On the methodology of isew, gpi... (neumayer, 2000)

15

Click here to load reader

description

Actividad: ¿A qué se refiere el autor con la hipótesis del nivel crítico (threshold hypothesis)?

Transcript of On the methodology of isew, gpi... (neumayer, 2000)

Page 1: On the methodology of isew, gpi... (neumayer, 2000)

Ecological Economics 34 (2000) 347–361

ANALYSIS

On the methodology of ISEW, GPI and related measures:some constructive suggestions and some doubt on the

‘threshold’ hypothesis

Eric NeumayerLondon School of Economics and Political Science, Houghton Street, London WC2A 2AE, United Kingdom

Received 14 October 1999; received in revised form 26 January 2000; accepted 27 January 2000

Abstract

Existing country studies of the Index of Sustainable Economic Welfare (ISEW), the Genuine Progress Indicator(GPI) and related measures, while sharing the same basic methodological approach, differ with respect to thevaluation of important items. This paper provides a critical, but constructive, discussion of the various methods usedfor the valuation of non-renewable resource depletion and long-term environmental damage, and for the weightingof consumption expenditures for income inequalities. Several recommendations are given on how to improve themethodology for future updates of existing studies or for the construction of new measures. Sensitivity analysis showsthat if these recommendations are followed for the valuation of resource depletion and long-term environmentaldamage, then the so-called ‘threshold’ hypothesis, which seems to have gained empirical support from all studiesundertaken so far, fails to materialise. This suggests that, as far as factors related to the environment are concerned,the widening gap between ISEW and GPI on the one hand and gross national product (GNP) on the other, mightbe an artefact of highly contestable methodological assumptions. © 2000 Elsevier Science B.V. All rights reserved.

Keywords: Index; Welfare; Sustainability; Resources; Environmental damage; Inequality

www.elsevier.com/locate/ecolecon

1. Introduction

Following the pioneering work by Daly et al.(1989) and Cobb and Cobb (1994) for the US, theconstruction of an Index of Sustainable Economic

Welfare (ISEW) has become quite popular withstudies undertaken for an increasing number ofcountries. An ISEW has, for example, been con-structed for Austria (Stockhammer et al., 1997),Chile (Castaneda, 1999), Germany (Diefenbacher,1994), Italy (Guenno and Tiezzi, 1998), theNetherlands (Rosenberg, Rosenberg et al., 1995),Scotland (Moffatt and Wilson, 1994), SwedenE-mail address: [email protected] (E. Neumayer).

0921-8009/00/$ - see front matter © 2000 Elsevier Science B.V. All rights reserved.

PII: S 0921 -8009 (00 )00192 -0

Page 2: On the methodology of isew, gpi... (neumayer, 2000)

E. Neumayer / Ecological Economics 34 (2000) 347–361348

(Jackson and Stymne, 1996) and the UK (Jacksonet al., 1997). Sometimes these studies come, withonly slightly changed methodology, under thename of Genuine Progress Indicator (GPI), as, forexample, in Australia (Hamilton, 1999) and theUS (Redefining Progress, 1999). For Australia,there also exists a related measure, which comesunder the name of sustainable net benefit index(SNBI) (Lawn and Sanders, 1999).

Computation of an ISEW/GPI usually startsfrom personal consumption expenditures. Theseexpenditures are weighted with an index of in-come inequality. Then, certain welfare-relevantcontributions are added, such as the services ofhousehold labour and the services of streets andhighways, whereas certain welfare-relevant lossesare subtracted, such as so-called ‘defensive expen-ditures’, costs of environmental pollution, costs ofdepletion of non-renewable resources and long-term environmental damage costs. The resultingindex is regarded as a more accurate indicator ofsustainable economic welfare than a country’sgross national product (GNP), which, accordingto proponents of ISEW/GPI, even if not origi-nally invented for such a purpose, is used bypolicy makers and in everyday language as ayardstick for economic welfare.1

The methodology used for ISEW/GPI studieshas been criticised by some authors, including thepresent one (see Nordhaus, 1992; the contribu-tions in Cobb and Cobb, 1994; Atkinson, 1995;Neumayer, 1999a,b). However, whereas Neu-mayer (1999b), for example, provides a generalconceptual critique, this paper’s objective is moreconfined and more concrete. It aspires to putforward some constructive suggestions on themethodology used for ISEW, GPI and relatedmeasures, and to shed some doubt on the so-called ‘threshold hypothesis’. More specifically, it

focuses on three items: the valuation of the deple-tion of non-renewable resources (Section 2), thevaluation of long-term environmental damage(Section 3) and the adjustment of consumptionexpenditures for income inequality (Section 4).These items exert a significant influence on mostISEW/GPI and related measures.

