Physical David Papineau Interviewed by Richard Marshall

download Physical David Papineau Interviewed by Richard Marshall

of 17

Transcript of Physical David Papineau Interviewed by Richard Marshall

  • 7/27/2019 Physical David Papineau Interviewed by Richard Marshall

    1/17

    physicalDavid Papineau interviewed by Richard Marshall.

    [Photo; Steve Pyke]

    David Papineau is still roving in the deep philosophical waters even

    though he knows that hell never know everything. He keeps writing hard

    core books about his philosophical thoughts covering things such as

    physicalism and how come everyone isnt a physicalist, substance and

    property dualism and Kripkes worry that the mind brain identity is just

    contingent. He wonders why philosophers think theres something wrong

    with just knowing the facts. He thinks about the nature of colour

    experiences, representation, and avoids mixing up methodological issues

    with metaphysical ones. He thinks about the significance of Schrodingers

  • 7/27/2019 Physical David Papineau Interviewed by Richard Marshall

    2/17

    cat,about whether there are any special laws that are not reducible to

    physics and about the usefulness of historical kinds. This is a deep water

    big beast from the philosophical depths: bangin.

    3:AM: What made you become a philosopher? Has it been worth it?

    David Papineau: My first degree was in mathematics. That was great, but

    it didnt help with many of the things that puzzled me. I became a

    philosopher because I wanted to understand everything, especially those

    things that didnt make sense. And that has continued to be my

    philosophical motivation. Thats one reason I have such a roving

    philosophical eye once I have figured out a philosophical topic to my

    satisfaction, I find myself moving on to new problems.

    Has it been worth it? Absolutely. (I now realize that I wont have quite

    enough time to understand everythingbut that hasnt stopped me

    wanting to understand as much as I can.)

    3:AM: You are an ontological naturalist. You think that modern science

    makes some species of physicalism an irresistible position dont you?

    Can you explain what your arguments are?

    DP: Its simple enough. Nearly everybody nowadays accepts the causal

    completeness of physicsevery physical event (or at least its probability)

    has a full physical cause. This leaves no room for non-physical things to

    make a causal difference to physical effects. But it would be absurd to

    deny that thoughts and feelings (and population movements and

    economic depressions . . .) cause physical effects. So they must be

    physical things.

    Note how this argument only bites for those things that do have physical

    effects. If numbers say, or moral properties, have no physical effects, then

    this argument gives us no immediate reason to say that they too must be

    physical.

    You might want to askif there is such a simple argument for physicalism,

    how come everybody hasnt always been a physicalist? Thats a good

    question, and there is a good answer. The causal completeness of

    physics wasnt widely accepted until recently. A century ago mainstream

  • 7/27/2019 Physical David Papineau Interviewed by Richard Marshall

    3/17

    science was still quite happy to countenance vital and mental powers

    which had a downwards causal influence on the physical realm in a

    straightforwardly interactionist way. It was only in the middle of the last

    century that science finally concluded that there are no such non-physical

    forces. At which point a whole pile of smart philosophers (Feigl, Smart,

    Putnam, Davidson, Lewis) quickly pointed out that mental, biological and

    social phenomena must themselves be physical, in order to produce the

    physical effects that they do.

    3:AM: This is not an eliminativist position regarding the mind but is

    reductionist isnt it?

    DP: Yesat least in the sense in which reductionist simply means

    neither eliminativist nor dualism. Philosophers sometimes also use

    reductionist more strictly, to mean type-identities between mental and

  • 7/27/2019 Physical David Papineau Interviewed by Richard Marshall

    4/17

    physical categories, and to exclude non-reductive physicalisms like

    metaphysical functionalism. Im not so sure that I am a reductionist in the

    strict type-identity sense. The issues here are messy. But I certainly a

    reductionist in the more general sense which is opposed to eliminativism

    and dualism.

    3:AM: Substance dualism is a target of this approach isnt it?

    DP: Yes. But so is property dualism.

    3:AM:Tim Crane, for example, might happily concede the arguments

    about substance dualism but not concede that this means no species of

    dualism cant be sustained. How do you respond to that sort of challenge?

