Linking Psychological and Philosophical Viewsdnarvaez/documents/Reilly_Narvaez... · 2018-11-29 ·...

29
For author’s use only. PTSc 5 (2018), 51–79 DOI 10.1628/ptsc-2018-0005 ISSN 2195-9773 © 2018 Mohr Siebeck Timothy S. Reilly and Darcia Narvaez Character, Virtue, and Science Linking Psychological and Philosophical Views In the past century, both philosophy and psychology have reawakened to virtue, but mostly independently. How can the disciplines integrate their approaches to virtue scholarship? We examine three key assertions from virtue ethics in light of empirical research in psychology: (1) that virtue is realized in habits and dispositions, (2) that virtue is realized by a mean between extremes (doctrine of the mean), and (3) that virtue relates to human flourishing and the telos. We discuss selected contempo- rary psychological programs – structural examinations of personality, expertise, and developmental studies – and consider their strengths and limitations in light of phil- osophical concerns and as they relate to virtue generally and specifically in science. We finish by suggesting areas for future fruitful inquiry at the intersection of virtue ethics and psychology. 1. Introduction With increasing attention to virtue in psychology and the relevance of psy- chological theory and research to virtue ethics in philosophy (e. g., Annas et al 2016; Miller et al. 2015; Timpe and Boyd 2014; Peterson et al. 2017), we examine psychological research in light of philosophical conceptions of vir- tue. In doing so, we intend to highlight relevant research for philosophical consideration in the hope of providing some pathways into empirical studies for philosophers. At the same time, we hope that this entices psychologists to integrate philosophical concepts more explicitly into their work. Finally, we emphasize the implications of this work for understanding virtue in science. Traditional societies have always been concerned with raising virtu- ous community members (Deloria 2006). Western education historically integrated religiously-based character development into lessons (e. g., McGuffey’s Readers), even at the university level. But with increasing di- versity of religious backgrounds, religiously-guided character education di- minished in public schooling (Arthur 2014). Noting a decline in moral- ity across US society in the mid-20th century, moral education scholars

Transcript of Linking Psychological and Philosophical Viewsdnarvaez/documents/Reilly_Narvaez... · 2018-11-29 ·...

Page 1: Linking Psychological and Philosophical Viewsdnarvaez/documents/Reilly_Narvaez... · 2018-11-29 · Character, Virtue, and Science 55 For author’s use only. of automaticity or spontaneous

For author’s use only.

PTSc 5 (2018), 51–79 DOI 10.1628/ptsc-2018-0005 ISSN 2195-9773 © 2018 Mohr Siebeck

Timothy S. Reilly and Darcia Narvaez

Character, Virtue, and ScienceLinking Psychological and Philosophical Views

In the past century, both philosophy and psychology have reawakened to virtue, but mostly independently. How can the disciplines integrate their approaches to virtue scholarship? We examine three key assertions from virtue ethics in light of empirical research in psychology: (1) that virtue is realized in habits and dispositions, (2) that virtue is realized by a mean between extremes (doctrine of the mean), and (3) that virtue relates to human flourishing and the telos. We discuss selected contempo-rary psychological programs – structural examinations of personality, expertise, and developmental studies – and consider their strengths and limitations in light of phil-osophical concerns and as they relate to virtue generally and specifically in science. We finish by suggesting areas for future fruitful inquiry at the intersection of virtue ethics and psychology.

1. Introduction

With increasing attention to virtue in psychology and the relevance of psy-chological theory and research to virtue ethics in philosophy (e. g., Annas et al 2016; Miller et al. 2015; Timpe and Boyd 2014; Peterson et al. 2017), we examine psychological research in light of philosophical conceptions of vir-tue. In doing so, we intend to highlight relevant research for philosophical consideration in the hope of providing some pathways into empirical studies for philosophers. At the same time, we hope that this entices psychologists to integrate philosophical concepts more explicitly into their work. Finally, we emphasize the implications of this work for understanding virtue in science.

Traditional societies have always been concerned with raising virtu-ous community members (Deloria 2006). Western education historically integrated religiously-based character development into lessons (e. g., McGuffey’s Readers), even at the university level. But with increasing di-versity of religious backgrounds, religiously-guided character education di-minished in public schooling (Arthur 2014). Noting a decline in moral-ity across US society in the mid-20th century, moral education scholars

Page 2: Linking Psychological and Philosophical Viewsdnarvaez/documents/Reilly_Narvaez... · 2018-11-29 · Character, Virtue, and Science 55 For author’s use only. of automaticity or spontaneous

52 Timothy S. Reilly and Darcia Narvaez

For author’s use only.

began to advocate character education, making recommendations inspired by religious and ancient Greek notions of virtuous character (e. g., Ryan and Lickona 1987; Lickona 1983; Wynne and Ryan 1993). However, these philosophical models are not well applied in practice. For example, instead of promoting an ethic of virtue, most character educational programs have been rooted in deontological or utilitarian assumptions and goals1:

In most accounts of character education, one cultivates virtues mostly to better fulfill one’s obligation and duty (the ethics of requirement) or to prevent the rising tide of youth disorder (character utilitarianism, or the ethics of consequences). Although one can conceive of virtues as providing action-guiding prescriptions just as deontological theory does (Hursthouse 2003), the point of virtues in most accounts of character edu-cation is to live up to the prescriptions derived from deontic considerations: to respect persons, fulfill one’s duty to the self and to others, and submit to the natural law (Lapsley and Narvaez 2006, 257).

What is called character education actually then typically focuses on an ethics of requirement (e. g., should Heinz steal the drug?) or an ethics of consequences (e. g., will more people benefit from x or y?), and not on an ethics of virtue.

In Western psychological studies of character, early empirical studies searched for cross-situational consistency in moral character in children, which was presumed necessary for demonstrating good character. But they had difficulty finding it, driving the whole enterprise underground (Hart-shorne and May 1928, 1929, 1930). With the importation of neo-Piaget-ianism by Lawrence Kohlberg in the mid-20th century, deontological ap-proaches dominated moral psychological research for the rest of the century (Kohlberg 1981, 1984; Lapsley 2006)2. These approaches focused primarily

1 From Lapsley and Narvaez 2006, 257: “G. Watson (1990) suggested a useful tripartite division of ethical theory: the ethic of requirement (where the primary moral consid-erations concern rational judgments of obligation and duty and the moral appraisal of action), the ethic of consequences (various forms of utilitarianism), and the ethic of virtue. An ethics of virtue is distinguished from the others by its claim that the basic moral facts are facts about the quality of character (arête); that judgments about agents and their traits have explanatory primacy over judgments about duty, obligation, and utility; and that deontic judgments about obligation and action appraisal are, in fact, derived from the appraisal of character and ancillary to it. ‘On an ethics of virtue,’ he writes, ‘how it is best or right or proper to conduct oneself is explained in terms of how it is best for a human being to be’ (p. 451).”

Hence, a virtue ethics has two features: (1) It makes a claim of explanatory primacy for aretaic judgments about character, agents, and what is required for flourishing; and (2) it includes a theory about ‘how it is best or right or proper to conduct oneself ’ in light of what is known about human excellence.”

2 Erikson describes the resolution of each of the stages in his life-span theory as entail-ing virtue; however, this is a largely unexplored area of his work (though his theory is

Page 3: Linking Psychological and Philosophical Viewsdnarvaez/documents/Reilly_Narvaez... · 2018-11-29 · Character, Virtue, and Science 55 For author’s use only. of automaticity or spontaneous

53Character, Virtue, and Science

For author’s use only.

on the individual’s preferred way of making moral judgments in response to moral dilemmas, empirically measuring the developmental progress of moral reasoning. The flaws in a focus on reason alone became apparent when empirical linkages between reasoning and action were found to be weak (Lapsley 2006; Koenigs et al. 2007). Other scholars began to suggest additional factors critical for moral behavior, such as self-identity (Blasi 1980) – i. e., in order to take what is judged to be the moral action, one must be morally motivated – morality must be a central concern to the self.

The scope of moral functioning expanded further. Comprehensive ap-proaches to educating moral behavior emphasized the importance of a host of psychological components and subcomponents beyond moral reasoning capacities alone, such as ethical sensitivity, ethical motivation (including self-identity), and implementation capacities (Rest 1983; Narvaez and Rest 1995). As with early studies of moral development, holistic approaches to moral character were centered around character formation in schools. One such holistic approach integrates self-authorship and ethical skills (sensitiv-ity, judgment, focus, action) within a context of guided mentoring, commu-nity support, and positive climate, all addressing the question “Who should I be(come)?” (e. g., Narvaez et al. 2004). Although programs such as these did not use the term ‘virtue,’ in effect they were oriented to its development.

Recently, the broader field of psychology, outside of education, has shown an interest in studying virtue per se (e. g., Frimer and Walker 2009; Damon and Colby 2015; Reimer et al. 2012; Monroe 2001), especially with the rise of positive psychology (e. g., Peterson and Seligman 2004). Theoretical psy-chologists have begun to develop frameworks to support more robust em-pirical and theoretical models of virtue in psychology (Fowers 2012; Narvaez 2014, 2016; Nelson and Slife 2017). Nevertheless, conceptions of virtue in psychology vary considerably.

In light of Aristotelian concepts of virtue, this paper reviews psychologi-cal research, most of which does not explicitly aim to be about virtue. Even when this research seeks to directly examine virtue and character, it does so in a general and incomplete way, making theoretical connections to philo-sophical concepts challenging. We primarily sample from theories, studies, and programs of research that speak to virtue in practice if not by name. We provide empirically-derived explanations and terminology to bridge the divide between psychology and philosophy, drawing mostly from per-sonality, educational, and developmental psychology. We also seek to apply

foundational for research on generativity and purpose, as we will discuss later) (Erikson 1961, 1968).

Page 4: Linking Psychological and Philosophical Viewsdnarvaez/documents/Reilly_Narvaez... · 2018-11-29 · Character, Virtue, and Science 55 For author’s use only. of automaticity or spontaneous

54 Timothy S. Reilly and Darcia Narvaez

For author’s use only.

the insights gained to the nature of a virtuous scientist. How does or could psychology shed light on the nature of a virtuous scientist in light of philo-sophical categories?