In evaluating the results of their work, propo-nents of ISEW/GPI have put great emphasis on aclearly discernible trend of the ISEW/GPI in al-most all studies undertaken so far: starting fromaround the 1970s or early 1980s, depending on thecountry, the ISEW/GPI no longer rises very muchor even falls, whereas GNP continues to rise. Asan explanation for this widening gap betweenISEW/GPI and GNP, Max-Neef (1995, p. 117)has put forward the so-called ‘threshold hypothe-sis’: ‘for every society there seems to be a periodin which economic growth (as conventionallymeasured) brings about an improvement in thequality of life, but only up to a point — thethreshold point — beyond which, if there is moreeconomic growth, quality of life may begin todeteriorate’. This ‘threshold hypothesis’ is referredto in almost every recent ISEW/GPI study andMax-Neef (1995, p. 117) himself regarded theevidence from these studies ‘a fine illustration ofthe Threshold Hypothesis’. Anielski (1999, p. 3)suggests that the hypothesis confirms ‘what manyAmericans and Canadians feel and are experienc-ing — the economy and stock exchanges may besoaring but average citizens sense the steady ero-sion of their economic quality of life’.

This paper argues that proponents of ISEW/GPI consider their results too easily as evidencefor the ‘threshold hypothesis’. It suggests that, asfar as depletion of non-renewable resources andlong-term environmental damage contribute tothe widening gap between ISEW/GPI and GNP,this gap might be the artefact of highly con-testable methodological assumptions. Sensitivityanalysis is employed to demonstrate that theseitems no longer give rise to a threshold if theassumption of a cost escalation factor in thevaluation of non-renewable resource depletionand the assumption of cumulative long-term envi-ronmental damage is abandoned.

1 Some studies refer to gross domestic product (GDP) in-stead of GNP. The difference between GNP and GDP is thatGDP includes output produced by foreigners within the na-tional boundaries and excludes output produced by nationalsabroad. As the difference between GNP and GDP does notmatter here, the following paragraphs usually only refer toGNP, except when a study explicitly refers to GDP.

Page 3: On the methodology of isew, gpi... (neumayer, 2000)

E. Neumayer / Ecological Economics 34 (2000) 347–361 349

2. Depletion of non-renewable resources

As concerns the depletion of natural resources,the method used by various studies differs onthree major aspects: first, either replacement costsor resource rents are used to compute the deduc-tion item; second, either national consumption ornational extraction is the reference for valuation;and, third, if the resource rent method is used,then either total resource rents are deducted orthe so-called El Serafy method is used for calcu-lating resource user costs, which are then de-ducted.

2.1. Replacement costs or resource rents?

Let us start with the first and most fundamentaldifference. The ambiguity between either using theresource rent method or the replacement costmethod stems back to the original US ISEW.Whereas Daly et al., (1989) and Cobb and Cobb(1994) in their original ISEW computations de-ducted the total value of mine extraction, therevised ISEW in Cobb and Cobb (1994) switchedto the replacement cost method: for non-renew-able energy extraction each barrel of oil equiva-lent was valued at a replacement cost which wasassumed to escalate by 3% per annum between1950 and 1990 and was anchored around anassumed cost of $75 in 1988. The Austrian, Ger-man and Italian ISEW followed Daly et al.,(1989) in deducting the total value of mine pro-duction. The Australian SNBI study also appliedthe resource rent method, but computed usercosts according to the El Serafy method. TheChilean, Dutch, Scottish, Swedish and UK ISEWand the Australian and US GPI, on the otherhand, followed the replacement cost method ofthe revised ISEW in Cobb and Cobb (1994) to-gether with the 3% escalation factor.

There is a clear rationale for using the resourcerent method: because non-renewable resources areirreversibly lost in the process of use, non-renew-able resource extraction represents the (partial)liquidation of an existing capital stock. Rentalincome that accrues from resource extraction is,therefore non-sustainable into the future andshould either fully (total resource rents) or partly

(user costs according to El Serafy method) bededucted. The resource rent method is inspired bythe idea of sustainable income and aims to sepa-rate the sustainable from the non-sustainable in-come parts. The rationale for using thereplacement cost method, on the other hand, iscompletely different. It stems from the idea thatnon-renewable resource use, which cannot be pro-longed forever and is therefore, not sustainableinto the indefinite future, would have to be re-placed by renewable resources.

The replacement cost method suffers from twomajor problems, however: first, the underlyingassumption is that non-renewable resource usehas to be fully replaced by renewable resources inthe present; second, the escalation factor assumesthat replacement costs increase over time. As con-cerns the first problem, there is no convincingrationale for why non-renewable resources wouldhave to be fully replaced by renewable resourcesin the present when there are still available re-serves that would last for many decades. Forexample, the static reserves to extraction ratio,which gives the time of how long proven reserveswould last at current extraction levels, was 41years for oil, 63 years for natural gas and 218years for coal at the end of 1998 (BritishPetroleum, 1999).2 If non-renewable resources arecheaper than renewable resources, as Cobb andCobb (1994) assume and is certainly correct forenergy resources, then a rational resource extrac-tor would be foolish not to use up the remainingnon-renewable resources first, before switching torenewable resources later on. For the same rea-son, it seems odd to deduct replacement costs forthe totality of resource use in the present year.The relatively high replacement cost of 75 US$ in1988, which has been taken over by other studiesas well, only makes sense if total current non-re-newable resource use would need to be replaced

2 On the one hand, the static reserves to extraction ratiooverestimates available resource reserves as extraction is likelyto increase in the future. On the other hand, it underestimatesavailable resource reserves as new reserves become available.For example, while oil extraction has increased from 58 mil-lion barrels per day in 1973 to about 72 million barrels per dayin 1998, proven oil reserves have not only failed to decrease,but have even increased from 630 thousand million barrels to1050 thousand million barrels (British Petroleum, 1999).

