Pantheism in Spinoza and the German Idealists

download Pantheism in Spinoza and the German Idealists

of 16

Transcript of Pantheism in Spinoza and the German Idealists

  • 8/16/2019 Pantheism in Spinoza and the German Idealists

    1/16

    Pantheism in Spinoza and the German Idealists

    F. C. Copleston

    Philosophy, Vol. 21, No. 78. (Apr., 1946), pp. 42-56.

    Stable URL:

    http://links.jstor.org/sici?sici=0031-8191%28194604%2921%3A78%3C42%3APISATG%3E2.0.CO%3B2-A

    Philosophy is currently published by Cambridge University Press.

    Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available athttp://www.jstor.org/about/terms.html. JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless you have obtainedprior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you may use content inthe JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use.

    Please contact the publisher regarding any further use of this work. Publisher contact information may be obtained athttp://www.jstor.org/journals/cup.html.

    Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printedpage of such transmission.

    The JSTOR Archive is a trusted digital repository providing for long-term preservation and access to leading academic journals and scholarly literature from around the world. The Archive is supported by libraries, scholarly societies, publishers,and foundations. It is an initiative of JSTOR, a not-for-profit organization with a mission to help the scholarly community takeadvantage of advances in technology. For more information regarding JSTOR, please contact [email protected].

    http://www.jstor.orgFri Feb 22 09:40:52 2008

    http://links.jstor.org/sici?sici=0031-8191%28194604%2921%3A78%3C42%3APISATG%3E2.0.CO%3B2-Ahttp://www.jstor.org/about/terms.htmlhttp://www.jstor.org/journals/cup.htmlhttp://www.jstor.org/journals/cup.htmlhttp://www.jstor.org/about/terms.htmlhttp://links.jstor.org/sici?sici=0031-8191%28194604%2921%3A78%3C42%3APISATG%3E2.0.CO%3B2-A

  • 8/16/2019 Pantheism in Spinoza and the German Idealists

    2/16

    PANTHEISlM I N S PIN O ZA A N D T H E G E R M A N

    IDEALISTS

    F.

    C.

    COPLESTON

    J. M A

    IN an essay on pantheism Schopenhauer observes that his chief

    objection against it is tha t it says nothing , th at it simply enriches

    language with a superfluous synonym of the word world. I t can

    hardly be denied that by this remark the great pessimist, who was

    himself an atheist, scored a real point. For if a philosopher starts

    off with th e physical world and proceeds to call i t God, he ha s no t

    added anything to the world except a label, a label which, if we

    ta ke into account the ord inary significance of the word

    God, might well app ear unnecessary and superfluous: one might

    just as pertinently say th at the world is the world as th at the world

    is God. Neither the Jew nor the Christian nor the Moslem under-

    stan d by God the physical world, so th at , if someone calls th e

    physical world God, he cannot be taken to mean that the world is

    God according t o th e Jewish or Christian or Moslem understanding

    of God. Does he mean any more than that the physical world is

    ultimately self-explanatory, that no Cause external to the world,

    no transce nde nt Being is requisite or admissible, i.e. th at there is no

    G o d ? If th at were all there is in pantheism, the l att er would indeed

    be indistinguishable from atheism, and those who called Spinoza

    an atheist would be fully justified.

    As far as Spinoza is concerned,

    I

    do not hesitate to say that his

    system , when looked a t under one of its aspects, is indeed atheistic,

    and t h at , so far as th at aspect is concerned, th e word God, which

    he em ploys so frequently, is a superfluous label. Some of those w ho

    accused Spinoza of atheism h ad a personal and interested m otive

    in doing so, for, hav ing undergone the influence of Descartes and

    realising the app arent connection between Spinszism an d C artesian-

    ism, the y were eager t o dissociate themselves from a system,

    which, at least superficially, seemed to have its roots in the phil-

    osophy of the Fren chm an, and what more effective means could they

    employ to dissociate themselves from that system than abuse of

    i ts au th o r? I But even if some of those w ho accused Spinoza of

    atheism had an interested motive in doing so, it does not follow th at

    I d~ not say this out of any hostility to Cartesians, long since dead, nor,

    of course,

    do

    accuse them of any insincerity: their at ti tude was only natural

    in view

    of

    some consequences which, as Leibniz hints, might seem to follow

    from Descartes doctrine.

    4

  • 8/16/2019 Pantheism in Spinoza and the German Idealists

    3/16

    P A N T H E I S M I N S P I N O Z A A N D G ER M A N I D E A L I S T S

    this judgment was necessarily withou t foundation. F rom one point

    of view Spinozism can be regarded a s the u tm ost possible generali-

    sation of th e at tit ud e of contemporary science towards the m aterial

    world, as a linking up of all phenom ena, physical an d psychical,

    pas t, present and to come, in one great interconnected system, one

    intelligible and self-dependent cosmos. Looked at from this point of

    view, Spinozism is atheistic, for to call t he cosmos God is to denude

    th e term God of all its tradition al significance and to render i t mean-

    ingless. If the cosmos is God, there is no God, and th e m an who

    declares th a t th ere is no God is an athe ist. Thus , if taken in its

    determ inistic, mechanical,

    scientifico-mathematical

    aspect, Spinozism

    is an atheistic system.

