OF ORIGINS OF THE WORLD IN SCIENCE AND THEOLOGY

48
INTERNATIONAL FUND FOR THE INVESTIGATION OF SCIENCE AND THEOLOGY NAMED AFTER P.A. FLORENSKY OF ORIGINS OF THE WORLD IN SCIENCE AND THEOLOGY PETROPOLIS St.-Petersbuig 1993

Transcript of OF ORIGINS OF THE WORLD IN SCIENCE AND THEOLOGY

Page 1: OF ORIGINS OF THE WORLD IN SCIENCE AND THEOLOGY

INTERNATIONAL FUND FOR THEINVESTIGATION OF SCIENCE AND

THEOLOGY NAMED AFTER P.A.FLORENSKY

OF ORIGINS OF THE WORLDIN SCIENCE AND THEOLOGY

PETROPOLISSt.-Petersbuig

1993

Page 2: OF ORIGINS OF THE WORLD IN SCIENCE AND THEOLOGY

TEOJIOITOtHMeHH D.A. OJIOPEHCKOTO

O IIEPBOHAHAJIAX MHPA BHAYKE H TEOJIOFHH

CaHKT-IïeTepoypr1993 r.

Page 3: OF ORIGINS OF THE WORLD IN SCIENCE AND THEOLOGY

CoaepxaHHc:crp.

K).C. (MocKBa). üpocrpaHCTBO — 9Hayxe H pe,iHrnn.

C.B. (Mocxsa) . Taoeu, TBopenne H Hayxa. 25

M. F. ( HcnaHHs). Haoajio Mnpa H qerupe 41KOHuenryajibHbie pesojiiouHH B cpM3nne.

KapaaaeB 3.O. (CaHKT-IIeTep6ypr). JIoruKa H 58npo6/ieMa Haqana BPCMCHH.KoneihcHH K.B. (CauKT-nerepöypr) . npocrpaacr- 72BO H BpCMH KÜK BsaHMOfleHCTByKimne cyGcTanmiH.Ky JiakOB K).H. (HoBOCHOHpCK) . üpo&ieMa nepso- 82OCHOB obi-rus H MHP BbicmeM peanbHOcra.JTeCKOB JI.B. (MocKsa) . Konuenmia TBOpeHHsi Bce- 101jieHHOH H MaTepHajiHcnraecKas <pHjioco4>H9.MHxaüjiOBCKHH B.H. (CamtT-nerepöypr) . Hayq- 125HO-reopeTHMecKoe Mbtni^eHHe, sapasbifi CMBIC-I Hnpoö.aeMa Ha^a/ia M H pa.HryMCH BeimaMiiH (HOBHK). (CaHKT-nerep6ypr) . 137OCOÖCHHOCTH nOHHMÜH HS MHp03AaHHfl B XpHCTHaH-

CKOH rpafluuHH.CBCTOB K). H. (CamcT-IIeTepöypr) . npoöjieMa ca- 148MO3apo*aeHnsi JKM3HH na Seiscne H ero npeaonpeae-

A.B. (CaHKT-IleTepoypr) . IlpoöjieMa 169nepBOHaiaji H crpyicrypH Norpa B OCHOBHHXrno3Hbix

UexMHcrpo H.3. (XapbKOB. YxpaHHa) . O saxy VMC 182H npefl-BaicyyMe.M*aH BaüryHb (Rnraif). üpofuieMa nepBOHa<Kuia 192MUpa B flpCBHCH KHT3HCKOH CpVLIOCOCpHH.

Page 4: OF ORIGINS OF THE WORLD IN SCIENCE AND THEOLOGY

Drees W.B. (Nether lands) . Timelessness in 203cosmology and its relevance for Philosophy andReligion or "Is Timelessness a religions problem?"Dyffy M.C. (United Kingdom). Clock — time, 245physical measurement, and the age of the Universe.Melnikov V.N. (Moccow). On observable effects of 280extra dimensions.Nesteruk A.V. (St.Petersburg). The Approach of the 287"Transcendental Realism" to the idea of Time inmodern physics and cosmology.Heller M. (Poland). Singularities, Quantum 314Creation, History, and the Existence of the Universe.Pienkowski M. (Poland). The concept of Time in 327

Physics ad Metaphysics.Schmilz — Moorman K. (Germany). Creatio ex 341nihilo et En Arche as opposed to the QuantumVacuum and the Big Bang.ABSTRACTSBen — Dov Y. (Israel). Time: static, directional and 351creative.Bialas V. (Germany). The Idea of Historial Time 353process and division.Burgos M.E. (Venezuela). Quantum mechanics and 354time irreyersibility.Drago A. (Italy). The option for a particular kind of 358time surrogates the option for the kind of infinity.Gale G. (USA). Space, Time, and Observation in 361Milne's Cosmology.Leslie J. (Canada). Time and the Anthropic 363Principle.

Page 5: OF ORIGINS OF THE WORLD IN SCIENCE AND THEOLOGY

KOe CflMHCTBO) . OflHO pO*flaCT flBH , KOTOpOC OOOSHaTOCT ÜHb

H HH. flsa poxyjaer rpH, Koropoe oóosHaiaercs HHB, #H HrapMOHHs.TpH pCDKflaer ace Bemecrea, B KOTOpwx npoasjia-ercfl flao.

3. Haqajio MHpa een» KOHCU MHpa. C ogHofl cropOHbi, flaoas-iserca HaiajiOM MHpa.flao pox^aex ace, c apyroft cropo-Hbi, Becb MHP B03Bpamaexca B ßao, i.e. KOHCU MHpa — Aao.Bce BOSHHxaer H3 flao H npespamaercs B ZUo.

4. Zlao K3K Hatiano H KOHCU MHpa npe#craBJisieT COÓOHBceoömnii SUKOH MHpo3,naHH9.,Q[ao poxgaer see cymecrsa,oflHOBpeMCHHO Zlao npoaanaercsi BO scex semax qepes Aa,npH BO3flCMCTBHH ÜHb H 9Ln. flofl JI.3 nOHHMaCTCS MHflHBHflV-

ajibHaa KOHKperasaiiHa semeâ. B STOM CMbicne J^a or^Hia-erca OT KOHCpyuHaHCKoro noHSTHa, no KoropOMy Ha ecn>

BbimeorwcaHHbie OIKO^W H HanpaBJieinia npHHaAnexcaT KjipeBHCH KHraacKOH (pn.ioco4)Hn,r^aBHUM o6paaoM 30 HHHa-CTHH XaHb (206 r. flo H.a. — 220 r. H.3.) . KaK MH yxe BHflCJiH,B C3MOM Hawajie KHTaücKOH (pM-aococ{)HH npoö^CMa nepsona-uajia MHpa ne 6wia nocraBjieHa, 4iiuioco4)bi HCKanH npHOHnysroro MHpa. To^bKO Ha 6cwee sp&noM arane pasBHina KHraH-CKOH (pH/IOCOCpHH , KOFfla nOflBH-lHCb T3KHC Kpv HHWe CpHJlOCO-

(pbi, KaK KoH(pyunH, Jlao- Us« , T.e. B anoxy Hynmo-MxaHro(pHJiococpbi (JIao-u3bi,ryaH-u3bj) naqajiH paccMarpHsaTbnpodneMy nepsona^aji MHpa. A B ApesnerpeiecKoâ cpHJio-co4>HH, npH ee sapoxaemiH, (pmiococjjbi HaiajiH ocrpwe jyi-CKVCCHH BOKpyr npoß^cMbi nepBOHaqajia MHpa. Tax, Oanec

B icaiecTBe nepsoiiarana MHpa BOfly, AHBKCH-— oecnpe^e.ifaHoe, AHaKCHMCH — BO3^yx, TepaxjiHT —

oroHfa H T.fl. OflHaxo fleno HC B TOM, HTO OHH Haaura B KanecraenepBOHaqajia MHpa. Cyrb STOM npoOJieMbi samitoqaercfl BCTpCMJICHHH CpmiOCOtpOB nOH9Tb OKpyxaiOIOHH MHp. B 3TOM

CMUOie, no cyra ae.ia, npo6/ieMa nepBonaiajia H irpooVieManepBonpw 'iHHbr oxpyxaioiiiero MHpa oflHa H Ta ace. flpesHneK3KHM-TO nyrCM CTpeMHUIHCb nOHSTb 3TOT HOCTOSHHO H3MC-

202

Page 6: OF ORIGINS OF THE WORLD IN SCIENCE AND THEOLOGY

MHp, ara omwionraecKaH rpaanunsi 6buia H BH FpeuHH, H B apesHCM Knrae.

JlHTeparypa1. HpeBHeKHTaflcKafl 4>Hjioctxt)Ha. 3noxa Xain>. M., 1990. C.233.2. HCTOpHB KHT3HCKOH <J)H.1OCO4)MII. M. , 1989. C. 18-19.

3. Oómaa HcropHs KHraftctcoft $iinoccxi»ni (na KHT. as.). B 5 T. T.l.H, 1988. C. 13.

Willem B.Drees

TIMELESSNESS IN COSMOLOGY AND ITSRELEVANCE FOR PHILOSOPHY AND RELIGION.

or"IS TIMELESSNESS A RELIGIOUS PROBLEM?"

Bezinninsgcentrum Free University

nNether-lands fax (0)20-

I ntroduclion

In his Gifford lectures, which may become a classic like hisearlier texts on religion and science, Ian Barbour seems tospeak for quite a few when he concludes as metaphysicalimplications of current pnysics:

• Time is not the unwinding of a pre-determinedscroll of events but the novel coming-to-be of un-predictable events in history. In relativity, time isinseparable from space. There are no purely spatialrelationships, only spatiotemporal ones. All of thisis radically different from the Newtonian world ofabsolute space and time, in which change consistedof the rearrangement of particles that are themselves

203

Page 7: OF ORIGINS OF THE WORLD IN SCIENCE AND THEOLOGY

unchanging. We will find a similar emphasis on changeand the emergence qf genuine novelty in astronomy andevolutionary biology. The historicity of nature isevident in all the sciences. (Barbour 1990,123).

