Life Histories, Evolution, is · LIFE HISTORIES, EVOLUTION, AND SALMONIDS 23 which case, A. is the...

16
LIFE HISTORIES, EVOLUTION, AND SALMONIDS 21 This book is about salmonid fishes and the ways in vi hich study ing salmonids can inform general problems in is olution M own ins oh ement with salmon dates to the fall of 969 when, at the urging of Professor 3. T. Bonner, I attempted to apply my then nascent ideas on life history evolution to the genus Salmo. The occasion was the weekly ecology brown bag at which I had been scheduled to speak, and the ensuing discussion focused on the adaptive merits of semelparous versus iteroparous reproduction. Dr. Bonner, it transpired, spent his summers in Nova Scotia where he enjoyed angling for salmon. He was impressed by the tremendous obstacles elsewhere’ encountered by these fish when they returned from the ocean to spawn. Even though S. salar is technically iteroparous, it was apparent that individuals often had but a single crack at reproduction (Belding 1934) 1 should go to the lviii itimcs he proposed solicit the assist lni.e of P F Elson a fisheries biologist at the research station in St Andrews and Id irn about salmon Perhaps there were d ita that would inform the theorl I vi as developing Peihaps I would gain insight as to why Oncorhynchus is obligatorily semelparous and Salmo is not 2 And so sihen the spring semester ended I droxc north knowing little enough about the animals I had chosen to study, but convinced, as only a graduate student can he, that they would doubtless conform to my expectations. In due course, I met Dr. Elson who took me under a fatherly wing. With his assistance and encouragement, data were gathered, the theory refined, and results published (Schaffer and Elson 1975; Schaffer 1979a). Thereafter, I moved on to other taxa (Schaffer and Schaffer 1977, 1979) and other questions Schaffdr 1955). Thirty years later, an invitation arrived to write this chapter. Let me begin by thanking the editors for affording me an opportunity to revisit a formative stage in my scientific career. 1 Theory of Life History Evolution 1 1 Nature of the Problem According to Merriam-Webster (http://www.refdesk.com/), demography is the statistical study of human populations especially ivith reference to size and density, distribution, and vital statistics.’ Such studies need not be restricted so humans. One can just as well construct life tables for animals (Deevey 1947) and plants (Harper 1977), although in the latter case, especially, the situation he complicated by ambiguity as to just what constitutes an individual. Such hniea1ities iside one of the more iiterstin aspci.ts ol non human ddmogrs play is the fact that age-specific schedules of reproduction and mortality can vary drannticilly among closeh related species and v.en among populitions of the same spceies Some of this s iiiation is nothing more than the proximm. reflec tion of diffeiences in environmental quality But this is not the whole stors \nimal and plant life histories are also the products of es olution having been molded to i greater or lesser degree by natural scktion Regarding this second source of demographic variation, it is important to bear in mind that characters such as egg size and number, gestation period, generation time, and so on, are Life Histories, Evolution, William M. Schaffer and Salmonids

Transcript of Life Histories, Evolution, is · LIFE HISTORIES, EVOLUTION, AND SALMONIDS 23 which case, A. is the...

Page 1: Life Histories, Evolution, is · LIFE HISTORIES, EVOLUTION, AND SALMONIDS 23 which case, A. is the rate at which the population ultimately multiplies.8 It is this final fact that

LIFE HISTORIES, EVOLUTION, AND SALMONIDS 21

This book is about salmonid fishes and the ways in vi hich study ing salmonids caninform general problems in is olution M own ins oh ement with salmon datesto the fall of 969 when, at the urging of Professor 3. T. Bonner, I attempted toapply my then nascent ideas on life history evolution to the genus Salmo. Theoccasion was the weekly ecology brown bag at which I had been scheduled tospeak, and the ensuing discussion focused on the adaptive merits of semelparousversus iteroparous reproduction. Dr. Bonner, it transpired, spent his summers inNova Scotia where he enjoyed angling for salmon. He was impressed by thetremendous obstacles elsewhere’ encountered by these fish when they returnedfrom the ocean to spawn. Even though S. salar is technically iteroparous, it wasapparent that individuals often had but a single crack at reproduction (Belding1934) 1 should go to the lviii itimcs he proposed solicit the assist lni.e of P FElson a fisheries biologist at the research station in St Andrews and Id irn aboutsalmon Perhaps there were d ita that would inform the theorl I vi as developingPeihaps I would gain insight as to why Oncorhynchus is obligatorily semelparousand Salmo is not 2 And so sihen the spring semester ended I droxc northknowing little enough about the animals I had chosen to study, but convinced,as only a graduate student can he, that they would doubtless conform to myexpectations. In due course, I met Dr. Elson who took me under a fatherly wing.With his assistance and encouragement, data were gathered, the theory refined,and results published (Schaffer and Elson 1975; Schaffer 1979a). Thereafter, Imoved on to other taxa (Schaffer and Schaffer 1977, 1979) and other questionsSchaffdr 1955). Thirty years later, an invitation arrived to write this chapter. Letme begin by thanking the editors for affording me an opportunity to revisit aformative stage in my scientific career.

1 Theory of Life History Evolution

1 1 Nature of the Problem

According to Merriam-Webster (http://www.refdesk.com/), demography isthe statistical study of human populations especially ivith reference to size

and density, distribution, and vital statistics.’ Such studies need not be restrictedso humans. One can just as well construct life tables for animals (Deevey 1947)and plants (Harper 1977), although in the latter case, especially, the situation

he complicated by ambiguity as to just what constitutes an individual. Suchhniea1ities iside one of the more iiterstin aspci.ts ol non human ddmogrs

play is the fact that age-specific schedules of reproduction and mortality can varydrannticilly among closeh related species and v.en among populitions of thesame spceies Some of this s iiiation is nothing more than the proximm. reflection of diffeiences in environmental quality But this is not the whole stors\nimal and plant life histories are also the products of es olution having beenmolded to i greater or lesser degree by natural scktion Regarding this secondsource of demographic variation, it is important to bear in mind that characterssuch as egg size and number, gestation period, generation time, and so on, are

Life Histories, Evolution, William M. Schaffer

and Salmonids

Page 2: Life Histories, Evolution, is · LIFE HISTORIES, EVOLUTION, AND SALMONIDS 23 which case, A. is the rate at which the population ultimately multiplies.8 It is this final fact that

22 EVOLUTION ILLUMINATED: SALMON AND THEIR RELATIVES

often correlated with traits such as body size (Bonner 1965; Calder 1984;Schmidt-Nielsen 1984), upon which selection also can act. As a result, inferringthe phenotypic targets of past selection can be problematic. It follows that thebiologist seeking adaptive explanations for particular life history phenomena iswise to focus on closely allied forms that differ principally with regard to thecharacters in question. Put another way, the sensible adaptationist, as opposed toideologically inspired caricatures (Gould and Lewontin 1979) thereof, is guidedby the expectation that “related species will differ in the direction of theirrespective optima.”3

1.2. Early Investigations

The late I 960s and early 70s were years of heady optimism for evolutionaryecologists who believed that simple mathematical models could offer a usefulaccounting of the broad brushstroke patterns observable in nature (Kingsland1985). Forever associated with this conviction will be the name of RobertHelmer MacArthur whose Mozartian career spanned a scant 15 years.4 Bestknown for his interest in biogeography (MacArthur and Wilson 1967;MacArthur 1972) and competitive exclusion (May and MacArthur 1972;MacArthur 1958, 1969, 1970; MacArthur and Levins 1967), MacArthur alsocontributed (1962; MacArthur and Wilson 1967) to the corpus theoretica nowknown as the theory of life history evolution (Roff 1992, 2002; Stearns 1976,1977, 1992). This line of inquiry traces to the work of Lamont Cole (1954) whowas among the first to advocate a comparative approach to the study of animaldemographics. Especially, Cole sought to understand the adaptive significance ofdivergent schedules of reproduction and mortality, in which regard, he presumed that fitness, the elusive “stuff’ of evolution, is usefully approximatedby the rate at which an asexual individual and its identical descendants multiplyunder the assumption of unchanging probabilities of reproduction and survival.As discussed by Leslie (1945, 1948), Keyfitz (1968), and others, this rate isdetermined by the so-called “stable age equation,”

I = (1)i=O

where, £ is the probability of living to age i, and B1 is the effective fecundity of ani-year-old.5’6

Equation (1) is a polynomial equation of degree n + I from which it followsby the Fundamental Theorem of Algebra that there are n + I (possibly complexand not necessarily distinct) values of A for which the equality holds. Thesevalues are called “roots,” and we may arrange them in order of decreasingmagnitude, that is, A1 A2} > ... A,,

.‘ If one neglects post-reproductiveage classes, the Peron’—Frobenius theorem (Gantmacher 1959) guarantees thatx1 is real and positive. Moreover, we can usually replace the inequalities,

i IA2 ... A,, , with strict inequalities, A1 > RI >...> P+ in

LIFE HISTORIES, EVOLUTION, AND SALMONIDS 23

which case, A. is the rate at which the population ultimately multiplies.8It is thisfinal fact that justifies identification of Ai with fitness.

Equating fitness with A1 enabled Cole to inquire as to the circumstancesfavoring alternative schedules of birth and death. In particular, he argued thatdelaying the onset of reproduction would generally be disadvantageous, in whichregard, he posed his famous paradox (text box) concerning the ubiquity of theperennial habit. Implicit in Cole’s analysis was the notion of tradeoffs: over thecourse of evolution, he imagined, current fecundity can be exchanged for subsequent survival and reproduction, an idea that George Williams (1966a) latermade explicit via the concept of “reproductive effort.” Of course, many mutations result in fitness diminutions all round, that is, reductions in both reproduction and survivorship, Modulo the effects of small population size, suchvariations are eliminated by selection—which is what Levins (1968) meantwhen he observed that it is only those genotypes corresponding to points onthe margins of a fitness set that matter.

