Judicial Declaration of Public Policy

19
The Journal of Appellate Practice and Process The Journal of Appellate Practice and Process Volume 10 Issue 2 Article 2 2009 Judicial Declaration of Public Policy Judicial Declaration of Public Policy Ruggero J. Aldisert Follow this and additional works at: https://lawrepository.ualr.edu/appellatepracticeprocess Part of the Jurisprudence Commons, Law and Society Commons, and the Rule of Law Commons Recommended Citation Recommended Citation Ruggero J. Aldisert, Judicial Declaration of Public Policy, 10 J. APP. PRAC. & PROCESS 229 (2009). Available at: https://lawrepository.ualr.edu/appellatepracticeprocess/vol10/iss2/2 This document is brought to you for free and open access by Bowen Law Repository: Scholarship & Archives. It has been accepted for inclusion in The Journal of Appellate Practice and Process by an authorized administrator of Bowen Law Repository: Scholarship & Archives. For more information, please contact [email protected].

Transcript of Judicial Declaration of Public Policy

Page 1: Judicial Declaration of Public Policy

The Journal of Appellate Practice and Process The Journal of Appellate Practice and Process

Volume 10 Issue 2 Article 2

2009

Judicial Declaration of Public Policy Judicial Declaration of Public Policy

Ruggero J. Aldisert

Follow this and additional works at: https://lawrepository.ualr.edu/appellatepracticeprocess

Part of the Jurisprudence Commons, Law and Society Commons, and the Rule of Law Commons

Recommended Citation Recommended Citation Ruggero J. Aldisert, Judicial Declaration of Public Policy, 10 J. APP. PRAC. & PROCESS 229 (2009). Available at: https://lawrepository.ualr.edu/appellatepracticeprocess/vol10/iss2/2

This document is brought to you for free and open access by Bowen Law Repository: Scholarship & Archives. It has been accepted for inclusion in The Journal of Appellate Practice and Process by an authorized administrator of Bowen Law Repository: Scholarship & Archives. For more information, please contact [email protected].

Page 2: Judicial Declaration of Public Policy

THE JOURNAL OFAPPELLATE PRACTICE

AND PROCESSESSAY

JUDICIAL DECLARATION OF PUBLIC POLICY*

Ruggero J. Aldisert**

I. INTRODUCTION

I have been writing judicial opinions for fifty years: since1969 as a federal appellate judge on the Third Circuit, and foreight r ears before that on the Pennsylvania Court of CommonPleas. For nearly forty years of that time, I have offered myadvice as an expert opinion writer to other judges in opinion-

*Adapted from Ruggero J. Aldisert, Opinion Writing ch. 4 (2d ed., AuthorHouse 2009).The reader should be aware that both Opinion Writing and this article draw on material firstpublished in Ruggero J. Aldisert, The Role of Courts in Contemporary Society, 38 U. Pitt.L. Rev. 437 (1977) and Ruggero J. Aldisert, Philosophy, Jurisprudence andJurisprudential Temperament of Federal Judges, 20 Ind. L. Rev. 453 (1987).**Senior United States Circuit Judge, Chief Judge Emeritus, United States Court ofAppeals for the Third Circuit, whose books include Opinion Writing, 2d Ed. (AuthorHouse2009); The Judicial Process: Text, Materials & Cases (2d ed., West Pub. Co. 1996); Logicfor Lawyers: A Guide to Clear Legal Thinking (3d ed., Natl. Inst. for Trial Advocacy1997); Winning on Appeal: Better Briefs and Oral Argument (2d ed., Natl. Inst. for TrialAdvocacy 2003); Road to the Robes: A Federal Judge Recollects Young Years & EarlyTimes (AuthorHouse 2005). Many thanks to my 2008-2009 law clerks Meehan Rasch andMatthew P. Bartlett for their help in preparing this Essay, as well as for their invaluableassistance, along with my 2007-2008 clerks Rita K. Lomio and Anika Christine Stucky, inediting Opinion Writing, 2d Ed.

1. The Pennsylvania Supreme Court required trial judges to write an opinion in everycase that was appealed; to play it safe, I wrote an opinion in every final judgment.