In his emphasis on time, Barbour is a typical representant ofcontemporary anglo-saxon discussions on 'religion andscience', which either tend to result in a position based on'process philosophy' or in some form of evolutionary theism.

Big bang cosmology has been related to theological ideaswith respect to the beginning of the Universe, to itscontingency, and to its dynamic nature. This latter emphasishas its roots in the dialogue between theology and evolutionarybiology, but Big Bang cosmology is often invoked as anadditional scientific discovery which shows the dynamic,evolving character of the Universe. For example, 'astrophysicsadds its testimony to that of evolutionary biology and otherfields of science. Time is irreversible and genuine noveltyappears in cosmic history' (Barbour 1989). Most discussionsabout the future assume such a dynamic nature of the universe.

However, some cosmologists, especially quantumcosmologists, interpret their own field differently. As StephenHawking expressed it in an interview with Time (Feb.8 1988),'the universe would not be created, not be destroyed: it wouldsimly be. What place, then, for a Creator?'

There seem to be three challenges from modern cosmologyto the notion of a dynamic, evolving Universe. Firstly, physicsdoes without the notion of a unique present. All momentsqualify as a possible present. Hence, there is no way toincorporate the idea of a flow of time. Secondly, fundamentalphysical and cosmological theories deal with whole possiblehistories of a system aside of, or perhaps instead of, describingthe system as evolving in time. And thirdly, in quantum

204

Page 8: OF ORIGINS OF THE WORLD IN SCIENCE AND THEOLOGY

cosmologies time is a phenomenological construct and not abasic aspect of reality (section 2).

In the article, I want to call into question the emphasis ontemporality in religious views of the universe. The traditionalfocus on the 'beginning' is both unconvincing, expecting toomuch out of the Big Bang cosmology, and religiously misguided(section 3) . However, when timelessness receives more creditthan it regularly receives, it may well be that God is moreunderstood as a platonistic supreme good than as an actor intime.

I will argue (in section 5), after a brief view of sometheological stances with respect to divine timelessness anddivine activity (section 4), that the presence of those twodifferent perspectives offers opportunities for theology.

This is not to deny that there is a problem of time, in that thecosmological perspective (no flowing present, etc.) seem toconflict with our common sense experinece. We have learnedto accept that modern science suggests an understanding ofreality which appears to be against 'common sense', at leastsince the Earth was understood to be moving. For example, wenow consider, still speculatively, an understanding of space ashaving many other (compact) dimensions aside of the threeexperienced. But such a problem about the tension betweencommon sense and a cosmological understanding of time neednot be a problem for a religious understanding of the Universe.

2. TIME IN COSMOLOGY

Phrases like "evolution in time", "beginning", and"end" are 'a psychological hangover from thepeculiar human experience of time, not as positingany sense in which a point actually "moves" alongthe path in S', the abstract space of possible states(C.J.Ishaml988).

i

205

Page 9: OF ORIGINS OF THE WORLD IN SCIENCE AND THEOLOGY

Time is a terribly complex subject, discussed in manyphilosophical treatises; I mainly following the discussion byPeter Kroes (1985).

2.1. The absence of a flowing present»There is a common-sense awareness of the present as special

moment, the boundary between the past and the future.Besides, this present is 'moving' towards the future as 'time ispassing away'.What is this special moment in the context ofphysics and cosmology? Is this an objective phenomenon or isit mind-dependent? If it would be mind-dependent, absentfrom pnysical reality, how does one reconcile mentalevents.which have the property of becoming, and physicalevents without that property? Unless one also holds that thereis no becoming in the mind — but why is the illusion sopersistent? If one opts for an objective, mind-independentview, one needs to face the question of whether the flow oftime can be made part of the physical description.

Questions about the flow of time have often been mixed upwith issues of order, a linear order relation, and withasymmetry between the past direction and the future direction.However:

I. An order relation seems necessary for flow, but is notsufficient — we do not perceive anything flowing along theline representing the real numbers; a present is necessary forthe notion of a flow of time.

II. Time asymmetry is neither sufficient nor necessary. In anasymmetric process all moments qualify as potential presents.There is no way to single out on the basis of a time-asymmetricdescribtion a present as our present. And even in purelysymmetric reversible systems, say a frictionless pendulum or aplanet orbiting a star, we still have the impression that there isa present position, which immediately is superseded by another'present* position, and so forth.

Events in the past seem necessary and fixed in memories,while events in the future seem contingent. It has been

206

Page 10: OF ORIGINS OF THE WORLD IN SCIENCE AND THEOLOGY

attempted to use this modal difference to formulate adistinction between the past of the present moment and itsfuture and hence an objective notion of 'the present'. However,this cannot 'be reformulated into a physical discourse so as toallow a physically significant distinction between past, presentand future' (Kroes 1985, 200).

The language of physics is, at least at the present moment,unable to deal adequately with the notion of a flow of time(Kroes 1985, 211). Physicists eliminate in their study ofphysical reality those aspects that make phenomena unique,including the unique 'here' and 'now'. An objective theory ofthe flow of time would precisely do the opposite, as it wouldsingle out a unique moment of time as the present. Subjective,mind-dependent, theories are, still according to Kroes, notbetter off.

2.2. The whole of time in spacetime descriptions«One could compare a universe to a film — each single picture

representing a three dimensional universe at a certain moment.Either one can take the perspective of the viewer, who sees allthe pictures subsequently in time, and hence sees action,movement, 'evolution' or the perspective of the manufacturer,who handles the whole film as a single entity, for instance inselling or storing. The film still has a 'story', but there is nomovement, no action or 'evolution'. The same holds for books.This section wants to point to a similar feature of physicaldescriptions. This need not imply determinism — which seemsto be the case in the example of a film.

Whithin physics there often are two descriptions.(1) General relativity, which is the theory behind the Big

Bang theory and hence the basis for the notion of a dynamicuniverse, has as its most fundamental entity four dimensionalspace-time. That level of description is like having the wholefilm: all are equally present, there is nothing like flow ormovement. It is, however, often possible to decompose thefour dimentional description in a description of three

207

Page 11: OF ORIGINS OF THE WORLD IN SCIENCE AND THEOLOGY

dimentional space evolving in time (Misner,Thorne, Wheeler1973).

(2) Physical theories as different as Newton's mechanics,thermodynamics, and quantum theories have been formulatedin terms of abstract spaces (with as many dimensions as thenumber of parametes like position and velocity of eachparticle), which represent all possible states of the system bypoints. A trajectory, a line of such points, represents a possible'history' of a system. At this level of description, the theory isnot about evolving systems, but about whole histories repre-sented by the different trajectories. Formulating a theory asbeing about the set of possible histories (trajectories) meansthat one abstracts from the specific intitial conditions.

(3) Light takes the fastest path from a source to a receiver.In a homogeneous medium this is a srtaight line. One veryuseful description is in terms of all possible paths, and thenhaving a selection rule (principle of least action) to determinewhich path is actually taken. As before, the physicaldescription works with complete 'possible histories'. Suchprinciples of least action are very pervasive in physics. Thisidea has been incorporated in the path integral formalism,which is extensively used in contemporary field theory(particle physics).

It seems as if the 'holistic' picture of theories about wholehistories implies determinism — one can only sell completefilms once they are complete. However, selling is an action intime , and hence leads to the other type of description. Thetimeless approach, without claiming to have the finalperspective of one's world at a certain moment of time, doesnot imply determinism. This can be explained with the notionof 'universe pictures'.

A universe picture is, according to McCall (1976), acomplete description of a history of universe, including past,present and future. Assuming that the past is fixed and thefuture is a set of possibilities, a universe picture at a certain

208

Page 12: OF ORIGINS OF THE WORLD IN SCIENCE AND THEOLOGY

moment is like a tree: one stem (fixed past) and many branches(future possibilities). The present of a universe picture is thepoint where the branching begins. McCall hopes to formulatean objective flow of time in terms of such trees, as later treesare subtrees of earlier trees. That, however, does not single outa unique tree as corresponding to the present (Kroes 1985,203f.).

One can about the whole set of trees, hence possibleuniverse pictures, without implying that the future isdetermined or even already should have happened — as isnecessary for having the complete film. One course, having the'last' tree of a series — which would consist of only a stemwithout branches — would mean that everything is fixedrelative to the present defined by that tree, but then everythingis in the past. Talking about systems in terms of such treesprovides a language for talking about complete historieswithout implying determinism. Determinism is a feature ofsome physical theories which can be formulated in this'complete history' way, like classical mechanics and GeneralRelativity. But that does not warrant the inverse argument, thatsuch a timeless description is necessarily tied up withdeterminism.

Both the difficulties in giving a physical expression of theflow of time and the presence of a timeless imply that onecannot appeal to modern cosmology and physics for supportfor the claim that we live in a dynamic, evolutionary world.However, the conclusion need not be only negative. Thepresence of two different perspectives offers also someopportunities for theology, as I will argue below.

2.3. Time's onological status in quantum cosmologies.If a theory deals with space-time or complete histories, there

still is time as an order parameter form one side of history, itsbeginning, to the other side, the end. However, even such astatus for time is disputed in quantum cosmologies. In generalterms, once space and time become subject of description in

209

Page 13: OF ORIGINS OF THE WORLD IN SCIENCE AND THEOLOGY

terras of quantum physics they lose the property of definitelocation in space and time. What would a moment in time be ifit would not have a definite location in time?

Andrej Linde seems to understand time as phenomenologicalnotion which can be introduced by an observer inside a'bubble', if this bibble is sufficiently long-lived (1985, 289).Time is also a phenomenological construct in the cosmology ofStephen Hawking. Time, as a parameter ordering differentstates representing universes at a single moment, could bedefined on the basis of the fields and the geometry of therespecrive states. In both cosmologies the notions of time andspace-time are approximations which are not valid for 'small'space where quantum effects are important.