    This aspect, however, is not the only aspect under which the

    philosophy of Spinoza car1 be regarded . Ben eath the logical schema-

    tism of thi s massive system, with its definitions and

    axioms, its propositions and proofs, its Q.E.D.'s and it s corollaries,

    which appear so cold and dispassionate, there can be heard the cry

    of a

    TYeltschmerz

    of a hunger for the Infinite. In the

    Tractatus de

    intellectus emendatiogzs

    Spinoza speaks of the va ni ty an d futil ity of

    th e pursu it of riches or fame or pleasure, and declares th a t i t is only

    love for a th ing etern al an d infinite which is the source of unmixed

    joy, while his ethical system culminates in the amor intellectualis

    Dei.

    It is true that Spinoza's philosophy is extremely intellectualist,

    and th at his conception of love as an active and ration al emotion

    is scarcely what we ordinarily understand by the term love: but it

    is also true that there is discernible in his thought and attitude a

    reaching ou t beyond the tra ns ito ry phenomena of experience to th e

    Infinite Being of w hich th ey a re th e manifestation . God, for Spinoza,

    was certainly no t the personal Creator-God of orthodox Jud aism,

    bu t He was the In finite, the ultim ately real, possessed of an infinity

    of att rib ut es , and the charac ter of infinity, the ascription t o God of

    attributes unknown to the human mind, most probably permitted

    a psychological attitude towards the infinite Substance which

    Spinoza could hardly have adopted towards the actual world of

    experience considered precisely as such. In his Ethics Spinoza starts

    with God, the self-explan atory Subs tance, the principle of intelligi-

    bility, so that God was, in a sense, something more real than His

    manifestations or modes, more ultimate, as though God were the

    ocean and God's finite modes, th e existential dur at ion of which is

    transitory, the waves and ripples on the ocean's surface. Substance

    m ay no t exist a pa rt from i ts successive modifications, determined

    in their natu re and succession, b u t it is easy to see tha t,

    in so far as Spinoza's mind w as fixed on the infinitude of th e Sub-

    stance, the phenomenal world could take on the appearance of

    comparative unreality: God was All. From this standpoint Spinoza

    4

  • 8/16/2019 Pantheism in Spinoza and the German Idealists

    4/16

    P H I L O S O P H Y

    can scarcely be called an atheist, for, though he does not conceive

    God as Spirit, it is the world, rather than God, that he suppresses.

    "Spinozism," say s Hegel, "might really just a s well or even bet te r

    hav e been terme d Acosmism (tha n atheism), since according to its

    teaching it is not to the world, finite existence, the universe, that

    reality and permanency are to be ascribed, but rather to God alone

    as the substantial."

    B ut if there is an aspect of Spinozistic panthe ism un der which it

    cannot simply be termed atheistic, it does no t follow tha t i t escapes

    from othe r ob jections which can be levelled against it precisely in so

    far as it is pantheistic and no t atheistic. For exam ple, if one sta rts

    with the infinite Substance, God, it is impossible to demonstrate

    th a t t he m odifications of Substance mus t follow or t o explain their

    appearance, for an infinite Substance will, ips0

    facto

    realise all its

    potentialities in undivided simplicity: to speak strictly, it will have

    no potentialities, b u t will be Act pure an d simple. am no t, of course,

    dem anding th at Spinoza should deduce the actu al series of pa rticulars,

    for he observes th a t to d o this is beyond the power of the hu m an

    mind, which is a reasonable answer, even on the pantheistic hy-

    pothesis. But, since it is his express teaching that contingency has

    reference only to th e imperfection of our hu ma n an d limited know-

    ledge, it follows th a t t he modifications of Substance are in them -

    selves determined an d necessary, no t co ntingent, a nd one is justified

    in d emand ing a dem onstratio n of this necessity in general, for it is

    essential to the pantheistic position. Again, when Spinoza distin-

    guishes the different levels of cognition, from imuginatio up to the

    intuition of th e To tality , he does no t explain how inadeq uate ideas

    can exist a t all. If they exist, then the y mus t be referred u ltimately

    to God, since all tha t exists is in Go d: bu t how can God have inade-

    qu ate ideas, even u nder an d through His finite modifications? Th e

    notion that one is a person distinct from God may be an incorrect

    notion, but, if so, how does it come abou t th a t such a notion can be

    formed and is frequently formed Moreover, th e difficulties atte nd ing

    Spinoza's ethical system are obvious to all serious stud en ts of his

    philosophy as a whole. Blyenbergh's controversial letters may or

    may not have been tiresome productions, but, as the late Professor

    de Burgh rem arked , his objections remained unanswered for the ve ry

    simple reason that they were unanswerable.

    Of

    course it may well

    have been better for Spinoza to be inconsistent rather than con-

    sistent, since his ratio nal eth ic gives evidence of his personal high-

    mindedness, but internal inconsistency cannot be considered a

    testimonial for a system of philosophy. Spinoza, unlike Descartes,

    did not start from

    a

    fac t of experience bu t from a hypo the tical

    unique Substance, a me taphysica l llypothesis no t given in experience,

    with the result th at he ha d, "absent-mindedly" (as Kierkegaard

  • 8/16/2019 Pantheism in Spinoza and the German Idealists

    5/16

    P A N T H E I S M I N S P I N O Z A A N D G E RM A N I D E A L I S T S

    remarked apro+os of Hegel), to forget and leave unexplained data

    of experience which obviously needed exp lanation . Leibniz, on th e

    other hand, though convinced, like Spinoza, that Reality is an

    intelligible and significant system, was led by his regard for experi-

    ence, for individuality, for activity, to postulate a different kind of

    unity from th at postulated b y Spinoza, maintaining bo th th e plurality

    of indiv idual beings an d the significance an d intelligibility of the

    hierarchy of being as a whole.