Page 4: On the methodology of isew, gpi... (neumayer, 2000)

E. Neumayer / Ecological Economics 34 (2000) 347–361350

with renewable resources in the present. Again,this bears the question why a rational resourceextractor should switch to extremely expensiverenewable replacement resources, when muchcheaper non-renewable resources are still avail-able. Why not wait with switching until somepoint in the future, when switching becomes nec-essary and is likely to be much cheaper as thetechnology for the extraction and use of renew-able resources will have improved?

Related to this last point is the second problem,the 3% escalation factor, which has also ratheruncritically been taken over by other studies. As arationale for this assumption of constantly in-creasing replacement costs, Cobb and Cobb(1994, p. 267) refer to the costs per foot of oildrilling which they report to have increased byabout 6% per annum during the period of high oilprices in the 1970s, which triggered the explo-ration and drilling of more difficult to exploit oilfields. They reason that ‘when the limits of aresource are being reached, the cost of extractingthe next unit is more costly than the previous unit’and that ‘this principle presumably applies also torenewable fuels, though not as dramatically as tooil and gas’, which is why the escalation factor isassumed to be 3 instead of 6%. Especially withrespect to renewable energy resources, such rea-soning might be erroneous, however. The mostlikely candidate for replacing non-renewable fuelsis renewable solar energy. But the solar energyinflux exceeds current world energy demand by atleast one order of magnitude (Norgaard, 1986), sothat the limits of this resource are unlikely to bereached. Also, costs for solar energy use are cur-rently high because the technology is still in theearly stages of development, but costs will fallover time as technology improves (Lenssen andFlavin, 1996). Instead of assuming replacementcosts to escalate by 3% per year, it might thereforebe more appropriate to assume that replacementcosts are falling over time.

The replacement cost method with the 3% esca-lation factor contributes to the ‘threshold hypoth-esis’. The method computes the deduction term as

RC(t)=R(t)· 75 $ ·1.03(t−1988)

where R is resource use and t is the year ofcomputation. This deduction term will rise overtime if R does not fall by more than 3% perannum. What is more, the deduction term will riseat a rate faster than GNP if the growth rate ofGNP is smaller than 3% plus the growth rate ofresource use:

RC·

RC\

GNP·

GNPif

GNP·

GNPB0.03+

R,

where a dot above a variable represents its partialderivative with respect to time. If resource usedoes not fall significantly and GNP grows at arate of less than 3%, which is not uncommon,then the replacement method together with the3% escalation factor, ceteris paribus, causes anincreasing gap between GNP and the ISEW/GPI,thus contributing to the ‘threshold hypothesis’.Exactly this has happened in the existing studies,as Fig. 1 shows, which presents the indexed trendof GNP/GDP together with the indexed trend forresource depletion with the 3% escalation factorfor a selection of four country studies: the Dutch,Swedish, US and UK ISEW.3 As can be seen, theindexed trend for resource depletion with the 3%escalation factor is growing at a faster rate thanthe indexed trend of GNP/GDP, thus causing awidening gap over time. Ceteris paribus, thiswidening gap will translate into a widening gapbetween a country’s ISEW and its GNP/GDP andcreate evidence for the ‘threshold hypothesis’. Thereplacement cost method together with the 3%escalation factor has a substantial influence on theISEW or GPI. The item depletion of naturalresources represents, for example, approximately37% of all deduction items in the US ISEW in1990, 31% in the UK ISEW in 1996, 21% in theSwedish ISEW in 1992 and 36% in the DutchISEW in 1992.

If instead replacement costs are not assumed toescalate by 3% per annum, but, for the sake ofargument, are assumed to remain constant, thenthe item ‘depletion of non-renewable resources’no longer gives rise to a ‘threshold hypothesis’.

3 Because the threshold hypothesis refers to a period duringthe 1970s or early 1980s, for ease of exposition 1970 is thestart year in the figure.

Page 5: On the methodology of isew, gpi... (neumayer, 2000)

E. Neumayer / Ecological Economics 34 (2000) 347–361 351

Fig. 1. (a) The Netherlands ISEW. (b) Sweden ISEW. (c) United Kingdom ISEW. (d) United States ISEW.

Page 6: On the methodology of isew, gpi... (neumayer, 2000)

E. Neumayer / Ecological Economics 34 (2000) 347–361352

Fig. 1. (Continued)

Page 7: On the methodology of isew, gpi... (neumayer, 2000)

E. Neumayer / Ecological Economics 34 (2000) 347–361 353

See Fig. 1 again, which also shows the indexedtrend for resource depletion without the escala-tion factor. In the US and the UK indexed GNP/GDP is now rising faster than resource depletiondue to decreasing non-renewable resource inten-sity of GNP/GDP, thus creating the opposite of athreshold effect.4 In the Swedish and Dutch case,both trends have a similar shape over time, sothat resource depletion does not contribute to awidening gap between ISEW and GDP.

