated OIE literature to clarify the meaning ofrules, our work here remains focused on this strand of literature. Similarly for example, the work of Giddens (1984)

    refers to routinized behaviour, but does not clarify the meaning of routines. Hence later, we examine literature whichoffers more detailed conceptualisations of routines. See also Stones (2005, pp. 46-48) for a critique of Giddens use of

    rules)