    DP: Well, the causal argument I gave above doesnt just imply that there

    cant be a non-physical mental substance, but also that there can t be

    non-physical mental properties. (Tim is always a bit cagey about exactly

    what he thinks at this particular point. Im having dinner with him on

    Saturday and will press him about it.)

    3:AM: Kripke has anti-materialist arguments at the end of his Naming

    and Necessityand you think hes wondering how mind brain identity

    seems false even to people like yourself doesnt he? How do you handle

    his challenge?

    DP: Kripke says that physicalists like me cant explain the apparent

    contingency of mind-brain identities. He maintains that, if I really believed

    that pains are C-fibres, then I ought no longer to have any room for the

    thought that they might come apart. His argument is that, since pains

    arent identified via some contingent description, but in terms of how they

    feel, I have no good way of constructing a possible world, so to speak,

    where C-fibres are present yet pains absent.

    (For the experts, note that Im here reading Kripke quite differently from

    the widespread two-dimensionalist reading which takes him to be saying

    that the problem for physicalists is simply that mind-brain identities are a

    posteriori. This seems to me an absurd misreading of Kripke.)

    My response to Kripke is simply to point out that mind-brain identity claims

  • 7/27/2019 Physical David Papineau Interviewed by Richard Marshall

    5/17

    are very counter-intuitive. They continue to seem incredible even to

    committed physicalists like myself. And that is why I go on half-thinking at

    an intuitive level that there is a possible world with C-fibres and no pains. I

    simply havent fully freed myself from the dualist intuition that even in the

    actual world pains involve something more than from C-fibres. So of

    course I intuitively think that they might come apart in other possible

    worlds, even if they contingently co-occur in the actual world. (If pains are

    extra dualist states generated by brain states, courtesy of the contingent

    laws of nature operating in this world, then it immediately follows that

    those brain states could occur without the conscious states, in a world

    with different laws of nature.)

    In truth, as Kripke points out, a clear-headed physicalist shouldn t be

    thinking any of these dualist thoughts. If pains are one and the same as C-

    fibres firing, then there really isnt any possibility of having one without

    the other. Once you properly appreciates physicalism, this dissociation

    should cease to appear possibleC-fibres with pains should strike you as

    no more possible than squares without rectangles.

    From my perspective, then, Kripkes intuition of contingency isnt a

    thought that physicalists are somehow required to continue respecting

    even after they have embraced their physicalism. Rather it is simply amanifestation of the psychological difficulty of fully embracing physicalism

    in the first place.

    This is a very straightforward response to Kripke, one that cuts through

    the huge literature on the explanatory gap and two-dimensional

    semantics. This whole literature is motivated by the idea that there is

    something deficient about our current theoretical understanding of the

    mind-brain relation, and that therefore we need some different anddeeper perspective that will somehow render mind-brain identities

    transparently true. I say that there is nothing deficient about our current

    theoretical grasp of mind-brain identities. The problem is only that they are

    counter-intuitive. This doesnt show that there is anything wrong with our

    theoretical understanding, any more than the intuition that the Earth is at

    rest shows that there must be something theoretically wrong with

    Copernicanism, or the intuition that time is moving shows that there is

    something theoretically wrong with the block universe B series view of

  • 7/27/2019 Physical David Papineau Interviewed by Richard Marshall

    6/17

    change. (A hankering for transparent understanding, grasp of natures,

    having things revealed as they are, and so on, seems to run through a lot

    of current philosophical debate. I dont get it. Whats wrong with just

    knowing the facts?)

    Of course, there remains the question of why we should find mind-brain

    identities so persistently counter-intuitive, if they are true. But this is a

    simple psychological question, and there are a number of plausible

    explanations. Indeed this is a topic that is quite extensively discussed

    outside philosophy, by developmental psychologists and theorists of

    religion among others, under the heading of intuitive dualism. It is rather

    shocking that so few of the many philosophers working on the

    explanatory gap are familiar with this empirical literature.