2.2. Resource production or resourceconsumption?

In the last section, it has not been made clearwhether resource use refers to the extraction orconsumption of resources. The reason is thatsome studies differ on this respect. On the onehand, all studies using the resource rent methodvalue the extraction of resources. This is correctas the resource rent method attempts to determinethe sustainable parts of an income stream derivedfrom resource extraction. Only rents from re-source extraction, not from consumption, enterthe national income accounts. Therefore, to de-duct the value of consumption instead wouldmean to deduct something that has never beenadded in the first place.

On the other hand, the studies using the re-placement cost method are not consistent in theirreference point. Whereas the revised US ISEW inCobb and Cobb (1994) and the US GPI estimatethe cost for replacing national extraction, theAustralian GPI and the Chilean, Dutch, Scottish,Swedish and UK ISEW estimate the cost forreplacing national consumption of non-renewableresources. Methodologically correct is the valua-tion of consumption, not extraction. This is be-cause the rationale behind the method is toreplace non-renewable resource use. Where theseresources come from, whether they are importedor domestically extracted, simply does not matter.The idea behind the replacement cost method isnot to cancel out non-sustainable income streams,as it is with the resource rent method. Instead, the

idea is to estimate the costs of replacing all non-renewable resources in use for production.

2.3. Total resource rents or user costs accordingto the El Serafy method?

Finally, those studies that use the resource rentmethod are not unanimous on whether to deducttotal resource rents or merely the user costs com-puted according to the El Serafy method. Totalresource rents are deducted in the original US,Austrian, German and Italian ISEW, whereas theAustralian SNBI study uses the El Serafy method.The difference matters as user costs are in generalonly a fraction of total resource rents (see theappendix to this paper).

In my view, the El Serafy method is to bepreferred. This is because, given substitutabilitybetween natural capital in the form of non-renew-able resources and other forms of capital, such asmanufactured or human capital, the finite incomestream from a non-renewable resource stock canbe transformed into a lower infinite stream ofincome from other forms of capital (Hartwick1996). What the El Serafy method does is tocompute the difference between these two incomestreams and to deduct the resulting so-called usercosts of non-renewable resource extraction. De-ducting total resource rents instead implies thatone cannot sustain an infinite stream of incomefrom a finite non-renewable resource via investingthe resource rents into other forms of capital (seealso Neumayer, 2000).

3. Long-term environmental damage

As concerns the valuation of long-term environ-mental damage, or the costs of climate change asthis item is sometimes called, the fundamentalquestion is whether this value should accumulateover time or not. All but the Australian GPIstudy have opted for accumulation. It is the objec-tive of this section to show that accumulation isincorrect.

Most studies follow the approach taken byDaly et al. (1989) and Cobb and Cobb (1994) invaluing each barrel of oil equivalent of annual

4 The same holds true for the US GPI, which is not shownhere for reasons of space limitations.

Page 8: On the methodology of isew, gpi... (neumayer, 2000)

E. Neumayer / Ecological Economics 34 (2000) 347–361354

nonrenewable energy resource consumption at$0.50 in 1972 dollars. This value is deducted fromthe ISEW in this year, but also in all followingyears. Similarly, in any given year not only thevalue for current resource consumption is de-ducted, but the values from all past years as well.Cobb and Cobb (1994, p. 74) provide as justifica-tion for this accumulation approach that they‘imagined that a tax or rent of $0.50 per barrel-equivalent had been levied on all non-renewableenergy consumed during that period and set asideto accumulate in a non-interest-bearing account(...). That account might be thought of as a fundavailable to compensate future generations for thelong-term damage caused by the use of fossil fuelsand atomic energy.’

Jackson et al. (1997, p. 23) realise in theircomputation of the UK ISEW that ‘the majorproblem with this approach (...) is the arbitraryway in which a charge is calculated’. Instead theypurport to value each tonne of greenhouse gasemissions with its marginal social cost, which theycorrectly define as reflecting ‘the total (dis-counted) value of all the future damage arisingfrom that tonne of emissions’. Strangely, however,they follow Cobb and Cobb (1994) in letting thisdamage accumulate over time. Stockhammer etal. (1997) similarly compute marginal social dam-age costs for the Austrian ISEW — and let theestimated damage accumulate over time.

Accumulation is theoretically incorrect (Atkin-son, 1995; Neumayer, 1999a). This is easiest to seewith the UK ISEW study. In valuing each tonneof emissions with its marginal social cost, the totalfuture damage of this tonne of emissions is al-ready valued. To let this value accumulate overtime is self-contradictory and therefore simplywrong as it leads to multiple counting of the totalfuture damage. Jackson et al. (1997) value eachtonne of carbon with a marginal social cost of£11.4 in 1990 prices. With accumulation, thepresent value damage caused by one tonne ofcarbon is simply infinite without discounting or£11.4/r with discounting, where r is the discountrate. With a discount rate of, say, 5% per annum,the present value damage per tonne of carbon is£228. This present value damage per tonne ofcarbon of £228 is nothing else but the marginal

social cost per tonne of carbon, which contradictsJackson et al.’s earlier assumption of marginalsocial cost of £11.4 (Jackson et al., 1997).