2. Comparing Aristotelian Virtue Concepts with Psychological Research and Theory

In Western philosophy, most discussions of virtue begin with Aristotle’s Ni-comachean Ethics (Anscombe 1958) or Aquinas’ Summa Theologiae (Mac-Intyre 1981). Although lists of virtues are often prescribed, we focus on an Aristotelian perspective on the basic features of virtuous character, which typically includes one or more of the following: (1) habitual disposition, (2) acting according to the golden mean, and (3) aiming for the telos or flour-ishing of human beings. We discuss these briefly and relate them to psycho-logical constructs as well as to virtue in science, and then present a more in-depth discussion of a particular psychological program of study that pro-vides productive empirical findings relevant to virtue, especially in science. We close our presentation of psychological work with an integrative section, drawing heavily on work in developmental psychology, elucidating some of the psychological roots of virtue formation.

a) Personal Continuity

Dispositional Habits. Aristotle’s notion of habits and habituation refers to learning by doing with regular and consistent practice under the guidance of a virtuous mentor (Steutel and Spiecker 2004; Narvaez and Lapsley 2005). When virtue is described as dispositional, it refers to a set of sensibilities and capacities (perceptions, orientation, attitudes, feelings, thinking, motivation, action) that become ‘natural’ with practice and essential to oneself (Roberts 2017; Titus 2017). Virtue is not effortful but becomes spontaneous (Slinger-land 2015). One must be well-mentored to develop in a virtuous rather than a vicious direction, and one’s character is co-constructed by the community from the very beginning (Nicomachean Ethics; Narvaez 2014). Virtuous in-dividuals have developed ways of perceiving, feeling, thinking, choosing, and acting that lead them to be more likely to contribute to the wellbeing of the community (Norton 1991). Mentored practice leads to settled dis-positions to behave in particular ways on a routine basis without reflective choice, deliberation, or planning (Steutel and Spiecker 2004). This descrip-tion aligns with contemporary cognitive science, including the requirement

Page 5: Linking Psychological and Philosophical Viewsdnarvaez/documents/Reilly_Narvaez... · 2018-11-29 · Character, Virtue, and Science 55 For author’s use only. of automaticity or spontaneous

55Character, Virtue, and Science

For author’s use only.

of automaticity or spontaneous action (Narvaez and Lapsley 2004; Varela 1999).

Although virtue theorists often use the term ‘habits’ to describe virtu-ous dispositions, many psychologists cringe at the term. Psychologists his-torically have conducted extensive research on habits, particularly with animals, and in the field the term can be problematic because of its asso-ciation with a discredited psychological theory, behaviorism, which implies a Cartesian-mechanistic worldview of passive subjects shaped by external forces or guided by disembodied minds. In this view, habits are sets of knee-jerk conditioned responses that ignore individual initiative in construct-ing a response. Yet, according to cognitive science, ‘dispositions to act’ are based on schemas (generalized knowledge structures that combine emotion, cognition and action) developed from patterns of experience (Lapsley and Narvaez 2006). However, more accurately, and corresponding to ancient descriptions of virtuous behavior (Yearley 1990), humans are “thoroughly embodied and embedded, actively and directly engaged in practical, prere-flective commerce with the world” (Narvaez and Witherington 2018).

Aristotelian habitus conforms to views in philosophy that describe virtue as skill development (Annas 2011), to views in educational and developmen-tal psychology referring to the development of expertise formed through extensive skill development (Ericsson and Charness 1994; Hatano and Ina-gaki 1986), and to dynamic moral psychological theory as mentioned earlier (Narvaez and Lapsley 2005; Narvaez and Bock 2014). We discuss the notion of skill below when addressing expertise.

In contemporary empirical research, individual behavior is often under-stood in terms of ‘traits.’ The two dominant subfields committed to un-derstanding individual behavior – personality psychology, emphasizing the study of individuals and variation among them, and social psychology, em-phasizing the role of context in psychological functioning – typically define traits as a person’s generalized tendencies to behave consistently across situ-ations (e. g., Costa and McCrae 1992). However, traits are typically meas-ured at the population or group level, comparing group means to make generalizations (nomothetic approach), and studies do not focus on varia-tion among individuals (respecting the uniqueness of each individual – the ideographic approach). The nomothetic approach is too general to predict any individual’s particular pattern of behavior with regularity. Moreover, the notion of traits misleads in that individuals do not carry traits from situation to situation, as they would, for example, blue eyes. Thus, the term ‘trait,’ like the term ‘habit,’ is also insufficient for describing virtue. Instead, and more aligned with virtue theory, dispositions shift by situation in a

Page 6: Linking Psychological and Philosophical Viewsdnarvaez/documents/Reilly_Narvaez... · 2018-11-29 · Character, Virtue, and Science 55 For author’s use only. of automaticity or spontaneous

56 Timothy S. Reilly and Darcia Narvaez

For author’s use only.

person-by-context interaction, leading to variability across contexts but also consistency within contexts and within persons (Lapsley and Narvaez 2005, 2006). Further, trait theorists’ examination of dispositions typically is not tied directly to considerations of virtue (although see Fleeson and Jayawick-reme 2015 for a new approach).

Whereas social scientific research on virtue and character has its roots largely in education, Sigmund Freud is credited with the initiation of a per-sonality research program in which he intertwined morality with his tripar-tite division of the psyche (note that his theory is thoroughly discredited among social scientists today). In contrast, personality theorists like Gordon Allport attempted to extricate personality psychology from concern with moral evaluation (Allport 1927). Today when virtue is mentioned by per-sonality researchers, it is often thinly defined (see especially Peterson and Seligman 2004, and critiques by Peterson et al. 2010; Van Slyke et al. 2012; Miller 2013; Roberts 2017; Kinghorn 2017; Titus 2017; Nelson and Slife 2017). Notably, Aristotle himself acknowledged that “most of these [virtu-ous] states also have no names, but we must try, as in other cases, to invent names ourselves” (Nicomachean Ethics 1108a). To be sure, it is an impedi-ment to empirical study that many states of character have no names. None-theless, several researchers have addressed moral and spiritual dispositions broadly, such as moral identity (Frimer and Walker 2009), moral expertise (Narvaez and Lapsley 2005), spiritual identity (Schnitker et al. 2017), and moral chronicity (Narvaez et al. 2006). These research programs indicate that some dispositions relate to moral or spiritual functioning, especially in the case of individuals who conceive of themselves and the world in moral or spiritual terms. What is needed, then, is a closer examination of histori-cally prominent conceptions of habits, traits, and personality in psychology in order to differentiate them when considering virtue.

Dispositions in science can be studied empirically. In our work, we are utilizing conceptions of virtues from Aquinas (Aquinas 1991) and contem-porary virtue epistemology (e. g., Baehr 2011), contrasting laboratory sci-entists with ensemble musicians on their ratings of ideal and actual disposi-tions in their discipline (Reilly and Narvaez, in preparation). However, more complex notions of virtues must be adopted to advance our understanding of virtue in science, drawing on qualitative approaches including interview and ethnography.

Psychological Structural Models of Personality. Complex theoretical models of personality attempt to address multiple levels of behavior and to avoid the pitfalls mentioned above (i. e., the limitations of the concepts of habit and

Page 7: Linking Psychological and Philosophical Viewsdnarvaez/documents/Reilly_Narvaez... · 2018-11-29 · Character, Virtue, and Science 55 For author’s use only. of automaticity or spontaneous

57Character, Virtue, and Science

For author’s use only.

trait). One structural approach to personality proposes three ‘levels’ of per-sonality structure, based on existing lines of research: traits, characteristic adaptations (e. g., goals), and narratives (e. g., life stories) (McAdams 1996). As noted above, trait disposition research (e. g., Big Five theory; Costa and McCrae 1992) aggregates group data to look for recurring patterns of gen-eral dispositions across individuals, making the assumption that individuals’ patterns of behavior are similar across a variety of situations. The limitations of a trait approach are addressed in McAdams’ theory by two additional loci of personality. Characteristic adaptations are an individual’s typical way of being in the contexts in which they find themselves. They are expressions of dispositions within particular situations or circumstances, and may become more complex over time (McAdams 2013). Conforming to the person-by-context individual signatures mentioned earlier, such adaptations encom-pass both reactive responses to the situations a person encounters (e. g., the manner of responding to criticism from a family member) and intentional engagements in the pursuit of particular ends (e. g., seeking to improve family relationships). Characteristic adaptations are often researched in the form of an individual’s varied goals, strivings, and projects (Emmons 1999; Little 1993). Finally, individuals construct narratives and identities to inte-grate characteristic adaptations into a coherent story, structuring an iden-tity and sense of continuity over time. Thus one can think of an individual’s characteristic adaptations as a complex system, and narratives as attempts to describe and justify that system.

One type of relevant characteristic adaptation studied empirically is purpose – a goal that is personally meaningful but also of consequence to the world beyond the self (Damon et al. 2003). An individual’s purpose can serve to organize narratives, guide selection of subordinate goals, and channel expression of traits (Malin et al. 2014). Another area important to our reconceptualization of virtue in psychology is the notion of identity. In narrative and identity research, moral identity refers to placing moral-ity as central to the self (Frimer and Walker 2009; Narvaez and Lapsley 2009). Moral self and identity are shaped during the course of development (Kochanska et al. 2010; Reimer et al. 2009). Moral identity correlates with behaviors such as civic involvement, volunteering, and more productive behavior in the workplace (Cohen and Panter 2015). Emmons provides evidence of relationship between spiritual identity, meaning, and life satis-faction (Emmons 1999). Identity also encompasses redemption narratives, stories of personal growth in the face of setbacks or losses (McAdams and Guo 2015). These narratives are associated with individuals’ involvement in generative activities, such as volunteering and other contributions to

Page 8: Linking Psychological and Philosophical Viewsdnarvaez/documents/Reilly_Narvaez... · 2018-11-29 · Character, Virtue, and Science 55 For author’s use only. of automaticity or spontaneous

58 Timothy S. Reilly and Darcia Narvaez

For author’s use only.

one’s community, especially towards children, supporting the thriving of future generations.

Prior to the formation of traits, characteristic adaptations, and narra-tives, temperament is a term used to describe differences among children that emerge at a very early age (based on interactions between early life ex-perience and biology) in facets of behavior such as emotionality, sociabil-ity, activity level, and self-regulation, and that can remain relatively stable across the life span (Buss and Plomin 1984; Rothbart 2007; Shiner et al. 2012; Shiner and DeYoung 2013; Josefsson et al. 2013). Temperament may be setting the stage for a given individual’s expression of virtuous behavior, in alignment with theories describing the interplay of traits, characteristic adaptations, contexts, and well-being, components conducive to flourish-ing given one’s life circumstances and the needs present in one’s community (e. g., Emmons 1999; McGregor and Little 1998; Little 2008).

Imagine, for instance, Carrie, a woman whose self-perceived purpose is to promote sustainable energy through science. She tells stories about her child-hood when she felt moved by the plight of newly hatched turtles crossing a busy road (temperament) and how this spurred her on to become concerned about the environment, hearing from environmentalists about their work (narrative), and so to come to think of herself as an environmentalist (iden-tity). She forms relationships with those in energy research, educates herself on environmental issues, and also seeks work, relationships, and leisure ac-tivities conducive to her effective long-term pursuit of a career in sustainable energy (characteristic adaptations). These goals require frequent social inter-action and stimulation, which suit her tendency toward extroversion (trait).