What about potentially beneficial variations? To first approximation (Crowand Kimura 1970; Charlesworth and Williamson 1975), the likelihood of afavorable mutation being fixed depends on its selective advantage, which, inthe present case, reflects the values of the partial derivatives,

8A1/dB1 = (j/A)/Vr (2a)

Cole’s ParadoxCole asserted that “for an annual species, the absolute gain in intrinsic populationgrowth ... achieved by changing to the perennial reproductive habit would be exactlyequivalent to adding one individual to the average litter.” His argument was asfollows:

Consider an annual plant, which produces B,, seeds and then dies, and a corresponding perennial which produces B5 seeds and itself survives with probability oneto reproduce the following year and again with probability one, the year after that, adinfinitum, The annual and its descendants multiply yearly at rate A,,, = B,,; the perennial and its descendants, at rate A, = B + 1 Energetically, seeds are “cheap” compared to adaptations that permit plants to overwinter. Why then, asked Cole, aren’tperennials replaced by annual mutants which “trade in” the energy required for longlife for a small increment in seed production?

The answer (Charnov and Schaffer 1973) is that the B’s are “effective fecundities,”that is, the numbers of seeds that germinate and themselves survive to set seed. Thatis, B,, = cb,,, and B = cb5, where b’s are the numbers of seeds produced, and c is theaforementioned germination-survival probability. For the annual population to growmore rapidly than the perennial, it is therefore necessary that b,, > b8 + 1/c, or, in thecase that adults survive with probability p < 1, that b,, > b + p/c. Often, c <p, inwhich case, (p/c)>> 1. Then, superiority of the annual requires b,, >> b5, which is tosay, an increase in fecundity substantially in excess of a single seed.

Page 3: Life Histories, Evolution, is · LIFE HISTORIES, EVOLUTION, AND SALMONIDS 23 which case, A. is the rate at which the population ultimately multiplies.8 It is this final fact that

/dp = ((/; )/ IT) (v1_ /i’0)

(Hamilton 1966; Emlen 1970; Caswell 1979)C Here,

= (; /t1) ? ‘

is the reproductive value (Fisher 1930) of an i-year-old, which is simply theexpectation of current and future offspring discounted by appropriate powersof ;.

.

° Correspondingly,

= (i +

is the total reproductive value of a population that has achieved stable agedistribution.

Equations (2a) and (2h) suggest two principal conclusions:

I. Increased reproduction at earlier ages confers greater benefits to fitnessthan comparable increases at later ages. This reflects the fact that, so longas

‘.> 1. the term, (t /.i) necessarily declines with age.

2. The benefits of increased survival are often greatest at intermediate ages.This is because (dj/i:ip1)depends on reproductive value, which generallypeaks at, or shortly after, the age of first reproduction (Fisher 1930).

1.3. Fixation ofAdvantageous Mutants in the Presence ofDensity Dependence

Thus far, we have assumed constant rates of reproduction and survival. This isappropriate for populations growing exponentially. Of course, real-world populations do not multiply indefinitely. Rather, their growth rates are arrested by avariety of limiting factors, the effect of which is to reduce reproduction andincrease mortality. It is important therefore to inquire as to what happenswhen life history parameters manifest density dependence, that is, when ?depends on both population numbers and phenotype. To this end, we studythe fate of an advantageous mutant arising in a population at equilibrium withrespect to both age structure and density. In what follows, we denote the wildtype phenotype ), the mutant phenotype, ‘ and the corresponding equilibriumdensities (carrying capacities), K1I and K’. Please refer to Figure 1. 1.

When the mutant first appears, the wild type is in approximate equilibrium,and (, K0) 1. At the same time, the mutant’s rate of increase, by virtue ofits being advantageous, exceeds 1. That is,

‘ (‘. K) > 1. More precisely, themutant manifests a selective advantage,

LIFE HISTORIES, EVOLUTION, AND SALMONIDS 25

KOK1j

1. Fitnes , r(g’. N) = (I/N)(dN/dt), plott d against den itv fo wild vpe andnotyp s, g and e’ In the course of sohing horn g to g’, the population’s

m den ity inc eases from K,, to K’

s — [r(’. K11) — r(q0.K0)] Aq(dr/d\_k, 0 (5)

/ I ‘ Since c > 0, the number of mutants iiwreases and, ‘a ith it, thei’’n’c overall size. At the sanw time, increasing density forces reductionsr. s of increase of both phcnotxpes. Now ; K’) < 1, and the numbertspe individuals begins to decline, Still, N < K’, and the numbei of

.1 continues to increase, albeit more slowly, E entualls, the wild t pe‘it, and population size stabilizes at the new carrying capacity, N K’,

larger than the old. At this point, the mutant’s frequenes, p = 1, and its.i’iltiplication, , I K’) = 1.

iding this scenario, there are two principal caveats. In th first place, wesubstitution process to be slou , by sshkh we mean quasi %tOtic, that

ough that both density and age stiucttu e ti ack their respectix e equili1 o r quire that the fitness of the mut’int e\ceed that of the wild tspeI range of population densities, [K0, K’]. According to this, substitut s orable mutant is formally quit alent to mt rsp cific competition

o growth isoclines do not cross. Absent this assumption, we are intoI c f r ersus K select’on as these concepts are traditionally formulated

nd Wilson 196 ; Piank 1970)‘phenotype,” that is, , r fers to the B’s or p’s above, we may use

( a) and (2h) to e’saluate dr/dq — (1/i I )(ij/dq). This ignores theof tradeoffs, for example, between current fecundity and subsequent

i n and survival. If the e are tradeoffs, these must b taken intoliscussed in Shaffei (10, 9b). To summarize, the machiners des’el

Ce densit\-independent ease Lan he applied to density-dependenten satisfaction of certain assumptions.

24 EVOLUTION ILLUMINATED: SALMON AND THEIR RELATIVES

and

r mA1

0

(h i

(3)

(4)

N

Page 4: Life Histories, Evolution, is · LIFE HISTORIES, EVOLUTION, AND SALMONIDS 23 which case, A. is the rate at which the population ultimately multiplies.8 It is this final fact that

26 EVOLUTION I LLUMINATED: SALMON AND THEIR RELATIVES LIFE HI STO RI ES, EVOLUTION, AND SALMON IDS 27

1.4. L!fe History Evolution as an Optimization Problem

2

A(E) = B(E) + p(E) (6a)

= B(E) + p(E)g(E)

The notion of reproductive effort was first linked to Cole’s mathematics byGadgil and Bossert (1970) who framed life history evolution in terms of costsand benefits. Specifically, they considered the set of age-specific reproductiveexpenditures, E [E1..... Ej, and assumed explicit dependencies of thefecundities, B1, and survival probabilities, P = /P), on E. The computerwas then used to determine the expenditures, E = [E(3..... E], maximizing?. As discussed by subsequent authors (Taylor et al. 1974; Leon 1976;Schaffer 1983), this is an optimization problem (Bellman 1957; Leitmann 1966;Intrilligator 1971) whereby a set of “controls,” the E1, are adjusted to maximizean ‘objective function,”

Because the dependence of ? on the controls, E = [E0,..., Ej, is via theireffect on the B’s and ps, viewing life history evolution as an optimizationproblem focuses our attention on the functional dependencies, B1(E1),p1(Ej,and so on. Concerning these, we note the following:

1, Effective fecundity will generally be an increasing function of reproductive effort at the current age and possibly a decreasing function of expenditure at prior ages. That is, 8B1/aE1 > 0 and dB1/dE1 < 0, for I < i.In the special case that B11 =g1(E1)B1, the rate, g1, at which fecunditymultiplies from one year to the next will he a decreasing function ofreproductive effort at the current age, that is, Bg,/0E1 < 0.

3. Post-reproductive survival will also be a decreasing function of reproductive effort at the current age and possibly a decreasing function of expenditure at prior ages. That is, dp1/BE1 < 0, and dp1/dE1 0 for j < i.

This brings us to one of the more interesting subjects in life history theory,namely the adaptive significance of “big bang reproduction” (semelparitv)whereby a single, often spectacular, bout of breeding is followed by the organism’s obligate demise. Concerning this matter, Gadgil and Bossert (1970) suggested that such a strategy should be favored by concave (i.e., accelerating,)dependencies (positive second derivatives) of effective fecundity and post-breeding survival on reproductive effort. Conversely, they proposed that convex, (i.e.,decelerating dependencies (negative second derivatives), should favor moremodest levels of reproduction and, hence, post-reproductive survival and iteroparity. The distinction is illustrated in Figure 1.2 for the special case in whichthe functions B-(E) and p1(E1) are the same for all age classes, and there is acommon reproductive effort, E = = E1 = ... = E,,.

Under these assumptions, and in the limit that the number of age classes,n — , the multidimensional optimization problem collapses (Schaffer 1974a)to the simpler chore of maximizing

:eure 1.2. Optimal reproductive expenditure under difErent assumptions regarding the

:Jcofi between current effective fecundity, B(E), and subsequent survival, p(E, for

pulations growing according to Eq. (ha). Optimal expenditures are values of E at

Jich ?.(E) = B(E} + piE) is maximal. a. BIE) and p(EJ are accelerating functions (posltwe

:ind derivatives) of E. In this case, ?dEj passes through a minimum, E5, and the optimal

xpnditure is 0 or 1. b. The dependencies, B(EJ and p(E) are decelerating functions

iuSatit’e second derivatives) of E with the consequence that the optimum expenditure,

is often between 0 and 1. c. and d. More complex dependencies. In c, E= 0 or

E< i; in d, 0 < E < I or = I. Functions and parameter values used to compute

these figures are as follows: a. B(E) = E2: = 1.0: p(E) = jr(l — F)2, ir = 0.7. b.