James Hartle, Hawking's co-author in the fiest technicalexposition of his on quatum cosmology, has developed theseideas in a somewhat different direction. He consider twooptions. The first is to abandon the spacetime, and thereby time(e.g., the work of Wootters). We only have features in thepresent which are interpreted as records of the past, but thatpast might well be an illusion. Hartle rejects this as anoverreaction to a technical problem in the formalism ofquantum mechanics. An alternative, which Hartle seeks todevelop, is to assume that (not to be split as space-time) isfundamental, and to develop a fitting way of calculatingquantum probabilities. As a consequence, some features ofordinary descriptions are lost; among them causality and theidea that the Universe has a specific state at a moment of timeHis formalism allows, in principle, the prediction of all possibleobservations. But it does not allow for an organization of thosepossible observations into a series of spaces at subsequent'times. The spacetime is essential upon this view; causality andseparate moments of time are approximations.

A more fundamental role for time seems involved in the workof Roger Penrose. He suggests that it is guantum physics thatis only approximately valid. Time might therefore be

210

Page 14: OF ORIGINS OF THE WORLD IN SCIENCE AND THEOLOGY

meaningful for small spaces as well. However, the mostfundamental formalism will not have objective reality of spaceand time. Rather, these notions will be consequences of morefundamental entities. (Penrose's twistor program, which hasnot been very successful so far, intends to describe bothspace-time and particles in terms of a single type offundamental entities, twistors.)

Frank Tipler follows an approach more similar to those ofOnde, Hawking, and Hartle. He too consider time to be aphenomenological construct. 'At the most basic ontologicallevel, time does not exist' (Tipler 1989,237). We only observerelationships between objects in space and the theory encodesall possibilities at once in the wave function of the Universe.Tipler assumes a boundary condition which requires allclassical to terminate in an omega point. He therefore needs awell defined time (as ordering parameter) in at least one seriesof subsequent spatial universes. The possibility of a temporalordering seems more or less accidental in Hawking'scosmology. By contrast, Tipler's cosmology requires such apossibility; it has been shown by Tipler that the TeilhardBoundary Condition (requiring an omega-point) implies theexistence of a global time (as parameter).

Conclusion: time's status is, at least, disputed. Time mightstill have some fundamental status, but it might also berecognizable only 'for large spaces'. Anyhow, suchcosmologies are not directly in line with evolutionary biologyas dealing a dynamic and evolving Universe. Therefore,theological insights developed in the dialogue with theevolutionary understanding of the natural world are notdirectly extendable to the dialogue with cosmology. The BigBang model is often presented as describing an evolutionaryuniverse. That a possible representation. However, the morespeculative ideas at the frontier of cosmological research, andeven standard theory of space-time (General Relativity),

211

Page 15: OF ORIGINS OF THE WORLD IN SCIENCE AND THEOLOGY

suggest that the evolutionary presentation is one of limitedvalidity, and not the most fundamental one.

One might object, against taking the timeless view seriously,that the timelessness is a feature of those theories, and neednot be a feature of the world. However, we do not access to theworld independent of our theories. Theories generate theontology, the way we take the world to be. Hence, in takingthese cosmological theories seriously we need to consider thetimeless perspective they suggest.

3. CREATION AND BEGINNING.

The Big Bang theory has been understood as support for atheistic understanding of the Universe, either through acosmological argument (see 3.1 ) or through apparent parallelswith either the first chapter of Genesis (3.2) or the doctrine ofcreatio ex nihilo (3.3). However, all such arguments arewanting due to the limited validity of the Big Bang theory aswell as for other reasons.

3.1. A Cosmological ArgumentThe argument has a simple logical structure of two premises

and a conclusion, at least in the version of Craig (1979, 63) :' 1. Everything that begins to exist has a cause of its existence.2. The universe began to exist.3. Therefore the universe has a cause of its existence.'

The first premise

• Is so intuitively obvious that no one in his right mindreally believes it to be false....Indeed the that any-thing, especially the whole universe, could pop intoexistence uncaused is so repugnant that mostthinkers intuitively recognise that the universe'sbeginning to exist entirely uncaused out of nothingis incapable of sincere affirmation. (Craig 1979,141).

212

Page 16: OF ORIGINS OF THE WORLD IN SCIENCE AND THEOLOGY

This premise — nothing from nothing, everything has cause— is a metaphysical assumption. Hoyle used it against the BigBang model with a finite past; other, e.g. Craig, use it to arguefor the existence of something 'beyond' the Universe. I shallconcentrate on the use of science as support for this premise.

'Nothing from nothing' understood as the requirement ofprevious material appears simmilar to the conservation law inscience. Therefore, this rule seems supported by evidence forthe conservation of energy, momentum, charge and the like.However, those conservation law that are believed to be validfor the Universe as a whole conserve a total quantity which iszero, ui> For the total charge. Other conservation laws, likeconservation of mass and energy, are not applicable to theUniverse as a whole or total to zero as well. As far as thescientific conservation laws are concerned, the Universe mightcome from a 'nothing'. If one objects to this on the basis of exnihilo nihil fit, one is using a metaphysical principle, some-thing like 'concervation of actuality', which is not equivalentwith or justified by the scinntific conservation laws.

'Nothing from nothing' as a requirement of a precedingcause seems also similar to the mathodological principle ofsufficient reason: one should always seek reasons. Scince'could not abandon the presupposition that reasons can begiven for the properties or patterns things are found to have,without surrendering its very character as a continuing andendless quest for such reasons, and for continually better waysof expressing these reasons' (Munitz 1974, 105). However,as emphasized by Munitz, this methodological rule should bedistinguished from the metaphysical principle of sufficientreason, which states that there must be such reasons, whetherwe can find them or not. This latter principle is outside, al-though it is supported by the instances that in searching forreasons science has been successful. Quantum theory might beinterpreted as an example where the metaphysical principle isnot valid. The evolution according to the Schrodinger equation

213

Page 17: OF ORIGINS OF THE WORLD IN SCIENCE AND THEOLOGY

is determinate, but the 'reduction' to one of the possible statesis indeterminate, unpredictable and 'without cause'.

The second premise is defended on philosophical grounds,especially through an argument for the impossibility of theexistence of an actual infinite set. Although I have doubtsabout this reasoning, I leave that to focus on the use of naturalscience. Craig claims empirical confirmation for this premise.

He makes two claims:(1 ) The Big Bang theory shows that there was a 'beginning'.

The Steady State theory is observationally ruled out, while theoscillating model is incorrect since our Universe is everexpanding.

(2) The entropy (discorder) of the Universe is increasing,because 'by definition the universe is a closed system, since itis all there is' (Craig 1979, 131). An eternal universe wouldhave reached its state of maximal entropy and be in totalequilibrium. Thus follows that our Universe must have had abeginning. The idea, originally due to Boltzmann, that auniverse at low entropy might be a gigantic fluctuation in auniverse in equilibrium, is rejected since the fluctuation wouldhave to be so big, and hence so improbable, as to be ruled out.

Quantum effects are complety absent in these two empiricalarguments for the second premise, which is a serious omission,since they bear on entropy, on the possibility of an oscillatinguniverse, and on a 'universe from nothing'.

(1) Although there were in 1979 nearly no results inquantum cosmology, there was consensus among cosmologiststhat a complete theory needed a quantum theory of gravity. Aphilosopher could (and should) have known that there was alimit to the validity of the standard Big Bang theory. Theconsensus, which perhaps existed a decade ago, about theUniverse having had an absolute beginning some ten to twentybillion years ago, has disappeared. In current cosmologicalresearch (see 3) there are a few different approaches to theperiod before the standard model, and these different

214

Page 18: OF ORIGINS OF THE WORLD IN SCIENCE AND THEOLOGY

approaches have different implications for the cosmologicalargument. Some are eternal, without a 'beginning', othershave an uncaused 'appearance out nothing' — whichchallenges the first premise. I will argue that some scientistsclaim too much. The 'nothing' is like a physical vacuum;existing and a philosophical nothing. But still, to reach Craig'sconclusion, one needs to make clear why only those programswhich work with a 'beginning' are correct science. And, as itstands today, there is no such criterion for what counts as goodscience — at least not one used by the scientific community inselecting articles for inclusion in their journals.

(2) Besides, I have doubts concerning the use ofthermodynamics. There are three meanings of 'open' involvedin this section:

(a) Open as forever expanding with diminishing density. Inthis sense, the Universe might be open according to Big Bangcosmology.

(b) Open as having interaction with an environment.(c) Open as regarding the applicability of the Second Law

of Thermodynamics.Craig, and others as well, mix those meanings by saying that

the Universe is by definition closed (having no environment,meaning b) and so the Second Law is applicable (meaning c).However, that is not correct for an expanding universe.Entropy 'is carried away into the expanding space' by thebackground radition. The expansion works as if there is anenviroment, although there is none. (More precisely, themaximal entropy increases in an expanding universe, and thisincrease goes faster than entropy production during mostphases. As Prautschi (1982, 595) concludes, the universedoes not approach a maximal entropy. Rather, the non-equilibrium becomes more pronounced. However, the entopyper comoving (expanding) volume approaches a constantvalue. Hence, there is a kind of 'heat death' for the Universeaccording to this reasonong based upon the standard Big Bang

215

Page 19: OF ORIGINS OF THE WORLD IN SCIENCE AND THEOLOGY

model.) Meanings b and c are equivalent if the notion'environment' is unproblematic, but not for expandinguniverses.

Besides, the absence of a clear concept of entropy in relationto gravity makes the application of the concept of entropy tothe whole Universe disputable. And the statistical character ofthe Second Law might allow for the occasional occurrence ofstates of low entropy in an otherwise eternal universe inequilibrium. In combination with the inflationary scenario thefluctuation does not need to be big, nor is it obvious that a muchsmaller universe with observers like us would be more prob-able. In Craig's book the belief in the unrestricted validity oflaws like the Second Law is too strong. I am not defending theskeptic view that we can not know anything about the veryearly universe, but I call for cautiousness in the use of commonsense notions or law known to be valid under 'ordinary'circumstances.