    The hostile attitude to Spinozism which prevailed for a long

    time gave way to a new at tit ud e towards th e end of t he eighteenth

    ce ntur y, an d Novalis' descrip tion of Spinoza as the God-intoxicated

    man is well enough known. The Romantics, however, tended to

    look on Spinoza through their own coloured spectacles. That the

    latter's logical schematism was shot through and enlivened, for

    Spinoza himself, by

    a religious awe in presence of the Infinite and by

    a conform ity to the Divine Will is, as have suggested above,

    probably true: but any personal piety there may have been on the

    philosopher's part should be traced, not so much to his system and

    its effect as to his upbringing in a Jewish family an d t o a transference

    t o Dezcs-substantia of the psychological at ti tu de th a t a n or tho do x

    Jew would manifest tow ards the Creator-God of Judaism . T here is

    little indication in the pages of Spinoza's writings th a t he felt an y

    of th at emotion in the fa ce of phenomenal Natu re which roman tic

    poets have shown (tho ugh th at , of course, does not prove t h at he

    never felt such emotion) he speaks little, if a t all, of the bea uty of

    Nature. He was doubtless filled with ad miration an d wonder a t t he

    sight of the reign of law, a t th e majesty of the cosmos as an eterna l,

    significant and coherent system, just as he found that he could not

    be satisfied with an y m erely finite good: b ut we should certainly no t

    look to the Ethics for the poetic, quasi-mystical emotion manifested

    by romantic poets towards the natural Totality, an emotion partly

    inspired by th e keen perception of n atu ral beau ty, as also by a

    feeling, no t essentially based on science and m athem atics a nd logical

    reasoning, of one Life pulsating in N ature as a whole and in the

    hum an frame. If one can safely refer to F aust's famous declaration

    to Margarete withou t laying oneself open to th e charge of having

    dub bed Goethe a romantic, Spinoza would never have said,

    Gefiihl ist Alles: it was no t f o r no thing th a t he spoke of th e love of

    God a s the intellectual love of God. T he rev ival of inte rest in Spinoza

    da tes from th e time of the correspondence between Jacobi a nd

    Mendelssohn, and i t is only na tur al for us to-da y t o look back on his

    system in the light of German ph ilosophy: but we should do well to

    remember that Spinoza's acquaintance was with Jewish Neo-

    platonic speculation, with Cartesianism, and with a certain amount

    of Scholasticism. The conception of the divine Substance, modified

    5

  • 8/16/2019 Pantheism in Spinoza and the German Idealists

    6/16

    P H I L O S O P H Y

    in it s manifestations, might be term ed a conflation of th e Neo-

    platonic em ana tion theory w ith th e Scholastic doctrine of created

    substance and accidents, a conflation made and thought out in face

    of th e Cartesian dualism, thou gh itself strong ly influenced by Carte-

    sian themes. Spinoza was a philosopher who was convinced th at th e

    intellect can find its satisfaction only in the Infinite, and in this

    respect his thought, despite its mathematico-scientific aspects,

    betray s some kinship with th at of Plotinus and St. Augustine: b u t

    he was not an aesthetic romanticist .

    W hen one turn s from the philosophy of Spinoza to t h a t of the

    elder Fichte, it is as though one were transported from a gallery

    of sculpture to th e sta nd a t an Olympic race: th e atmosphe re of

    quiet contemplation gives place to one of energy and activity.

    Generalisations, of course, are often inaccurate and loose, and

    Spinozism cannot justly be called a merely static philosophy, while

    there is more in the system of F ichte tha n a n emphasis on ac tio n;

    but it is probably not fanciful to see the difference in character

    between th e retiring Jewish lens-grinder an d the pa trio t who delivered

    the Addresses to the German People and wished to go as philo-

    sophic chaplain to the Prussian troops in the war of liberation

    reflected

    in

    their respective philosophies. Moreover, the dominion

    of the geometrical method and of mechanical physics had been

    invaded by a new sense of historical becoming, of development,

    which was, be it remarke d, p ar tly d ue to th e work of Leibniz, in

    spit e of those who would see in his philosophy nothin g b ut logic and

    mathematics exceeding their limits. German speculative idealism

    was certainly influenced by Spinoza, but the Spinozistic pantheism

    was rethough t in a more dynamic form and (a most im port ant point)

    it h ad passed throug h th e fire of t he K an tian Critique, a fact which

    rendered a new approach inevitable, for the post-Kantian idealist

    would be unable t o sta rt from the concept of substance.

    K a n t affirmed th e transcen dental ego as logical condition of the

    un ity of experience, tho ug h it was no t for him an object of the oretical

    knowledge. Fich te seized on th e idea of th e transcende ntal ego (as

    the I-subject, which is always presupposed by the I-object, but

    never itself becomes object) and tried to deduce therefrom empirical

    consciousness. Protesting t h a t the Ka ntia n thing-in-itself was a n

    unnecessary piece of luggage, once given the Kantian Critique, he

    declared that by denying the existence of the thing-in-itself he was

    b u t rendering K an t consistent with himself, declaration which m a y

    have been largely justified in fact, though Kant himself rejected the

    claim. However, whether Fichte was fulfilling Kant or maiming

    him, he obviously could not, in making the object the creation of

    th e subject, ma ke it the creation of the empirical subject as such,

    since it is clear enough that the object is something given to the

    6

  • 8/16/2019 Pantheism in Spinoza and the German Idealists

    7/16

    P NTHEISM IN SPINOZ ND GERM N IDE LISTS

    empirical sub ject, something which it finds in existence, w ith w hich

    it is confronted. He had, therefore, to derive the object , not from

    the empirical subject but from the meta-empirical subject , the

    transcendental ego. Th e lat ter, the n, became his start ing-po int , and

    from the transcendental ego he attempted to deduce dialectically

    th e division of experience in to the empirical subje ct and t he empirical

    objec t. K an t s logical condition of experience th us beca me

    a

    real

    an d ultim ate principle of exp lanation in regard t o hu m an experience.