PIE) = (2E — E ) = 1 0 p(E) = 7r(1 — F j = 0 c 13(E) = (3E — 2F) /‘ = 1 0

p(E)=T(1_E),=0.7.d.B(E)PE1.0P(E)=(]—2E+2E),x=OO

If effective fecundity, B(E, multiplies at rate, g(E), each year, this expressiongeneralizes to

(6b)

(Schaffer 1974a; Schaffer and Gadgil 1975). In either case, there is a tradeoff

between current and future components of fitness: current fecundity and sub

sequent survival (Equation (6a)) or current fecundity and subsequent survival

multiplied by the yearly rate at which fecundity multiplies (Equation (6b)).

Returning to Figure 1.2, we note that when B(E) and p(E) are concave

bigure I .2a), the optimal expenditure, 13*, is either 0 or 1. Often, both of

these so-called “boundary” solutions correspond to local maxima in ?.(E).

(onversely, when B(E) and p(EJ are convex (Figure 1 .2b), 13* will often he

.jnermediate between 0 and 1. That is, one has the “interior” solution,

E < 1.

Page 5: Life Histories, Evolution, is · LIFE HISTORIES, EVOLUTION, AND SALMONIDS 23 which case, A. is the rate at which the population ultimately multiplies.8 It is this final fact that

28 EVOLUTION ILLUMINATED: SALMON AND THEIR RELATIVES LIFE HISTORIES, EVOLUTION, AND SALMONIDS 29

The dependencies in Figures I.2a and I .2b are very simple. Figures L2c andI .2d illustrate more complicated possibilities. Here, as in Figure 1 .2a, there canbe two expenditures corresponding to local maxima in fitness. Of these, one isalways a boundary solution, that is, E = C) [Figure 1 .2c) or 1 (Figure 1 .2d), whilethe other is often an interior solution, that is, 0 < < 1.

Of the four fecundity curves in Figure 1.2, the sigmoid function (Figure1 .2c) is arguably the one most often occurring in nature. Sigmoidal dependencecombines the idea of ‘start-up costs” to reproduction with the notion ofdiminishing returns when expenditure is high. ‘vVCth regard to start-up costs,we note that in most organisms the commitment to breed entails an initialinvestment that, of itself, yields nothing in the way of viable offspring. Inanadromous fishes, for example, this investment, involving physiologicalchanges that facilitate returning to fresh water, an often costly upstream migration, and so on, can be substantial (Hendry et al. 2003b—this volume).Intraspecific competition—among males for females and among females fornesting sites—will also serve to increase the range of effort values for whichfecundity evidences an accelerating dependence on expenditure. In extremecases, such factors may have the effect of making the entire function concaveas in Figure l.2a.

Other factors can be expected to have the opposite effect, that is, to promote diminishing fecundity returns at high effort values (the decelerating portion of the curve). Examples include competition among sibs for resources(including parental attention) and the tendency of numerous, tasty offspring toattract natural enemies.

‘With regard to post-reproductive survival, the functional dependencies mostfrequently occurring in nature are arguably convex functions of the sort shown inFigure 1 .2b. Biologically, such curves correspond to the idea that the consequences to post-breeding survival of increasing reproductive expenditure onlybecome significant when investment exceeds some threshold. But here again,changing biological and environmental circumstances can mold the dependency.For example, organisms in poor condition to begin with may manifest abruptdeclines in post-breeding survival at intermediate levels of expenditure—inwhich ease the dependency will be convex—concave as shown in Figure 5 ofSchaffer and Rosenzweig (1977). Conversely, the onset of reproduction mayinvolve the initiation of morphological changes or behaviors that place the animal at immediate risk—think breeding coloration in birds—even though theenergetic investment itself is modest. Then, survivorship may evidence an initialdrop, in which case the curve will he concave—convex, as shown in Figure 4 ofSchaffer and Rosenzweig (1977). If sufficiently pronounced, such effects canmake the curve entirely concave (Figure 1 .2a).

Regarding such considerations, we make two observations. The first is thatthey are difficult to quantify in the field (Schaffer and Schaffer 1977). Second,they can be confusing to think about, essentially because one is attemptingto squeeze too much biology into a single variable. These are issues to whichwe will return in Sections 2 and 3. For the present, we reiterate that even thesimplest model life histories can manifest alternative solutions to the same

1.5. Characterizing an Optimal L!fe History

My own contribution to life history evolution with age structure was technical.As a student, I absorbed MacArthur’s dictum that undue reliance on the computer is an invitation to counter-example. What would you do,’’ he once askeda visiting systems ecologist describing the results of an elaborate computer simulation, ‘if someone pulled the plug?’ And so, I fretted about what was going oninside Gadgil’s computer. Eventually, I convinced myself (Schaffer 1974a,1979h) that selection acts to maximize reproductive value at all ages, a resultwhich I later discovered had previously been conjectured by Williams (1966a).’ I

More precisely, it turns out that the reproductive value, (v/c0), of each age classis maximized with respect to the expenditure, E1, at that age. 12 In symbols,

i\Iax(;.1 ) —=> Nlax(i’,/i,). all IFC

\chich is read, ‘‘maximizing I by adjusting all of the expenditures is equivalentto maximizing each reproductive value, i’/v, with respect to E1.’ At about thesame time, Taylor et al. (1974) and Pianka and Parker (1975) independentlycame to the same conclusion.

Intuitively, Equation (7) makes sense—reproductive value being the age-specific expectation of current and future reproduction discounted by appropriito powers of One can further show (Schaffer 1974a) that these two components of fitness, that is, current and future reproduction, are exchangeable:maximizing (v1/v0) with respect to E1 also maximizes the sum, B +

ohere the second term, p(i’÷i/vo), is sometimes referred to as the ‘‘residualreproductive value,” RRV, of an i-year-old. The complement to Equation (7)is thus

Max(?1)<=> Max[B+p1(v+1/v0)], all E

Equation (8) is the analog of Equations (6) appropriate to cases in whichare distinguishable age classes. Among other things, it allows for the defi

mtion (Schaffer and Gadgil 1975; Schaffer 1979a) of costs and benefits. Inparticular, with a small increase, AE, in reproductive expenditure at age i, we

Sri associate the

circumstances. With more than one age class (see below), the possibilities formultiple optima proliferate

(/)

(8)

Benefit (AE) = AB, AE(3B,/flE,) (9a)

Cost (AE) = ARRV1 ... {iip.(v. I /v0)]/4E I (9h)

Page 6: Life Histories, Evolution, is · LIFE HISTORIES, EVOLUTION, AND SALMONIDS 23 which case, A. is the rate at which the population ultimately multiplies.8 It is this final fact that

30 EVOLUTION ILLUMINATED: SALMON ANDTHEIR RELATIVES LIFE HISTORIES, EVOLUTION, AND SALMONIDS 31

p(E)B(E)

Z

E

IA

1.6. Predictions of Simple Models

While Equations (7) and (8) speak to the nature of an optimal life history, theycannot he used to compute one directly. This is because the optimal reproductive expenditure for any particular age class depends on the reproductive expenditures at all ages. 13 As discussed below, this leads to the study of curves(surfaces) of conditional optima whereby one computes the optimal value of E1for representative reproductive expenditures at the other ages (Schaffer andRosenzweig 1977). Before turning to such matters, however, let us first reviewwhat can be learned from single age class models. In this instance, the followingresults can be deduced:

1. Semelparity versus iteroparity (Schaffer 1 974a; Schaffer and Gadgil1975). We have already remarked upon the fact that the evolution ofbig-bang” reproduction is predicted under circumstances that make for

concave, that is, accelerating dependencies of life table parameters onreproductive expenditure (Figures L2a, 1.2d). So far as I am aware,the existence of accelerating dependencies in a natural population hasyet to be demonstrated convincingly. Still, one can speculate as to thebiological circumstances that would have this effect. In the case of semelparous Agavaceae, Schaffer and Schaffer (1977, 1979) proposed (withsome empirical support) that accelerating dependencies of effectivefecundity on effort may result from competition among flowering plantsfor pollinators. Similarly, concavity of the fecundity function in Pacificsalmon may result from competitive interactions among reproductives(see below). In such cases, reproductive success depends, not on an individual’s reproductive effort per Se, but on his/her effort relative to that ofother individuals in the population. This suggests a connection betweenbehavioral components of reproductive expenditure and dispersal, asdiscussed in Schaffer (1977).

2. Allocation in proportion to relative returns (Schaffer 1974a; Schafferand Gadgil 1975). This is the theory’s most general prediction:Increasing fecundity per unit investment favors greater reproductiveeffort (Figure 1 .3a); increasing post-reproductive survival or year-to-year growth in fecundity per unit investment favors reduced reproductiveexpenditure, which is to say, greater allocation to maintenance andgrowth (Figure 1 .3b).

3. Effects of juvenile (pre-reproductive) versus adult (post-reproductive)mortality (Schaffer l974a; Schaffer and Gadgil 1975). This is a specialcase of the previous result, As such, it merits separate mention because itserves to emphasize the fact that the fecundities in Equation (2) areeffective fecundities, that is, the numbers of offspring that survive to becounted as young-of-the year at census time. Accordingly, increasing(decreasing) survival rates among juveniles will select for greater (lesser)rates of reproductive expenditure. This is in contrast to changing survivalrates among adults that select in the opposite direction.

—JzZ”

8(E) + p(E)

/—-----

E1

figure 1.3. Consequences to optimal reproductive expenditure, E, of per unit efforthnges in effective fecundity, B(E), and post-reproductive survival, p(E), n a modelcithout age structure, a. Reducing B(E) reduces E*. b. Reducing p(Ej increases E*.