The conclusion: a cosmological argument for the existenceof God which is based on the 'beginning' of the universe doesnot work, and certainly not on the basis of the Big Bang theory— which has a limited domain of validity. It must be aphilosophical argument, without appeal to empirical evidencefor a beginning of the Universe or for ex nihilo nihil fit

3.2. Parallels with Genesis?

• In the beginning God created the heavens and theearth. The earth was without form and void, anddarkness was upon the face of the deep; and theSpirit of God was moving over the face of the waters.Gen.l:l-2.

Before evaluating the nature of apparent parallels betweenbiblical references to creation and the Big Bang theory we willfirst briefly present the way major contemporary biblicalscholars understand the biblical narratives.

216

Page 20: OF ORIGINS OF THE WORLD IN SCIENCE AND THEOLOGY

Cosmogonie légendes serve a variety of functions. Besidesexplaining the actual world with its tragic elements like deathand decay, they legitimize social or religious structures andtraditions, present an ideal against which the actual practicesare measured, provide a background to the ethics of a culture,and so on.

In the Bible, the world is seen as created. But it does notpresent just one view of 'how'. Dominant is the emphasis on'who', the one God related to Israel. Monotheism is notprimarily a philosophical statment. It expresses an existentialinterest: one God implies that enemies don't have a' God aspowerful as Israel's God. Important is that the God who ispresent in the life and history of Israel is also the One who wasat the beginning, and who has the power to create or changewhatever is nessesary to his people. The world itself is notdivine; there is a qualitative difference between God and hiscreatures.

Genesis 1, the well-known story of the creation in sevendays, is not the major and certainly not the only, text wherereflections on God as the Creator can be found. The first fewchapters of Genesis have been overemphasized as the storiesabout creation and fall, the sources for cosmogony andanthropology. Such an emphasis neglects the variety ofBiblical images concerning creation. Besides, it tends tomisinterpret Genesis as if it were an answer to ourcosmological questions. From the second verse on , the storyof Genesis 1 concentrates on 'the earth' as the context of life.This includes a vision of social life, especially through itsemphasis on the Sabbath, the seventh day, which is a majorelement in the identity of the people of Israel.

Both the Big Bang idea and the biblical narratives evoke theimage of a sudden appearance of the world. A similarity of sucha general nature is not very surprising; there are at that levelonly two possibilities: either the Universe had a suddenbeginning or it had not such a beginning. In many cultures there

217

Page 21: OF ORIGINS OF THE WORLD IN SCIENCE AND THEOLOGY

have been narratives expressing such a sudden beginning ofthe world.

Parallels with a more informative content fail upon closerinspection. For instance, the supposed parallel that both theBig Bang idea and Genesis describe a sudden appearance outof nothing is not based on reading of Genesis 1 in its context.Genesis 1 does not answer questions about the (non) existenceof primordial matter. And similarly for other biblical referencesto 'creation'. Statements that appear to say something about the'out of nothing' have a different function, mostly to express acertain view of God, God's power and God's relation tomankind, especially the people of Israel. Besides, there is notone single coherent biblical concept of the creation process. Acouple of images are used, some more in Une with ex nihilo,like God ordering as a king that there must be light, others moreat odds with it, like God working as a potter.

In general, claiming such parallels is only possible if the textor idea is taken out of its context. The content is read — in acertain way —, but its function is neglected. Sal Restivo ( 1984)has analyzed the claimed 'parallelism' between physics andEastern mysticism. Parallels can only be established if there issomething to be compared, namely statements in a commonlanguage. I agree with Restivo about major problems with sucha procedure:

1. Translations. Both statements are translations, both in thelinguistic (from Hebrew and from mathematics) and in thecultural sense (a culture of a far past and the scientific,theoretical culture).

2. Representativity. If two statments are used to argue for aparallel between two conceptual structures (moden scientificand biblical world view), the question arises whether thestatements are representative for the whole. Genesis 1 is notrepresentative for the whole Bible, or even the Old Testament,wich is mostly about the history of Israel. A parallel betweenGenesis 1 and the Big Bang idea would not imply that the Big

218

Page 22: OF ORIGINS OF THE WORLD IN SCIENCE AND THEOLOGY

Bang theory confirmed a religion based on the Old Testament,since the most important aspect from the biblical point of view,God's presence throughout history, is missing. Similarly forthe scintific side, since the Big bang theory describes theevolution of the Universe after 'the first fraction of a second',and not the 'beginning', which is beyond the limits of itsapplicability.

3. The different functions of language. In science the mainfunction is the communication among scientists aboutobservations, experiments and theories. Conceptual clarityand logical consistency are impotant for such a purpose.Religious language serves other functions, like reassuring andcomforting people and evoking moral attitudes. Whether thereis some common aspect of language is to be discussed later, butthere is surely much difference in this respect. Claimingparallels without paying attention to the function of languageis not satisfactory.

4. The languages of science and religion influence eachother. Words used one context get used — with anothermeaning — in a different context. Parallels based on the useof the same world might be a consequence of such 'corruptionof languages'. Notoriously risky are words like 'energy','order', 'nothing', and also 'creation'. The use of the creatioex nihilo formula in articles treating the beginning of theUniverse as a quantum event might be of such a nature.

3.3. Parallel with creatio ex nihilo?Creatio ex nihio as a philisoph ical statement expressing the

Christian view of creation arose in the second century A.D. Asfor other parts of Christian doctrine, the doctrine of creationbecame what it has become by accepting and refusing elementsof other religious and philosophical ideas, especially inconfrontation with Gnosticism, Marcionitism, and Platonism.Gnosticism and Marcionitism have ifluenced the decisionsabout the canon (retaining the Old Testament) and theformulations of confessions ('I believe in God, the Creator of

219

Page 23: OF ORIGINS OF THE WORLD IN SCIENCE AND THEOLOGY

the heavens and the earth'), which are at the basis of allsubsequent theological thought about creation. For gnosticsand for Marcion the origin of evil and the origin of the materialworld go together. Therefore, the world cannot be theintended product of the good God who is the father of JesusChrist. It must have been made by a different God. Accordingto the Christian theologians, the whole creation (material andspiritual) is distinct from God, but made by the same God whois present in Israel and Jesus, and so the creation is not theproduct of a lesser or other God. Being distinct from God isincluded in creatio, while being made by no one else but theGod of Israel and Jesus is part of ex nihilo.

Platonism had a cosmogony which assumed a few enternalprinciples: the Demiurge who made the world, the ideas, andthe Matter. Creatio ex nihilo expresses objections againstindependent eternal principles aside from God. The ideas areinterpreted as God's thoughts, and the existence of eternal,ungenerated matter is denied.

Necessity in history is disputable, but I agree with May(1978, 153) that . given tne philosophical context in thesecond century of Christianity, creatio ex nihilo as anontological statement was to be expected as a nessesaryconsequence of Biblical traditions in a critical confrontationwith the philosophical ideas about 'principles'.

The majority of western theologians in the twentiethcentury have taken the doctrine of creation as unrelated to thenatural sciences. Many deny the significance of metaphysicsor cosmology, philosophical as well as scientific, for faith andtheology. Separation has been based on dichotomies betweenGod's self-revelation in Christ and man's discovery (Barth,neo-orthodoxy), or between subjective involvement andobjective detachment (existentialism, Bultmann), or on ananalysis of different functions of language. In the neo-orthodox approach, creation is interpreted from theperspective of salvation. In the existentialist approach, belief

220

Page 24: OF ORIGINS OF THE WORLD IN SCIENCE AND THEOLOGY

in God as the Creator is an expression of a new understandingof one's own life. In the linguistic approach, saying that theworld has been created is not a factual statmen, but anexpression of a way of looking at the world, having a certainattitude with respect to the world.

The concept of creatio ex nihilo is, even if impotant, usedin many ways. Eberhard Wolf el (1981) warns againstsubstantiating the nihil. In the context of creatio ex nihilo thenihilo expresses that God was alone and that the act of creationis a self-limitation of God. God, the necessary existent, is theontological principium ex quo, from which all contingenciesresult. As a result, the creatio ex nihilo is not really ex nihilo,but out of the fullness of God. This is neither substantial norcausal, but 'mystical'. As such, there is no conflict with thephilosophical principle ex nihilo nihil fit.

Process philosophers and theologians defend a view forwhich the word pan-en-theism has been coined as a middlebetween theism, God transcending the world, and pantheism,God totally immanent in the world. God, according to processtheologians, is not the cosmic moralist, nor the unchanging andpassionless absolute, nor the controlling power, nor thesanctioner of the status quo (Cobb and Griffin 1976, 8f.).'Process theology rejects the notion of creatio ex nihilo, if thatmeans creation out of absolute nothingness. That doctrine ispart and parcel of the doctrine of God as absolute controller.Process theology affirms instead a doctrine of creation out ofchaos' (Cobb and Griffin 1976, 65). Charles Hartshorne(1948, 30) defended that divine creativity nonetheless wasdifferent from human creativity.

• What does distinguish God is that the precedingphase was itself created by God , so that he, unlikeus, is never confronted by a world whose coming tobe antedates his own entire existence. There is nopresupposed 'stuff' alien to God's creative work; but

221

Page 25: OF ORIGINS OF THE WORLD IN SCIENCE AND THEOLOGY

rather everything that influences God has alreadybeen influenced by him, where as we are influencedby events of the past with we had nothing to go. Thisis one of the ways in which eminence is to bepreserved without falling into the negations ofclassical theology.

The Universe is coeternal to God, but there are no enduringthings within that Universe, thus preserving God's uniqueness.

The basic things about claims to parallels have already beensaid in the conclusion to the section on the creation narratives.In the case of creatio ex nihilo one could make a strongerargument for a parallel. Unlike the narratives, it is supposed tobe part of coherent systematic reflection. The other functionsof the narratives, like comforting people or evoking certainattitudes, have moved to the background. However, event ifthere would be a parallel of the ex nihilo formula and currentscientific cosmology, it should be forgotten that the religiousdoctrine serves other functions besides the cognitive one,functions which are not part of the parallel with science.