    3:AM: While we are on conscious experience, you deny that we can

  • 7/27/2019 Physical David Papineau Interviewed by Richard Marshall

    7/17

    really see a million colours. This is territory that Pete Mandik is also

    looking into isnt it? You offer an alternative to the orthodox view, and then

    argue that phenomenological scrutiny isnt going to help decide which is

    right. So first could you set out the two views?

    DP: Colour experience is a new topic for me. Im not sure how closely itrelates to my previous work.

    The orthodox view of colour experience assumes that, when we see a

    colour difference between two surfaces viewed side-by-side, this is

    because we have different responses to each of the two surfaces viewed

    singly. Since we can detect colour differences between something like ten

    million different surfaces, this implies that we are capable of ten million

    colour responses to surfaces viewed singly.

    I dont think that we are capable of anything like this many possible colour

    responses. Instead I argue that the perception of colour differences

    between two surfaces viewed side-by-side is a gestalt phenomenon.

    There is a brain mechanism that works to identify colour differences

    directly, without first identifying the absolute colour of each surface. So on

    my view there is no reason to suppose anything like ten million colour

    responses to surface viewed singly.

    I think my view is rather more radical than Pete Mandiks. Both of us want

    to show that colour perception doesnt transcend what can be

    conceptualized, but I dont think he goes so far as to deny that it doesn t

    involve different responses to all the discriminable surfaces.

    On the methodological issue, I think that would be hopeless to try to

    adjudicate between my view and orthodoxy by appeal tophenomenological introspection. We need to know about brain

    mechanisms.

    3:AM: So why does phenomenological scrutiny not help? Does this relate

    your enthusiasm for phenomenal concepts? Youve written about

    Wittgensteins Private Language Argument and argued that phenomenal

    concepts are inconsistent with Wittgenstein. So who winsWittgensteins

    argument or phenomenal concepts? Or both?

  • 7/27/2019 Physical David Papineau Interviewed by Richard Marshall

    8/17

    DP: The phenomenal concept issue is rather different, I think. Here the

    question is whether there are concepts of experiences that are made

    available to subjects solely in virtue of their having had those experiences

    themselves. Is there a way of thinking about seeing something red, say,

    that you get from having had those experiences, and so isn t available to a

    blind person? Many contemporary philosophers would say yes, despite

    the fact that such concepts seem to conflict with Wittgensteins private

    language argument. I have written a paper arguing that phenomenal

    concepts do indeed conflict with the private language argument, and that

    this is bad for Wittgenstein.

    Still, as I said, this issue about phenomenal concepts is different from your

    previous question of whether we can decide the structure of colour

    perception by phenomenological introspection. After all, in supporting

    phenomenal concepts I am in a sense siding with introspection against the

    more behaviourist Wittgensteinians. But even so I dont think that

    introspection is powerful enough to resolve the specific issue about how

    many colours you can see.

    3:AM: So what approach do you recommend?

    DP: As I said, I dont think that we can figure out what is going on inconscious colour perception just by phenomenological introspection. We

    need to know about brain mechanisms as well. We need to figure out what

    information is present in the mechanisms that constitute conscious colour

    perception. If neuroscientific research shows that those mechanisms only

    contain comparative information about colour differences, and have

    thrown away more fine-grained information about the absolute colours of

    single surfaces, then that would support my position, in a way that just

    introspecting our colour experiences cant.

    The use of neuroscientific data to help resolve phenomenological

    questions is proving a common theme in much contemporary thinking

    about the mind. How rich are the contents of visual perception? Does

    vision only tell us about shapes and colours, or does it also represent

    higher categories like lemon or umbrella? Again, when we view a scene

    fleetingly, do we consciously see all the details even though we dont

    retain them, or do we not see them in the first place? Neurological

  • 7/27/2019 Physical David Papineau Interviewed by Richard Marshall

    9/17

    information is crucial to deciding these questions. After all, they are so

    interesting precisely because unaided introspection cannot resolve them.

    Rather we need to know what is going on in the brain activities that

    constitute visual awareness.