4. Under density dependence, optimal reproductive strategies maximizecarrying capacity (Schaffer and Tamarin 1973). This is the life historicalrealization of MacArthur’s (1962) reformulation of Fisher’s (1930)Fundamental Theorem of Natural Selection. Two examples are givenin Figure 1.4. Here we plot optimal expenditure as a function, E(N),of density and equilibrium density as a function, N*(E), of reproductiveeffort. In the first instance (Figure 1 .4a), density is assumed to reducejuvenile survival and hence effective fecundity; in the second (Figure1 .4b), increasing population numbers are assumed to reduce post-reproductive survival. In both cases, the optimal expenditure changes withpopulation size so as to maximize the carrying capacity, which is whatMacArthur’s more general analysis predicts.. At the same time, the meansby which this maximization is accomplished differ: in the first case,optimal reproductive effort declines with density; in the second, optimalexpenditure increases. At first glance, the second result would seem to beat odds with the theory of r- and K-selection, which holds that r-selectedspecies produce more young and are generally shorter lived than their K-selected counterparts. The discrepancy vanishes on consideration of the

Page 7: Life Histories, Evolution, is · LIFE HISTORIES, EVOLUTION, AND SALMONIDS 23 which case, A. is the rate at which the population ultimately multiplies.8 It is this final fact that

32 EVOLUTION ILLUMINATED: SALMON AND THE! R RELATIVES LI FE H STO RI ES, EVO LUTI ON AND SALM ON DS 33

E

0

E

0

N 7!

N

Figure 1.4. Optimal reproductive effort, E”(N), and equilibrium density, N*(E), underalternative assumptions regarding the effects of increasing population size, a. Increaseddensity reduces pre-reproductive survival. Optimal effort declines with density.(E, N) = B(E, N) +p(E) = e’’(2E — E2) + (l — E2); c = 0.5; = 5.0; x = 0.8. h.Increased density diminishes post-reproductive survival. Optimal effort increases withdensitv A(E, N) = B(E) +p(E. N) = fl(2E — E2) ± re(l E2); c = 0,5; = 0.95;

= 0.8.

fact that under conditions of crowding, it is the youngest individuals thatusually experience the most additional mortality.

5. Year-to-year variation in relative returns is selectively equivalent toreducing the mean return in a constant environment (Schaffer 1974b).Suppose the effective fecundity, B(E), and stirvival, p(E), functions aresubject to year-to-year variations that result from environmental fluctuations. Choosing the populations geometric mean rate of increase,

1

1cm (n)

(a) Variation in effective fecundity per unit investment selects forreduced reproductive expenditure;

b) Variation in post-reproductive survivorship and growth favorsincreased reproduction.

These results are sometimes cited (Stearns 1976) as an evolutionaryexample of bet-hedging.” In fact, the arguments from which theyfollow have nothing to do with risk minimization (Schaffer 1974h).More generally, if variations in reproduction and survivorship per unitexpenditure are predictable, selection will favor adaptations that alloworganisms to read” the environment and respond adaptively.

1.7. Optimal Allocation with Age Structure

With the addition of age structure, the problem of deducing general resultsbecomes more difficult. As noted above, this is because the optimal reproductiveexpenditure for any particular age class depends on next year’s reproductivevalue, and thus on the reproductive expenditures at all ages. Taking thiscomplication into account yields the following results:

1. Selective consequences of altered returns per unit investment depend onthe age classes affected (Schaffer 1974a; Schaffer and Rosenzweig1977). As before, increasing effective fecundity for the current age classfavors increased reproductive expenditure at that age, whereas increasingpost-reproductive survival and/or growth per unit effort for the currentage class selects for reduced expenditure (again, at that age). ln addition,increasing fecundity or survivorship per unit investment at earlier ageclasses increases the optimal current expenditure. This is because thesechanges increase ? and thereby reduce subsequent reproductive value(v+/v). Conversely, increasing fecundity or survivorship at later ageclasses reduces the optimal current expenditure because such changesincrease subsequent reproductive value, These results are summarizedin Table 1.1.

Table 1.1. Consequences to current optimal reproductiveeffort, E, of increased effective fecundity and survival perunit investment.

Life history parameter affected

Current age Later ages Earlier ages

p,(E,) B1(E,) p,(E,) B,(E,) p,(E)

Consequence to

a.

(E, Nj

b.

(E, Nj

NjE)

V//

as our criterion of optimality yields the following results: t t

Page 8: Life Histories, Evolution, is · LIFE HISTORIES, EVOLUTION, AND SALMONIDS 23 which case, A. is the rate at which the population ultimately multiplies.8 It is this final fact that

34 EVOLUTION ILLUMINATED SALMON AND THEIR RELATIVES LIFE HISTORIES, EVOLUTION, AND SALMON IDS 35

2. Reduced reproductive effort in older individuals can be adaptive. Gadgiland Bossert (1970) proposed that optimal effort invariably increases withage, a conclusion that suggests declining expenditures in older individualsare a maladaptive consequence of aging. Subsequently, Fagen (1972)produced a counter-example and observed that almost any age-specificpattern in optimal effort is possible depending on the way in which thefunctions B,(E,) and p,(E) vary with age. In retrospect, one imagines thatGadgil and Bossert were misled by the fact that their model life historiesassumed a maximum age following which death was obligate. Providedthat fecundity increases monotonically with effort, the optimum expenditure for this final age class is necessarily 100%, that is, in terms ofEquation (8), (v÷1/v11)= 0 for all values of E1, which should thus bechosen to maximize B. It follows that optimal effort increases fromthe penultimate to the final age class, and, oftentimes, the pattern cascades back to the younger age classes.

From a computational point of view, assuming a fixed life span may beconvenient. However, on biological grounds, it is often more realistic tosuppose that even the oldest individuals have a non-zero probability ofsurviving another year. In such cases, there is no maximum age class perse, and optimal reproductive investment can decline in the later ageclasses. In particular, reduced per-unit effort fecundity in older individuals, as typically results from aging, can favor reductions in reproductiveeffort. This suggests a distinction between organisms in which body sizeand fecundity increase throughout life, and those in which body size andreproductive potential plateau. Some sample computations are presentedin Table 1.2 wherein I report some results for a five-age-class model.Under the assumption of continuing age-dependent increases in potentialfecundity, optimal effort increases with age regardless of what oneassumes about the final age class. 14 Conversely, when fecundity perunit investment peaks at intermediate ages, the Gadgil—Bossert modelonly obtains if one assumes the obligate demise of individuals in theoldest age class. Absent this assumption, that is, if one regards the oldestage class as “adults” which survive from one year to the next with constant probability, optimal expenditure can manifest the up—down patternnoted above. I These results underscore the selective link between senescence, as the term is usually understood, that is, the onset of degenerativedisorders of the sort targeted by geriatric medicine, and optimal lifehistory evolution, 16

1.8. Optimal Effort for Multiple Age Classes

Thus far, I have emphasized the evolution of reproductive expenditure atindividual age classes, either in single age-class models, or in multi-age-classmodels, with expenditures at the other age classes implicitly held constant. Tocomplete our discussion, we consider selection on the entire set of reproductive expenditures, E = E,. That is, we treat the life table as a whole. To

Table 1.2. Age-specific optimal effort, E*.

Age class0 1 2 3 “Adults”

I. Potential fecundity increases with age

Maximum return on investment

B, 0.50 1.00 2.00 3.00 4.00

Optimal effort

Case A. Adults die after one year

E’ 0.34 0.36 0.45 0.57 1.00

Case B. Adults survive with probability P/iE,* 0.34 0.35 0.43 0.53 0.66

II. Potential fecundity declines in old age

Maximum return on investment

B, 0.50 1.00 2.00 1.00 0.50

Optimal effoit

Case A. Adults die after one year

0.37 0.44 0.73 0.76 1.00

Case B. Adults survive with probability 4

0,37 0.44 0,72 0.72 0.63

B,(E,) = /%(2E E); x,(E,) x,( 1 —= 10.50.0.60. 0.70. 0.65,0.501.

do this, we introduce the notion of curves (or surfaces) of conditional optima thatspecify the optimal reproductive effort at a particular age for some suitably:hosen set of expenditures at the other ages (Schaffer 1974a; Schaffer andRosenzweig 1977). We emphasize that this approach is neither esoteric nordifficult to implement. In practice, one identifies an age class of interest anduomputes the optimal reproductive effort at that age for a large number of‘xpenditures at the other ages. For example, in the case of two-age-classmodels, one calculates the curve of optimal expenditures, Eo*(E1), at age 0for representative values of E1 and the corresponding curve, E1*(Eo), for repress’ntative values of E11. The resulting curves are then plotted in the E0 — E1plane and inspected. Points at which the curves intersect maximize A withct’spect to both expenditures and consequently correspond to optimal life hisLoris’s, With three age classes, the curves become surfaces in E0 — E1 —

spwe; and, with n + I > 3 age classes, hypersurfaces in E() —... — E space.10 an entirely analogous fashion, one can compute curves (surfaces) of condi

Page 9: Life Histories, Evolution, is · LIFE HISTORIES, EVOLUTION, AND SALMONIDS 23 which case, A. is the rate at which the population ultimately multiplies.8 It is this final fact that

36 EVOLUTION ILLUMI NATED: SALMON AND THEIR RELATIVES LIFE HI STOR I ES, EVOLUTION AND SALMO NI DS 37

tional minima in fitness. From the viewpoint of adaptive topographies (Wright1 96), intersections of curves (surfaces] of conditional optima correspond topeaks on an adaptive landscape; intersections of curves (surfaces) of conditionalminima, to r’alievs; and intersections of conditional maxima with minima, tosaddles.