    As fa r as a mere th eo ry of knowledge is concerned, as far as the re

    is question only of a logical ana lysis of experience, one migh t tr ea t

    th e transcendental ego as a principle of explanation w ithou t com-

    m itting oneself to an y definite state m en t as to it s ontological sta tus ,

    with ou t affirming th at there is one transc end ental ego or a plurality,

    without coming down definitely either on the side of idealistic

    monism or on that of pluralism. After all, Aristotle taught the

    existence of an active intellect, bu t, so far as we are concerned, it

    remains doubtful w hether he po stulated one active intellect com mon

    to all men, as the Averroists interpreted him, or ascribed an indi-

    vidual active intellect to each individual man, as St . Tho mas Aquinas

    interpreted him. B ut i t i s obviously a short s tep to take from th e

    assertion of th e transc end ental ego as ulti m ate principle in th e

    analysis of experience t o th e assertion th a t i t is th e Transcendental

    Ego with capi ta l le t ters : in fact in a f d y idealis t philosophy this

    transition would seem t o be inevitable, if solipsism is t o be avoided ,

    and F ichte stoutly denied th at he was a solipsist. I n Fichte s system ,

    therefore, K an t s tran scen den tal ego blossomed ou t as th e Absolute

    Eg o, the ultim ate source of finite sub jects and o bjects (or ra th er of

    finite subjects and of finite objects via the former), the modest

    Ka ntian theo ry of th e su bject s active constitutive function in

    knowledge turning into a system of Transcendental Subjective

    Idealism.

    It is not, however, very easy to see exactly how Fichte regarded

    the relation between the finite consciousness and the Absolute Ego.

    I t is obvious enough th a t he could not teach pantheism in th e sense

    of sim ply identifying N atu re with God an d God with Na ture, since

    Nature was, for him, no more than object-for-a-subject: in an

    idealist sy stem of the typ e propou nded by Fich te natur alistic

    monism was ou t of t h e question and also substan tial pantheism. H e

    could no t identify God with S ubstance, if substance was som ething

    secondary a nd derive d: th e concept of subs tance was th e result of

    th e application of an a iriori form, and th at form was derivate an d

    not ultim ate. (This inability t o a dm it t h e su bstan tiality of

    God was one of th e reasons why F ich te was accused of atheism , a

    charge the justice of which he indignantly d enied.) B u t wh at was th e

    precise relation between the Transcendental Ego and the finite

    7

  • 8/16/2019 Pantheism in Spinoza and the German Idealists

    8/16

    P H I L O S O P H Y

    eg o? W as the la tte r a canalisation, as it w ere, of the former, an

    em anation of the un itary E g o ? Such would be the pantheistic

    interpretation, and there is certainly much in the philosopher's

    writings which would seem to make such an interpretation not only

    justifiable but also inevitable. Yet it must be remembered that

    the reason why the world is posited is, for Fichte, that it should

    serve as a field for free mo ral endeavou r. There is one moral law, bu t

    i t is manifested in the particu lar m oral vocations of finite individuals,

    and , in so far as they fulfil their m oral vocation, they contribute to

    the concrete realisation of the m oral world-order. This fine conception.

    with its emphasis on moral activity and freedom, not only corre-

    sponded to Fich te's energetic charac ter, bu t is also in conflict with an y

    complete pantheism, since the latter is, logically speaking, deter-

    ministic in charac ter. How ever, even if, as is probab le, Fichte's

    deduction of th e finite ego is justly taken to im ply a kind of e m ana tion

    or a self-diremption of the Absolute Eg o within itself, he went on

    in late r years to develop a m ore religious version of his system in

    which the Absolute Ego or Moral W ill appears rath er as the Absolute

    Being, of which finite egos are the manifestations, and to which they

    should strive consciously to return, though no individual is ever

    completely absorbed or swallowed up in God. There seems to be

    envisaged an unending app rox im ation to God, reminiscent of K an t's

    theo ry of th e asym pto tic approach t o moral perfection: Fich te was

    too energetic in character to yield to the fascination of the idea th at

    all individuals are at length completely merged in the one Being.

    He would no t, it is true, allow th at G od is "personal," bu t th a t was

    because he regarded the a scription of person ality to God as neces-

    sarily anthropom orphic, because he though t of God as supra-person al,

    which is not the same th ing as infra-personal.