If we desire to understand the virtuous scientist, cases like Carrie’s may be a starting place for both psychologists and philosophers. Scholars can con-sider the entire personality system, the individual, her history, and her con-text. This means, first of all, that it is not virtuous for everyone to become a scientist rather than to pursue other potential purposes and identities avail-able to them. Nonetheless, for those who do choose to become scientists, this identity should contain a moral (and perhaps spiritual) dimension, connect with the broader narrative of their lives, and be expressed through virtuous characteristic adaptations. This is only a partial picture, and one we will ex-pand on in later sections of the paper.

b) Excellence

Doctrine of the Mean. Virtue in situ operates on a continuum, with virtue representing situational balance in the center, and cacostatic responses – too

Page 9: Linking Psychological and Philosophical Viewsdnarvaez/documents/Reilly_Narvaez... · 2018-11-29 · Character, Virtue, and Science 55 For author’s use only. of automaticity or spontaneous

59Character, Virtue, and Science

For author’s use only.

much or too little – representative of viciousness at both ends (Narvaez 2014; Roberts 2017; Titus 2017). According to Aristotle, virtue lies in the mean be-tween excess and defect of passions, appetites, and actions: “To feel them at the right times, with reference to the right objects, toward the right people, with the right motive, and in the right ways, is what is both intermediate and best, and that is characteristic of virtue” (Nicomachean Ethics 1106b). This is referred to as the doctrine of the mean, sometimes called the golden mean. Perceptions, feelings, thoughts, motives, or actions relevant to the specific goals of a given virtue take place in the middle of the continuum, avoiding vicious extremes, with consideration of one’s own qualities and present circumstances (Losin 1987). For instance, in displaying fortitude, an ability to act well in spite of risk, especially risk to oneself, an individual displays neither the vice of rashness nor that of cowardice. Rashness might emerge if an individual takes a risk in pursuit of an end not worthy of that risk. Cowardice, in contrast, occurs when an individual does not take a risk that is worth taking.

Psychology generally has been more attuned to the cacostatic polarities of the behavioral continuum rather than to the mean. For example, psy-chologists examine psychopathological dispositions such as externalizing (aggression toward others) or internalizing (aggression toward self), or the notions of undercontrol (impulsive) or overcontrol (self-inhibited) (Achen-bach 1974; Asendorpf and Van Aken 1999). There is little focus on consist-ent excellence, except in expertise research (discussed below). Furthermore, the mean is conditioned on the telos, which is to say that the proper mean in any given situation, community, or individual life is that which is most conducive to the flourishing of the community (more on this below in the section on telos). Thus, while we acknowledge the doctrine of the mean as an important facet of Aristotle’s virtue ethics, we emphasize that it has important theoretical and empirical limitations, as it is not independently amenable to psychological measurement, and, moreover, some actions and passions have no broadly accepted or easily discernible mean (Lapsley and Narvaez 2006).

The doctrine of the mean extends to an individual’s choices, not just reac-tions. Those pursuing the mean are, ideally, moving toward better and bet-ter choices and coming closer and closer to excellence. For example, if our scientist, Carrie, haphazardly and routinely puts herself in harm’s way im-pulsively and mindlessly, for no greater purpose, even if she responds well to those situations, it would be hard to attribute virtue to her. A multi-faceted personality structure perspective, like that presented above, allows us to consider the particularities of the individual and her circumstances, not just

Page 10: Linking Psychological and Philosophical Viewsdnarvaez/documents/Reilly_Narvaez... · 2018-11-29 · Character, Virtue, and Science 55 For author’s use only. of automaticity or spontaneous

60 Timothy S. Reilly and Darcia Narvaez

For author’s use only.

the ideal for the immediate situation. This includes individuals’ agency in choosing which goals to pursue in the first place and their work to shape the situations in which they find themselves (see also Sternberg 2003). The ideal end of a human life is its telos (see below for more), but individuals must ori-ent themselves to this through pursuit of the mean. Thus, the doctrine of the mean extends to choices that affect individuals’ life narratives and adapta-tions, such as whether a student chooses to attend medical school or to com-mit to a year of voluntary service, and the social and personal consequences of these decisions. Indeed, the virtuous person would be expert in ethical self-authorship and self-direction, rather than only an expert in a particular domain (for a similar claim from a philosophical perspective see MacIntyre 2016). This is to say that the virtuous are capable, when necessary, through normative reflection and deliberation, of determining the mean, directing themselves toward the mean, and pursuing excellence well.

Aristotle’s main point about the mean is not moderation, as most assume, but excellence in flexible response to varying situations (Kupperman 1999). “The virtuous person does not follow habits or rules inflexibly but adapts conduct to particular circumstances” (Lapsley and Narvaez 2006). A virtu-ous person adopts an orientation of openness, connection, and compassion, responding to the unique dynamics of a situation agilely, unencumbered by rigid rules or scripts; this is a signal of good health (Koutstaal 2013). Such an orientation can be facilitated by supportive developmental contexts, which promote excellence neurobiologically, socially, and morally (Narvaez 2014). Aristotle’s notion of flexible response in behavior aligns with studies of adap-tive expertise.

Nonetheless, different sets of skills may be most relevant to certain pro-cesses within the practice of science. When scientists are seeking evidence regarding a hypothesis, uniformity (e. g., an exacting and precise method for collecting data) is often emphasized over individualized and varied meth-ods. As a result, in conducting experiments there is a certain intentional inflexibility. The experimental scientist controls for individual differences and attempts to control all aspects of a situation other than the variable to be manipulated (uniformity of task and situation). Flexibility occurs outside the experimental situation, in the study design and interpretation of results (especially surprising results), and the generation of new hypotheses.

Expertise. Moral psychology typically examines special cases of decision making (e. g., trolley problems, the Heinz dilemma, eating dog)3 instead of

3 Trolley problems refer to a class of dilemma in which the choice is between allowing a

Page 11: Linking Psychological and Philosophical Viewsdnarvaez/documents/Reilly_Narvaez... · 2018-11-29 · Character, Virtue, and Science 55 For author’s use only. of automaticity or spontaneous

61Character, Virtue, and Science

For author’s use only.

real-life situations. The decision cases used in research represent veridical decision making: that is, parameters and ‘right’ answers are preselected by the experimenter (“here is a case – what would you do?”). Brain-damaged patients reason quite well with such circumscribed cases, making it hard to distinguish them from ‘normals’ (Goldberg 2002). However, the form of decision-making required in virtuous action is not veridical but more like what Goldberg calls adaptive. Adaptive decision making occurs in the flow of life events where one must pick out what is critical information (rather than it being pre-selected by the experimenter, as in the dilemma studies mentioned above). Prefrontally-damaged patients fail at this type of task. The individual must make sense of an array of complex stimuli in real time. From an information-processing perspective, this requires “sorting and pri-oritizing inputs, weighing possible actions and effects, checking intuitions and reasoning, and a multitude of other functions that lead to successful action” (Narvaez 2010, 171). Experts display these capacities to a greater extent than novices. Experts operate in the ‘sweet spot,’ the golden mean, of action. Virtuous persons have such skills too, but these skills are enhanced by attention to the ongoing and changing dynamics of a situation, bringing emotional presence and engagement with others to each situation, mind-fully acting in a way that promotes the flourishing of all. Thus, adaptiveness is part of virtuous behavior, but virtue entails ethical factors cognitive sci-entists typically ignore.

Veridical and adaptive decision-making could be said to mirror different types of expertise. Routine expertise reflects veridical expertise or technical competence, the ability to solve familiar, well-structured problems in the domain. Adaptive expertise displays more flexible capacities – the ability to work with a dynamic fluctuation and capacities to create new methods of problem solving (Hatano and Inagaki 1986).

Within psychology, expertise means mastery of a domain, involving much more than intellect or narrow craftsmanship. It is a ‘knowhow’ comprised of integrated sets of knowledge: declarative (what), procedural (how), and conditional (when and how much). Experts have more and better organ-ized knowledge that they apply in the right way at the right time (Hogarth 2001). They are motivated for excellence in what they do. Experts perceive the world differently, noticing details and opportunities missed by novices,

trolley to strike a number of people or, through personal behavior, causing a trolley to hit someone else (Foot 1967); the Heinz dilemma is Kohlberg’s most famous dilemma – should Heinz steal the drug that could save the life of his wife (Kohlberg 1981); Jonathan Haidt used graphic and unusual dilemmas to test gut reactions such as whether it is permissible to eat your dog if it is killed by a hit and run driver (Haidt et al. 1993).

Page 12: Linking Psychological and Philosophical Viewsdnarvaez/documents/Reilly_Narvaez... · 2018-11-29 · Character, Virtue, and Science 55 For author’s use only. of automaticity or spontaneous

62 Timothy S. Reilly and Darcia Narvaez

For author’s use only.

and acting with greater perceived affordances (action possibilities). Experts often act spontaneously with automatic and effortless behavior, unlike nov-ices who must consciously follow rules step by step (Dreyfus and Dreyfus 1990). The expert behaves in the right sort of way for the situation, accessing considerable tacit knowledge (Ericsson et al. 2006). In addition, they have ‘negative expertise’ – they attend to intuitions that signal uncertainty (Ho-garth 2001), and are aware of what actions not to take in solving a problem (Minksy 1997). All of this is dependent on learning from extensive embod-ied practice (Varela 1999).

The notion of expertise has been applied to virtue development, such as “everyday ethical coping” (Dreyfus and Dreyfus 1990), in schooling (Nar-vaez 2006), and across the lifespan (Narvaez 2011, 2012, 2014). The exper-tise framework allows a breakdown of ethical skills that a virtuous agent would need to have. Using an information-processing framework, everyday ethical expertise involves at least four processes (Narvaez and Rest 1995; Rest 1983; Rest and Narvaez 1994):

Experts in ethical sensitivity are better, for example, at quickly and accurately reading a moral situation, taking the perspectives of others, and determining what role they might play. Experts in ethical judgment solve complex moral problems by reasoning about, for example, codes, duty, and consequences for a particular situation. Experts in ethical focus revere life and deepen commitment. Experts in ethical action know how to keep their ‘eye on the prize,’ enabling them to stay on task and take the necessary steps to get the ethical job done. Experts in a particular excellence have more and better organized knowledge about it, have highly tuned perceptual skills for it, have deep moral desire for it, and use at least some highly automatized, effortless responses (Narvaez 2010, 171).