Figure 1.5 shows the result of applYing this approach to a two-stage lifehistory in which there is a single juvenile age class followed by an infinite numberof adult age classes wherein individuals survive with constant probability fromone year to the next. I Four examples, corresponding to each of the single classmodels of Figure 1.2, are given. In each case, the thick white lines are curvesof conditional optima F (F ) md L (Fr) and the thin w bit lines are ui yesof conditional minima, E5 (F) and E,1 (F1). In addition, reproductive effortpairs, (F1, F0), are color-coded according to fitness value as indicated by thedifhrent shades of gray. Color versions of Figures 1 .5—1.7 and 1 .9 are postedat http://www.oup-usa.org/sc/0l9514385X and at http://biil.srnr.arizona.edu,whereat ancillary material including an animation is also available. In FigureI .5a, we consider accelerating dependencies of effective fecundity and postreproductive survival on reproductive effort. In this case, there is a single globalminimum in fitness with the conseqOence that optimal life histories, lE1,

= (0.0). (0. 1), and so on, are all boundary solutions corresponding to zeroreproduction or the maximum possible reproduction at the diffhrent age classes.In Figure 1 Sb, we consider decelerating dependencies of fecundity and survival(in reproductive effort. Here, there is a single, interior maximum in fitness.Figures 1 Sc and I 3d treat cases in which effective fecundity and post-reproductive survival are more complex. Here, the fitness landscapes evidencemLiltiple peaks and valleys.

As further discussed in the following section, studying curves of conditionaloptima allows one to think more clearly about the evolution of life histories as awhole. In particular, this approach facilitates the elaboration of falsifiablepredictions regarding the selective consequences of changing environmentalcircumstances affecting reproduction, growth, and survival.

1.9. Optimal Age of First Reproduction

One consequence of the theory is that it generates predictions regarding theoptimal age of first reproduction, a character more readily quantified thansmall variations in reproductive expenditure. In this regard, recall that wheneffective fecundity functions are sigmoidal (Figure 1 .2c), there can he twovalues of reproductive effort corresponding to local maxima in Sf1. Of these,one is always zero, in which case, the organisms don’t reproduce, while thesecond is often intermediate between 0 and 100%. In such cases, factors thatincrease optimal reproductive expenditure within an age class also act tolower the optimal age of first reproduction. Conversely, factors that reduceoptimal expenditure within age classes favor delays in the onset of breeding.Computations illustrating these effects for the two—stage life history studied

HgUre 1.5 Adaptive topographies and optimal reproductive expenditures in a two-d.Ce ijuvenile-’adult) life history. The coordinate axes. P. and F,,, are juvenile andsloE reproductive effort. Reproductive effort pairs. (F,, F,), are color coded by‘ep%.). TFe thick white lint’s are curves of conditional optii;ia, i%fE,) and g,,*f,]

ehereon I is maximized. The thin white lines are curves of conditional Ouui,fla

vhereon is minimized. Color versions of these hgures are posted at http://ww.oup-usa.org/sc/( 11 P5] 43S5X and at http://hili/srnr.arizona.edu. whereat ancillary

:i,,iterial is also available, a. The effective fecundity and post-reproductive survivaltnctions are oeceleroting functions of reproductive effort as in Figure 1 .2a. In thisN:. tnere iS a single global ni uiniuiil in fitness and m ultiple’ optimal life histories.In’ latter correspond to zero or I oD’;’h reproduction at each age. b. The effective

tes undity and post-reproductive survival functions are lecelerating functions of reproductive effort as in Figure 1 .2h. Here, there is a single global maximum in fitness. c.Fffi’ctive fecundity is a sigmoid function of effort; post-reproductive survival declineslinearly as in Figure 1 .2c. In this case, there are two prominent adaptive peaks, thetaller of which corresponds to no reproduction by juveniles and high effort by adults,sI, Effective fecundity is a linear function of effort; post-reproductive survival, areverse sigmoid as in Figure 1 .2d. Effective fecundity and post-reproductive survivaljunctions as in Figure 1.2.

Figure 1,5 (but with the added possibility of year-to-year increases inlective fecundity among adults) are given in Figures 1.6 and 1.7. Figure

documents the fecundity effect. With increasing fecundity per unit

-‘ceenditure in both stages ol the life cycle, the optimal life history can

Page 10: Life Histories, Evolution, is · LIFE HISTORIES, EVOLUTION, AND SALMONIDS 23 which case, A. is the rate at which the population ultimately multiplies.8 It is this final fact that

33 EVOLUTION ILLUMINATED: SALMON AND THEIR RELATIVES LIFE HISTORIES, EVOLUTION, AND SALMONIDS 39

Figure 16. Effective fecundity effect, Changing adaptive topographies and optimalreproductive expenditures in response to increasing fecundity potential (effectivefecundity per unit effort) in a tsvo-stage life history. Curves of conditional optimaand minima and reproductive effort pairs, (E,, Ej, color coded as in Figure 1.5.Color versions of these figures are posted at http://www.oup-usa.org/sc/019514385Xand at http://bill/srnr.arizona.edu, whereat ancillary material is also available. Lifehistory functions, B(E) and p,(F) as in Figure ] .2c (fecundity a sigmoidal functionof effort: post-reproductive survival, a linear function with ‘r, = 0.8; ra = 0.9). Post-reproductive growth function, g,(E) = 1 + y(l — Ei), with y = = 2.0. a.

= 0.5. b. fi, = = 2.0; c. /1j = 3.0; d. fi, = = 5.0. With fecundityper unit effort low, juveniles should not reproduce. As potential fecundity increases,the optimal life history shifts to one in which reproductive effort is high at bothstages in the life cycle.

shift from one in which only adults reproduce to one in which both ageclasses manifest high expenditures. Figure 1.7 documents the effect ofincreasing the rate—again, in both life cycle stages—at which fecundity multiplies from one age to the next. Here, the shift is in the opposite direction:increasing this rate selects for delayed reproduction. To complete the story,we note that increasing post-reproductive survival per unit expenditure alsoselects for delayed reproduction (not shown).

Figure 1.7. Post-reproductive growth rate effect. Changing adaptive topographies andoptimal reproductive expenditures in response to increasing post-reproductive growthpotential in a two-stage life history. Curves of conditional optima and minima andreproductive effort pairs, (Ei, E,,), color coded as in Figure 1.5. Color versions of

these figures are posted at http://svsvw.oup-usa.org/sc/0 1951 4385X and at http:XYhill/srnr.arizona.edu, whereat ancillary material is also available. life history functions, BdE,)and f.E,) as in Figure l.2c with , = -= 1.5 and 9. = 0.8: -r,, = 0.9. Post-reproductivegrowth function, g(E,), as in Figure l.. a. = = ((.0. b. = y,, 0.5; c.y, = = 1.0; d. y = = 2.0. For low grosvth potential, the optimal life history corre.sponds to large reproductive expenditures by juveniles and adults. With increasinggrowth potential, the optimal life history shifts to one in which the onset of reproduction is delayed, that is, juveniles nn longer reproduce.

As discussed, for example, by Roff (1992) and Stearns (1977, 1992), the theory

as here elaborated ignores a great deal of biological detail. Rather than reviewthis material, I here focus on the following, more fundamental deficiencies:

1. Insufficiency of reproductive effort as a descriptor of allocation. Use of asingle set of control variables, E = [E1 ,], ignores the fact that thereare multiple functions to which resources can he allocated. For example,in modeling plant life histot ies it is useful to distinguish allocation to

2. Limitations

Page 11: Life Histories, Evolution, is · LIFE HISTORIES, EVOLUTION, AND SALMONIDS 23 which case, A. is the rate at which the population ultimately multiplies.8 It is this final fact that

40 EVOLUTiON ILLUMINATED: SALMON AND THEIR RELATIVES

reproduction, growth, and storage (Schaffer et al. 1982; Chiariello andRoughgarden 1983; Schaffer 1983). In short, the E, in Equations (7) and(8) should really be E11, where the second subscript refers to the physiological function targeted.

2. Insufficiency of reproductive effort as a descriptor of reproductive style.This is an extension of #1, the point being that energy allocated to reproduction can itself be partitioned in various ways. We have already alludedto this fact in reviewing the functional dependence of fecundity on effort.Thus, in many species, one wants to distinguish energy expended ondifferent aspects of reproduction, for instance, to distinguish mate competition from the actual production of offspring, the cost of birthing,from post-partern parental care, and so on.

3. Total effort versus effort per offspring. This is a further extension of# 1.Most organisms produce multiple young, with the consequence thatselection can act on both the effort expended per offspring and thetotal effort. ‘ In the absence of age structure, this leads to

?4E. ci = Bt. e) ±g(E)p(E) t6c)

where E is total reproductive effort, and e is the caloric expenditure peroffspring. With E held constant, maximizing ?.(E,e) collapses to the

clutch size problem” as it was studied in the I 950s and 60s by DavidLack (19661 and his associates. In this case, and with a cap on juvenile

survival, c(e), the optimal expenditure per offspring, e, is the value of eat which c(e) is tangent to the line,

c=ek (ID

of greatest k as shown in Figure 1 Sa. This so-called marginal valuesolution” (Charnov 1976) was proposed independently by Smith andFretwell (1974) and Shaffer and (dadgil (1975). The latter authorsalso considered the war in which competition among juveniles selectsfor increased parental expenditure. What happens if we allow bothexpenditures, that is, total and per offsprmg, to varvZ One answer isshown in Figure 1.8 wherein we assume that offspring survival dependsonly on e. Then the optimal effort per offspring, e’, is independent of thetotal expenditure. On the other hand, the optimal total expenditure,E5(e), depends on e. In particular, E(e) rises and falls as shown in thefigure, and, in fact, is maximal when e -= e. There is no mystery to this:e’ maximizes effective fecundity, B(E,e), aiad, so long as post-reproductive survival depends only on the total expenditure, the consequence ofsetting e = e’ is to maximize ff(e.

As discussed by Parker and Begon (1986), McGinlev (1989), andHendry and Day (2003), more complex dependencies result when juvenile survival depends not only on effort per offspring hut also on the total

u,.L

ENe)

L_li_NJ

Figure 1 .8. Evlutinof ‘ff,rt i/er offsprine. ,‘and the joint evolution of total effort, E.and ,‘. a. Optin 11 value, a’. of ,‘ is that for svhih uvenile turvival, p,’i, is tangent t’’ thestraght line, c ri’, of in’eat,”st Ic h. Covariation of effdrt per offipring and total repro

ye xendii ore. Because ,‘ oavin’, izes effective ida’. inditv, the optimal total es penditore, E(eJ, is maxirria) at ,‘ — e, For these alco1atioi’,s. s’ hich are purely illustrative, it is

1 rrd th it (, I — r, < ear ii — 1/r i, r stith o __ (1 2 and — 1

number o1 offsprini’ produced. For additional discussion on such. mattersin the context ol siilmonids, see Finum et al. 12(i03—tli;a i’oirtme).