THE JOURNAL OF APPELLATE PRACTICE AND PROCESS Vol. 10, No. 2 (Fall 2009)

Page 3: Judicial Declaration of Public Policy

230 THE JOURNAL OF APPELLATE PRACTICE AND PROCESS

writing seminars and through my book Opinion Writing,2 whichfor many years was distributed free of charge to all federal trialand appellate judges, and to all state appellate judges, when theytook the bench. Over the past year, as I have revised andprepared Opinion Writing, 2d Ed. for availability to a wideraudience, I have endeavored to provide my best practicalguidance on the nuts and bolts of opinion writing, style, andstructure, as well as on the judicial decisionmaking process andthe theoretical underpinnings of opinion writing. I haveencouraged opinion writers to keep their readers in mind as theywrite, and have advised opinion readers on how better to

4understand the opinion-writing process. However, nocomprehensive discussion of opinion writing theory can becomplete without a discussion of judicially declared publicpolicy.

Recent criticism of judges-whether as lawmakers or asinterpreters of constitutional or statutory text-has beenparticularly strong when they base decisions on considerationsof public policy. Such decisions generate controversy ongrounds both political and institutional. Public policy issuesmore readily inspire the familiar labels of "liberal,""conservative," "strict constructionist," or "a Bork-type." Theyprovoke criticism from social, economic, and politicalperspectives. Some critics argue from an institutionalperspective, contending that articulating policies for the publicinterest is the task of state and national legislatures rather thanfederal or state judiciaries. Depending upon the viewpoint of thecritic, judges who seek to advance the common good expresslythrough policymaking are pilloried as either "activists" or"traditionalists." This controversial aspect of judicialresponsibilities demonstrates the interplay among the

2. Ruggero J. Aldisert, Opinion Writing (West 1990) [hereinafter Opinion Writing1990]. The first edition of Opinion Writing was not made available to the general public.

3. I was commissioned by West Publishing to write Opinion Writing 1990 as anexpansion of discussions held at the Senior Judge Seminars sponsored by the Institute ofJudicial Administration at New York University in 1970-1971, 1973-1982, and 1985. Itreflected, also, ideas discussed in opinion writing seminars I taught for newly appointedjudges at the Federal Judicial Center in 1974-1980 and 1982.

4. See Ruggero J. Aldisert, Meehan Rasch & Matthew P. Bartlett, Opinion Writingand Opinion Readers, 31 Cardozo L. Rev. 1 (2009).

Page 4: Judicial Declaration of Public Policy

JUDICIAL DECLARATION OF PUBLIC POLICY

components of the trichotomy of legal philosophy,jurisprudence, and jurisprudential temperament.

II. OVERVIEW OF JUDICIAL DECLARATION OF PUBLIC POLICY

Roger J. Traynor admonished us not to "be misled by thehalf-truth that policy is a matter for [only] the legislators todecide."5 The courts are continually called upon to weighconsiderations of public policy when adding to the content of thecommon law, when filling in statutory gaps left by aninattentive, divided, or politically sensitive legislature, and whenapplying constitutional precepts to changing and novelcircumstances. In all these aspects of the judicial process,considerations of public policy may be compelling or evendecisive. David A. J. Richards emphasized the same point,noting that policy considerations underpin even the thresholddoctrines of justiciability:

[T]he proper ends of adjudication surely at least sometimesinclude policies. For example, the many discretionary rulesof standing, ripeness, mootness, and the like clearly rest inpart on policies of conserving judicial resources, a socialpolicy of maximum output from limited inputs. Even asidefrom the problematics of the proper weight of principle andpolicy in understanding these rules, many cases ofadjudication on the merits clearly invoke policies, as inmany instances of statutory construction. Even where thereis no clear legislative intent, courts invoke policyconsiderations sua sponte in order to effectuate a sensiblelegislative result; the burgeoning area of federal commonlaw is one example.6

These American authorities have rejected sentimentsvoiced by English judges of an earlier era: that "public policy... is a very unruly horse and when once you get astride it younever know where it will carry you,"7 and that judges are more

5. Roger J. Traynor, Reasoning in a Circle of Law, 56 Va. L. Rev. 739, 749 (1970).

6. David A.J. Richards, Rules, Policies, and Neutral Principles: The Search forLegitimacy in Common Law and Constitutional Adjudication, 11 Ga. L. Rev. 1069, 1097-98 (1977) (footnotes omitted).