    Th e strong ly religious an d m ore contem plative aspect of Fich te's

    later philosophy appears especially in his so-called popular works,

    works w hich Hegel dismisses in his

    istory of Philosophy

    as edifying

    but irrelevant from the philosophic viewpoint. But though the

    lectures t o which refer m ay not have been composed from a stan d-

    point which Hegel would recognise as adequately speculative, and

    though i t is the standpoint of the

    Wissenschaftslekre

    which one has

    to take most into account when one is considering the historical

    connection between Fichte, SchelLing and Hegel, the lectures are of

    som e im portanc e when one is considering the system of Fich te by

    itself, fo r they indicate the direction taken by th e philosopher's

    tho ug ht in his later years. They sm ack somewhat of the pu lpit, b u t

    all three of th e great G erman m etaphysical idealists began with th e

    stu dy of theology, and Fic hte often tend ed to a do pt the role of a

    philosophic preacher. W hether the cha racter of his late r

    works should be taken to indicate an advance from idealistic

    8

  • 8/16/2019 Pantheism in Spinoza and the German Idealists

    9/16

    P A N T H E I S M I N S P I N O Z A A N D G E R M A N I D E A L I S T S

    pantheism to unequivocal theism or not, is obscure; but in my

    opinion F ichte never was an o ut-an d-ou t pantheist. T h at his idealist

    standpoint effectually prevented his asserting pantheism of the

    Spinozistic br an d, hav e alread y noted, as also th at his insistence

    on freedom a nd mo rali ty appears t o be inconsistent with a n y rigorous

    form of pan theism . Leaving ou t of account th e very g reat differences

    in content and atmosphere between their systems, one might insti-

    tut e a comparison between Fichte 's thoug ht, a t least in i ts more

    developed stages, an d t h a t of Plotinus. Th e latte r did not believe

    in free creation ou t of no thing an d employed th e meta pho r of e m ana-

    tion to express th e procession of subo rd ina te hyp ostases, an d ulti-

    m ately of t h e world, from th e One, b ut h e insisted th at th e One was

    not in a ny w ay diminished thro ugh the eman ation. So Fichte, in m y

    opinion, while no t p repared to accept literally th e Christian doctrine

    of creation, did not believe th a t t h e Absolute is diminished or changed

    throu gh th e emergence of finite consciousnesses. In oth er words,

    neither the system of Plotinus nor th a t of F ichte can be term ed

    unequivocal theism or unambiguous pantheism.

    f

    imman-

    ence receives th e em phasis in F ichte's earlier thoug ht, th e transcend-

    ence of t he Absolute is m ore emphasised in his later developm ent,

    and th at is probably as far as we can get .

    The sy stem of Fich te was a system of transc end ental subjective

    idealism, characterised by a strongly marked ethical interest: in

    th e syste m of Schelling a rom an tic view of N atu re is subs titute d for

    Fichte 's theory that Nature is a mere means to moral endeavour,

    and the lat ter 's dyna mic att i tud e gives place t o one more contempla-

    tive in tone, artistic creation and aesthetic experience receiving the

    emphasis rather than moral striving and self-conquest. To speak of

    the system of Schelling m ay occasion surprise in view of th e fac t

    that historians of philosophy have been accustomed to discover a

    nu m be r of philosophies held successively by Schelling; bu t, on the

    one hand, the stages of his thought do not constitute separate

    philosophical sy stem s so much as th e result of fur the r reflection on

    positions already attained, so that they exhibit a more or less con-

    tinuous process of developm ent, while, on th e o ther han d, it is the

    middle stage which is really chara cteris tic of Schelling, more so

    than his earl ier Fichtean standpoint or the somewhat bizarre

    speculations of his later years when he w as trying t o coun teract t he

    influence of Hegel a t Berlin. confine m y att en tio n, therefo re, to

    th e stage (or stages) represented by th e philosophy of Na ture an d

    the system of Identity.

    As he moved aw ay from the position of F ich te, Schelling cam e to

    conceive of Nature as a meaningful organism, a totality, striving

    upw ards tow ards consciousness und er th e impulse of th e W orld-soul

    or principle of organisation in the cosmos. Nature is not the dead

    D

    9

  • 8/16/2019 Pantheism in Spinoza and the German Idealists

    10/16

    P H I L O S O P H Y

    m aterial of our du ty , but is a d ynam ic process in which things are

    bu t trans ito ry products of an endless becoming. There is one stre am

    of Life in N atu re, bu t Na ture, which is always striving after th e

    perfect representation of the Absolute, differentiates herself on

    various specific levels into those individuals, the succession a nd

    tran sitory character of w hich betra y th e fact t h a t the y a re unsuccess-

    ful attempts to manifest the Absolute. In its highest production,

    however, human consciousness, Nature is enabled to turn back on

    herself an d t o realise her un ity in reflection. The highest developm ent

    of consciousness is achieved in a rtistic genius and it s creations, for

    in th e w ork of a rt th e Infinite and the ideal are perfectly represented

    in finite form , an d th e syn thesis of freedom a nd necessity is brought

    about.

    If in his philosophy of Natu re Schelling proceeded from th e side

    of the ob ject, in his system of tra nsce nde ntal idealism he star te d

    with the subject and tried t o show how spirit issues forth from itself

    until it reaches its supreme expression in aesthetic experience and

    it s fullest objectification in ar tistic creation, th e two poles of s piri t

    an d m atter, subject an d object, being united in the work of ar t and

    perfec tly fused together. Reflection on this finite union of sp irit an d

    na tur e led Schelling to the conception of the Absolute as S pirit

    and N ature i n ide nti ty : the A bsolute is the pure iden tity of Being

    and Thought, standing behind all finite manifestations, all differ-

    en tiatio ns , as the vanish ing-point of all differences, the a ll-embracing

    and undivided Ide ntity . (Schelling proceeded to introduce from

    Platonism an ete rna l world of Ideas, God's intu itions of H imself,

    th e true things-in-themselves, which are the exemplars of all empirical

    things, an d which it is the sublime function of t he arti st to rep resent

    in the concrete work of a rt .)