4. Insufficiency of age as a descriptor of potential reproduction, growth,and survival. Especially in organisms with indeterminate growth. size isoften of equal, if not greater, importance than age in determining components of fitness. If size is the principal determinant, one can replaceEquation (1) with th.e corresponding equation that describes the growthof a population in svhich individuals are categorized by size or “stage.” Ifboth factors are important, an ‘ age by stage•’ description is required.

5. Dose—response relations, In many species. patterns of reprodutiveexpenditure depend on euvironmental circumstance. In such cases,what is selected among is not a set of age-specific reproductive efforts,

hut rather a set of ‘‘dose—response relations, the ‘dose being the environmental state, often as reflected iw the organism’s size or condition, andthe “response,” the age-specific expenditure. Such relationships—-alsocalled “norms of reaction” (Hutchings 2003—this volume)_vary

LIFEHISTORIES EVOLUTION ANDSALMONIDS 41

1L1EEne)

Page 12: Life Histories, Evolution, is · LIFE HISTORIES, EVOLUTION, AND SALMONIDS 23 which case, A. is the rate at which the population ultimately multiplies.8 It is this final fact that

42 EVOLUTION ILLUMINATED: SALMON AND THEIR RELATIVES LIFE HISTORIES, EVOLUTION, AND SALMONIDS 43

between and within species. For example, some desert birds (these notesare being written in Tucson, Arizona) are notoriously flexible with regardto the onset of breeding, in which regard they are influenced by variationsin rainfall. Other species respond primarily to photoperiod and arelocked into fixed breeding seasons. Likewise, a positive correlationbetween pre-reproductive growth rates and the age of first reproductionis widely observed in both plants (Harper 1977) and animals (Aim 1959).

6. Insensitivity of fitness to variations in allocation. As usually articulated,life history theory makes no reference to the expected degree of dispersion about a putative optimum. In fact, one expects that the selectivepressures that mold life histories in nature are often minuscule, that is,adaptive topographies of the sort shown in Figures 1.5—1.7 will he quiteflat. In this case, finite population effects guarantee that real-world populations will be suboptimal. The question then becomes not whethernatural populations exhibit optimal behavior—they won’t—hut ratherthe degree to which deviations from optimality preclude validation ofthe theory. See also Finum et al. (2003—this volume).

7. Life history evolution and nonlinear population dynamics. The theoryreviewed here antedates the realization (May 1976; Schaffer 1985) thatecological populations can manifest complex dynamics independent ofenvironmental fluctuations. With regard to life history evolution, non

linearity introduces the twist of deterministic fluctuations in populationdensity and, hence, selective pressures which, over the short term, arepredictable. There is also the contrapuntal issue as to the consequences topopulation dynamics of variations in life history.

3. The Theory Applied to Atlantic Salmon

3.1. Age of First Spawning

As discussed by Stearns and Hendrv (2003—this volume), salmonid life historiesmake interesting grist for the theorist’s mill. As a graduate student, I deducedpredictions regarding the effects of environmental factors expected to influencethe optimal (sea) age of first reproduction in anadromous North AmericanAtlantic salmon. The predictions were tested by comparison with data fromover 100 stocks obtained from, or with the assistance of, what was then theFisheries Research Board of Canada. In particular, I considered the selectiveconsequences of the following environmental factors: (a) the energetic demandsof the upstream migration as indexed by river length; (b} the rate at which fishfrom different rivers gain weight in the ocean after their first summer at sea; and(c) the intensity of coastal and estuarine fishing as indexed by the numbers ofcommercial nets.

Because angling statistics were the principal source of data for most rivers, Irelied largely on the mean weight of angled fish as a proxy variable for the age offirst return. So long as the frequency of repeat spawners is low (generally true),

this procedure is wholly defensible (see Table I of Schaffer and Elson 1975), theincrease in weight resulting from each additional summer at sea being largecompared to variations in weight among fish of the same (sea) age.

With regard to these factors, it was predicted that the optimal age of firstspawning should (a) increase with river length—because increased energeticdemands of migration depress effective fecundity per unit reproductive effort;1’(h) increase with ocean growth rate—because this increases residual reproductive value per unit expenditure; and (c) decrease with the intensity of commercial fishing—because larger (= older) fish are more likely to be trapped thansmaller (= younger) individuals.2021

To confirm that these predictions do, in fact, derive from the theory, werefer hack to the two-stage life history model of the preceding section. In thecontext of Atlantic salmon, think of these equations as modeling the adult (postsmolt) phase of the life cycle with everything that goes on in the river and duringthe first summer at sea being collapsed into the effective fecundity Function ofthe first age class.. In this spirit, we view the “juvenile” age class as “grilse,” fishthat spend a single summer in the ocean before returning to the river, and the‘‘adult” age classes as “salmon,” fish that spend two or more summers at seabefore spawning.

Figure 1 .6 addresses the river length effect on assumption that the moredemanding the swim upstream, the greater the fraction of reproductive effort(sensu lato) that must be allocated to migration as opposed to reproduction perse. With migratory costs high (long rivers), fecundity per unit effort is reducedand fitness maximized by one sea-year fish not returning to spawn (Figures 1 .6aand 1 .6b). Conversely, with migratory costs low, fecundity per unit effort is highand selection favors reproduction by both age classes (Figures 1 .6c and I .6d).

Figure 1.7 addresses the ocean growth rate effect. Here the rate at whichfecundity can increase from one year to the next, that is, the growth function,g1(E), is varied. For low rates of post-reproductive growth potential, reproduction by both age classes is favored (Figures 1 .7a, I .7h). For higher values of thisfunction, an optimal life history is one in which only ‘salmon” reproduce(Figures l.7c, l.7d).

Finally, in Figure 1.9, we study the selective consequences of commercialfishing. Since commercial gear preferentially removes larger individuals, wemodel the effect of coastal and estuarine fishing by reducing both the effectivefecundity and post-reproductive survival functions of older individuals, The notunexpected result is a shift from life histories in which one sea-year fish do notreproduce (Figures 1 .9a, I .9b) to those in which they do (Figures 1 .9c, I .9d).

To varying degrees, all three predictions were supported by the data. Theresults of subsequent studies (Thorpe and Mitchell 1981; Scarnecchia 1983;Fleming and Gross 1989; Myers and Hutchings 1987a; N . Jonsson et al.I ‘-9 I a; L’Ahée-Lund 1991; Hutchings and Jones 1998) of S. solar and othera1monids, however, were mixed. The follow-up investigations focused principally on the first prediction (but see Myers and Hutchings l987a; Hutchings and1’nes 1998), that is., on the effect of increasing costs of migration imposed asodexed by length of the river or mean annual discharge. This is something of a

Page 13: Life Histories, Evolution, is · LIFE HISTORIES, EVOLUTION, AND SALMONIDS 23 which case, A. is the rate at which the population ultimately multiplies.8 It is this final fact that

44 EVOLUTION ILLUMINATED, SALMON ANDTHEIR RELATIVES LI FE HISTORIES, EVOLUTION. AND SALMON IDS 45

pity, inasmuch as the original analysis suggested that river length effects aresubject to masking or accentuation by the other variables.22 In particular, riverlength, while strongly correlated with delayed reproduction in some regions(Baie de Chaleur, North Shore of the Gulf of St. Lawrence), evidenced nosuch relationship in others (New Brunswick and Newfoundland) In discussion,BIson and I suggested that this variation might reflect regional differences incommercial fishing pressure, and rowth rates in the ocean. \Vith regard tothe latter point, populations 1rorn reDions manifesting a significant effect of riverlength also the highest post—griisc growth rate.s at sea, a finding sub—scquentlv confirmed by I lutehings and Jones (1998) in a study notable for itsinclusion of data Irons both European and North American stocks. Such synergy

is, in fact, to he expected, that is, if fish grow less rapidly at sea, the benefits ofpostponing reproduction are diminished.

3.2. Variation in inter-spawning Intervals

One of the patterns reported by Schaffer and Elson (1975) was the observation(their Figure 7) that interspawning intervals, that is, the number of summersspent at sea between migrations into freshwater, was positively correlated withthe mean age of first return. This finding was subsequently confirmed forNorwegian Atlantic salmon by N. Jonsson Ct al. (1991 a) who ascribed it tothe fact that larger (= older) fish require a longer period of ocean feeding tomend.24 The twist that life history theory brings to the discussion is that factors(reduced fecundity per unit effort, increased post-reproductive growth rate) thatselect for delayed reproduction should also select for increasing intervalsbetween reproductive episodes.

3.3. Life in the River

Contemporary science being the collective endeavor that it is, graduate studentsembarking upon what they believe to he a novel course of investigation often(and to their not inconsiderable chagrin) discover as their work progresses thatthey are hot alone. In ms own case, a thesis (Schiefer 1971) relating heightenedfreshwater growth rates among parr to increased rates of pre—migratorv sexualmaturation and early return from the sea was submitted to the University ofWaterloo even as I worked to complete trw own dissertation. These observationswere in accord with the widely held belief (I-luntsman 1939) that growth rates infresh water are an important determinant of the period salmon spend at seabefore returning to the river. They are also consistent with the theory elaboratedabove: greater pu-reproductive growth rates increase fecundity per unit investment for all age classes and thereby lavor increased reproductive expenditureand an earlier age of first spawning. This point was first made in the paper withElson. Later (Sr haIler I 979a), I extended the argument by considering a modelin which river and ocean stages of salmonid life histories were explicitly distinguished. The latter analysis further predicts that the age at which young salmongo to sea should vary inversely with growth rates in the river, which prediction isconsistent with the observation that the age of ocean-hound smolts increaseswith latitude (Power 1969; Schaffer and Elson 1975).