That accumulation is incorrect is not asstraightforward to show with the Cobb and Cobb(1994) approach, as they do not base their valua-tion on marginal social costs. Instead, as men-tioned, they justify valuing long-term environ-mental damage from fossil fuel consumption by$0.50 per barrel of oil equivalent with the ideathat this would represent the money to be setaside in order to compensate future generationsfor long-term environmental damage. As before,however, accumulation leads to multiple countinghere as well. This is because with accumulationmoney for the damage caused by each unit ofemissions is set aside not only in the year ofemission, but for each subsequent year as well.Again, the present value of damage caused, butthis time per barrel of oil equivalent, is equal to$0.50/r, which equals $10 at a discount rate of 5%per annum. With a carbon content of 0.13 tonnesper barrel of oil (Poterba, 1991), this translatesinto a present value damage per tonne of carbonof about $75, which is much smaller than the £228of the UK ISEW.

Note that I do not claim here that a marginalsocial cost per tonne of carbon of $75 (US ISEW)or £228 (UK ISEW) would be unjustifiable. It istrue that $75 is close to the upper end of damagecost estimates as reported in IPCC (1996, pp.179–224) and £228 is way beyond the most pes-simistic upper estimation end. But, given uncer-tainty and ignorance about the exactconsequences of global warming, such high esti-mates are not absurd per se. However, if propo-nents of ISEW think that the marginal social costper tonne of carbon emitted is so high, then theyshould make their assumption explicit and theyshould not use methodologically incorrectaccumulation.

The accumulation of long-term environmentaldamage costs exerts a substantial influence on theISEW or GPI. This item represents, for example,approximately 33% of all deduction items in theUS ISEW in 1990, 23% in the UK ISEW in 1996,30% in the Swedish ISEW in 1992 and 12% in theDutch ISEW in 1992. Accumulation of long-term

Page 9: On the methodology of isew, gpi... (neumayer, 2000)

E. Neumayer / Ecological Economics 34 (2000) 347–361 355

environmental damage costs also contributes tothe ‘threshold hypothesis’. Fig. 2 presents theindexed trend of GNP/GDP together with theindexed trend of accumulated long-term environ-mental damage and non-accumulated long-termenvironmental damage. As can be seen, the in-dexed trend for accumulated long-term environ-mental damage is growing much faster than theindexed trend of GNP/GDP, thus causing awidening gap over time. As with the item resourcedepletion when replacement costs are assumed toescalate at 3% per annum, this widening gap willceteris paribus, translate into a widening gap be-tween a country’s ISEW and its GNP/GDP, thuscontributing to the ‘threshold hypothesis’.

If instead long-term environmental damage isnot accumulated, then it no longer gives rise to a‘threshold hypothesis’. See Fig. 2 again. In the USand the UK indexed GNP/GDP is now risingfaster than long-term environmental damage dueto decreasing emission intensity of GNP/GDP,thus creating the opposite of a threshold effect.5

In the Swedish and Dutch case, both trends havea similar shape over time, so that long-term envi-ronmental damage does not contribute to awidening gap between ISEW and GDP.6

One might think that even if long-term environ-mental damage is not accumulated over time, athreshold effect might still arise if marginal socialcosts per tonne of emitted carbon are assumed toincrease over time. To let marginal social costsincrease over time is correct as the marginal socialcost per tonne of emitted carbon is a positivefunction of the accumulated stock of carbon stillresident in the atmosphere. In other words, thehigher the historically accumulated carbon con-centration in the atmosphere, the higher the socialdamage caused by each additional unit of emittedcarbon. Jackson et al. (1997, p. 24) actually followthis approach in assuming ‘firstly that the mar-ginal social cost in 1990 is equal to £11.4 per

tonne [of carbon, E.N.], and secondly that themarginal social cost in any year is proportional tothe cumulative carbon emissions from the year1900 up to that point in time [emphasis added].’ Itcan be seen, however, from Fig. 2 for the UKISEW that a threshold effect does not arise even ifmarginal social cost is increasing over time, aslong as the annual damage itself is not accumu-lated over time. Whether a threshold effect canarise under differing, but still plausible assump-tions about the rate of increase of marginal socialcost deserves some further attention and cannotbe ruled out at this stage with confidence. But atleast for the UK ISEW, the only study so farusing rising marginal social costs, the thresholdeffect fails to materialise.

4. Adjustment for inequality

As concerns adjusting consumption expendi-tures for income inequalities, studies differ quitesubstantially on the method chosen, which ispartly to be explained by international differencesin the availability of relevant data. It would bebeyond the scope of this paper to provide a fulldiscussion here. Instead I will concentrate on afundamental difference between the approachtaken in the UK ISEW and in the rest of thestudies.

4.1. Atkinson index or other indices?

Whereas Jackson et al. (1997) use an index,which allows the choice of a parameter represent-ing society’s aversion to inequality, all other stud-ies use an index, mostly the Gini coefficient,which does not offer such a choice. Jackson et al.use the so-called Atkinson index (Atkinson 1970),which is defined as:

Atkinson index=1−exp�%(Yi/Y)1/(1−o)fi

n1/(1−o)

where Yi denotes the income of all individuals inthe ith income group (n groups altogether), fi

denotes the proportion of the population withincomes in the ith range; and Y denotes the meanincome. The extreme boundary cases are o=0,

5 The same result holds true for the Austrian, German andItalian ISEW, which is not shown here for reasons of spacelimitations.

