Linguistics As1

download Linguistics As1

of 10

description

An example essay for a graduate linguistics course, on the meaning of words and semantics.

Transcript of Linguistics As1

  • How can we dene the meaning of a word?

    October 22, 2014

    1 Introduction

    Despite the fact that the mental lexicon appears to be organized by meaning (at

    least partially) [Marslen-Wilson, 1994, Meyer and Schvaneveldt, 1971], there is

    no consensus on what word meaning... means [Braun and Sider, 2007]. Many

    dierent, pairwise incompatible theories of meaning were proposed as solutions

    during the last century.

    To provide a basis for comparing these dierent theories, I will begin with

    an overview of the explanatory work a theory of meaning is expected to do.

    After establishing the comparison criteria, I will present three competing

    theories (the classical, prototype and exemplar theories) by summarizing their

    claims and evaluating their explanatory performance.

    In the conclusion, I will single out exemplar theory as the most promising

    candidate, and attempt to identify possible future directions.

    2 Comparison criteria

    The quality of a scientic theory is a function of its explanatory power. This

    section provides a short review of several inuential linguistics studies. In the

    1

  • sequel, I will compare the competing theories by their ability to account for the

    phenomena revealed by these experimental results.

    For detailed explanations of the experiments, the reader is referred to the

    respective original papers.

    2.1 Typicality

    In 1973, Rips et al.[Rips and Smith, 1973] demonstrated the existence of a typ-

    icality gradient: people classied some species of birds as more typical than

    others, and this typicality was shown to correlate with the verication time of

    sentences involving these species. The usual example: robins are rated more

    typical than eagles, and verifying the truth of Aneagleisabird takes more time

    than that of A robin is a bird .

    The results have been replicated for various categories including clothing,

    vegetables and furniture, as well as dierent sentence processing tasks [Rosch.E., 1975].

    Somewhat surprisingly, even abstract number-theoretic categories (e.g. prime

    numbers) display typicality eects

    [Armstrong and Gleitman, 1983].

    2.2 Fuzzy Boundaries

    Some categories have fuzzy boundaries. On the level of a single individual,

    one thinks of where a cup ends or a bowl begins (which may depend on its

    contents!) [Labov, 1973], on the interpersonal level, more pressing issues, e.g.

    the controversial boundary between fetus and human being in the abortion

    debates.

    Cognitive anthropoligsts were not the rst to notice the issue of fuzzy degree

    of membership (despite what some sources claim! [CogLinWiki, 2014]). Indeed,

    while Aristotle armed the existence of essential properties, he regarded mean-

    2

  • ing as inherently fuzzy and ambigous, at least on the interpersonal level; so have

    most philosophers since then [Tierney, 2002, Peirce, 1902].

    The most important study is due to Labov [Labov, 1973]: no set of attributes

    (in their case, opposing sentences) is sucient to unambigously separate bowls

    from cups. However, a careful analysis of the data led to the creation of an

    accurate linear classier

    1

    .

    2.3 Knowledge Eect

    Background knowledge also aects categorization, as well as determination of

    meaning. Best exemplied by the recenty study of Lin et al. [Lin and Murphy, 1997]:

    the same items in the synthetic category tut get wildly dierent typicality scores

    depending on whether tuts are introduced as agricultural or venatic tools.

    2.4 Mental Lexicon

    An important goal for a theory of meaning (at least w.r.t. linguistics) is ex-

    plaining the organization of the mental lexicon. Several studies indicate that

    the mental lexicon is organized semantically. The most important experimental

    idea of this eld is priming: the observation that detecting or recalling a stim-

    ulus biases the processing speed of subsequent stimuli [Marslen-Wilson, 1994,

    Meyer and Schvaneveldt, 1971]. An example, certainly semantic: dog is a prime

    for wolf [Matsukawa, 2005]. The verication time eects in typicality are also

    instances of priming.

    Another phenomenon that requires explanation is that humans can acquire

    new vocabularly, and that newly learned words take their place among the

    others. Related to that, one should also mention compositionality: the common

    1

    attributes are assigned weights, the sum of all weights (hence linearity) is proportional to

    predicted degree of membership

    3

  • sense observation that the meaning of a compound depends on the meaning of

    its constitutents[Kamp and Partee, 1995].

    3 Theories of Meaning

    3.1 The Classical (Aristotelian) Theory

    3.1.1 Description

    A misnomer, since the theory is neither classical nor related to Aristotle. In its

    clearest formulation, given by Labov

    2

    [Labov, 1973], the classical theory holds

    that meaning is

    discrete: concepts are clearly separated from each other by formal or functional

    properties,

    invariant: all occurrences of a concept are the same,

    conjunctively-dened: all essential properties must be present together for a

    concept to be recognized,

    composed-of-atomic-primitives: categories cannot be subdivided indenitely;

    i.e. every concept satises a unique checklist of criteria.