Expertise is often analyzed according to particular capacities in this way. No-tably, the virtuous person would display aspects of all these components in dynamic interplay from situation to situation (Narvaez and Lapsley 2005). Specific skills comprising each component can be identified, potentially expanding the list of virtues to be developed (Stichter 2018). In fact, virtue theory would require the four components to be co-developed, whereas de-ontological or consequential ethics would allow them to be developed in-dependently, emphasizing especially ethical judgment and ethical action4. Further, the skill breakdown above leaves out practical wisdom, which a virtuous person would display in deciding when and how particular skills should be used, but expertise, including virtue, does include the desire for excellence and flourishing (Narvaez 2013, discussed below).

Ethical expertise in science is particularly demanding, given the diffi-cult-to-predict nature of research and its consequences (Moran 2014). To

4 Thanks to Mark Graves for pointing this out.

Page 13: Linking Psychological and Philosophical Viewsdnarvaez/documents/Reilly_Narvaez... · 2018-11-29 · Character, Virtue, and Science 55 For author’s use only. of automaticity or spontaneous

63Character, Virtue, and Science

For author’s use only.

consider the possible ethical consequences of one’s discoveries, scientific ethical expertise requires not only adaptive expertise in a highly specialized domain and skill in working with collaborators and students under the pres-sures of finding funding for one’s work, but an ethical imagination that keeps one’s actions and creations within the bounds of ethical research practice. Discussing conceptions of virtue as skill, Matt Stichter points out that ethi-cal expertise in real-life situations is intertwined with power issues (Stichter 2018). No doubt this is true for science as well and should shape our under-standing of flourishing in science. Returning to the model of personality developed earlier, ethical expertise in science is a necessary feature of the characteristic adaptations of a virtuous scientist, ordering their dispositions to accord with the doctrine of the mean5. But to what end? Virtuous action also requires the notion of telos.

c) The Highest Ends

Telos and Flourishing. The telos describes the proper end toward which an individual’s efforts should be directed and typically refers to human flour-ishing, broadly construed – i. e., fostering the fullness or perfection of one’s human nature and improving humanity as a whole (Aquinas, S. Th.; Aris-totle, Nicomachean Ethics; Annas 1993; Titus 2017)6. An individual’s telos is pursued through virtuous, rather than vicious, means. Thus, data fabrica-tion, which is vicious in its dishonesty, cannot lead to the realization of the telos. Whereas a virtuous person has little difficulty avoiding actions that un-dermine flourishing, vicious individuals are more likely to struggle to engage in behavior conducive to flourishing, as a result of habits and dispositions directed toward other ends. The selection of virtuous means both reflects virtuous character and lubricates a virtuous disposition towards further re-finement. In other words, individuals who cultivate virtuous perceptions,

5 It must be noted that it is virtually impossible to empirically investigate the virtue of an individual – that is, an individual’s disposition to act in a manner that is virtuous, given a particular situation. There is no way to set up an experiment with controls and no way to understand the situation from the viewpoint of the actor without interfering with the action. Further, the claim or implied assertion that psychological science can evaluate virtue in a single setting or in thin-slice formats, rather than across time and situations, impoverishes and diminishes the concept of virtue. Thus, survey data need to be in-terpreted with caution. Ideally, a person is observed and understood across contexts, avoiding the fundamental attribution error (Ross 1977), a common error in Western societies that attributes the cause of a behavior to a stable personal characteristic rather than to the contingencies of a particular situation or context.

6 Flourishing is sometimes circumscribed by a particular community or polis (Annas 1993; Kinghorn 2017), or with regard to the divine (Titus 2017).

Page 14: Linking Psychological and Philosophical Viewsdnarvaez/documents/Reilly_Narvaez... · 2018-11-29 · Character, Virtue, and Science 55 For author’s use only. of automaticity or spontaneous

64 Timothy S. Reilly and Darcia Narvaez

For author’s use only.

feelings, thoughts, and tendencies to act will develop virtuous habits and dispositions, though how they are to do so is often limited in specification, at least in ancient philosophical accounts from the West (Eastern accounts are another matter). We take up virtue development separately below, as psychology has much to offer in this realm.

The telos is not a typical focus of psychology, even as psychologists are increasingly interested in eudaimonic theories of well-being rather than individualistic and hedonic conceptions (see for instance Vittersø 2016). Nonetheless, these theories rely on approaches to eudaimonia that rarely extend beyond narrow prosocial concerns (encouraging better local social relations), and certainly do not capture the holistic and communal flourish-ing implicated in the telos. Concepts of the telos and flourishing are mat-ters that involve value decisions, and contemporary psychologists generally tend to shy away from such discussions, with the exceptions of humanistic psychology – where meaning and self-transcendence, or the ‘terminal ends’ of values, have been a focus of discussion for over fifty years (e. g., Maslow 1943; Rogers 1951, 1961; Frankl [1959] 1984) – and psychology of religion (e. g., Emmons 1999; King and Whitney 2015). Although Maslow focused on self-actualization of one’s unique potential as vital for flourishing soci-eties, today most discussions focus on individual and subjective phenom-ena (e. g., “Does your life feel meaningful?”), rather than considering the flourishing of communities, the broader Aristotelian meaning of flourishing (Maslow 1971). Positive psychology, for instance, has advanced a variety of subjective framings for describing human flourishing and transcendence: self-transcendence (Wong 2016), happiness (Lyubomirsky et al. 2005), self-actualization (Maslow 1943), purpose (Bronk 2013), thriving (e. g., Bundick et al. 2010), and personal flourishing (e. g., Keyes 2007).

It must be underscored that in the view of Aristotle, virtue and flourish-ing come about through and for a supportive community (Norton 1991). No one flourishes alone. However, unlike the Aristotelian assumption of a com-munity foundation, modern psychology, guided by Western enlightenment thinking, predominantly emphasizes individuals and their self-fulfillment. For the most part, psychology retains the focus on person-level flourish-ing, rather than on the social or communal flourishing which are essential to Aristotelian accounts of the virtues. In contrast, exemplar studies, which begin with those whose efforts are recognized as contributing to societal flourishing in some fashion, offer a promising avenue for research into telic concerns, often emphasizing the centrality of identity to the achievement of exemplarity, an exemplarity recognized by the community (e. g., Frimer and Walker 2009; Gardner et al. 2001; Damon and Colby 2015).

Page 15: Linking Psychological and Philosophical Viewsdnarvaez/documents/Reilly_Narvaez... · 2018-11-29 · Character, Virtue, and Science 55 For author’s use only. of automaticity or spontaneous

65Character, Virtue, and Science

For author’s use only.

In the domain of science, given the power of scientific technology to af-fect not just local communities but the world, the scope of the community relevant to telic considerations is especially important. Considering only one community or generation and ignoring the effects of one’s actions more broadly can have dire consequences. For example, corporate scientists have sometimes aimed for their company’s flourishing at the expense of human health, as in the case of Thomas Midgley (Kitman 2000), who, knowing lead’s abiding toxicity, nevertheless invented leaded gasoline, the dominant form of gasoline for many decades in the USA, which still has lingering effects in soils, the atmosphere, and waterways. In addition, even scien-tists intending to foster worldwide human flourishing take actions that in the end can cause harmful side effects, such as how the green revolution spearheaded by the work of agroscientist Norman Borlaug brought about increased crop yield but also, for example, decreased biodiversity of crops, increased economic inequality, and led to profligate use of pesticide and herbicides that has altered worldwide insect and bird populations (Mann 2018). These challenges bring to mind questions such as the following: Is it possible to think of the flourishing of all humans within one’s scientific vo-cation? Does flourishing necessarily require a narrower conception of com-munity? Should the flourishing of non-human entities (living or non-living) be included in conceptions of the telos?

Psychological Development and Virtue. Whether we are discussing personal-ity structure, expertise, or exemplarity, development must have taken place. No one is born an expert. No one is born expressing adult virtue. Such ca-pacities must be cultivated. Yet most scholarship in philosophy and psychol-ogy focuses on adult behavior, leaving the specifics of virtue development largely a mystery.

Virtuous behavior is difficult to find in the young because it takes life experience to develop the greater and better organized knowhow (prac-tical wisdom) that experts demonstrate (Hursthouse 2003; Narvaez et al. 2010). Although Aristotle waved his hand towards the cultivation of virtue through the guidance of mentors and the gradual learning of dispositions and sensibilities, little detail was provided. On the other hand, Mencius was more precise about the development of virtue, emphasizing the importance of guided practice in learning specific capacities: attending to situations, extending feeling from old to new situations, and doing both with intelli-gent awareness (Varela 1999). Virtue is not about following habits or rules. Mencius describes the virtuous person as one who ‘flows’ from situation to situation with spontaneous wise action – without a ‘self ’ to protect or be

Page 16: Linking Psychological and Philosophical Viewsdnarvaez/documents/Reilly_Narvaez... · 2018-11-29 · Character, Virtue, and Science 55 For author’s use only. of automaticity or spontaneous

66 Timothy S. Reilly and Darcia Narvaez

For author’s use only.

concerned about, without deliberation about what is the right thing to do. For those in training, however, one must deliberately practice attention, ex-tension, and mindful awareness. Deliberation or reflection comes into play in new situations when wise and compassionate spontaneous action is not yet forthcoming.

More recent empirical research demonstrates that temperament is ini-tially fashioned in early life, even during gestation (Davis et al. 2007), but especially postnatally because of children’s marked immaturity at birth and extensive postnatal development (Montagu 1986; Trevarthan 2011). Tem-perament is influenced by the nature of the parent-child relationship: for example, mutually responsive orientations promote agreeableness, consci-entiousness, and cooperation (Kochanska 2002). Moral temperament is also seeded at this time as bracing self-protection or open relational attunement, rooted in neurobiological structures that underpin capacities for social-ity (Narvaez 2014). Humans as social mammals inherit a nest of practices (soothing birth, extensive breastfeeding and affection, responsiveness to minimize distress, multiple responsive adult caregivers, free play, and ex-tensive social support) that optimize biopsychosocial development (Narvaez 2016). When the nest is provided, structures that are scheduled to develop are supported (Narvaez 2014, 2015). In early life, these include both self-regulatory systems and tacit social capacities and motivation, capacities that are foundational to the development of virtue (Gleason and Narvaez 2014). Moral exemplars and generative adults, who take action to improve the world for future generations, often note their supportive childhoods (Oliner and Oliner 1988; Walker et al. 2010; McAdams and Guo 2015).