7. Richardson v. Mellish, 2 Bing. 229, 252, 130 Eng. Rep. 294, 303 (1824) (Burrough,

Page 5: Judicial Declaration of Public Policy

THE JOURNAL OF APPELLATE PRACTICE AND PROCESS

to be trusted as interpreters of the law than as expounders ofpublic policy. 8 And yet, more recent United Kingdom jurists donot follow the teachings of the earlier era. The venerable LordDenning, for instance, applied the modem view in his discussionof the measure of damages in a tort case:

At bottom, I think the question of recovering economic lossis one of policy. Whenever the courts draw a line to markout the bounds of duty, they do it as a matter of policy so asto limit the responsibility of the defendant. Whenever thecourts set bounds to the damages recoverable-saying thatthey are, or are not, too remote-they do it as a matter ofpolicy so as to limit the liability of the defendant. 9

Justice Hopkins of the Appellate Division of the New YorkSupreme Court was similarly realistic in declaring that amongthe several devices available as bases for decisions-such asmaxims, doctrines, precedents, and statutes-public policy isprimary. As he put it, "[t]he other grounds for a judicial decisionyield to the declaration of public policy, once that policy isascertained."'1 0

Although much of the controversy concerning judicialimplementation of public policy is of recent vintage, the practiceitself is longstanding and well established in common lawadjudication. As early as 1881, Justice Holmes wrote:

The very considerations which judges most rarely mention,and always with an apology, are the secret root from whichthe law draws all the juices of life. I mean, of course,considerations of what is expedient for the communityconcerned. Every important principle which is developedby litigation is in fact and at bottom the result of more orless definitely understood views of public policy; mostgenerally, to be sure, under our practice and traditions, theunconscious result of instinctive preferences andinarticulate convictions, but none the less traceable to viewsof public policy in the last analysis. 1

8. In re Mirams, (1891) 1 Q.B. 594, 595.9. Spartan Steel & Alloys Ltd. v. Martin & Co. (Contractors) Ltd. (1973) 1 Q.B. 27,

36.10. James D. Hopkins, Public Policy and the Formation of a Rule of Law, 37 Brooklyn

L. Rev. 323, 323 (1971).11. Oliver Wendell Holmes, Jr., The Common Law 35-36 (Little Brown 1881).

Page 6: Judicial Declaration of Public Policy

JUDICIAL DECLARATION OF PUBLIC POLICY

Notwithstanding the importance of these considerations tojudicial decisionmaking, it is well to remember that judges arefar more constrained than legislators in fashioning or declaringpublic policy. Professor and former Yale Law School DeanWellington offers the thoughtful suggestion that

when a court justifies a common law (as distinguished froma statutory or constitutional) rule with a policy, it isproceeding in a fashion recognized as legitimate only if twoconditions are met: The policy must be widely regarded associally desirable and it must be relatively neutral. 2

This poses an obvious question: How may-indeed, how can-acourt determine whether a policy is socially desirable?Wellington recommended that in fashioning common law onpublic policy grounds, the court first look

to the corpus of law--decisional, enacted, andconstitutional-to determine whether relevant policies havereceived legal recognition....[i]n determining the extent of a policy's social desirability,a court should examine such things as political platforms,and take seriously-for this purpose-campaign promisesand political speeches. The media is a source of evidenceand so too are public opinion polls. Books and articles inprofessional journals, legislative hearings and reports, andthe reports of special committees and institutes are allevidence. 13

The sound requirement of neutrality extends toconstitutional and statutory interpretation as well as to commonlaw adjudication. The principle of neutrality demands thatjudges, who are intentionally shielded from the pressures ofinterest groups by the structure of American government, shouldnot justify their rulings by accepting the demands of one interestgroup at the expense of another that is not party to thelitigation.1 4 Professor Wechsler bore the brunt of muchcriticism-unfounded and undeserved-for his 1959 Holmes

12. Harry H. Wellington, Common Law Rules and Constitutional Double Standards:Some Notes on Adjudication, 83 Yale L.J. 221, 236 (1973).