14, Males versus Females

One of the more interesting discussions in the salmonid life history literature(see Gross 1996; Fleming and Reynolds 2003-—-tliis i’olitnie; Hutchings 2003—this i’olume) revolves about the adaptive significance of precocious maturation bymale parr. This phenomenon appears to reflect the fact that parr can slip pastterritorial adult males and fertilize some fraction of the female’s eggs (Jones1959; Fleming and Gross 1994). That comparable forces may also be at work

Fgure 1 g Commercial tish,’rv ,“fTSct. Chanin adaptive topographies and optimalreproductive expenditures in response to increasinU eunim ercial fishing pressure as

modeled Iw reductions in Ic r’ nditv and post—reproductive survival per unit effort

among adults in the Lwo-uaee life history model of Figures 1.5—1 .7. Curses ofconditional optima and minima and reproductive effort pair’.. (L.. E,), color coderl

as in Fiure I 5. Color scroons oi these nDures are post’d at http:/Cssswoupusaorg/seu 1951 4355X and .it b.ttp ,/hili’srnr.irizona edu. whereat ancillary material

als( J iiiaL I I I t I ii ‘ ri / IF I I 1 /1 1 n I ian& I A with p1.0 and x, = 0.5 Post-rep,.’ Active growth function, gLl, as in Figure 1,7 with

/ y=20a fl=lo =ii b/=Oh r_0-D / =04 r,=O22

N 0.2; 7t,, = 0.1125. Diminishing adult components of fitness lowers the optimal age of first reproduction.

Page 14: Life Histories, Evolution, is · LIFE HISTORIES, EVOLUTION, AND SALMONIDS 23 which case, A. is the rate at which the population ultimately multiplies.8 It is this final fact that

46 EVOLUTION ILLUMINATED SALMON AND THEIR RELATIVES LIFE HISTORIES, EVOLUTION. AND SALMONIDS 47

among adult fish is suggested by the fact that, even though the mean age ofreturning adults varies from river to river, the average sea age of returningmales is almost invariably less than that of returning females (Schaffer 1979a).

4. Pacific Salmon Versus Atlantic Salmon and Trout

Although post-spawning mortality approaches 100% in some populations of S.salar, there are other populations in which multiple returns to the river are thenorm, and it is not unheard of for individuals to reproduce five times or more(Ducharme 1960). This is in contrast to Pacific salmon in which anadromousindividuals are ohligately semelparous. During the upstream migration,apparently irreversible changes occur (Neave 1958; Foerster 1968; Groot andMargolis 1 991): individuals stop feeding; the digestive tract is resorbed; and thejaws, especially in males, elongate to form a fearsome kype (Fleming andReynolds 2003—this volume). In some species, males also develop a pronounced

hump and there is the acquisition, to varying degrees depending on species, ofcharacteristically gaudy spawning culors in both sexes. In thinking about theadaptive significance of these changes, I was first drawn to images of indomitablesockeye salmon fighting their way a thousand miles inland as they traverse rivers

such as the Snake and Columbia in western North America. Under such circum

stances, one can well imagine effective fecundity functions of the sort shown inFigure 1 ,2a, with anything less than a maximum effort resulting in the individual’s death befru’ it reaches the spawning grounds. Further reflection, however,

suggests that such considerations do not explain the origin of semelparity in this

group.In the first place, anadromous rainbow trout or steelhead (0. mvl..’iss),

cohabit the same river systems and, in some cases, make the same gruelingupstream migrations. Yet this species, like 5, salar, with which it was previously

grouped as S. gairdneri, is iteroparous. It follows that, if the adaptive significanceof semelparitv in Oncorliviichus relates to the rigors of migration, one mustconfront the fact that these factors, while operative on the ancestors of contem

porary Pacific salmon, had no. 5u(l effect on the line leading to steelhead.In addition. many Pacific salmon, br example, silver (coho) salmon inCalifornia, spawn in short, coastal streams (Shapovalov and ‘Taft 1954). For

these populations, getting back out to sea would seem to he no more of aproblem than it is for multiple spa\vning S. solar in the rivers of southeastern

Canada. Similarly, landlocked populations of Oncorhvnc/ius generally undertakelittle in the wa of spawning migrations. Yet, like their anadrornous cousins,these populations are semelparous. In short, the distribution of reproductiveand migratory habit suggests that the evolution of semelparity in

Oncorhvnchus is unrelated to migratory stress. This forces us to look to other

possible explanations. Among them, are the following:

1. Semelpanity in contemporary Oncorhvnchus is maladaptive, having beenretained only because the ability to re-evolve repeated reproduction has

been lost (Crespi and Teo 2002). This is the “hen’s tooth” explanation.It holds that big bang reproduction in extant populations is reflective ofselective regimes past. In this case, migratory stress may, indeed, havebeen the critical factor in the evolution of semelparity, but the ability tore-evolve the iteroparous habit was subsequently lost. This hypothesisraises the fascinating question as to whether or not heretofore unreportedvestiges of Oncorhvnchus’ iteroparous heritage persist in extant populations of the Japanese species, 0. mason and 0. rliodurus, which aregenerally held (Neave 1958; Stearley and Smith 1993; McKay et al.

1996; Oakley and Phillips 1999; Osinov and Lebedev 2000; Kinnisonand Hendry 2003—this volume) to be primitive for the group.

2. Semelparitv and iteroparity in salmonids represent multiple optima inallocation schedules (Schaffer l979a). According to this, both strategiesare adaptive, that is, they correspond to alternative adaptive peaks in thehere and now. The advantage of this explanation is that, with effectivefecundity functions as in Figure 1 .2d, alternative optima corresponding toiteroparous and semelparous reproduction are predicted. The problem isthat with so many populations isolated to varying degrees by thetendency of individuals to return to the waters of their birth (Hendrvet al. 2003a—this volume), one expects at least occasional jumps fromone adaptive peak to the other. In short, the hypothesis of alternativeevolutionary’ optima in contemporary populations is inconsistent withthe phylogenetic distribution of parity modes.

3. Semelparity in Oncorhyiwhus is adaptive by virtue of the acquisition oftraits that increase effective fecundity per unit effort, thereby selectingfor increased effort (Crespi and Teo 2002). Recently this idea wasadvanced by Crespi and Teo (2002), who conjectured that increasedegg size in Oncorhynchus, to the extent that it serves to increase effectivefecundity, may have selected for greater reproductive expenditure. Thequestion left unanswered is whether or not the effect would be sufficientto drive optimal levels of expenditure to the maximum. More precisely,increasing juvenile survival does not make for concavity in the effectivefecundity function.

4. Semelparity in Oncorhynchus is adaptive by virtue of the acquisition oftraits that make post-reproductive survival unlikely regardless of reproductive expenditure (Crespi and Teo 2002). Such traits would makefor concave dependencies of residual reproductive value on currentreproductive expenditure (Figure 1.2), thereby increasing the likelihoodof selection for maximum reproductive expenditure. In this regard,Crespi and Teo (2002) suggest that Pacific salmon are characterizedby more extensive ocean foraging than Atlantic salmon and trout, andthat this would likely act to reduce post-reproductive survival. Analternative hypothesis, for which there is currently no evidence, isthat physiological innovations in Pacific salmon may preclude post-spawning resumption of a saltwater existence. On the face of it, thishypothesis would seem to stumble on the fact that immature Pacific

Page 15: Life Histories, Evolution, is · LIFE HISTORIES, EVOLUTION, AND SALMONIDS 23 which case, A. is the rate at which the population ultimately multiplies.8 It is this final fact that

48 EVOLUTION ILLUMI NATED: SALMON AND THEIR RELATIVES LIFE HISTORIES, EVOLUTION, AND SALMONIDS 49

salmon make the transition to marine environments as a matter ofcourse. Still, experience teaches that the loss of plasticity with age isa common feature of biological systems,

5. Seinelparitv in Oncorhvnchus is adaptive by virtue of the acquisition oftraits that make For accelerating dependencies of effective fecundity onreproductive expenditure, independent of the costs of migration intofresh water (Willson 1997; Crespi and Teo 2002). This possibility isdiscussed by Willson (1997) and Crespi and Teo (2002), who emphasizethe importance of competition for mates among males and nesting sitesamong females who further defend their eggs after fertilization. Amongsalmonids, these traits appear to be most highly developed in Pacificsalmon, suggesting that semelparity in these species is essentially a consequence of sexual selection (Fleming and Reynolds 2003—this volume).

Of these five possibilities, which are not mutually exclusive, it is the last thatis arguably the most intriguing. In the first place, intraspecific competition provides a mechanism that can keep driving populations toward higher and higherlevels of reproductive investment, in effect manufacturing accelerating fecunditycurves (Figure 1 .2a) along the way. This is because reproductive success in suchcircumstances is a function of an individual’s relative (as opposed to absolute)expenditure. Second, this hypothesis is consistent with the exaggerated secondmv sexual characters (kvpe, hump, and gaudy spawning colors) which distinguish semelparous Oncorlivuchus as a group. It further suggests a tie—in with theobservation that semelparous salmonids generally breed under higher densitiesthan their iteroparous allies, Specifically, high densities of spawners favorincreased competition for mates and nesting sites, territorial defense of fertilizedeggs, and increased per offspring allocation by females in the form of larger eggs—which is to say, the innovations of which we have been speaking. So perhaps theproblem’s solution is already in our grasp. And perhaps not. For, as A. Hendryhas emphasized in correspondence, the situation is really quite complex, bothwith regard to the selective agents that may have triggered the process and thesequence in which traits were acquired. And of course, there is the not so minorconsideration that, viewed across the animal kingdom, sexual selection doesn’talways ‘‘run away.’’ In short, the matter remains niurkv, for which reason, thisessay concludes, not with an answer, hut with an open question As such, it is anappropriate way to end a prolegomenon, though clearly not so satisfying as beingable to trumpet “Problem solved7’ Maybe next time.

lck,ioele’dgnierts I stould like to dediLate this chapter to the memory of Paul F. Elsonand Robert 1-1. MacArthur, who helped me on my was’,

The ideas reviewed here reflect the tutelage of John Bonnr’r, Paul bIson, Henry Horn,Eghert Leigh, and Robert MacArthur, Mike Rosenzweig caught and helped repair a grievous error in my first attempt (Schaffer 1974a) to understand the life historical consequences of age structure. Characteristically, he suggested that we report the mistake andits correction together (Schaffer and Rosenzweig I 97) I am also grateful to contrihutorcto the present volume: Bernard Crespi, Andrew Hendrv, \lichael Kinnison, lom Quinn,and Eric Taylor, who kindly corresponded with me ahoLit salmonids and their evolution.