According to Narvaez, virtue is initiated ‘bottom up,’ from early life ex-perience within a species-typical development system that shapes embodi-ment, including for virtue (Narvaez 2014, 2015, 2016). Embodiment refers to the fact that humans are biosocially constructed in early life from ex-perience with caregivers and community members. Many neurobiological systems (e. g., endocrine systems, vagus nerve function, stress response) are foundational for self-regulation and social capacities. Neurobiological and implicit systems are socially constructed by immersed experience. A species-typical developmental system or nest7 shapes sensorimotor and pro-cedural intelligences, the foundation for later characteristic adaptations and

7 Every animal has evolved a nest for its young that matches up with the maturational schedule of offspring, optimizing normal development (Gottlieb 2002; West-Eberhard 2003; Stotz and Narvaez 2019). Humans have a nest too, whose characteristics largely match up with those of social mammals who emerged over 30 million years ago (Kon-ner 2005, 2010).

Page 17: Linking Psychological and Philosophical Viewsdnarvaez/documents/Reilly_Narvaez... · 2018-11-29 · Character, Virtue, and Science 55 For author’s use only. of automaticity or spontaneous

67Character, Virtue, and Science

For author’s use only.

self-narratives, to be deeply socially-oriented. Social expertise develops in layers of capacities necessary for participation in a synchronous ‘flow’ of in-terpersonal action where the individual’s systems (neurobiological, implicit, and explicit) coordinate to maintain relational attunement and communal focus, expressing virtue in action.

In terms of the three aspects of virtue, childhood experiences shape neu-robiological foundations for virtue and proto-virtue dispositions in meas-urable ways, with the evolved nest providing the natural context for this bottom-up development. A species-typical childhood shapes the neuro-biological and implicit structures around a socially-oriented homeostasis (a socially-oriented golden mean), coupling sensorimotor knowhow with proto-virtuous, then virtuous, capacities. The evolved nest, lasting for dec-ades, provides the context for virtue development and flourishing within a community.

Virtue is difficult to develop in species-atypical environments. Individu-als who do not receive all the facets of the evolved nest are characteristically less self-regulated, empathic, and cooperative (Kochanska et al. 2010; Nar-vaez, Gleason, et al. 2013; Narvaez, Wang, et al. 2013; Narvaez et al. 2016). All of this likely makes it more challenging for them to orient their lives to the telos. A species-atypical system leaves gaps in the foundations for vir-tue, necessitating a reliance on rules and scripts to navigate social life unless extensive healing interventions or similar experiences occur. For example, studies of immersion in L’Arche communities have noted, at least anecdo-tally, benefits for individuals who have grown up in challenging environ-ments (Reimer 2013). It is not clear, however, how much post-childhood experiences can revamp neurobiological structures (e. g., stress response and vagal tone – both important for social functioning) to attain consistent, cross-situational virtuous responses.

Children spend a great deal of time in schooling. But it appears chal-lenging to actually educate for the complexities of virtue in classroom set-tings. Lapsley and Narvaez note that it is difficult in practice to distinguish character education from cognitive developmental moral education (e. g., moral discussion) (Lapsley and Narvaez 2006; cf. Kohlberg 1984). For all the appeal to Aristotle and virtue, character education, as we noted in the introduction, practically embraces the ethics of requirement just like inter-ventions based on Kohlberg’s moral stage theory. Both approaches empha-size obligation, duty, and universal principles, and measure success in terms of improved conduct. The focus for both is “deciding the good thing to do rather than the sort of person to become,” and “the fact that character educa-tion is so thoroughly deontological and utilitarian with so little in common

Page 18: Linking Psychological and Philosophical Viewsdnarvaez/documents/Reilly_Narvaez... · 2018-11-29 · Character, Virtue, and Science 55 For author’s use only. of automaticity or spontaneous

68 Timothy S. Reilly and Darcia Narvaez

For author’s use only.

with virtue ethics is not inherently problematic, although it does attenuate some hope that virtue ethics would open up a new front in moral psychol-ogy and education” (Lapsley and Narvaez 2006, 257–58).

No matter the moral emphasis in the curriculum, students tend to ad-vance more in some aspects of their development and less in others, across an array of pedagogies (see Seider et al. 2017). Schools often focus on one or two virtues (e. g., honesty, kindness) and can show increases in student scores on the outcome measures used. But this is not evidence of virtue as we have defined it. Skills for getting along with others certainly are building blocks towards virtue, but the development of full-blown virtue requires a more holistic approach that entails extensive mentoring from wise and re-sponsive elders and virtuous models, coached guidance during immersed social experience, guided reflection, and extensive practice across situations (Narvaez et al. 2003)8.

Ethics education in science tends to focus on reasoning about dilemmas (e. g., Han and Jeong 2014), rarely addressing virtue development. Fostering virtue in science would necessitate a broader scope than deontological and utilitarian ethics. Although practice and honing of a broad set of domain-specific skills beyond reasoning are needed (e. g., perceptual and attention skills; sensitivity to domain issues and domain effects on society and the environment; action skills for all relevant situations plus their particulari-ties), these must be deployed in the right way at the right time. Such learn-ing requires extensive modeling and mentoring, as occurs in fields like sur-gery where mistakes are costly. Drawing on models from outside the field of moral education may help to guide revisions in science ethics education. For example, talent development emphasizes the importance of models in de-veloping independent student projects focused on the common good (e. g., Renzulli et al. 2006). Expertise development highlights the value of deliber-ate focused practice (Ericsson and Charness 1994). Science education could benefit from consideration of alternative approaches to science, like those of Native science, where maintaining virtuous relations with the natural world is integral to doing science properly, and can only be learned with the guid-ance of wise elders (e. g., Cajete 2000; Medin and Bang 2014).

8 And we must recall that virtue in its full definition is not apparent in the young (Hurs-thouse 2003), including college students, and, moreover, high levels of psychosocial maturity are almost never reached before the age of 40 (Kegan 1982).

Page 19: Linking Psychological and Philosophical Viewsdnarvaez/documents/Reilly_Narvaez... · 2018-11-29 · Character, Virtue, and Science 55 For author’s use only. of automaticity or spontaneous

69Character, Virtue, and Science

For author’s use only.

3. Implications and Future Directions for Scholarship in Virtue and Science

Our contribution here to the scholarship of scientific virtue is threefold. First, we propose that virtuous scientists are disposed to engage in science as adaptive ethical experts who are living lives ordered to promoting the flourishing of communities, in part as a result of formation in developmen-tal contexts that conduce to the flourishing of the scientist. What this adap-tive expertise looks like can be examined by both psychologists and philoso-phers. Although ethical expertise research provides important insights into the development of capacities and the golden mean in practice, and could be considered a necessary component of a virtuous system of characteristic adaptations, it has yet to be tied clearly to flourishing. At the intersection of expertise and identity lies moral or ethical identity (e. g., Hamilton and LaVoi 2017; Nakamura et al. 2009). When ethical identity orients expertise, it con-cerns itself with human flourishing. But how does expertise contribute to the flourishing of a particular practice and the communities that practice serves? Initiating empirical research on scientific purpose, scientific moral identity, scientific spirituality, scientific generativity, and scientific transcendence, all of which consider individuals as transcending themselves in some way, could provide pathways to addressing this question. Still, philosophical guidance is needed – specifically, domain-specific descriptions of what human flourish-ing looks like in scientific contexts. And, because virtue is a communal affair, additional studies of morally exemplary scientific communities as well as their members would be beneficial (e. g., Nakamura et al. 2009).

Second, virtuous scientists should be thought of as self-authoring, which is to say that they reflect on and deliberate about their good, their vocational practice, and the good of the community in a way that leads to these goods. As Clarke, following Murdoch (Murdoch 2001), points out, much like a jazz musician puts a personal stamp on his music, so a virtuous person, who necessarily is guided by a personal inflection of moral terms and concepts, expresses virtue in a unique way (Clarke 2018). “The virtuous person is one who has linked his inner life to open, ordinary life” (47). It may also be pro-ductive to explore existing life span studies (like the Grant, Berkeley, and Terman longitudinal studies) to examine those who became virtuous scien-tists, and who may provide insight into a variety of individual pathways. A developmental focus is needed, as too often attention is drawn to scientific heroes on one end or scientific scoundrels on the other, to the neglect of the lifeways of ordinary scientists. A deeper engagement with virtue and virtue theory within personality psychology may be fruitful, in particular explicitly

Page 20: Linking Psychological and Philosophical Viewsdnarvaez/documents/Reilly_Narvaez... · 2018-11-29 · Character, Virtue, and Science 55 For author’s use only. of automaticity or spontaneous

70 Timothy S. Reilly and Darcia Narvaez

For author’s use only.

examining life purpose as it relates to virtue theory. Vocational narratives, which have yet to be studied, serve to integrate personality, through orient-ing characteristic adaptations to the telos. Such narratives likely include life stories of generative lives, lives oriented to the good of future generations (McAdams 2015; McAdams and Guo 2015). Virtuous individuals are also engaged in the pursuit of one or more purposes oriented to the telos as cen-tral goals, with personal capacities and goals integrated into life pursuits. Thus research on purpose stands to enrich virtue theory. Virtue theorists are also likely to benefit from engagement with empirical studies of vocational stories and identities – that is, how individuals respond to the ‘call’ of their traditions and the narratives they construct through engagement with them.

Additionally, engagement with conceptions of virtue outside those in Ar-istotelian philosophy is worthy of attention, both psychologically and philo-sophically. For example, an Eastern philosophical definition is more explic-itly demanding and requires additional description, which we do not have the space to engage in here. In brief, however, these conceptions tend to de-scribe how a virtuous individual acts in each situation: wisely, compassion-ately, and selflessly (without ego, scripts, rules, or mindless habits) (Varela 1999). The goal is to be fully present in each situation without self-oriented goals. It remains to be seen whether this can be translated into a Western sci-entific context. Similarly, Native science is more holistic in its expectations of the scientist and more inclusive in its ethical concerns. Because of intel-lect’s tendency toward arrogance and ruthlessness, Native science is wary of letting it alone guide action; the heart must be the ultimate guide, and it must be well developed and well-tended (Cajete 2000). Humans live in an earth community and rely on its flourishing, so the Native scientist is always concerned with the wellbeing of the other-than-human, treating them with respect. In this way, Native conceptions of virtue and science are distinct from Aristotelian virtue, which focuses primarily on human interests and wellbeing (Narvaez 2014). This is especially important given the ecological impact of science and the challenges it presents, noted above.