6 The same result holds true for the Chilean ISEW (notshown here).

Page 10: On the methodology of isew, gpi... (neumayer, 2000)

E. Neumayer / Ecological Economics 34 (2000) 347–361356

Fig. 2. (a) The Netherlands ISEW. (b) Sweden ISEW. (c) United Kingdom ISEW. (d) United States ISEW.

Page 11: On the methodology of isew, gpi... (neumayer, 2000)

E. Neumayer / Ecological Economics 34 (2000) 347–361 357

Fig. 2. (Continued)

Page 12: On the methodology of isew, gpi... (neumayer, 2000)

E. Neumayer / Ecological Economics 34 (2000) 347–361358

which implies no aversion to inequality whatso-ever, and o=�, which implies extreme aversionto income inequality in only taking account oftransfers to the very lowest income group.

The great advantage of this approach is that inchoosing o, the researcher makes explicit his orher implicit assumption on society’s aversion toincome inequality. Alternatively, the researchercan try to estimate o from revealed preferencestudies of consumer behaviour. Pearce and Ulph(1995), for example, provide an estimate of o forthe UK from a survey of the empirical literaturewith a lower bound of 0.7, an upper bound of 1.5and a best estimate of 0.8.

If instead, for example, the Gini coefficient isused, then usually 1 year is set as the base year forthe index. In the US GPI, for example, which usesthe Gini coefficient, 1968 is set as 100, because ‘itrepresented the lowest Gini coefficient over the1950–1998 period, thus the least income inequal-ity. All other years are then compared to thisbenchmark’ and an index is created (RedefiningProgress, 1999). The inequality adjusted consump-tion expenditures are reached via dividing unad-justed expenditures by this index and multiplyingwith 100. This approach is very ad hoc and theresearcher’s underlying assumptions about soci-ety’s aversion to income inequality are not expli-cated. With the Atkinson index, on the otherhand, the researcher is forced to explicate his orher implicit assumptions regarding society’s aver-sion to income inequality The researcher can evenattempt to minimise the influence of his or herown value judgements in trying to estimate soci-ety’s revealed preferences.

4.2. Index of welfare or sustainable income?

In using an index of inequality to adjust con-sumption expenditures, great care needs to beapplied to adequately interpret the resultingISEW/GPI. More generally, as soon as indexing isapplied to one of its items, interpretation mustfollow either of two lines: First, the ISEW/GPIcan be interpreted as an index as well. If so, thenonly changes in the index over time can meaning-fully be interpreted. For example, one can saythat the ISEW/GPI rose or fell in a certain year

by x percent. The absolute level of the ISEW/GPI, on the other hand, bears no meaning andshould not be referred to then. Second, if theISEW/GPI is interpreted in absolute terms ratherthan as an index, then a statement is needed onwhat the base year of indexing part of its compo-nents has been. This is because the absolute levelof ISEW/GPI crucially depends on choosing abase year for indexing as the reference point.Thus, the US GPI per capita in 1997, for example,needs to be stated as follows: 6521 in constantchained 1992 dollars with base year 1968 forincome inequality indexing.

Related to this point, the ISEW/GPI needs tobe interpreted as a measure of welfare, not assustainable or Hicksian income. Amongst otherthings, this is because, due to the indexing, theresulting ISEW/GPI cannot be interpreted as theincome that society can safely consume and be aswell off at the end of the year as at the beginning.Daly et al. (1989, p. 84) were clearly aware of thiscrucial point. Lately, however, this distinctionseems to have become blurred. England (1998, p.265), for example, in praising ISEW suggests thatit ‘is directly comparable to gross domesticproduct’. However, the absolute level of ISEW/GPI cannot be directly compared to the absolutelevel of GNP as the absolute level of ISEW/GPI isweighed by an index for income inequality,whereas GNP is not. Meaningful comparison isconfined to the trend of ISEW/GPI over timecompared to the trend of GNP.

5. Conclusion

From the analysis above follow several recom-mendations for researchers who intend to updateexisting or create new studies of ISEW, GPI orrelated measures. First, if one uses the resourcerent method for the valuation of non-renewableresources, then the reference point should be na-tional extraction of non-renewable resource deple-tion, not consumption, and one should considerestimating user costs according to the El Serafymethod instead of deducting total resource rents.Second, if one uses the replacement cost method,then the reference point should be national con-

Page 13: On the methodology of isew, gpi... (neumayer, 2000)

E. Neumayer / Ecological Economics 34 (2000) 347–361 359

sumption of non-renewable resources, not extrac-tion, and some thought should be given towhether the totality of non-renewable resourcesneeds to be replaced in the present. More impor-tantly, future researchers should seriously con-sider abandoning the 3% cost escalation factor.Third, long-term environmental damage shouldnot be accumulated, as doing so leads to multiplecounting. Fourth, future researchers should con-sider using the Atkinson index if they want toadjust consumption expenditures for income in-equality, as this index demands explication of theimplicit assumption about society’s aversion toinequality. Fifth, with indexing applied to any ofits items, the resulting ISEW/GPI cannot be di-rectly compared to GNP in absolute terms. Whileit is tempting to do so, no such comparison ismeaningfully possible. Only trends over time canbe compared.