There is a variety of views within Christianity. A beginningof the Universe seems similar to creatio ex nihilo, but for manytheistic theologians today an eternal Universe is also accept-able. It would, in their opinion, still need a ground (not atemporal cause) for existence, or the Christian attitudes can beexpressed without making a claim about an original event.Process theologians think that only an eternal Universe iscompatible with their ideas. They defend an analogy betweendivine and human activity, both using other entities. Thisanalogy is also present in the linguistic structure of the theistic'God creates ex nihilo'. But the analogy is so strongly qualifiedby the nihil that a fundamental difference between God'screativity and that of humans is expressed.

3.4. Beyond the Big Bang theory: Hawking's example.

Page 26: OF ORIGINS OF THE WORLD IN SCIENCE AND THEOLOGY

• The conclusion of the affort so fan universe with noedge in space,no beginning or end in time, andnothing fora creator to do. (Carl Sagan 1988, x).

In the introduction to Stephen Hawking's bestseller A BriefHistory of Time, Carl Sagan suggests that there might benothing for a creator to do. He thus ties the notion of God tothe notion of a beginning. This view rests on a view of God'srole in creation which is not the view of most more developedtheologies (i). The second issue is the claim that physicalcosmology is now able to describe creation out of nothing, asclaimed, for instance, by Hawking. Such a physical concept ofnothing is not indentical to the philosophical concept. Thisbrings us to the contingency of existence (II). Creatio exnihilo has traditionally two components, origination and de-pendency at all moments. Deism, in general, emphasizes onlythe first, God's role in the beginning. However, most of therecent cosmologies emphasize a structural similarity of allmoments. Therefore, the understanding of creatio ex nihilo asdependency, which might be seen as the counterpart of God'ssustaining activity, fits easier wich recent cosmological ideas.Henc, if one looks for a religious interpretation, a theisticinterpretation fits better than a deistic one (III).

(I) Edges en deismFor Carl Sagan the issue is simple: If Hawking is right that

there is no absolute beginning of reality, than there is no needfor a creator. This is quite similar to arguments by others a thatbeginning in the Big Bang sense supported belief in a creator.However, this is not the only possible position. Quite a numberof theologians and others have argued that the two — aphysical beginning and belief in God — are relatively inde-pendent.

One could have an image of God as the great watchmakerwho constructed the world and wound the spring — beforeletting it run by itself according to the original design. In

223

Page 27: OF ORIGINS OF THE WORLD IN SCIENCE AND THEOLOGY

relation to such an image of God the beginning is veryimportant, for it is there that the watchmaker did his (or her)job. This kind of theological imagery has been quitewidespread in the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries and itis perhaps still the most widespread image, aside from that ofGod as 'an old man up there'. Belief in the watchmaker-Godbeen labelled deism, in contrast to theism, which holds thatGod is also actively involved in the processes of the world atlater moments. Contemporary theologians have, in manydifferent ways, argued that it is of major importance to see Godas related to the present. A purely deistic concept of God is nota serious option within contemporary theology, because sucha God would not be relevant to us and the ways we shape ourlives.

The removal of a beginning would imply that the'watchmaker' God is not a défendable image. That seems to bethe essence of Sagan's remark. However, that is not a deathblow to theism, as it is not the King of God theism defends. Forsome theologians it is even the other way round. For instance,process theology argues that there is no absolute beginning ,but only an eternal process in which the world and God exeninfluence on each other. This particular one does not fit theHawking theory either, because the view of the nature of timeis very different. But the example of such a theology, which isintellectually quite well developed, shows that theology is notnecessarily tied up with an absolute beginning, an edge to time.

Whether it is possible to develop a theological view whichfits the whole picture, not only the edgelessness but also thenature of time, the determinism and the completeness suggestedin the Hawking cosmology remain to be seen. But Sagan'sargument 'no edge, hence no God' is not decisive. Aside fromthe possibilities which might still be present in the context ofthe Hawking cosmology, one needs to keep in mind also thestatus of this cosmology, the presistcnt pluralism in

<-£

Page 28: OF ORIGINS OF THE WORLD IN SCIENCE AND THEOLOGY

contemporary cosmology, especially where cosmologies touchon fundamental metaphysical questions.

(II) NothingHartle and Hawking interpreted their own proposal for the

wave function of the Universe as giving the probability 'for theuniverse to appear from Nothing' (Hartle and Hawking 1983,2961 ). In this subsection I will argue that the Hartle-Hawkingtheory does not describe such an 'appearance out of nothing'if that is taken in its absolute sense. Neither do other theories,such as those of Vilenkin. In the next subsection I will arguethat the Hartle-Hawking theory can be interpreted in the senseof creatio ex nihilo (creation out of nothing), but that thistheological notion should then be understood as a view of theUniverse as being sustained by God at every moment ratherthan as a cosmogonie expression.

There is one sense in which this theory can most clearly beunderstood as creation from 'nothing'. Ordinary calculationsoften assume a state at one moment and laws to calculate thestate at another moment. In such situations one might say thatthe second state arises out of the first state. There is in theHartle-Hawking approach at the timeless level no reference toa state other than the 'resulting' state. As it is compact, it is theonly boundary present in the calculation. The theory gives aprecise meaning to the notion of 'nothing' as absence of otherboundaries in the calculation.

However, this should not be misunderstood as appearanceout of nothing. Appearance is a temporal notion, which doesnot fit with this level of description.Expressions like'tunneling from nothing' are of a mixed nature, and not suitableto describe the basic idea of this theory. Tunneling connotes atemporal process, while the 'from nothing' applies to a kind oftime-independent actuality.

The 'nothing' is not an absolute nothing. One 'must stillgrant the existence of quite a body of preexisting laws ofNature in order to get away with this trick' (Barrow 1988,231 ;

225

Page 29: OF ORIGINS OF THE WORLD IN SCIENCE AND THEOLOGY

similarly Heller 1987, 421), for example quantum laws andfields as well as mathematical logic. The 'nothing' which has aprecise meaning in the context of this proposal is not anabsolute ' nothing' in a more philosophical sense.

There are serious problems when one tries to combine thelanguage of probabilities with the notion of 'nothing'. I willfirst formulate two objections in general terms, and thenformulate one in the terms of the quantum cosmology of Hartleand Hawking.

(1) The probability of finding "head" when tossing a coinis +, but there 50% chance of getting an actual "head" is onlythere if and only if someone tosses a coin, so if and only if oneof the possible outcomes is realized. A mathematical idea ofgetting a universe from nothing does not give physicaluniverse, but only the idea of a physical universe—assumingthat there is a difference between the Universe and amathematical idea about the Universe. There has to be someinput of 'Physical reality'. Perhaps that is an aspect of thenothingness, but that makes it into a physical entity and notnothing at all.

(2) Physical probabilities, as exemplified by radioactivedecay, start with something, an initial situation (a particle inspace and time) becoming another situation (other particles inspace and time). The probability is the chance that thetransition from situation one to situation two happens during acertain interval of time, or that the particle is found in a certainvolume of space, or something of that nature. Even if onereduces the entities in the first situation as much as possible (noenergy, no matter fields, etc.), talking about probabilities onlymakes sense if there is some structure with measure (like time)present in the first situation.

These two arguments both are in the description from withintime. It is difficult, if not impossible, to get outside that whentalking about probabilities. That also shows up in the third,more technical, argument.

226

Page 30: OF ORIGINS OF THE WORLD IN SCIENCE AND THEOLOGY

(3) Before interpreting a wave function as an amplitude forprobabilities, the normalization must be established. In the caseof a single particle, without creation or destruction , the wavefunction is normalized by requiring that the integral of theprobabilities over the whole space must yield one at anymoment: the particle must be somewhere. Hartle use for thewave function of the Universe something similar (Hartle andHawking 1983, formula 4.3). It is the requirement that theprobability of having a metric at a three dimensional spacelike'surface' is one. If this is the way normalization is achieved ,the wave function gives the amplitude not that a state arisesfrom nothing, but that a certain state is there, given that theremust be a metric, i.e., a universe. (There are some technicaldifficulties as well, as I learned from CJ.Isham. It is not onlythat the normalization implicitly introduces the assumption thatthere is universe (by setting the outcome to one). Under somesimple assumtions the outcome of such calculation turns out tobe infinite, hence there is no way in which it can be normalizedto one .This can also be understood physically. The integrationis done while the time variable is still included. This would evenfor a single particle lead to an infinite outcome.'A moreplausible scenario is one in which the physical Hubert space[space which represents all states] is only obtained afterabstracting out the intrinsic time variable. This means that, likethe concept of real time/Lorentzian spacetime, the prob-abilistic interpretation of the theory only "emerges" from theformalism in some sort of semi-classical limit' (CJ.Isham inletter to the author, December 16 1987). Tipler (1986) dealsextensively with the non-normalizability.)

Interpreting the Hartle-Hawking wave function as givingprobabilities for appearance out of nothing is too strong,Rather, more défendable and modest, this approach'determines the relative probability of universes correspondingto different classical solutions' (Hawking 1984, 377).

(Ill) Cosmogony and dependency

£ /1

Page 31: OF ORIGINS OF THE WORLD IN SCIENCE AND THEOLOGY

Traditional theological ideas creatio ex nihilo have twopoles. On the one hand they refer to cosmogony, the cominginto being of our Universe. On the other hand they denote aneternal sustaining by God, ultimate dependence ai eachmoment. Chris Isham states that the latter 'is somewhatdecoupled from modern scientific thought' (Isham 1988,376),a view that is probably widely shared among theologians andscientists. In my view, the Hawking cosmology lends itselfmuch more to an interpretation in terms of sustaining than ofmaking. The basic entities are the three dimensional spaceswith their material content (fields). Therefore, these are to beseen in this context as the basic entities of creation, the "what"that is created. The calculations of their relative probabilitiescan be calculated on the timeless level. It is not that one resultsfrom the other or comes after the other. From the timelessperspective they are all coenternal, or they are all created"tunelessly". Hence they all equally related to the Ground ofBeing.