    Schelling's conception of N atu re as a to tali ty, a living an d dyn am ic

    process, a self-organising cosmos, was thorough ly rom antic in

    character, as also was the position assigned to the art ist, to aesthetic

    con templation and the work of a rt . Of course, Schelling was influ-

    enced by other philosophers who could scarcely be classed as

    romantics (e.g. his theory of N atu re below m an as slumbering spirit

    is reminiscent of p oin ts in th e Monadology of Leibniz , while his

    doc trine of the work of a rt a s the synthesis of freedom and necessity

    is partly an a ttem pt to settle a problem of K an t), bu t he was the

    great philosopher of the German romantic movement, fully imbued

    with the general romanticist worship of the To tality. For the

    logical and mathe matica l schematism of Spinoza he substituted

    the conception of life, of m ovement, of N atur e as a living uni ty ,

    a self-unfolding organism, an d in this he m ay be said w ith justice t

    h a r e constructed a rom antic and poetic Spinozism. B u t whereas the

    intuition postu lated b y Spinoza was primarily an intuition of t he

    50

  • 8/16/2019 Pantheism in Spinoza and the German Idealists

    11/16

    P A N T H E I S M I N S P I N O Z A A N D G ER M A N I D E A L I S T S

    To tality as an articu lated system , of Substance

    in

    its m anifestations,

    an d of the m odifications according to the ir place in Substance,

    Schelling's intuition of the Absolute was the intuition of a formless

    identity , a quasi-m ystical apprehension of (t o use Hegel's caustic

    phrase) the night in which all cows are black. In Schelling, as in

    Spinoza, we can see a certain desire for the Infinite, but it is signifi-

    cant that in the case of Schelling that Infinite is without form and

    void: he would have the Infinite, but it must be an Infinite in which

    all forms are indistinguishably merged, neither an infinite System

    nor infinite Form-a true roman ticist. (I n his late r thou ght Schelling

    advanced to a theistic position, accompanied b y various speculative

    extravaganza s, bu t i t is not to m y point to speak of his later theism.)

    If Fichte's emphasis on the Subject and Schelling's emphasis on

    the Object may be said to stand to one another as respectively

    thesis and antithesis, it was left to Hegel to attempt the synthesis,

    an d, whatever one may thin k of t he Hegelian system as such, one

    must admit that he was admirably equipped for the task. This

    bourgeois professor, who acquired a vast store of erudition ,

    patiently collected (even if his information was not always particu-

    larly accura te), was yet no t overwhelmed by t he weight of thi s

    intellectual baggage, bu t, w ith a tru ly astonishing power of syn-

    thesis, dialectical subtlety and imaginative insight, was able to

    car ry th e tout ensemble an d t o orde r it systematically in a grandiose

    an d com prehensive philosophy. K ierkegaard rema rked once th a t if

    Hegel h ad meant his system t o be simply an intellectual tour de force,

    he would have been the greatest philosopher who ever lived, but as

    he meant it seriously lie is merely a joke. Whether one agrees or not

    with Kierkegaard's sarcastic observation, it obviously presupposes

    th at one understand s what Hegel m eant, and yet th at is precisely

    the difficulty, to u nderstand exactly w hat Hegel meant by his

    system. One can, it is true, understand without much troub le Hegel's

    view of the relation of rom ant ic to classic a rt , or of reason to fa ith,

    or of the S tate to civil society, bu t t o und erstand rightly, and t o

    be able to feel sure th a t one un derstan ds rightly, his view of th e

    relation between the world and God, that is not so easy. One can, I

    think, be certain that Hegel did not accept voluntary creation out

    of no thing in time (t ha t he regarded as a theological Vorstzllzlng),

    bu t the obscurity of his language renders it very difficult to see

    wh at he really believed concerning the world's relation to G od. I n

    such poin ts to force an indub itable meaning o ut of Hegel's words is,

    as Ferrier obse rved, rathe r like trying to distil whisky ou t of a loaf

    of bread. In discussing the question of Hegel's theism or pantheism

    one is, then, hardly entitled to dogm atise, to assert th a t one's own

    interp retation is th e only possible or reasonable interp retation .

    K an t had asserted the p artial constitution by the sub ject of the

  • 8/16/2019 Pantheism in Spinoza and the German Idealists

    12/16

    P H I L O S O P H Y

    object as phenomenon, Fichte went on to assert the tot al constitu-

    tion of th e object by t he subject (in th e sense of th e Tran scend ental

    Ego): Hegel accepted this general idealist position, though he did

    no t accept the one-sided "sub jectivity" of Fi ch te, b u t agreed w ith

    Schell ing that Nature enjoys a more objective status than Fichte

    allowed her. The world, then, in its entirety, including the finite

    consciousness, is th e produ ct of the Cosmic Reas on, th e Id ea, Go d.

    Tho ught canno t be reduced to m atter, bu t we mu st not, as philo-

    sophers, remain in a dualistic position, so that matter must

    ultim ately be reduced to , or be seen as proceeding from

    thought. Being indeed is primary, but ultimate Being, as Aristotle

    saw, is Thought, though we cannot be content with Aristotle's

    position, which leaves Thought, the Idea or self-thinking Thought,

    w ithou t a n y organic connection with t h e world save th at of uncon-

    scious teleological attraction. One must utilise not only the Platonic

    conception of th e Demiurge bu t also th e Christian conception of th e

    p roduction of t he ~ o r l d y God, provided that one realises

    I

    speak

    for Hegel) th a t th e notion of a free an d vo luntary a ct of creation

    on G od's pa rt is an instance of theological anthrop om orph ism

    or symbolism, admirably adapted for the religious consciousness,

    b u t inadmissible from th e speculative stand po int of pure reason.