    A typical example would be bachelor, supposedly satisfying the unique checklist

    {unmarried,male}. Which is, of course, nonsense: what about a four yearold boy, or the Pope? Wittgenstein once remarked that no-one ever produced

    a working example of a denitional analysis, and not for the lack of trying

    [Wittgenstein, 1953]!

    2

    amusingly in the form of a classical checklist!

    4

  • 3.1.2 Evaluation

    The classical theory has little to say about typicality. By the way, this is not

    very surprising, since refuting this theory was an overarching goal of Rosch's

    typicality studies [Rosch.E., 1975]. Indeed, if verifying X is a bird involves a

    unique checklist, then it should take the same time for any bird X, but this

    is not what happens [Rips and Smith, 1973]. This also shows that the mental

    lexicon is not organized according to classical meaning. Needless to say, unique

    checklists also oppose fuzzy membership.

    What about compositionality? One observes that adjectives don't commute

    with hyponyms: hamsters are animals, but large hamsters are usually not

    large animals. This is at odds with a unique checklist for the word large3.

    3.2 Prototype Theory

    3.2.1 Description

    In the face of the numerous unexplained experimental phenomena, classical

    theory becomes untenable. Rosch's study provides the foundation for the most

    popular family of alternatives, the so-called prototype theories.

    The dening

    4

    feature is the presence of prototypes, i.e. summary representa-

    tions of concepts. The common variant (identied by Hampton [Hampton, 1979],

    and clearly inspired byWittgenstein's idea of family resemblances [Kamp and Partee, 1995])

    holds that a prototype is akin to a list of related features, weighted by impor-

    tance. Unlike the classical checklists, these feature lists don't care about dis-

    creteness, conjunctiveness or even consistency - e.g. a prototype for the word

    dog will include the attributes short hair and long hair, as well as beige

    3

    Some advocates of the classical theory react by claiming that large is polysemous. Sincepositing enough polysemy can account for any empirical observation, one would prefer a

    classical explanation for why this systematic polysemy occurs in the rst place.

    4

    Another essentialist notion! Should I say prototypical?

    5

  • and black, presumably with dierent weights!

    3.2.2 Evaluation

    Prototype theory is consistent with typicality

    5

    eects: an instance is more typ-

    ical than another if it has a higher weight of prototypical features. It is still

    unclear why X isabird is easier to verify for typical birds than for atypical ones,

    but at least one does not see an outright contradiction.

    The situation is even better with fuzzy boundaries. The weighted lists pro-

    vide a very natural framework for that. Armstrong observes that words with def-

    initional meanings (e.g. odd) still display typicality eects [Armstrong and Gleitman, 1983].

    However, this causes no actual problems, as long as one distinguishes typicality

    6

    from fuzzyness

    7

    . After all, an eagle, while atypical, is still unambigously a bird!

    On the other hand, it seems that prototype theory cannot account for the

    semantic structure of the mental lexicon. Compositionality is the usual culprit.

    Armstrong observes that if you combine, say foolish and bird into the phrase

    foolish bird, it is no longer a xed matter... which foolish elements and which

    bird elements are intended to be combined ([Armstrong and Gleitman, 1983]

    p. 272), and there are too many phrasal categories to be mentally represented in

    terms of prototypes [Armstrong and Gleitman, 1983, Kamp and Partee, 1995].

    Barsalou's experiment is denitive: people can make up categories on-the-y

    (e.g. clothing to take on a vacation), and even these ad-hoc categories, not

    described by a single word, produce typicality eects [Barsalou, 1983]. Such

    categories could not have been stable mental representations.

    5

    its raison d'tre

    6

    goodness of exemplar

    7

    degree of membership

    6

  • 3.3 Exemplar Theory

    3.3.1 Description

    Another reaction to the failures of the classical theory, this one due to Medin

    [Medin and Schaer, 1978]. The exemplar theory rejects summary representa-

    tions, opting instead for memories, e.g. the concept of dog being represented

    by the set of all remembered dogs. These memories are supposed to provide a

    basis for classication whenever a new object is encountered.

    Exemplar theory is a radical departure from the previous theories. On one

    hand, exemplars avoid the drawbacks of the classical and prototype theories, on

    the other hand, exemplar theory faces its own new, unique challanges.

    3.3.2 Evaluation

    Exemplar theory is the natural setting for typicality phenomena. Typical items

    are the ones that are the most similar to the remembered category members.

    This explains why e.g. a robin is a more representative bird than an eagle or

    an ostrich. Typical items are easier to categorize because they are similar to

    more category members [Medin and Schaer, 1978].

    Exemplars convincingly account for fuzzy boundaries: a newly encountered

    object can easily be similar to two or more remembered categories (e.g. both

    tocups and to bowls).

    Mental lexicon eects work so-so: priming is relegated to the realm of general

    memory, and one gets an eective

    8

    explanation for compositionality.