Another way to argue for the same conclusion: this shcemedoes not have an initial event with a special status. There is noway to pick one slice as the first of the sequence. Hence, allmoments have a similar relation to the Creator they are all "justbrute facts", or they are all equally created.

This view of God "sustaining" the world in all its "times"was transformed by Isham into another image, 'one can almostimagine the universe ... being held in the cup of God's hand'(Isham 1988, 405).

To summarize: this theory allows for a precise interpretationof ex nihilo, and it fits better with the idea that every space(with content) is equally created by God than with the ideathat God created 'in the beginning'. Questions about therelation between the two components of creatio ex nihilofollow. Understanding it as a cosmogonie process seems tosingle out a certain event as having a special relation to God.Sustaining tends to stress the similarity of states in their relation

228

Page 32: OF ORIGINS OF THE WORLD IN SCIENCE AND THEOLOGY

to God. Theologians who want to defend both components ofcreatio ex nihilo need to clarify the similarly and dissimilarlybetween the first and the later states in their relation to God.In the theory discussed here there is no moment with a specialstatus, and therefore the cosmogonie interpretation loses itsforce.

(IV)Different cosmologies provide different contexts for

theological thought. A theology which fits one cosmology neednot be in accord with the other cosmological researchprograms. Hawking's cosmology, as one of the well developedcontemprary programs, does not fit theologies with a strongemphasis on processes in time. Amazingly, this quantumcosmology seems much closer to two seventeenth centuryviews.The cosmology might perhaps be made consonant withtradition reformed theology, which saw everything aspredetremined by God. It might also be combined with aSpinozistic view of God and the world, where the world is oneof God's enternal modes of being. As does the traditionalreformed view, this approach accepts strict determinism. In asense, the Spinozistic view fits even better, as the Universeacquires in Hawking's cosmology some of God's charac-teristics, being timelessly, eternal, and 'necessary'.

There is one major difficulty in case one tries to combineHawking's cosmology with a Christian view of the world. Inthe way it has been presented here, the theory is about threedimensional spaces with material contenrt. They may beordered in time-sequences, but that is secondary. Therefore,the model lacks continuity between subsequent events, like thereading of the first and the second word of a sentence. Onemight evoke God as the One who gives continuity, but thatmakes God 'closing the gaps', to turn a phrase. In the majorChristian traditions there is sense of continuity, as God's greatdeeds in the past (e.g. Exodus, covenant on Sinai, Incarnation,Resurrection) are supposed to have relevance for today and

229

Page 33: OF ORIGINS OF THE WORLD IN SCIENCE AND THEOLOGY

for the future. In a Christian perspective, the past has to betaken up into the present in some way.

A final word of caution: this theory is not to be taken as theconclusion of science today. It is still in development, and it isone program among others, although one of the most elegantand coherent schemes. The special feauture of the Hartle-Hawking scheme is the absence of boundary as its proposal fora boundary condition. This absence of a boundary could be amodel, of limited validity, for reflection on creatio ex nihilo.

4. DOCTRINE OF GOD

4.1. The coherence of divine timelessness: Christianityand Plato

The statment that God is eternal may be understood in twoways (Pike 1970, IX):

— God is everlasting, hence God has an unending duration.— God is timeless, without duration.Friendrich Schleiermacher seems have defended the second

position, God being timeless as well as spaceless. FollowingPike, this implies both that God has neither location in spaceor time, say existing one meter to the right of ... or existingbefore or after another event, nor has he extension in space(filling a certain volume) or time (duration). As Augustine hasit (in Confessiones, Book XI, Ch 13):

• "Thy years do not come and go; while these yearsof ours do come and go, in order that they all maycome. All Thy years stand together, for they standstill, nor are those going away cut off by thosecoming, for they do not pass away. (...) Thy day nota daily recurrent, but today. Thy present day doesnot give place to tomorrow, nor, indeed, does it takethe place of yesterday".

Or, with Anselm of Canterbury (Proslogium, Ch. XIX):

230

Page 34: OF ORIGINS OF THE WORLD IN SCIENCE AND THEOLOGY

• "thou wast not, then, yesterday, nor wilt thou betomorrow; but yesterday and today and tomorrowthou art; or rather, neither yesterday, nor today nortomorrow thou art; but simply, thou art, outside alltime. For yesterday and today and tomorrow haveno existence, except in time; but thou, althoughnothing exists without thee, nevertheless does notexist in space or time, but all things exist in thee".

Discussing Boethius, Pike concludes that according toBoethius God is aware of time, though there is no way topredicate a time of awareness (Pike 1970, 12)

Pike analyses the logical relations of this classical under-standing of divine eternity as divine timelessness with otherdoctrines, like immutability, omnipresence and omniscience.Timelessness has consequences for the interpretation of otherattributes; consequences which he does not like. It is a Platonicinfluence with hardly any scriptural basis. 'What reason isthere for thinking that a doctrine of God's timelessness shouldhave a place in a system of Christian theology?' (Pike 1970,189f).

Whithin the context of philosophy of religion, explicitlyseeking to stand in the Biblical tradition, Paul Helm has arguedstrongly that divine eternity might be understood astimelessness. He understands timelessness not as a separateattribute, but rather as God's way of posessing certainattributes. For God's timelessness "justification can be foundin the need to draw a proper distinction between the creatorand the creature" (p. 17). Thus, "properties which the creatorand his creatures have in common are distinguished by theirmode of possession" (19). Though the Biblical narrativesspeak about God as speaking, etc., etc., the "introduction oftimelessness offers a etaphysical underpinning for God'sFunctioning as the biblical God" (21).

Timelessness may be understood with Boethius:

231

Page 35: OF ORIGINS OF THE WORLD IN SCIENCE AND THEOLOGY

• "Eternity , then , is the complete possession of allat once of illemitable life. ...Therefore, whateverincludes and possesses the whole fullness ofillimitable life at once and is such that nothing futureis absent from it and nothing past has flowed away"

One of the problems concerning the conception of a timelessGod concerns personality; as Hume has said:

• "A mind, whose acts and sentiments and ideas arenot distinct and successive; one, that is whollysimple, and wholly immutable, which has nothought, no reason, no will, no sentiment, no love,no hatred; or in a world, is no mind at all" (Hume,Dialogues concerning natural religion, as quotedbyHelmp.57).

As the concept of person or mind may be anthropocentric,it might well be that one might be willing to concede that Godis not a person in that sens, though the unattainabilkity undnon- manipulability might be reason to use 'person'— ratherthan 'thing'-language in talking about God.

Against Pike's "I see no reason", I see a couple of reasonscoming out of the encounter with cosmology why timelessnesmight have a place:

(l)Time is part of the created order. This is Augustine's viewof creatio cum tempore, and seems a reasonable interpretationof most contemporary cosmologies, the phenomenogical un-derstanding of time. It might be combined with the rejection ofa straightforward cosmogonie interpretation of creatio exnihilo. Hence, it is not meaningful to talk about God as if therewas time before the creation — God as everlasting.

(2) The presence of a timeless description, where the wholeis a unit including all moments, suggests that it is possible totalk about the relation of God to this whole — and not God at

232

Page 36: OF ORIGINS OF THE WORLD IN SCIENCE AND THEOLOGY

one moment to the Universe at that moment, differentiatingmoment in God.

(3) A piatonistic realism about mathematics has recentlybeen defended by Penrose (1989) ; cosmology (and hence ourunderstanding of the world) tends to share more in thatpiatonistic mathematics.

I therefore maintain that it is useful to understand, at leastpartly, God's transcendence with respect to space and time astimelessness. This emphasizes God's unity with respect to theworld.

That leaves us with, at least, two possibilities.(I) If God is understood as a being — more or less the

mainline theistic understanding, an assumption shared by Pikeand Helm, — there still might be an order, and perhaps evena flow, within God which could be labelled God's time. As myteacher in philosophy of religion , Hubbeiling, liked to ask :how could God otherwise enjoy music? If music is notenjoyable when all notes are played at the same moment, God'sperfection, also with respect to esthetical appreciation,requires that God has God's time. Karl Barth seems to havedefended a similar distiction between ordinary time and God'stime when he understood Jesus as the lord of time anddistinguished between an uncreated time which is one of theperfections of the divine being and created, with its successionof past, present, and future (KDIII/2, par.47). However, sucha notion of 'God's time' is hard to fit in once time is thoroughlyphysicalized (2.3) —lust like one isn't free to add one spatialdimension in contemporary superstring theories, anothertemporal dimension might be problematic as well.

(II) An alternative would be to deny that God should beunderstood as 'a being — a single individual possessingnegative as well as positive attributes' (Pike 1970, 1) Godmight, perhaps, be understood differently, say as ' being itself,'the Good', or — in the context with the natural sciences

233

Page 37: OF ORIGINS OF THE WORLD IN SCIENCE AND THEOLOGY

perhaps appropriate, 'intelligibility', perhaps a name for thelaw of nature.

In a sense, three positions may be distinguished, connectingthree epistemological attitudes to three metaphysical stances:

—Upon a critical realistic perspective, God migh be seen asa being up there, having certain properties. This being couldeither have an infinite temporal extension, may be whilechanging through experiences with the world, or have 'a time'of his (her) own.

— A more platonic understanding of God as an abstracteternity, Good, Intelligible or whatever,

— And, thirdly, a more pragmatic line of thought, which seeshuman understanding closely related to human acting. 'God'then doesn't refer to an objective realm, but rather is the termused whenever one wishes to claim the specific nature of valuesas something that go beyond any specific situation. The eternalwouldn't be located in some other realm (heaven), nor beawaited in some other time (Kingdom), but rather beexperienced now and here.