The work reviewed here was supported by Princeton University, the Universities of Utah

and Arizona, and the National Science Foundation. More important was the support I

received from my parents, Michael and Rose Schaffer, who gave mc my start, taught me to

distinguish right from wrong, and, in Dad’s case, insisted that I learn to write. Otherindividuals have also made a difference: That I remain intellectually active at what I

would have once considered an advanced age is due solely to Tatiana \“alentinovna,light of my life, with whom I am privileged to work and cohabit. That I hve had time

these past ten years for intellectual activity beyond the mind-numbing, day-to-day grind at

a university mired in mediocrity is due to the many teachers, trainers, and sitters who have

worked with ms son, Michael, or helped look after his interests. In particular, and with

apologies to those whose names I have forgotten, I thank Nancy Sergeant Abate. Rink and

Jack Campbell Judy Cowgill, Ben Duncan, Cindy C., Alex, Ned and Jamie Cittings,Sharon l-larrington, Linda Kuzman, Sherry Mulholland, Mary Ann Muratore, Steve

Nagy, Ralph Schmidt, Suzie Speelman, and Eddie Vanture. Michael himself gives mean

ing to life in ways that only a parent who’s “been there” can appreciate. G-d willing, he

will vet learn to read and comprehend these words.

Notes

I. Nova Scotia’s rivers themselves are short, gentle affairs,2. At the time, only semelparoos species (Pacific salmon) were assigned to

Oucorli\’ncIins (Neave I 9:S.3. This is an amended version of Levins’ 11966) “Principle of Optimality,” the

emendation being addition ot the word, ‘‘related.’’4. Struck down in his prime, MacArthur left the intellectual playing field, like the

runner of Housman’s poem, never having experienced defeat.5. For purposes of exposition, I suppose a time step of a year. and rther that the

population is censused annually, The numbers of individuals in the various age classes arethus the numbers alive at census time. By this accounting, the probability that an indivi

dual survives from birth to first census is absorbed by the 13’s. which become ‘‘effective

lhcundities,’’ Moreover, i,, necessarily equals 16. In some texts, the rate at which the population multiplies, A, is replaced by er,

thereby emphasizing the relation of Equation (I) to its continuous analog, I Zr’ J’ e l. nm div

(Fisher 1930), in which case, the rn’s are (no longer effective) fecundities.7. Recall that the magnitude of a complex number is the square root of’ the squares of

its real and imaginary parts added together, that is, if: r=x iy,j: = (. y 2I 2

S Equation (1) is the characteristic equation of the /inear growth process,

N(t + 1) ‘r A Np), where the N’s are vectors, the elements of which are the numbers

of individuals in the different age classes at times t and t + I, and A is the so-called“population projection” or “Leslie” matrix. Provided that A1 exceeds the other A’s inmagnitude, it follows that as t , Nit) c1 ;, N1 where c1 is a constant reflective of

the population’s initial age structure According to this, N1, which is an eigenvcctordefined by the relation AN = A . N . speciffcs the ‘‘stable age distribution.’’

9. For the reader uncomfortable with derivatives generally, and with partial deriva

tives in particular, we offer the following. lf the value of y depends on a second quantity,

x, the derivative, dv/dx, evaluated at x = is the rate at which y changes in response to a

vmall variation in x when ,v = x. If v depends on a number of quantities. say. me, x, and

then the paITial derivative. +iav, is the same rate of change, hut with the values of the

c’m.her variables fixed.

Page 16: Life Histories, Evolution, is · LIFE HISTORIES, EVOLUTION, AND SALMONIDS 23 which case, A. is the rate at which the population ultimately multiplies.8 It is this final fact that

50 EVOLUTION ILLUMINATED: SALMON AND THEIR RELATIVES LIFE HISTORIES, EVOLUTION. AND SALMONIDS 51

10. Equation (3) is the definition one finds in the textbooks and, as such, has perplexed generations of students, A more useful rendering of this expression can be had asfollows: Let p, be the probability of surviving from age i to i + 1, that is, p = /4 Nowmultiply the chicken scratches under the sum, that is, the terms following the

“ s,” bythe quantity in brackets outside it, Then Vi/V() = B/A1 +pB1/Af+pp÷1B+2/A+whence follows the verbal definition given above.

11. This result requires that varying reproductive effort at age i is without consequence to reproduction and survival at previous ages (Schaffer I 979b). On the face of it,this would seem always to he the case: time, after all, does not run backwards. In fact,there are instances when, so far as natural selection is concerned, the hand on the dialreally does turn counter-clockwise. Specifically, when there is extended parental care,resources expended on this year’s offspring can adversely affect the growth and survivalof their older siblings. This reduces the parents’ effective fecundity at previous ages.Similarly, if last year’s offspring fail to disperse, as in the case of organisms that propagate“vegetatively” (plants, corals, etc.), they may compete with this year’s progeny.

12. Equation (7) was misinterpreted (Schaffer 1981; Yodzis 1981) by Caswell (1980)who imagined the claim to be that the optimal expenditure at each age maximizes thereproductive value of all the age classes.

13. This is because E7, for example, depends on (vI/v) which, in turn, depends onand hence on all the E’s.

14. The set of optimal reproductive efforts, E*, were computed using a “downhillsimplex” algorithm (Press et al. 1992) to minimize (1/At). Note, however, that nothinghaving been proved, the proposed generality is purely conjectural.

15. With an infinite number of “adult” age classes, the stable age equation (1)becomes

= (B1 ± (A’aB,>/(). — Pa)

Here a is the age at which individuals achieve “adulthood,” while Ba and p,, are respectively adult fecundity and the probability of survival from one year to the next.

16. While the mathematics of senescence (Hamilton 1966) and life history evolutionare essentially equivalent, from a biological perspective the two topics are rather different.In the first case, one is concerned with adaptations that delay the onset of morbidity andmortality; in the latter, with the allocation of available resources to competing functions.

17. In terms of note 16, we consider the case in which a = 1.18. In fishes, an important determinant of effort per offspring is egg size. To first

order, the total caloric expenditure in females is thus n x e where n is the number of eggs.19, River length is, of course, but the crudest of measures of the cost of migration.

Subsequently, N. Jonsson et al. (1991 a) suggested that mean annual discharge is a betterindicator. For further discussion of migratory cost, see Hendry et al. (2003h—this volume)and references therein.

20. Obviously, if older fish are preferentially removed from the spawning run, themean age of returning fish will drop, a prediction fir which optimality theory is manifestlyunnecessary. In fact, what is being predicted is that the numbers of fish returning to spawnat an earls’ age, as indicated by census before they hit the nets, will increase. As discussed in(Schaffer and Elson 1975), this prediction is supported by increasing numbers of grilsetaken in a research trap on the N. W. Miramichi from 1961 to 1969.

21. For discussion of the many other consequences of human exploitation, see Young

(2003—this volume).22. There was also some confusion. For example, regarding our use of angling statis

tics (fish weight) as a proxy variable for the age of first spawning, Fleming and Gross(1989) and, to a lesser extent, N. Jonsson et al. (1991a), imagined that what was beingpredicted was variation in fish size per Se. Thus, the former authors reported as contradicting our results the observation that the size of returning female coho salmon variesinversely with river length. In fact, all of the fish in their studs’ spent the same number ofsummers at sea with the consequence that the reported variations in body size are irrelevant to the life historical predictions we were trying to test.

23. As noted above, commercial nets and weirs preferentially remove larger (= older)fish from the spawning run and therefore select for an early age of first spawning. In fact,there is evidence that this has happened. For example, in the case 0f the NorthwestMiramichi, the principal salmon river in New Brunswick, there is good reason(Hunstman 1939) to believe that the decades prior to those for which I was able to obtaindata witnessed dramatic declines in the abundance of 2- and 3-sea-year virgin fish. By wayof contrast, long-term angling records kept by the Moise Salmon Club (North Shore)indicate little change in the composition of the spawning run from 1930 to 197(1(Schiefer 1971).

24. My own take on this was to emphasize the fact that increased interspawningintervals were associated with increased losses in growth due to spawning which, in

turn, correlated with increased migratory costs as evidenced by river length. Supportingthis interpretation is the observation by N. Jonsson et al. (l991a) that post-spawningsurvival declines with the age of first return.

25. In what follows, I use the term “semelparity” to refer to the obligate demise ofpost-spawning adults, i.e., fish which have gone to sea and then returned to brackish orfresh water. This usage reflects the observation that, as in S. solar, male juvenile Pacificsalmon can reproduce more than once as parr (Unwin etal. 1999) and further that somePacific salmon returning to spawn have previously reproduced as parr (Tsiger etal. 1994).There may be occasional exceptions. For instance, Ricker (1972) cites published reports ofpurportedly “mending,” that is, post-spawning chinook (C). tshawytscha) adults taken insalt water.