    The world, then, proceeds from the Absolute, but what is the

    Absolute? It is not simply Substance, as Spinoza thought, nor

    is it Schelling's formless identity: it is Reason or Mind, it is Being,

    but Being in i ts true nature as Idea. Plato l ighted on a real truth,

    th at tru e being is Idea, b ut he failed to work out th e unity of t he

    Id ea or their relation to th e world, while he sepa rated th e I deas an d

    Nous, and did not realise the dynamic, self-expressing character of

    th e former. Th e Universal is indeed th e truly real, but the U niversal

    manifests itself in th e particular.

    Cosmic Reason, then, or the Idea or God manifests itself in the

    world of pa rticu larity , of finitude, imperfectly in N atu re, perfectly

    in Sp irit, above all in the universal philosophic activ ity of the

    hu m an mind . I n this activity the particularity of the individual

    is transcended, man rethinks th e thou ght of G od, apprehend s th e

    Divine Essence as wh at it is, i .e. thou ght, an d God a ttain s "existen-

    tial" self-consciousness in and through the human spirit. Man is

    essentially spirit , bu t he has also his place in Natu re, so th a t in man

    th e synthe sis of the Id ea an d Natu re is achieved. T he whole historical

    process in space and time co nstitutes th e self-manifestation of th e

    Absolute, bu t th e Absolute, being Id ea, can m anifest itself adequa tely

    only in what is like itself, in universal thought, in the history of

    philosophy, which, as a

    manifestation of the Absolute, transcends

    in point of adequacy the sensuous manifestation in art and the

    symbolic represe ntation in d ogm atic theology.

    5

  • 8/16/2019 Pantheism in Spinoza and the German Idealists

    13/16

    P A N T H E I S M I N S P I N O Z A A N D G E RM A N I D E A L I S T S

    W ha t, then, for Hegel is the precise relation of N ature to G od ?

    And w hat is th e precise relation of the finite mind to the m 70rld-

    spirit W as he a pan theist, or was he no t Hegel, it is true, explicitly

    rejected the charge of panthe ism, an d we mu st suppose th a t he

    really attached some meaning to this rejection, and was not simply

    dancing t o th e pipe of ministers, as Schopenhauer pu ts i t ; bu t it

    is no facile task to discover exactly what he did mean. He refused

    to identify this stone or that tree, i.e. the particular as such, con-

    sidered in its particularity, with God; but did he mean to imply

    th at the particular, considered precisely as such, is unreal, an d t h a t

    the real is objective Reason, God, alone? Or did Hegel suppose

    th a t God is simply the noetic stru ctu re of the world, the inside

    of the world, so to spe ak , which a tta ins self-consciousness an d self-

    reflection in and through the human spirit

    In this case the World-

    spirit would be little more than the universal activity of the hum an

    mind, considered as transcending the individual mind, subjective

    spirit, and the Hegelian system would perhaps be more properly

    termed an atheistic than a pantheistic system? Or did he maintain

    that the world is external to God, that God transcends the world

    ontologically, in which case he would be a theist

    That Hegel meant that God is simply the structural principle

    of

    Na ture, which first attain s the st atus of Spirit in man, is to m e

    unthinkable. If he really thought this, he would not have been the

    idealist th at he certainly was. Reason or the Idea must be, a t least

    logically, prior to Nature, and Nature must proceed from the Idea.

    This is clearly ta ug ht by the doctrine of th e dialectic. Moreover, it

    is a notorious fact that Hegel declared that the particular cannot

    be deduced. The critic may think that what Hegel should have

    said is that, though particulars are in principle deducible,

    n

    se,

    the hum an m ind cannot deduce them (and in suppo rt of this it may

    certainly be urged that Hegel stated that philosophy is concerned

    with the universal and not with particulars), but what he actually

    said was, not that

    he

    could not deduce particulars, but that par-

    ticulars could not be deduced. In other words, Hegel admitted an

    element of contingency in Na tu re he insisted th a t Natu re, precisely

    because of th e element of contingency an d imperfection, is an

    inadequate manifestation of the Absolute, that mindless Nature is

    bu t a stage on the road t o the adequ ate manifestation of th e Absolute

    as Spirit. B ut if Hegel was really no more th an an atheist th is element

    of particu larity a nd contingency is left without any explanation,

    and it is inconceivable that Hegel was content to leave unexplained

    the presence of particularity as such, even if philosophy cannot

    deduce any given particular. It may be said that, for Hegel, the

    universal comprises the particular and that the universal, i.e. the

    whole system of universals which co nsti tute s the A bsolute is self-

  • 8/16/2019 Pantheism in Spinoza and the German Idealists

    14/16

    P H I L O S O P H Y

    explanatory, so that the particular requires no further explanation;

    bu t it is obvious th at the u niversal does not comprise the particulars

    in such a way th a t it is confined to a ny given set of particulars (no

    more th an th e S ta te is confined to an y given set of individual

    citizens), so that the particulars must flow from the universal, and,

    if they flow from the universal, the latter is logically prior. The

    Ide a, the n, m ust be prior to th e contingent world of particulars,

    even if it is partially m anifested in th a t world, and in th is case Hegel

    cannot have been an atheist. He may have been a pantheist or a

    theist, bu t he was certainly not an atheist.