4.2. Creative acts, a single act, or creative values?As Gordon has formulated:

• For a monotheistic theology... it is the whole courseof history from its initiation in God's creativeactivity to its consumation whan God ultimatelyachieves his purposes, that should be conceived asGod's act in the primary sense" (Kaufman in "Onthe meaning of 'act of God'" in God the Problem,Harvard U.P. 1972, p. 139 as quoted by Wiles 1986,29).

This revisionary position, compared with the emphasis onmany specific acts of God, has been defended strongly byWiles. As he sees it, allowing for specific acts of God not onlyruns into trouble with the natural sciences; it also would leadup to the question why God doesn't interfere — God would

234

Page 38: OF ORIGINS OF THE WORLD IN SCIENCE AND THEOLOGY

seem to be morally blameworthy. I need not develop herefurther the discussion whether the world should be seen as asingle act of God , or whether specific acts are imaginable andplausible. However, it still is more or less the classical theisticpicture of a being, a person, acting. It is this concept of Godcreating the Universe which has been defended by thephilosopher of religion Richard Swinburne as plausible, or atleast as preferable over the idea that the Universe might simplybe, a brute fact.

Swinburne thinks that, in description of the evolution of theUniverse, God might come as either responsible for the state,as considered above, or as responsible for the laws. Each stateof the Universe will have a full explanation in terms of a priorstate and the natural laws. The most fundamental law isscientifically inexplicable. It must either be completelyinexplicable, or have a non-scientific explanation, i.e., a Godwho brighs it that the law operates. 'The choice is between theuniverse as stopping-point and God as stopping-point'(Swinburne 1979, 127).

According to Swinburne, a universe is more complex thanGod, so the latter stopping-point is preferable. Thesupposition that there is a God is an extremely simplesupposition. A God of infinite power, knowledge, and freedomis the simpleit kind of person which there could be, since theidea has no limitations in need of explanation. The Universe,on the other hand, has a complexity, particularity, and f initude'which cries out for explanation' (Swinburne 1979, 130).

There is no explicit use of science hi this argument. It mightbe rational and valid, but that is to be debated at the level ofphilosophical reasoning without support from science. Thescientific contribution lies in the description of the Universe.

However, if the choice between accepting the Universe as abrute fact or as needing an explanation of a different kind isjustified by comparing the simplicity of the two hypotheses (asSwinburne does), it is a matter of the utmost importance to

235

Page 39: OF ORIGINS OF THE WORLD IN SCIENCE AND THEOLOGY

understand how complex or simple the two alternatives are.Many cosmologists believe that their theories are of animpressive simplicity and elegance in structure andassumptions, even if the mathematics is difficult. Whether thismakes it more or less reasonable to regard the Universe as a'creation' is not clear (why could one not believe that Godmade a universe with a simple structure?), but it doesundermine Swinburne's argument based on simplicity.

Alternative, closer to a platonic strand: Leslie: creativevalues.

5. ETERNAL AND PRESENT: THEOLOGY IN TWOPERSPECTIVES

Almost all current theologians who take science seriously optfor a dynamic picture. Often, cosmic evolution is considered asan extension of biological evolution. When the physical viewof time is discusses, there is a strong emphasis on the flow oftime and the asymmetry of time. This is especially true forprocess theologians. An exception is the physicist and anglicanpriest John Polkinghorne, who sees an analogy between theduality of a timeless level of description aside of a descriptionfrom within time with the duality in theology between 'the Godof the philosophers' with emphasis on the static perfection andremoteness, and 'the God of Abraham, Isaac, and Jacob', withthe danger of too much anthropomorfism. "A true account willhold the two in balance" (Polkinghorne 1988, 6; see also p.XIII) A similar balance of theological notions related to thetwo descripyions is what will be searched for in this section.

5.1. Opportunities of the two descriptionsPhilosophical theology and theoretical science lake some

distance from common sense experience. At that level bothdescriptions, considering evolution in time and whole'histories', might be useful. They allow for different clusters ofassociations, and thereby help to see the world differently.However, they both have their own disadvantage as well.

Page 40: OF ORIGINS OF THE WORLD IN SCIENCE AND THEOLOGY

Combining both perspectives in relation to a present seems tome the most promising theological approach. The precisemeaning of all the terms is dependent upon the further systemin which the ideas participate. The following provides a briefoverview of the two networks of associated concepts.

A description within time takes history and evolution asbasic. Evolution is here a broad category, including cosmic,stellar, geological and cultural change. This resonates with atheological emphasis on 'Heilsgechichte' (salvation history).Creatio ex nihilo is most easily associated with questions aboutultimate origins, hence cosmogony. Creatio continua will bethe theological doctrine that deals with God's relation to theprocesses of change, especially God's relation to theemergence of novelty. Time is always there. Contingency isprimarily about events; instead of those events that Happenedsomething else could have happened, and the events of thefuture are still contingent. Initial conditions could have beendifferent. Necessity seems reflected in the laws, which are thesame for all moments in time. Value is easily related to thefuture — the qualities of decision will be judged by theconsequences. Hence, one has a ideological or utilistic kindof ethics. The eschaton, say the Kingdom of God , is closelyrelated to the future. God's relation to the world is most easilyformulated in terms of immanence or temporal transcendence(e.g., being before the world, or as luring towards a betterfuture).

The timeless perspective, or rather the perspective thatincorporates the whole of time, might be understood as a viewsub specie aeternitatis, a 'bird's-eye view', the whole ofhistory as if seen from beyond.

Creatio ex nihilo is not correlated with questions about theorigin. Rather, it reflects the question about the ground ofeverything. (For an atemporal understanding of 'ground' onecould think of the role of aximata in a mathematical system —they may come first in arguments. In the order of knowing,

237

Page 41: OF ORIGINS OF THE WORLD IN SCIENCE AND THEOLOGY

although they are, historically speaking, formulated only aftersome time. They are not prior to the system in the order ofbeing. They are the ground of the system, with the system.)Creatio ex nihilo might also be understood as expressio of Godsustaining the world at all moments. Creatio continua mightalso express this notion of sustaining, or in more traditionalterms, God's conservatie. However, it is stripped from theemphasis on change and novelty, which it has in the otherperspective. 'Novelty' is not a concept that fits in this timelessperspective, it belongs to the other language.

Time is more explicitly seen as part of the created order.Contingency is primarily the ontological kind: why is thereanything at all? Besides, the contingency of the law is moreexplicit: why this package and not another? The events are nolonger seen as contingent: they are all necessary relative to thewhole of history. Value must be understood as being there forevery event, just by being part of the whole web — or perhapseven more primitively, just by being. This lends itself morereadily to a deontological view of ethics, as expressed inImmanuel Kant's second formulation of the categoricalimperative, the ground rule for his ethical system, which statesthat one should never treat others only as means towardsends.They are always ends in themselves. Eschatology is lessconnected with the future, are more with God's transcendence.Transcendence is less easily underdtood as temporal (beforeand after the world); rather is a radical beyond — as if in acompletely different dimension.

Both these approaches are in danger of missing somethingessential. The perspective incorporating the whole of timemight result in a conservative, status-quo affirming, under-standing of eternal values — and thus divert attention fromcorcrete contexts of injustice and suffering to a timeless andeternal 'other place'. Doing without the perspective fromwithin time would mean the loss of concreteness. It might wellfit with a more purely Platonic philosophical thinking, or an

238

Page 42: OF ORIGINS OF THE WORLD IN SCIENCE AND THEOLOGY

Eastern perspective, but Christianity has emphasized the valueof particulars, and the importance of God's activities in theworld, for instance in the history of Israel. Taking only thetimeless perspective might, just as might an over-emphasis onunity, make it difficult to maintain this characteristic ofChristianity.

However, we need not take only the description from withintime. The timeless perspective also allows the expression ofvaluable convictions. It is especially valuable as it may openour thoughts to the possibility of something other than thetemporal, and hence to considerations about God'stranscendence. An evolutionary faith is in danger ofsubsuming present suffering and injustice under a futurehappiness, and thus becoming the optimistic expectation of an'other time'. Besides, the combination of the two perspectivesmight be more valuable than a mere juxtaposition of them.Prophetical criticism appeals to God's otherness ortranscendence — that is its Archimedean point to criticize thepresent.

5.2. The view sub specie aeternitatisSpeaking about God in a space-time framework which takes

the whole at once is not all that one could say about God as theEternal One. It only offers an entrance. With respect to thewhole of time one may make a similar suggestion of a beyondwhich has an atemporal transcendence, the Eternal. This is notcaught in the description. From the scientific perspective it canbe, at most, an assumed supplement 'out of the plane of thespace-time description'. This notion of atemporaltranscendence, and the correlated view of the whole of time,might be useful as an understanding of God. An ethical analogyhas been development by Sutherland.

As Sutherland argues, a view sub specie aeternitatis is notone that can be attained definitely. But it can be a notion, whichexpresses the intention to aim at an understanding of humanaffairs which goes beyond any limited outlook, whether of an

239

Page 43: OF ORIGINS OF THE WORLD IN SCIENCE AND THEOLOGY

individual, of a community or even of humanity (Sutherland1984, 88). The idea functions like the transcendentalregulative ideas of reason, as directing the understandingtowards a certain goal.

The unattainability, the transcendence, is essential. It issane to allow self-questioning in relation to a perspective otherthan one's own. If this 'other perspective' is accessible, like alist of eternal values, it might result in fanatism without self-questioning. The idea of the eternal as referring to somethingtranscending even one's most cherished view keeps faith open(Sutherland 1984, 110).

5.3. Axiologica I eschatology

• But the true longing of humanity is not for anafterlife; it is for the establishment of a justice hereand now that will make an afterlife unnecessary.

John Fowles 1980, 30.In this section I will sketch a framework for an eschatogy

from the perspective of the present, which emphasizes anatemporal transcendence.