Virtue scholars should also attend to how virtue develops, a topic which the developmental sciences can assist. Given the fact that most children in industrialized nations are raised outside of species-typical social systems, this makes virtue more difficult to achieve generally. As a result of species-atypical upbringings, many individuals develop their intellects out of syn-chrony with their emotional systems. Many of these children pursue higher degrees, including in science. It takes courage and extensive rehabilitation to reintegrate intellect and emotion, which many do not undertake. How do individuals without well-coordinated intellects and emotions in science

Page 21: Linking Psychological and Philosophical Viewsdnarvaez/documents/Reilly_Narvaez... · 2018-11-29 · Character, Virtue, and Science 55 For author’s use only. of automaticity or spontaneous

71Character, Virtue, and Science

For author’s use only.

develop virtue? How can science education help students to integrate mind and heart in a holistic manner? Can we move Western science towards a more holistic, relational, and emotionally attuned perspective, like that of Native science? Doing so seems essential to fostering scientific virtue. In light of these varying conceptions of virtue, we encourage psychologists to adopt explicit normative frames for evaluating virtue, emic (those of partici-pant populations) and etic (those emerging from theoretical perspectives), in general and in understanding virtue in science, rather than engaging in the fiction of performing strictly objective research.

Finally, our discussion of virtue has focused on three facets of virtue. It has not considered in depth classic virtue concepts such as justice, humil-ity, courage, or prudence. Each of these certainly has manifestations in sci-ence and is worthy of further study. Justice, perhaps especially as it relates to truthfulness and honesty, has manifestations in each scientific role, for those who serve as teachers, mentors, advocates, collaborators, experiment-ers, writers, and more. In addition, the relation of justice to courage and pru-dence bears examination. These and other specific virtues require targeted research, especially to examine the consequences of varying conceptions of virtue and science (including conceptions which reject virtue ethics). All of this is essential to creating a more complete picture of the virtuous scientist.

4. Conclusion

In this paper, we have sought to engage constructively with scholarship at the intersection of psychological research and philosophical conceptions of virtue. We have described how psychological studies address the three fac-ets of virtue (dispositions, golden mean, telos). McAdams’ structural model of personality addresses both dispositions and the telos, but provides less insight into the golden mean (McAdams 1996). Research on adaptive and ethical expertise may be especially helpful in understanding the doctrine of the mean within dynamic situations. Existing empirical research provides less insight into telic concerns and human flourishing, even though these reside at the heart of virtue. Vocational identity studies may remedy this lack. Psychological research has the most room to advance in addressing the telos, ideally through greater engagement with philosophical conceptions of flourishing. We think that the philosophy of virtue can benefit from engag-ing the research we have reviewed. Each field could be richly informed and stimulated by the other. We encourage such work in exploring what it means to be a virtuous scientist.

Page 22: Linking Psychological and Philosophical Viewsdnarvaez/documents/Reilly_Narvaez... · 2018-11-29 · Character, Virtue, and Science 55 For author’s use only. of automaticity or spontaneous

72 Timothy S. Reilly and Darcia Narvaez

For author’s use only.

References

Achenbach, Thomas M. 1974. Developmental Psychopathology. New York: Ronald.Allport, Gordon. 1927. “Concepts of Trait and Personality.” Psychological Bulletin

24:284–93.Annas, Julia. 1993. The Morality of Happiness. New York: Oxford University Press.–. 2011. Intelligent Virtue. New York: Oxford University Press.Annas, Julia, Darcia Narvaez, and Nancy Snow. eds. 2016. Developing the Virtues: Inte-

grating Perspectives. New York: Oxford University Press.Anscombe, Gertrude E. 1958. “Modern Moral Philosophy.” Philosophy 33:1–19.Aquinas, Thomas. 1991. Summa Theologiae: A Concise Translation [= S. Th.], translated

by Timothy McDermott. Notre Dame, IN: Christian Classics.Aristotle. 2002. Nicomachean Ethics, translated by Christopher Rowe, with philosophical

introduction and commentary by Sarah Broadie. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Arthur, James. 2014. “Traditional Approaches to Character Education in Britain and

America.” In Handbook of Moral and Character Education, edited by Larry Nucci, Darcia Narvaez, and Tobias Krettenauer, 43–60. New York: Routledge.

Asendorpf, Jens B., and Marcel A. van Aken. 1999. “Resilient, Overcontrolled, and Un-dercontrolled Personality Prototypes in Childhood: Replicability, Predictive Power, and the Trait-Type Issue.” Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 77:815–32.

Baehr, Jason. 2011. The Inquiring Mind: On Intellectual Virtues and Virtue Epistemology. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Blasi, Augusto. 1980. “Bridging Moral Cognition and Moral Action: A Critical Review of the Literature.” Psychological Bulletin 88:1–45.

Bronk, Kendall C. 2013. Purpose in Life: A Critical Component of Optimal Youth Devel-opment. New York: Springer.

Bundick, Matthew J., David S. Yeager, Pamela E. King, and William Damon. 2010. “Thriving across the Life Span.” In Handbook of Life-Span Development, edited by Willis F. Overton and Richard M. Lerner, 882–923. Hoboken: Wiley.

Buss, Arnold H., and Robert Plomin. 1984. Temperament: Early Developing Personality Traits. Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.

Cajete, Greg. 2000. Native Science: Natural Laws of Interdependence. Santa Fe: Clear Light.Clarke, Bridget. 2018. “Virtue as a Sensitivity.” The Oxford Handbook of Virtue, edited

by Nancy Snow, 35–56. New York: Oxford University Press.Cohen, Taya R., and A. T. Panter. 2015. “Character Traits in the Workplace: A Three-

Month Diary Study of Moral and Immoral Organizational Behaviors.” In Charac-ter: New Directions from Philosophy, Psychology, and Theology, edited by Christian B. Miller, R. Michael Furr, Angela Knobel, and William Fleeson, 150–63. New York: Oxford University Press.

Costa, Paul T., and Robert R. McCrae. 1992. Revised NEO Personality Inventory (NEO-PI-R) and NEO Five Factor Model (NEO-FFI) Professional Manual. Odesa, FL: Psy-chological Assessment Resources.

Damon, William, and Anne Colby. 2015. The Power of Ideals: The Real Story of Moral Choice. New York: Oxford University Press.

Damon, William, Jennifer Menon, and Kendall C. Bronk. 2003. “The Development of Purpose during Adolescence.” Applied Developmental Science 7:119–28.

Davis, Elysia P., Laura M. Glynn, Christine D. Schetter, Calvin Hobel, Aleksandra Chicz-Demet, and Curt A. Sandman. 2007. “Prenatal Exposure to Maternal Depression and

Page 23: Linking Psychological and Philosophical Viewsdnarvaez/documents/Reilly_Narvaez... · 2018-11-29 · Character, Virtue, and Science 55 For author’s use only. of automaticity or spontaneous

73Character, Virtue, and Science

For author’s use only.

Cortisol Influences Infant Temperament.” Journal of the American Academy of Child and Adolescent Psychiatry 46:737–46.

Deloria, Vine. 2006. The World We Used to Live in. Golden, CO: Fulcrum.Dreyfus, Hubert L., and Stuart E. Dreyfus. 1990. “What is Moral Maturity? A Phenom-

enological Account of the Development of Ethical Expertise.” In Universalism vs. Communitarianism, edited by David M. Rasmussen, 237–64. Boston: MIT.

Emmons, Robert A. 1999. The Psychology of Ultimate Concerns: Motivation and Spiritu-ality in Personality. New York: Guilford.

Ericsson, K. Anders, and Neil Charness. 1994. “Expert Performance: Its Structure and Acquisition.” American Psychologist 49:725–47.

Ericsson, K. Anders, Neil Charness, Paul J. Feltovich, and Robert R. Hoffman. eds. 2006. The Cambridge Handbook of Expertise and Expert Performance. Cambridge: Cam-bridge University Press.

Erikson, Erik H. 1961. The Challenge of Youth. New York: Anchor Books.–. 1968. Identity: Youth and Crisis. New York: Norton.Fleeson, William, and Eranda Jayawickreme. 2015. “Whole Trait Theory.” Journal of Re-

search in Personality 56:82–92.Foot, Philippa. 1967. “The Problem of Abortion and the Doctrine of Double Effect.”

Oxford Review 5:5–15.Fowers, Blaine J. 2012. “Placing Virtue and the Human Good in Psychology.” Journal of

Theoretical and Philosophical Psychology 32:1–9.Frankl, Viktor. [1959] 1984. Man’s Search for Meaning. New York: Beacon.Frimer, Jeremy A., and Lawrence J. Walker. 2009. “Reconciling the Self and Morality:

An Empirical Model of Moral Centrality Development.” Developmental Psychology 45:1669–81.

Gardner, Howard, Mihaly Csikszentmihalyi, and William Damon. 2001. Good Work: When Excellence and Ethics Meet. New York: Basic Books.

Gleason, Tracy, and Darcia Narvaez. 2014. “Child Environments and Flourishing.” In Ancestral Landscapes in Human Evolution: Culture, Childrearing and Social Wellbeing, edited by Darcia Narvaez, Kristin Valentino, Agustín Fuentes, James J. McKenna, and Peter Gray, 335–48. New York: Oxford University Press.

Goldberg, Elkhonon. 2002. The Executive Brain: Frontal Lobes and the Civilized Brain. New York: Oxford University Press.

Gottlieb, Gilbert. 2002. “On the Epigenetic Evolution of Species-Specific Perception: The Developmental Manifold Concept.” Cognitive Development 17:1287–300.

Haidt, Jonathan, Silvia H. Koller, and Maria G. Dias. 1993. “Affect, Culture, and Morality, or is it Wrong to Eat Your Dog?” Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 65:613.

Hamilton, Maya G., and Nicole M. LaVoi. 2017. “Coaches Who Care: The Ethical Pro-fessional Identity Development of Moral Exemplar Collegiate Coaches.” Journal of Moral Education 46:114–28.

Han, Hyemin, and Changwoo Jeong. 2014. “Improving Epistemological Beliefs and Moral Judgment through an STS-Based Science Ethics Education Program.” Science and Engineering Ethics 20:197–220.

Hartshorne, Hugh, and Mark A. May. 1928. Studies in the Nature of Character, Vol. 1: Studies in Deceit. New York: Macmillan.

–. 1929. Studies in the Nature of Character, Vol. 2: Studies in Service and Self-Control. New York: Macmillan.

Page 24: Linking Psychological and Philosophical Viewsdnarvaez/documents/Reilly_Narvaez... · 2018-11-29 · Character, Virtue, and Science 55 For author’s use only. of automaticity or spontaneous

74 Timothy S. Reilly and Darcia Narvaez

For author’s use only.

–. 1930. Studies in the Nature of Character, Vol. 3: Studies in the Organization of Char-acter. New York: Macmillan.

Hatano, Giyoo, and Kayoko Inagaki. 1986. “Two Courses of Expertise.” In Child Devel-opment and Education in Japan, edited by Harold W. Stevenson, Hiroshi Azuma, and Kenji Hakuta, 262–72. New York: Freeman.