The analysis in this paper has also shed somelight on the robustness of the ‘threshold hypothe-sis’. It has been shown that if no escalation factoris applied to valuing the depletion of non-renew-able resources, and if long-term environmentaldamage is not accumulated, then none of theseitems contributes any longer to a widening gapbetween ISEW/GPI and GNP. The other environ-mentally related items in a typical ISEW/GPI,such as costs of water, air and noise pollution,generally do not contribute to such a gap either,as they do not grow faster than GNP (for reasonsof space they could not be dealt with here in moredetail). One can therefore conclude from the anal-ysis above that variables related to the environ-ment do not provide evidence for the ‘thresholdhypothesis’. They only do so if a widening gapbetween ISEW/GPI and GNP is artificially cre-ated via the introduction of the 3% cost escalationfactor and the accumulation of long-term environ-mental damage.

This does not provide sufficient evidenceagainst the ‘threshold hypothesis’ in general, asother factors covered by ISEW/GPI might stillcreate a widening, but smaller, gap betweenISEW/GPI and GNP/GDP. Related research hasshown that, in general, the ‘threshold hypothesis’is not simply an artefact of the cost escalationfactor in non-renewable resource depletion and of

the accumulation of long-term environmentaldamage in all studies (Saito, 1999). To analyse themore general robustness of the ‘threshold hypoth-esis’, one needs to examine each study in muchmore detail. Such a task would be beyond thescope of this paper and is the subject of ongoingresearch. What this paper has tried to show,however, is that the threshold, if existent, is notdue to factors related to the environment.

Acknowledgements

I would like to thank Mako Saito for valuableresearch assistance. I would also like to thankGiles Atkinson and two referees, Saleh El Serafyand Phil Lawn, for helpful comments. I am grate-ful to Clive Hamilton and Mark Anielski for anenormously productive exchange of ideas and ar-guments — we tend to agree that we disagree. Allerrors are mine. Financial assistance from theEuropean Commission’s Marie Curie ResearchScheme (DGXII) is gratefully acknowledged.

Appendix A. Derivation of user costs according tothe El Serafy method

The formula for computing user costs accord-ing to the El Serafy method is derived from thefollowing reasoning (El Serafy, 1989): receiptsfrom non-renewable resource extraction shouldnot fully count as ‘sustainable income’ becauseresource extraction leads to a lowering of theresource stock and thus brings with it an elementof depreciation of the capital that the resourcestock represents. While the receipts from the re-source stock will end at some finite time, ‘sustain-able income’ by definition must last forever.Hence, ‘sustainable income’ is that part of re-source rents which if received infinitely wouldhave a present value just equal to the presentvalue of the finite stream of resource rents overthe lifetime of the resource.

Let P be the resource price, AC average extrac-tion cost, R the amount of resource extracted, rthe discount rate and n the number of remainingyears of the resource stock if extraction was the

Page 14: On the methodology of isew, gpi... (neumayer, 2000)

E. Neumayer / Ecological Economics 34 (2000) 347–361360

same in the future as in the base year, i.e. n is thestatic reserves to extraction ratio. Then thepresent value of total resource rents RR (P−AC)·R is equal to:

%n

i=0

RR(1+r)i=

RR�

1−1

(1+r)n+1

n1−

11+r

(1)

The present value of an infinite stream of ‘sustain-able income’ SI is

%�

i=0

SI(1+r)i=

SI(1+r)r

=SI

1−1

1+r

(2)

Setting Eq. (1) and Eq. (2) equal and rearrangingexpresses SI as a fraction of RR :

SI=RR�

1−1

(1+r)n+1

nThe user costs, representing the depreciation ofthe resource stock, would thus be

(RR−SI)=RR� 1

(1+r)n+1

n= (P−AC) · R

� 1(1+r)n+1

nIf r\0 and n\0, then user costs are only afraction of total resource rents (P−AC)·R. Thehigher r is, the lower are, ceteris paribus, usercosts. This is because a smaller share of resourcerents has to be invested in an alternative form ofcapital in order to provide a sustainable alterna-tive income stream if the rate of return on thisalternative investment is higher. Similarly, thehigher n is, the lower are user costs. This isbecause, for given resource extraction, a smallershare of the total resource stock is used up.

References

Anielski, M., 1999. Misplaced concreteness: Measuring gen-uine progress and the nature of money, paper presented atthe Canadian Society for Ecological Economics Confer-ence, 28 August 1999. Regina, Saskatchewan.

Atkinson, A.B., 1970. On the measurement of inequality. J.Econom. Theory 2, 244–263.

Atkinson, G., 1995. Measuring Sustainable Economic Welfare:A Critique of the UK ISEW, Working paper GEC 95-08.Centre for Social and Economic Research on the GlobalEnvironment, Norwich and London.

British Petroleum, 1999. BP Statistical Review of World En-ergy. British Petroleum, London.