Transformation as personal conversion or social change isan important theme in many theologies, especially inevangelical and political theologies. Natural theologies arisingout of experiences with the natural world mostly lack this; theytend to overemphasize the actual state of affairs as onedeserving wonder. However, a theologically adequate naturaltheology should, in my opinion, attempt to disclose thepossibilities for transformation of the natural order.

The idea of tranmsformation might suggest emphasis onanother state, either a future Kingdom or a Heaven 'up there'.Using a distinction made by John Hick (1977), adevelopmental view directed towards a future state ofperfection might be called Irenean. To struggle and to copewith evil is part of the process of growing , of maturing.Emphasis on the process might offer relief from the evil we do,

240

Page 44: OF ORIGINS OF THE WORLD IN SCIENCE AND THEOLOGY

as all things are supposed to work together for the final good.Such a view is in danger of diverting our attention from presentresponsibility to the anticipation of a future perfection willcome anyhow, effected by God. An 'Augustinian' view doesn'tfocus on future proces of perfection. Rather, as expressed inthe Reformed traditions, evil is taken very seriously. Theworldly process will not lead to perfection; the perfection is tobe expected in another realm, easily imagined to be spatiallydistinct, solely effected by God. Both views diminish therelevance of the present, and of our activities in the present,by locating perfection in another time, a future state ofmatur i ty , or another place, a heavenly state of bliss.

Combining the emphasis on transformation and on thepresent as the location of our responsabilities leads to apraxiological emphasis in theology, agaonst escapism toheaven or to an indefinite future.

In the further interpretation of a present orientedeschatology which deals with injustice, three elements shouldbe present (in my option, if one wishes to keep core elementsof the prophetical tradition) :

(1) judgment on the present, a valution;(2) appeal to action in response to that judgement,

conversion;(3) consolation in contexts of injustice, failure, and

suffering.In oder to develop an adequate eschatology which correlates

with the concern for justice, especially with the dimensions ofjudgment and appeal, we need to develop a metaphysicalscheme which is au fait with science. Such metaphysicsshould allow a theology which is primarily prophetical, aimedat critical relativizing the status quo , and evoking a response.Such a theology needs a difference between what is possibleand what is actual. The future is one which we make, not onewhich is definitely enfolded in the cosmic process. God might

241

Page 45: OF ORIGINS OF THE WORLD IN SCIENCE AND THEOLOGY

be understood as the source, or even the locus, of the valuesand the possibilities. Pour elements are needed.

l.The present is the central state of reference, and not a farpast or a far future.

2. Each actual present is correlated with a set of possibilities,alternatives for the near future of the present.

3. The consequences of the different options in a givenpresent are to some extent predictable.

4. A reference frame for evaluating the different options isneeded, an orientation on the space of alternatives.

Ad 1. The unique moment which is the actual present is notcaught by the language of physics. To take the present as abasic notion in one's view implies that one reaches beyond thescientifically describable. It seems preferable to do so, as it isthe locus of existence, the locus of decisions and actions thelocus where God should be relevant, if relevant anywhere.

Ad 2 and 3 .Total determinism eliminates the secondcondition. There are no alternatives, there is no morally ac-countable behavior. Nobody can make a difference for thesake of justice. The issue which needs further consideration,in, my opinion, in the reflection on faith and cosmology is notwhether God is to be understood as timeless or acting in time,but whether reality is of such a complexity and time is of sucha nature that one can speak meaningfully about responsiblehuman actions in time.

Unpredictability of consequences, which follows from totalindeterminism, eliminism, eliminates accountablity as well.There should be a partial predictability, at least a reasonableexpectation of the consequences for the near future, if oneprefers one alternative for action over another.

In actual practice, the predictability of complex systems likethe weather is limited. In most cases, predictions are better forthe near future than for the far future. The study of complexand chaotic systems has developed rapidly over the lastdecade. 'Chaos' sciences seem to offer possibilities for a

Page 46: OF ORIGINS OF THE WORLD IN SCIENCE AND THEOLOGY

scientifically adequate expression of a limited predictabilitywhile denying the possibility of a complete predictability, asone can never, in principle, know with sufficient accuracy allrelevant conditions. If, and this is a very sizable if, theepistemological unpredictability in chaos theories is integratedwith ontological indeterminacy as a possible interpretation ofquantum physics, one might perhaps be able to formulate aframwork the conditions 2 and 3 are fulfilled.

Ronger Penrose has in his recent The Emperor's New Mindargued that one should distinguish between the computable andthe true. Intuition plays a role in 'seeing the truth' of amathematical statement, even if it isn't provable within thesystem. May be that such distinctions offer more promise thanthe appeal to chaos-theories in integrating deterministicaspects of cosmology with human thought and action.

Ad4. The existence of moral, esthetic, or other, criteriarelevant to the choices is the most a-scintific. It is transcendentwith respect to the space-time framework. It might bring in theAugustinian 'other place' as a reference, relevant to the stepstowards the near future.

I therefore suggest to understand God both as the ground ofreality and as the source of values and possibilities. The firstelement, God as the ground, expresses the affirmation of thegoodness of finite reality and envisages a locus for objectiveimmortality. The second component, of possibilities andvalues, corresponds to the call for conversion for the sake of amore just future. In such a way one could combine thedimensions of depth and future, of mysticism and history.

Whether that might be conceived of intelligible in the contextof contemporary cosmology with its platonistic tendencies,needs further consideration. Among the issues to be consideredthus, the constructive side of science should also come into thepicture. The theories suggest a platonic reality, but they aremade by humans from their limited point of view, from 'the

243

Page 47: OF ORIGINS OF THE WORLD IN SCIENCE AND THEOLOGY

(conceptual and physical) world within the world' (JohnBarrow).

REFERENCES

Barbour, I.G. 1990, Religion in an Age of Science. San Franc.:Harper &Row.Barrow, J.D. 1988. The World Wilhin the World. Oxford Univ. Press.Cobb, J.B., D.R.Griffin. 1976. Process Theology: an IntroductoryExpresition. Manchester Univ.Press & Philed.: Westmister Press.Craig, W.L. 1979. The Kalam Cosmological Argument. London:Macmillan.Dress, WB 1990. Beyond the Big Bang: Quatum Cosmologies and God.La Salle: Open Court.Fowles, J. 1980. TheAristos. Flmouth (Cornwall): Triad/Granada.Frautschi, S. 1982. Entopy in an expanding U niverse. Science 217:593-9.Hartle, J.B. 1988. Quantum kinematics of spacetime. Physical ReviewD37: 2818-2832, 038:2985-2999.Hartle,J.B., S.W. Hawking. 1983. Wavefunction of the Universe. PhysicalReview D28:2960-2975.Hartshorae, C. 1948. The Divine Relativity. Yale University Press.Hawking, S.W. 1982. The Boundary Conditions of the Universe. InAsirophysical Cosmology: Proceedings of a Studyweek on Cosmologyand Fundamental Physics, eds. H.A. Breck, G.V.Coyne, M.S.Longair.Vatican: Pontifica Academia Scientiarum.—1984 . Quantum cosmology. In Relativity, Groups and Topology II.

eds. B.S. Dcwilt, , R.Stora. Amsterdam: North Holland.— 1988. A Brief History of Time. New York; Bantam Books.Heim, Paul. 1989. Eternal God. Oxford: Clarendon.Heller, M. 1987. Big Bang on ultimate questions. In Origin and EarlyHistory of the Universe: Proceeding of the 26th Liege InternationalAstrophysics Colloquium, July 1 — 4 1986. Cointre -Ougree (Belgique),Hick, J. 1966. Evil and the God of Love. London :Macmillan. (Rev. ed.1977).Isham, CJ. 1988. Creation of the universe as a quantum process. InPhysics, Philosophy and Theology, eds. R.J.Russell, W.R.Stoeger, andG.V.Coyne. Vatican: Vatican Observatory; distributed by Univ. of NotreDame Press.Kroes, P. 1985. Time: its structure and role in physical Theories.Dordrecht: Reidel.

244

Page 48: OF ORIGINS OF THE WORLD IN SCIENCE AND THEOLOGY

Leslie, J. 1979. Value and Existence. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.— 1990. Univrses.Linde, A.D. 1985. Particle physics and cosmology. Progress ofTheoretical physics, Supp. 85: 279-291.May, G. 1978. Schöpfung aus dem Nichts: Die Entstehung der Lehre vonder creatio ex nihilo. Berlin: Walter de Gruyter.McCall, K. 1976. Objective time flow. Philisophy of science 43:337-362.Misner, C.W., K.S.Thorne, J.A.Wheeler. 1973. Gravitation. San Franc.:Freeman.Munitz, M.K. 1974. The Mystery of Existence. New York Univ. Press.—1986. Cosmic Understanding. Princeton Univ. Press.Penrose, R. 1971. Time asymmetry and quantum gravity. In QuantumGravity 2, eds. C.J.Isham, R.Penrose, D.W.Sciama. Oxford:Clarendon.—1986. Big Bangs, Black Holes and 'Time's Arrow'. In The Nature of

Time, eds. R.Flood, M. Lockwood. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.— 1989. The Emperer's New Mind. Oxford Univ. Press.Pike, N. 1970. God and titnelessness. London: Routledge and KeganPaul.Polkinghorne, J. 1988. Science and Creation. London: SCM.Sagan, C. 1988. Introduction. In S.W.Hawking (1988).Smart, J.J.C. 1990. Our Place in the Universe. Oxford: BlackweU.Swinburne, R. 1979. The Existence of God. Oxford U.P.Tipler, F.J. 1989. The Omega Point as Eschaton: Answers toPannenberg's Questions to Scientists. Zygon.Wiles, Maurice. 1986. God's Action in the world. London: SCM.

Dr. M.C. DuffySchool of technology

Surnderland PolitechnicUnited Kindom, SRI 3SD

CLOCK—TIME, PHYSICAL MEASUREMENT, ANDTHE AGE THE UNIVERSE

Physical time and metaphysical timePhysics is about measurements wich rods and clocks, and

therefore the identification of the most accurate available

245