    Of course, without any appeal to introspective phenomenology at all, we

    couldnt get started on this kind of analysis in the first place, since the

    initial identification of the brain activities that constitute visual awareness

    must depend on correlating brain processes with phenomenological

    reports. But we can engage in a kind of useful bootstrapping here. First

    we use uncontroversial aspects of introspective phenomenology to figure

    out which brain activities are in general responsible for visual

    phenomenology and other features of consciousness. And then we use

    the neuroscience to tell us what information is present in those brain

    activities, and so to decide the trickier questions about the structure of

  • 7/27/2019 Physical David Papineau Interviewed by Richard Marshall

    10/17

    consciousness. We start and end with phenomenological data, but we

    couldnt have completed our inferential journey without the detour through

    brain science.

    3:AM: Does this relate to your anti-conceptualism about psychological

    representation? Dont you want to defend your views about psychologicalrepresentation as scientific reductions, rather than as results of conceptual

    analysis?

    DP: I think it helps to distinguish the local semantic question about the

    specific representational contents of perceptionwhat things do

    perceptual states represent?from the more general meta-semantic

    question of the nature of representationwhat it is for psychological

    states to have representational contents at all?

    On the former question, I rather incline towards conceptualism, in line

    with my view of colour perceptionI dont think that we can represent

    objects and properties for which we have no concepts, not even in

    perceptual experience. In this sense I differ from those who defend non-

    conceptual content like Michael Tye and Chris Peacocke.

    But this local semantic question isnt something that I have written about

    much, apart from my recent interest in colour vision.

    On the general meta-semantic question, by contrast, I have written a lot,

    mostly under the heading of teleosemantics. And herethough this is an

    entirely distinct issueI am very much inclined to be anti-conceptualist, in

    the sense that I think that the philosophical task (as always) is to come up

    with a synthetic theory that fits the empirical evidence, and not to analyse

    our a priori concept of representation or anything like that.

    3:AM: You also look forward to reducing causality to probabilities as part

    of this same approach dont you? And an issue here is avoiding mixing

    metaphysics with methodology. Can you explain this, and also why this is

    not a methodology issue but a metaphysical one?

    DP: A certain kind of methodologically-minded philosopher of science is

    quick to read off metaphysical conclusions from features of scientific

    practice. Chemists dont derive their laws from fundamental physics, so

  • 7/27/2019 Physical David Papineau Interviewed by Richard Marshall

    11/17

    reductive physicalism must be false. Biologists refer to natural numbers in

    some of their explanations, so numbers must exist. I think that this kind of

    thing makes for bad philosophy. The relevant features of scientific practice

    often have mundane explanations which dont point to any deep

    metaphysical moral. (Thus it would simply be messy and pointless for the

    chemists to essay physical reductions, or for the biologists to offer

    number-free explanations. Its a weird kind of science-worship that views

    these practical considerations as clues to the nature of reality.)

    Recent work on causation is a case in point. The metaphysical question is

    whether causal relations can be reduced to non-causal general

    regularities in some Humean style (though the modern Humean will work

    with probabilistic generalizations rather than deterministic ones). Now,

    methodological philosophers working on causal inference in practical

    areas of science (epidemiology, economics, agriculture, . . .) have

    observed that in practice causes are never inferred from probabilistic

    patterns alone. When scientists do infer new causal conclusions from

    probabilistic information, it is always against a rich background of prior

    causal assumptions. (No causes in, no causes out.) And many

    philosophers of science then move quickly from this practical

    methodological observation to the metaphysical conclusion that causation

    must somehow transcend any Humean pattern of probabilistic

    generalizations. But this is not a good inference. Even if causation is at

    bottom constituted by patterns of probabilistic generalizations, there are

    obvious practical reasons for using prior causal knowledge to help identify

    new causes, rather than trying to work everything out from first principles

    every time.