    The main diculty is with explaining knowledge eects: the study on tuts

    comes to mind [Lin and Murphy, 1997]. How can the typicality score of certain

    items be decided before any exemplars are encountered? Here, one reaches the

    explanatory limits of the theory [Nosofsky, 2011].

    8

    if not unproblematic; can there really be a set of remembered foolish things?

    7

  • Theory Typicality Fuzzy Boundaries Knowledge Eect Mental Lexicon eects

    Classical + Prototype + + + Exemplar + + +

    Table 1: Comparison of the theories of meaning

    4 Conclusion

    As Table 1 shows, there is no denitive end to the meaning debate. At least

    the failure of the classical model should be clear. Its successors, the prototype

    and exemplar theories, are much more powerful, but they still have signicant

    explanatory blind spots.

    The question of the mental lexicon is fundamental, yet Barsalou's work shows

    that prototype theory will not be able to account for that [Barsalou, 1983].

    The strongest candidate is therefore exemplar theory, which at least doesn't

    contradict the experimental evidence [Nosofsky, 2011]. One could hope for a

    further generalized exemplar theory, which solves the remaining issues. But are

    there new paradigms emerging?

    There's a lot of future directions to explore. Exemplar theory presumably

    needs to be integrated with theories of memory formation, which should provide

    evidence for the soundness of the concept. The case for prototypes is strong as

    well: while pure prototype theory cannot work, a pluralist approach could still

    maintain the word meaning has both prototype and exemplar features.

    Either way, we're far from done: while we have come a long way since the

    days of the classical, a truly satisfactory theory should correctly predict the

    results of these experiments, but it should also speak about several phenomena

    that we couldn't take into account

    9

    in this comparison: basic level categories,

    superordinates, induction, continuous valuations etc. Until we get there, the

    nature of meaning remains a mystery.

    9

    mostly because the present theories are agnostic or silent on these issues

    8

  • References

    [Armstrong and Gleitman, 1983] Armstrong, S. L., G. L. R. and Gleitman, H.

    (1983). What some concepts might not be. Cognition, 13:263308.

    [Barsalou, 1983] Barsalou, L. (1983). Ad hoc categories. Memory & Cognition,

    11:211227.

    [Braun and Sider, 2007] Braun, D. and Sider, T. (2007). Vague, so untrue.

    Nous, 41:133156.

    [CogLinWiki, 2014] CogLinWiki (2014). Aristotelian model of categorization.

    retrieved 17 Oct 2014.

    [Hampton, 1979] Hampton, J. A. (1979). Polymorphous concepts in semantic

    memory. Journal of Verbal Learning and Verbal Behavior, 18:441461.

    [Kamp and Partee, 1995] Kamp, H. and Partee, B. (1995). Prototype theory

    and compositionality. Cognition, 57(129-191).

    [Labov, 1973] Labov, W. (1973). J.N. Bailey and R. W. Shuy (eds.) New Ways

    of Analysing Variation in English, chapter The boundaries of words and their

    meanings. Georgetown University Press.

    [Lin and Murphy, 1997] Lin, E. L. and Murphy, G. L. (1997). The eects of

    background knowledge on object categorization and part detection. Journal

    of Experimental Psychology: Human Perception and Performance, 23:1153

    1169.

    [Marslen-Wilson, 1994] Marslen-Wilson, W. e. a. (1994). Morphology and

    meaning in the english mental lexicon. Psychological Review, 215:1+.

    9

  • [Matsukawa, 2005] Matsukawa, J. e. a. (2005). Conceptual versus perceptual

    priming in incomplete picture identication. Journal of Psycholinguistic Re-

    search, 6.

    [Medin and Schaer, 1978] Medin, D. L. and Schaer, M. M. (1978). Context

    theory of classication learning. Psychological Review, 85:207238.

    [Meyer and Schvaneveldt, 1971] Meyer, D. E. and Schvaneveldt, R. W. (1971).

    Facilitation in recognizing pairs of words: Evidence of a dependence between

    retrieval operations. Journal of Experimental Psychology, 90:227234.

    [Nosofsky, 2011] Nosofsky, R. e. a. (2011). The generalized context model: An

    exemplar model of classication. Formal Approaches to Categorization, 1:18

    39.

    [Peirce, 1902] Peirce, C. (1902). Vague. - entry in Dictionary of Philosophy and

    Psychology, J.M. Baldwin (ed.).

    [Rips and Smith, 1973] Rips, L. J., S. E. J. and Smith, E. E. (1973). Semantic

    distance and the verication of semantic relations. Journal of Verbal Learning

    and Verbal Behavior, 12:120.

    [Rosch.E., 1975] Rosch.E. (1975). Cognitive representations of semantic cate-

    gories. Journal of Experimental Psychology: General, 104:192233.

    [Tierney, 2002] Tierney, R. (2002). Aristotle's theory of language and meaning

    review. The Journal of Philosophy, 99:203209.

    [Wittgenstein, 1953] Wittgenstein, L. (1953). Philosophical Investigations.

    Blackwell.

    10