    Now, if Reason or the Idea is logically prior to Nature, and

    if

    a t

    th e same time creation through a free act of God is ruled out, the

    world must proceed timelessly from God (in the sense that no first

    mo ment of tim e can, even ideally, be assigned). God, th e Ide a,

    essentially tends to self-objectification, self-expression and mani-

    fest atio n: the Absolute, th e Universal, reflects itself in th e pa rticular

    and the finite, the One being mirrored in the many. Nature is thus

    external to God in the sense that particulars do not belong to the

    Divine Essence considered precisely as such, bu t Na ture is also the

    self-expression of God, God gone over, as it were, into ex tern ality ,

    God in H is otherness. God, by H is very na tur e, tend s to self-manifest-

    ation on th e existen tial level, an d th e first stage of th a t manifesta-

    tion is the Antithesis, mindless Nature, a stage on the road to the

    adequa te man ifestation of God in what is like Himself, in the uni-

    versal thought of the human spirit, The human being, considered

    precisely as the individual Smith or Jones, with his purely private

    thoughts and aspirations, is not God (so Hegel denied that he was

    a pan theist), b u t th e universal and developing though t of m an,

    which transcends the individuals who thin k i t, is the self-manifesta-

    tion of God, progressively reflecting on th e exte rna l level His undi-

    vided essential self-consciousness.

    Admittedly this is obscure, but the Hegelian system must be

    obscure if it is, as I think i t is, neither unambiguous theism no t unam -

    biguous pantheism.

    t

    is not unambiguous theism since the world

    proceeds from God by a necessity of God 's na tu re (thi s is surely the

    ontological fact corresponding

    to

    the logical transition in the

    dialectical deduction), an d th is imm ediately suggests either em anation

    or a k ind of self-diremption of the Absolute within itself. Again,

    there seems to be a tendency to identify the univeral thought of

    m an , not merely w ith a self-manifestation of t he A bsolute on th e

    extern al level, bu t w ith the ac tual self-consciousness of the Absolute.

    The Hegelian system, however, is not unambiguously pantheistic,

    an d could hardly be so, since no t only does Hegel adm it a n element

    of contingency in Nature, but derives Nature from the Cosmic

    Reason, so that human reason also must be a derivative, even if

    5

  • 8/16/2019 Pantheism in Spinoza and the German Idealists

    15/16

    P A N T H E I S M I N S P I N O Z A A N D G E R M A N I D E A L I S T S

    the Cosmic Reason works in and through the human reason. The

    Idea is prior, mindless Nature and the human spirit proceed from

    th e Id ea : the universal an d rational development of N ature an d

    Sp irit are alone tru ly significant and real, bu t th e element of im per-

    fection in Nature and the particularity in the life of subjective

    spirit are existential facts, facts which can only be explained if,

    although God is a t the heart of Na ture an d the hum an m ind, giving

    them significance, the imperfection of N atur e an d th e finitude of

    the particular human mind are due to their being an external

    expression of God or the Idea.

    I n a ny case, even if Hegel s system was fully pan theistic, he did

    no t lay himself open t o Schopenhauer s charge t ha t pantheism is

    simply a masked atheism, for God or the Cosmic Reason would be

    the only Being. He would, however, lay himself open to another

    charge brought by Schopenhauer, to the effect that in so far as

    pantheism has a meaning which is not already contained in atheism,

    it is an absurd ity, since it st ar ts with th e notion of God, borrowed

    from theism, and then goes on to depict God as transforming

    Himself into th e world as we know it. And would not Schopenhauer

    be right? If one starts with the Absolute and then depicts the

    his tory of th e world an d of m an as the Golgotha of th e Absolute,

    one thereb y tends t o cancel ou t the idea of God with which one

    started: not only does God become the eternal Romantic, but He

    becomes also the cosm ic Sufferer. Yet in po int of fact Hegel does

    seem to allow a distinction between God and Nature, as I have

    already indicated, and between God and the finite consciousness.

    He could not possibly identify God and the finite consciousness

    tout court since Nature obviously does not proceed from the finite

    consciousness as such, so th at God must a t least be

    Nore

    than finite

    consciousnesses taken together. Fu rther, as God or th e Id ea manifests

    Himself or itself, not only in and through the finite consciousness

    but also to the finite consciousness, there must be some real distinc-

    tion between them . W hether th e finite consciousness is im m ortal

    or no t, is another question (Hegel does not appear t o h ave troubled

    himself much about the matter), but, while the finite conscious~less

    exists, it cannot, as a particular consciousness, be called God:

    it is in God bu t i t is not God. Hegel s notion thu s seems to me to be

    rathe r one of panentheism tha n rigorous pantheism-a hy brid of

    theism and pantheism, an attem pt to have one s cake and eat i t

    at the same time, largely due to the attempt to force theism into

    the framework of a deductive system. If a philosopher

    st rts

    with

    God an d proceeds to deduce th e world, even if only in essence, some

    form of pantheism is the logical consequence; bu t th e resulting

    pantheism w ill bear far more resemblance to theism if he sta rts

    with th e idea of God as infinite Subject o r as Reason th an if he

  • 8/16/2019 Pantheism in Spinoza and the German Idealists

    16/16

    P H I L O S O P H Y

    sta rts with t he idea of God as Substance and proceeds to deduce

    more geometrico

    I t is perhaps significant th a t some orthodox the ists

    have a t times attemp ted t o "baptise" the H egelian system, whereas

    am n ot aware of any orthodo x theists who have seriously attem pted

    t o bap tise th e system of Spinoza, even if (as is surely possible'with

    any great philosopher) they have found stimulus and interest in

    the content of his philosophy.