    The funny thing is that recent methodological work on causation itself

    opens the way to a successful metaphysical reduction of causes to

    probabilistic generalizations. I am thinking of Bayesian Nets. The

    Bayesian Nets literature shows that, for any arrangement of causes, there

    is a possible set of probabilistic relationships that entails that

    arrangement. (No causes in, no causes out is a practical precept, not a

    principled constraint.) Dan Hausman has written a terrific bookCausal

    Asymmetrybuilding a reductive account of causation on this basis, and

    I have written a couple of articles in the same strain. But as far as I knowwe are the only two people who read the Bayesian Nets stuff in this way.

  • 7/27/2019 Physical David Papineau Interviewed by Richard Marshall

    12/17

    The reason, I suspect, is that nearly everybody else who works on

    Bayesian nets is a methodologist rather than a metaphysician, much more

    interested in the way science proceeds than in the nature of reality. And so

    they think that if scientific practice treats causes as irreducible, then thats

    good enough for them. Still, as I said, it is a bad idea to run metaphysics

    together with methodology in this way. Ive nothing against philosophers

    who are interested in the practicalities of science per se. Its their

    metaphysical aspirations that irk me.

    3:AM: Why dont you want to get into the box with Schrodingers cat and

    what is the significance of this thought experiment?

    DP: Schrdingers cat has a 50% quantum chance of coming out of the

    box alive and a 50% quantum chance of coming out dead. If you got in thebox with it, the same would apply to you. So you really don t want to do

    that.

    I favour an interpretation of quantum mechanics (the Everett

    interpretation) according to which reality branches in any chancy quantum

    situation. On this view, Schrdingers set-up will give rise to in two future

    branches of reality, one with a live cat, and one with a dead catand the

    talk of 50% chances just indicates that the two branches are both equallyreal futures of the cat that originally entered the box.

    Now, some philosophers have tried to make trouble for this interpretation

    by arguing that, if it were true, then you would have no reason not to get in

    the box with the cat. For on the Everett interpretation you would be sure to

    come out of the box alive. True thered also be a future in which you come

    out dead. But whats so bad about that, given that you wont be there to

    experience it, and that you survive happily in the only future that you willexperience?

    This is a terrible argument (and not made any better by David Lewis

    defending it at length in his last published papersee my David Lewis

    and Schrdingers Cat.) There may be good objections to the Everett

    interpretation, but this isnt one.

    Everybody agrees that a future in which you are dead is a very bad thing,

    and that it isnt made any better by your not being around to notice how

  • 7/27/2019 Physical David Papineau Interviewed by Richard Marshall

    13/17

    bad it is.

    Everettians will simply agree with this, and observe that it follows that it s a

    bad idea to get in the box with the cat. Doing so will cause the universe to

    contain a future where you are dead, alongside the one where you are

    alive, rather than leaving it as a universe where you are alive in all futures.Since a future where you are dead is a very bad thing, you really don t

    want to do that.

    3:AM: It seems to many people thinking about such matters that many of

    our complex cognitive capacities are innate, but that raises the issue

    about how they could be? How could we have evolved an innate capacity

    to recognize doorknobs, say, given that presumably when we were

    evolving our minds we didnt have doorknobs?

    DP: I dont have much use for the concept of innateness. The everyday

  • 7/27/2019 Physical David Papineau Interviewed by Richard Marshall

    14/17

    concept incorporates a number of different notions that can come apart in

    in many ways, and as a result encourages a range of dangerously

    fallacious inferences.

    Nor is it easy to tidy up the concept. I guess the best move is to try to

    equate innate with not learned. But this really only works as a necessarycondition. It looks a bit dotty as a sufficient condition. (Is my newfound

    ability to sing innate, just because it wasnt learned, but caused by that

    bang on the head last week?)

    Even if we go with the idea of innate as not learned, I doubt that anything

    worth calling a cognitive capacity will come out as innate. This is because

    it seems unlikely that evolution would ever bother to write the whole of any

    cognitive capacity into the genes, so to speak, instead of allowinginformation from the environment to play at least some part in shaping it.

    Of course our genes will make some capacities very much easier to learn

    than others, and of course our genes themselves are not learned. But the

    point remains that genes themselves are not cognitive capacities, and that

    anything worth calling a cognitive capacity will depend to some degree on

    learning and so not be innate.