Hogarth, Robin M. 2001. Educating Intuition. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Hursthouse, Rosalind. 2003. “Normative Virtue Ethics.” In Virtue Ethics, edited by Ste-

phen Darwall, 184–202. Oxford: Blackwell.Josefsson, Kim, Markus Jokela, C. Robert Cloninger, Mirka Hintsanen, Johanna Salo,

Taina Hintsa, Laura Pulkki-Råback, and Liisa Keltikangas-Järvinen. 2013. “Maturity and Change in Personality: Developmental Trends of Temperament and Character in Adulthood.” Development and Psychopathology 25:713–27.

Kegan, Robert. 1982. The Evolving Self: Problem and Process in Human Development. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

Keyes, Corey L. 2007. “Promoting and Protecting Mental Health as Flourishing: A Com-plementary Strategy for Improving National Mental Health.” American Psychologist 62:95–108.

King, Pamela E., and William B. Whitney. 2015. “What’s the ‘Positive’ in Positive Psy-chology? Teleological Considerations Based on Creation and Imago Doctrines.” Jour-nal of Psychology and Theology 43:47–59.

Kinghorn, Warren. 2017. “The Politics of Virtue: An Aristotelian-Thomistic Engage-ment with the VIA Classification of Character Strengths.” Journal of Positive Psychol-ogy 12:436–46.

Kitman, Jamie L. 2000. “The Secret History of Lead.” The Nation, March 2. Accessed July 14, 2018. https://www.thenation.com/article/secret-history-lead.

Kochanska, Grazyna. 2002. “Mutually Responsive Orientation between Mothers and their Young Children: A Context for the Early Development of Conscience.” Current Directions in Psychological Science 11:191–95.

Kochanska, Grazyna, Jamie L. Koenig, Robin A. Barry, Sanghag Kim, and Jeung Eun Yoon. 2010. “Children’s Conscience during Toddler and Preschool Years, Moral Self, and a Competent, Adaptive Developmental Trajectory.” Developmental Psychology 46:1320–32.

Koenigs, Michael, Liane Young, Ralph Adolphs, Daniel Tranel, Fiery Cushman, Marc Hauser, and Antonio Damasio. 2007. “Damage to the Prefrontal Cortex Increases Utilitarian Moral Judgements.” Nature 446:908–11.

Kohlberg, Lawrence. 1981. Essays on Moral Development, Vol. 1: The Philosophy of Moral Development. New York: Harper & Row.

–. 1984. Essays on Moral Development, Vol. 2: The Psychology of Moral Development. San Francisco: Harper & Row.

Konner, Melvin. 2005. “Hunter-Gatherer Infancy and Childhood: The !Kung and Oth-ers.” In Hunter-Gatherer Childhoods: Evolutionary, Developmental and Cultural Per-spectives, edited by Barry Hewlett and Michael Lamb, 19–64. New Brunswick: Trans-action.

–. 2010. The Evolution of Childhood. Cambridge, MA: Belknap.Koutstaal, Wilma. 2013. The Agile Mind. New York: Oxford University Press.Kupperman, Joel. 1999. “Virtues, Character and Moral Dispositions.” In Virtue Ethics

and Moral Education, edited by David Carr and Jan Steutel, 199–209. London: Rout-ledge.

Page 25: Linking Psychological and Philosophical Viewsdnarvaez/documents/Reilly_Narvaez... · 2018-11-29 · Character, Virtue, and Science 55 For author’s use only. of automaticity or spontaneous

75Character, Virtue, and Science

For author’s use only.

Lapsley, Daniel K. 2006. “Moral Stage Theory.” In Handbook of Moral Development, ed-ited by Melanie Killen and Judith Smetana, 37–66. Mahwah, NJ: Erlbaum.

Lapsley, Daniel K., and Darcia Narvaez. 2005. “Moral Psychology at the Crossroads.” In Character Psychology and Character Education, edited by Daniel K. Lapsley and F. Clark Power, 18–35. Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press.

–. 2006. “Character Education.” In Handbook of Child Psychology, Vol. 4: Child Psychol-ogy in Practice, edited by William Damon, Richard Lerner, Ann Renninger, and Ir-ving E. Siegel, 248–96. New York: Wiley.

Lickona, Thomas. 1983. Raising Good Children. New York: Simon and Schuster.Little, Brian R. 1993. “Personal Projects and the Distributed Self: Aspects of a Conative

Psychology.” In Psychological Perspectives on the Self, Vol. 4: The Self in Social Perspec-tive, edited by Jerry M. Suls, 157–85. Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.

–. 2008. “Personal Projects and Free Traits: Personality and Motivation Reconsidered.” Social and Personality Psychology Compass 2:1235–54.

Losin, Peter. 1987. “Aristotle’s Doctrine of the Mean.” History of Philosophy Quarterly 4:329–41.

Lyubomirsky, Sonja, Laura King, and Ed Diener. 2005. “The Benefits of Frequent Posi-tive Affect: Does Happiness Lead to Success?” Psychological Bulletin 131:803–55.

MacIntyre, Alasdair. 1981. After Virtue. London: Duckworth.–. 2016. Ethics in the Conflicts of Modernity: An Essay on Desire, Practical Reasoning, and

Narrative. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Malin, Heather, Timothy S. Reilly, Brandy Quinn, and Seana Moran. 2014. “Adolescent

Purpose Development: Exploring Empathy, Discovering Roles, Shifting Priorities, and Creating Pathways.” Journal of Research on Adolescence 24:186–99.

Mann, Charles C. 2018. The Wizard and the Prophet: Two Remarkable Scientists and Their Dueling Visions to Shape Tomorrow’s World. New York: Knopf.

Maslow, Abraham. 1943. “A Theory of Human Motivation.” Psychological Review 50:370–96.

–. 1971. The Farther Reaches of Human Nature. New York: Viking.McAdams, Dan P. 1996. “Personality, Modernity, and the Storied Self: A Contemporary

Framework for Studying Persons.” Psychological Inquiry 7:295–321.–. 2013. The Redemptive Self: Stories Americans Live by. Oxford: Oxford University

Press.–. 2015. “Psychological Science and the Nichomachean Ethics: Virtuous Actors, Agents,

and Authors.” In Cultivating Virtue: Perspectives from Philosophy, Theology, and Psy-chology, edited by Nancy Snow, 307–36. New York: Oxford University Press.

McAdams, Dan P., and Jen Guo. 2015. “Narrating the Generative Life.” Psychological Science 26:475–83.

McGregor, Ian, and Brian R. Little. 1998. “Personal Projects, Happiness, and Mean-ing: On Doing Well and Being Yourself.” Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 74:494–512.

Medin, Douglas, and Megan Bang 2014. Who’s Asking? Native Science, Western Science, and Science Education. Cambridge, MA: MIT.

Miller, Christian B. 2013. Moral Character: An Empirical Theory. Oxford: Oxford Uni-versity Press.

Miller, Christian B., R. Michael Furr, Angela Knobel, and William Fleeson. eds. 2015. Character: New Directions from Philosophy, Psychology, and Theology. Oxford: Ox-ford University Press.

Page 26: Linking Psychological and Philosophical Viewsdnarvaez/documents/Reilly_Narvaez... · 2018-11-29 · Character, Virtue, and Science 55 For author’s use only. of automaticity or spontaneous

76 Timothy S. Reilly and Darcia Narvaez

For author’s use only.

Minsky, Marvin. 1997. “Negative Expertise.” In Expertise in Context: Human and Ma-chine, edited by Paul .J. Feltovich, Kenneth M. Ford, and Robert R. Hoffman, 515–21. Menlo Park, CA: American Association for Artificial Intelligence.

Monroe, Kristen R. 2001. “Morality and a Sense of Self: The Importance of Identity and Categorization for Moral Action.” American Journal of Political Science 45:491–507.

Montagu, Ashley. 1986. Touching: The Human Significance of the Skin. New York: Harper & Row.

Moran, Seana. 2014. “An Ethics of Possibility.” In The Ethics of Creativity, edited by Seana Moran, David Cropley, and James Kaufman, 281–98. London: Palgrave Macmillan.

Murdoch, Iris. 2001. The Sovereignty of Good. London: Routledge Classics.Nakamura, Jeanne, David J. Shernoff, and Charles H. Hooker. 2009. Good Mentoring:

Fostering Excellent Practice in Higher Education. New York: Wiley.Narvaez, Darcia. 2006. “Integrative Ethical Education.” In Handbook of Moral Develop-

ment, edited by Melanie Killen and Judith Smetana, 703–33. Mahwah, NJ: Erlbaum.–. 2010. “Moral Complexity: The Fatal Attraction of Truthiness and the Importance of

Mature Moral Functioning.” Perspectives on Psychological Science 5:163–81.–. 2011. “Neurobiology, Moral Education and Moral Self-Authorship.” In Moral Edu-

cation and Development: A Lifetime Commitment, edited by Doret J. de Ruyter and Siebren Miedema, 31–43. Rotterdam: Sense.

–. 2012. “Moral Neuroeducation from Early Life through the Lifespan.” Neuroethics 5:145–57.

–. 2013. “Wisdom as Mature Moral Functioning: Insights from Developmental Psy-chology and Neurobiology.” In Character, Practical Wisdom and Professional For-mation across the Disciplines, edited by Mark Jones, Paul Lewis, and Kelly Reffitt, 24–40. Macon: Mercer University Press.

–. 2014. Neurobiology and the Development of Human Morality: Evolution, Culture and Wisdom. New York: Norton.

–. 2015. “The Co-Construction of Virtue: Epigenetics, Neurobiology and Develop-ment.” In Cultivating Virtue: Perspectives from Philosophy, Theology, and Psychology, edited by Nancy Snow, 251–77. New York: Oxford University Press.

–. 2016. “Baselines for Virtue.” In Developing the Virtues: Integrating Perspectives, edited by Julia Annas, Darcia Narvaez, and Nancy Snow, 14–33. New York: Oxford Univer-sity Press.

Narvaez, Darcia, and Tonia Bock. 2014. “Developing Ethical Expertise and Moral Per-sonalities.” In Handbook of Moral and Character Education, edited by Larry Nucci, Tobias Krettenauer, and Darcia Narvaez, 140–58. London: Routledge.

Narvaez, Darcia, Tonia Bock, and Leilani Endicott. 2003. “Who Should I Become? Citi-zenship, Goodness, Human Flourishing, and Ethical Expertise.” In The Positive and Negative in Moral Education, edited by Wiel Veugelers and Fritz Oser, 43–63. New York: Peter Lang.

Narvaez, Darcia, Tonia Bock, Leilani Endicott, and James M. Lies. 2004. “Minnesota’s Community Voices and Character Education Project.” Journal of Research in Char-acter Education 2:89–112.