Castaneda, B.E., 1999. An index of sustainable economicwelfare (ISEW) for Chile. Ecolog. Econom. 28, 231–244.

Cobb, C.W., Cobb, J.B., 1994. The Green National Product: aProposed Index of Sustainable Economic Welfare. Univer-sity Press of America, Lanham.

Daly, H., Cobb, H.E., Cobb, J.B., 1989. For the CommonGood. Beacon Press, Boston.

Diefenbacher, H., 1994. The index of sustainable economicwelfare: a case study of the Federal Republic of Germany.In: Cobb, C.W., Cobb, J.B. (Eds.), The Green NationalProduct: A Proposed Index of Sustainable Economic Wel-fare. University Press of America, Lanham, pp. 215–245.

El Serafy, S., 1989. The proper calculation of income fromdepletable natural resources. In: Ahmad, Y.J., Serafy, S.E.,Lutz, E. (Eds.), Environmental Accounting for SustainableDevelopment: A UNDP-World Bank Symposium. TheWorld Bank, Washington D.C, pp. 10–18.

England, R.W., 1998. Should we pursue measurement of thenatural capital stock? Ecolog. Econom. 27, 257–266.

Guenno, G., Tiezzi, S., 1998. An index of sustainable eco-nomic welfare for Italy, Working paper 5/98. FondazioneEni Enrico Mattei, Milano.

Hamilton, C., 1999. The genuine progress indicator: methodo-logical developments and results from Australia. Ecolog.Econom. 30, 13–28.

Hartwick, J.M., 1996. Sustainability and constant consump-tion paths in open economies with exhaustible resources.Rev. Int. Econom. 3, 275–283.

IPCC, 1996. Climate Change 1995 — Economic and SocialDimensions of Climate Change. Cambridge UniversityPress, Cambridge.

Jackson, T., Stymne, S., 1996. Sustainable Economic Welfarein Sweden: A Pilot Index 1950–1992. Stockholm Environ-ment Institute, Stockholm.

Jackson, T., Laing, F., MacGillivray, A., et al., 1997. AnIndex of Sustainable Economic Welfare for the UK 1950–1996. University of Surrey Centre for Environmental Strat-egy, Guildford.

Lawn, P.A., Sanders, R.D., 1999. Has Australia surpassed itsoptimal macroeconomic scale? finding out with the aid of‘benefit’ and ‘cost’ accounts and a sustainable net benefitindex. Ecolog. Econom. 28, 213–229.

Lenssen, N., Flavin, C., 1996. Sustainable energy for tomor-row’s world — the case for an optimistic view of thefuture. Energy Policy 24, 769–781.

Max-Neef, M., 1995. Economic growth and quality of life: athreshold hypothesis. Ecolog. Econom. 15, 115–118.

Moffatt, I., Wilson, M.C., 1994. An index of sustainableeconomic welfare for Scotland, 1980–1991. Int. J. Sustain.Dev. World Ecol. 1, 264–291.

Page 15: On the methodology of isew, gpi... (neumayer, 2000)

E. Neumayer / Ecological Economics 34 (2000) 347–361 361

Neumayer, E., 1999a. Weak Versus Strong Sustainability:Exploring the Limits of Two Opposing Paradigms. EdwardElgar, Cheltenham.

Neumayer, E., 1999b. The ISEW: not an index of sustainableeconomic welfare. Social Indic. Res. 48, 77–101.

Neumayer, E., 2000. Resource accounting in measures ofunsustainability: Challenging the World Bank’s conclu-sions, Environ. Resource Econ. 15, 257–278.

Nordhaus, W.D., 1992. Is growth sustainable?, Reflections onthe concept of sustainable economic growth, paper pre-pared for the International Economic Association Confer-ence, October 1992. Varenna.

Norgaard, R.B., 1986. Thermodynamic and economic con-cepts as related to resource-use policies: synthesis. LandEconom. 62, 325–327.

Pearce, D., Ulph, D., 1995. A Social Discount Rate for theUnited Kingdom, Working Paper GEC 95-01. Centre forSocial and Economic Research on the Global Environ-ment, UK.

Poterba, J.M., 1991. Tax policy to combat global warming: ondesigning a carbon tax. In: Dornbusch, R., Poterba, J.M.(Eds.), Global Warming: Economic Policy Responses.MIT Press, Cambridge (Mass), pp. 33–98.

Redefining Progress, 1999. The 1998 U.S. Genuine ProgressIndicator: Methodology Handbook, Redefining Progress,San Francisco.

Rosenberg, D., Oegema, P., Bovy, M., 1995. ISEW for theNetherlands: Preliminary Results and Some Proposals forFurther Research. IMSA, Amsterdam.

Saito, M., 1999. An Index of Sustainable Economic Welfare— Can it Be Evidence for the ‘Threshold hypothesis’.London School of Economics, London.

Stockhammer, E., Hochreiter, H., Obermayr, B., Steiner, K.,1997. The index of sustainable economic welfare (ISEW) asan alternative to GDP in measuring economic welfare: theresults of the Austrian (revised) ISEW calculation 1955–1992. Ecolog. Econom. 21, 19–34.

.