    Having said that, I do have quite a lot of sympathy for Fodors picture ofconcepts as information-free atomic entities which get locked onto their

    referents causally, and to that extent they neednt involve anything much

    in the way of learning. But even so it seems perverse to call them innate.

    Here we see again the oddity of treating not learned as sufficient for

    innate. Even if no learning to speak of was involved in locking my mental

    term onto doorknobs, it is odd to say that therefore my possession of a

    doorknob concept is innate, just as it is odd to say that my head-injury-

    caused singing is innate.

    3:AM: As a physicalist youll say that all laws are physical laws I guess.

    But a non-physicalist will say that there are non-physical laws such as

    laws in economics, or biology and psychology. Fodor writes about these

    as special sciences. Do you think there can be special sciences?

    DP: No, I think that there are non-physical laws all right: genuine (if not

    strict) laws written in the language of biology, economics, and so on. But Idont regard that as a contentious issue. Even reductionists about

  • 7/27/2019 Physical David Papineau Interviewed by Richard Marshall

    15/17

    chemistry will think that there are special chemical laws whose formulation

    makes essential use of chemical terminology.

    The contentious issue is whether there are any special laws that aren t

    reducible to physics. Fodor says yes, but I have always thought that there

    are issues here. It has always puzzled me, along with Jaegwon Kim andNed Block, that there should be genuine lawlike patterns at the special

    level, if physicalism is true (as Fodor agrees) yet the special laws are

    variably realized by different physical processes in different cases (as

    Fodor insists). Why should we always get the same results in the same

    circumstances, if what is going on at the physical level is so different in

    each case?

    In a number of papers I have explored the idea that natural selectionmight fill the gap. Sometimes selection processes can ensure that there is

    always some mechanism to produce such-and-such an effect in such-and-

    such circumstances, even though that mechanism will be different in

    different cases. All territorial birds have some way of discouraging

    conspecific invaders, but the mechanisms vary (songs, displays,

    odours, . . .). Natural selection has ensured that each species achieves

    the requisite effect somehow, but it doesnt care, so to speak, how the trick

    is done.

    I still think that this story works in some cases, especially in the case of

    people learning skills and other social behaviours (individual learning is a

    kind of selection process). But more recently I have become interested in

    another possible source of variably realized special science laws. The

    idea is inspired by Ruth Millikans notion of a historical kind. Millikan

    observes that some categorieschemical compounds, clouds, stars

    enter into a range of generalizations because their instances have acommon physical essence. These are eternal kinds. But other categories

    enter into a range of generalizations because they are all copied from a

    common source. These are historical kinds. For example, all the many

    copies of the Bible have the same first word, the same second word, and

    so on. Each individual version of the Nuer belief system contains the

    same tenet about twins, about ancestral spirits, and so on.

    I now think that many generalizations of interest in the special sciences

  • 7/27/2019 Physical David Papineau Interviewed by Richard Marshall

    16/17

  • 7/27/2019 Physical David Papineau Interviewed by Richard Marshall

    17/17

    to concrete reality.

    Let me finish with more two recent books that I learnt much from.

    Peter Godfrey-Smith. Darwinian Populations. This book focuses on

    concepts that are generally taken for granted in philosophic thinking aboutnatural selection, such as organism, heredity and reproduction. By

    challenging these notions Godfrey-Smith brings out what is and isnt

    essential to natural selection and opens up a fascinating range of new

    issues in the philosophy of biology.

    Richard Holton. Wanting Willing Waiting. Holton distinguishes two

    notions of weakness of willacting against your better judgement, and

    failing to stick to your resolutionsand shows that they are quite different.The book explores the latter idea, and uses a wide range of empirical

    studies to cast new light on such topics as will-power, temptation,

    addiction and free will.

    ABOUT THE INTERVIEWER

    Richard Marshall is still biding his time.

    Share on facebook

    Share on gmail

    Share on twitter

    Share on email

    More Sharing Services

    First published in 3:AM Magazine: Monday, April 8th, 2013.