Narvaez, Darcia, Tracy Gleason, and Christyan Mitchell. 2010. “Moral Virtue and Prac-tical Wisdom: Theme Comprehension in Children, Youth and Adults.” Journal of Genetic Psychology 171:1–26.

Narvaez, Darcia, Tracy Gleason, Lijuan Wang, Jeff Brooks, Jennifer B. Lefever, Ying Cheng, and Centers for the Prevention of Child Neglect. 2013. “The Evolved

Page 27: Linking Psychological and Philosophical Viewsdnarvaez/documents/Reilly_Narvaez... · 2018-11-29 · Character, Virtue, and Science 55 For author’s use only. of automaticity or spontaneous

77Character, Virtue, and Science

For author’s use only.

Development Niche: Longitudinal Effects of Caregiving Practices on Early Child-hood Psychosocial Development.” Early Childhood Research Quarterly 28:759–73.

Narvaez, Darcia, and Daniel K. Lapsley. 2005. “The Psychological Foundations of Every-day Morality and Moral Expertise.” In Character Psychology and Character Education, edited by Daniel K. Lapsley and F. Clark Power, 140–65. Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press.

Narvaez, Darcia, and Daniel K. Lapsley. eds. 2009. Personality, Identity, and Character: Explorations in Moral Psychology. New York: Cambridge University Press.

Narvaez, Darcia, Daniel K. Lapsley, Scott Hagele, and Benjamin Lasky. 2006. “Moral Chronicity and Social Information Processing: Tests of a Social Cognitive Approach to the Moral Personality.” Journal of Research in Personality 40:966–85.

Narvaez, Darcia, and James Rest. 1995. “The Four Components of Acting Morally.” In Moral Behavior and Moral Development: An Introduction, edited by William Kurtines and Jacob Gewirtz, 385–400. New York: McGraw-Hill.

Narvaez, Darcia, Lijuan Wang, and Ying Cheng. 2016. “Evolved Developmental Niche History: Relation to Adult Psychopathology and Morality.” Applied Developmental Science 4:294–309.

Narvaez, Darcia, Lijuan Wang, Tracy Gleason, Ying Cheng, Jennifer Lefever, and Lifang Deng. 2013. “The Evolved Developmental Niche and Sociomoral Outcomes in Chi-nese Three-Year-Olds.” European Journal of Developmental Psychology 10:106–27.

Narvaez, Darcia, and David Witherington. 2018. “Getting to Baselines for Human Na-ture, Development and Wellbeing.” Archives of Scientific Psychology (under review for final acceptance).

Nelson, James M., and Brent D. Slife. 2017. “A New Positive Psychology: A Critique of the Movement Based on Early Christian Thought.” Journal of Positive Psychology 12:459–67.

Norton, David. 1991. Democracy and Moral Development: A Politics of Virtue. Berkeley: University of California Press.

Oliner, Samuel P., and Pearl M. Oliner. 1988. The Altruistic Personality: Rescuers of Jews in Nazi Europe. New York: Free Press.

Peterson, Christopher, and Martin E. Seligman. 2004. Character Strengths and Virtues: A Handbook and Classification, Vol. 1. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Peterson, Gregory R., Michael L. Spezio, James A. van Slyke, Kevin Reimer, and Warren Brown. 2010. “The Rationality of Ultimate Concern: Moral Exemplars, Theological Ethics, and the Science of Moral Cognition.” Theology and Science 8:139–61.

Peterson, Gregory, James A. van Slyke, Michael L. Spezio, and Kevin Reimer. 2017. Hab-its in Mind: Integrating Theology, Philosophy, and the Cognitive Science of Virtue, Emo-tion, and Character Formation. Leiden: Brill.

Reilly, Timothy S., and Darcia Narvaez. “Virtue and the Scientific Researcher: Under-standing the Personality and Character of Scientists” (in preparation).

Reimer, Kevin S. 2013. “Unexpected Communion: Purpose, Vocation, and Develop-mental Disability.” Perspectives on Science and Christian Faith 65:199–203.

Reimer, Kevin S., Brianne M. DeWitt Goudelock, and Lawrence J. Walker. 2009. “Devel-oping Conceptions of Moral Maturity: Traits and Identity in Adolescent Personality.” Journal of Positive Psychology 4:372–88.

Reimer, Kevin S., Christina Young, Brandon Birath, Michael L. Spezio, Gregory R. Peter-son, James A. van Slyke, and Warren S. Brown. 2012. “Maturity is Explicit: Self-Impor-tance of Traits in Humanitarian Moral Identity.” Journal of Positive Psychology 7:36–44.

Page 28: Linking Psychological and Philosophical Viewsdnarvaez/documents/Reilly_Narvaez... · 2018-11-29 · Character, Virtue, and Science 55 For author’s use only. of automaticity or spontaneous

78 Timothy S. Reilly and Darcia Narvaez

For author’s use only.

Renzulli, Joseph S., Jennifer L. Koehler, and Elizabeth A. Fogarty. 2006. “Operation Houndsooth Intervention Theory: Social Capital in Today’s Schools.” Gifted Child Today 29:14–24.

Rest, James R. 1983. “Morality.” In Handbook of Child Psychology, Vol. 3: Cognitive De-velopment, edited by Paul H. Mussen, James Flavell, and Ellen Markman, 556–629. 4th ed. New York: Wiley.

Rest, James R., and Darcia Narvaez. eds. 1994. Moral Development in the Professions: Psychology and Applied Ethics. Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.

Roberts, Robert C. 2017. “Virtues and Belief in God.” Journal of Positive Psychology 12:480–88.

Rogers, Carl. 1951. Client-Centered Therapy: Its Current Practice, Implications and The-ory. London: Constable.

–. 1961. On Becoming a Person: A Therapist’s View of Psychotherapy. London: Constable.Ross, Lee. 1977. “The Intuitive Psychologist and His Shortcomings: Distortions in the

Attribution Process.” Advances in Experimental Social Psychology 10:173–220.Rothbart, Mary K. 2007. “Temperament, Development, and Personality.” Current Direc-

tions in Psychological Science 16:207–12.Ryan, Kevin, and Thomas Lickona. 1987. “Character Development: The Challenge and

the Model.” In Character Development in Schools and Beyond, edited by Kevin Ryan and Thomas Lickona, 3–35. New York: Praeger.

Schnitker, Sarah A., Benjamin Houltberg, William Dyrness, and Nanyamka Redmond. 2017. “The Virtue of Patience, Spirituality, and Suffering: Integrating Lessons from Positive Psychology, Psychology of Religion, and Christian Theology.” Psychology of Religion and Spirituality 9:264–75.

Seider, Scott, Jalene Tamerat, Shelby Clark, and Madora Soutter. 2017. “Investigating Adolescents’ Critical Consciousness Development through a Character Framework.” Journal of Youth and Adolescence 46:1162–78.

Shiner, Rebecca L., Kristin A. Buss, Sandee G. McClowry, Samuel P. Putnam, Kimberly J. Saudino, and Marcel Zentner. 2012. “What Is Temperament Now? Assessing Pro-gress in Temperament Research on the Twenty-Fifth Anniversary of Goldsmith et al. (1987).” Child Development Perspectives 6:436–44.

Shiner, Rebecca L., and Colin G. DeYoung. 2013. “The Structure of Temperament and Personality Traits: A Developmental Perspective.” The Oxford Handbook of Develop-mental Psychology, Vol. 2: Self and Other, edited by Phillip Zelazo, 113–41. New York: Oxford University Press.

Slingerland, Edward G. 2015. Trying Not to Try: Ancient China, Modern Science, and the Power of Spontaneity. New York: Broadway Books.

Sternberg, Robert J. 2003. Wisdom, Intelligence, and Creativity Synthesized. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Steutel, Jan, and Ben Spiecker. 2004. “Cultivating Sentimental Dispositions through Ar-istotelian Habituation.” Journal of the Philosophy of Education 38:531–49.

Stichter, Matt. 2018. “Virtue as Skill.” The Oxford Handbook of Virtue, edited by Nancy Snow, 57–81. New York: Oxford University Press.

Stotz, Karola, and Darcia Narvaez. 2019. “Niche.” In Encyclopedia of Personality and Individual Differences, edited by Virgil Zeigler-Hill and Thomas Shackelford. New York: Springer (in press).

Timpe, Kevin, and Craig A. Boyd. eds. 2014. Virtues and their Vices. New York: Oxford University Press.

Page 29: Linking Psychological and Philosophical Viewsdnarvaez/documents/Reilly_Narvaez... · 2018-11-29 · Character, Virtue, and Science 55 For author’s use only. of automaticity or spontaneous

79Character, Virtue, and Science

For author’s use only.

Titus, Craig S. 2017. “Aquinas, Seligman, and Positive Psychology: A Christian Approach to the Use of the Virtues in Psychology.” Journal of Positive Psychology 12:447–58.

Trevarthen, Colwyn. 2011. “What Is It Like to Be a Person Who Knows Nothing? Defin-ing the Active Intersubjective Mind of a Newborn Human Being.” Infant and Child Development 20:119–35.

Van Slyke, James A., Gregory R. Peterson, Warren S. Brown, Kevin S. Reimer, and Mi-chael L. Spezio. eds. 2012. Theology and the Science of Moral Action: Virtue Ethics, Exemplarity, and Cognitive Neuroscience. New York: Routledge.

Varela, Francisco. 1999. Ethical Know-How: Action, Wisdom, and Cognition. Stanford: Stanford University Press.

Vittersø, Joar. ed. 2016. Handbook of Eudaimonic Well-Being. New York: Springer In-ternational.

Walker, Lawrence J., Jeremy A. Frimer, and William L. Dunlop. 2010. “Varieties of Moral Personality: Beyond the Banality of Heroism.” Journal of Personality 78:907–42.

Watson, Gary. 1990. “The Primacy of Character.” In Identity, Character and Morality, edited by Owen J. Flanagan and Amélie Rorty, 449–70. Cambridge, MA: MIT.

West-Eberhard, Mary J. 2003. Developmental Plasticity and Evolution. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Wong, Paul T. 2016. “Self-Transcendence: A Paradoxical Way to Become Your Best.” In-ternational Journal of Existential Psychology and Psychotherapy 6:9.

Wynne, Edward A., and Kevin Ryan. 1993. Reclaiming Our Schools. New York: Merrill.Yearley, Lee H. 1990. Mencius and Aquinas: Theories of Virtue and Conceptions of Cour-

age. New York: State University of New York Press.

Timothy S. Reilly University of Notre Dame (Notre Dame, IN, USA) [email protected] Darcia Narvaez University of Notre Dame (Notre Dame, IN, USA) [email protected]