13. Id. at 236-37.14. Id. at 238.

Page 7: Judicial Declaration of Public Policy

234 THE JOURNAL OF APPELLATE PRACTICE AND PROCESS

lecture on neutrality, given at Harvard Law School. 15

Commenting in 1975 on that criticism, he reasserted theimportance of his principle:

The central thought is surely that the principle onceformulated must be tested by the adequacy of its derivationfrom its sources and its implications with respect to othersituations that the principle, if evenly applied, willcomprehend. Unless those implications are acceptable theprinciple surely must be reformulated or withdrawn.16

This, I suggest, is but the jurisprudential expression ofImmanuel Kant's categorical imperative: "Act only on thatmaxim through which you can at the same time will that itshould become a universal law."'17 (I concede of course thatsome subscribe instead to George Bernard Shaw's advice: "Donot do unto others as you would that they should do unto you.Their tastes may not be the same."' 8)

The essence of neutrality is the quality of evenhandedness,a recognition that whatever influence special interests may havein legislative decisionmaking, the imposition of special burdenson, or the granting of special favors to, a particular group has noplace in adjudication-no place, that is, absent principledreasons for being there. Special-interest decisionmaking is foronly the legislative branch, which has perfected the art; statutesare the products of a series of marginal adjustments andcompromises among various semi-independent groups.9

Legislation is the art of accommodation, and politics is the art ofthe possible. And the possible is conditioned by the ballot box.Modem legislators seem to accommodate only the perceiveddesires of the parochial constituencies whose members elect orsupport them, setting aside any consideration of what is

15. Herbert Wechsler, Toward Neutral Principles of Constitutional Law, 73 Harv. L.Rev. 1 (1959).

16. Herbert Wechsler, Remarks at Federal Appellate Judges' Conference (Fed. Jud.Ctr., Wash., D.C., Mar. 12, 1975), in Ruggero J. Aldisert, The Judicial Process 630-31 (2ded., West Pub. Co. 1996).

17. Immanuel Kant, Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals 88 (H.J. Paton trans.,Barnes & Noble, Inc. 1964).

18. George Bernard Shaw, Man and Superman: A Comedy and a Philosophy 227(Brentano's 1903) (section titled Maxims for Revolutionists).

19. See Martin Shapiro, Freedom of Speech: The Supreme Court and Judicial Review29 (Prentice Hall 1966).

Page 8: Judicial Declaration of Public Policy

JUDICIAL DECLARATION OF PUBLIC POLICY

preferable for the entire population of the state or nation. Evenwithin their own electorates, they often fail to equate numberswith influence, for experience has taught them that minoritiespunish, but majorities seldom protect.

The judiciary is not equally restrained by, or susceptible to,the interests of electorates confined within relatively smalllegislative districts, nor does it have available to it thelegislature's opportunities for largess. Judges can learn what iswidely regarded as desirable by identifying, isolating, and thenweighing the same factors legislators would take into account-and then, when it is proper to do so, ignoring those factors.Because they can, with courage and dignity, eschew parochialand partisan factors, judges are able to make their decisions onthe fairly neutral bases of principles and rights.

Assuming the essential element of neutrality, we must turnnow to a broader canvas of the factors relevant to policydeclaration. How is the judge to ascertain the public interest andthe policies that will advance it? Dean Rostow addressed thisproblem as a search for the "common morality of a society. 2 °

Professor Friedmann believed it necessary to identify thecollective judgment in terms of the basic norms of thecommunity's life. He suggested that a primary source ofinformation would be the general state of contemporarylegislative policy, but argued also that the judge should turn tothe state of organization in the society in which he lived, makenote of the groupings and pulls of the major social forces of hissociety, be aware of society's pluralistic aspects, and recognizethe state of modem science. 2

Professor Hart also discussed the importance ofascertaining the conventional morality of an actual social group,referring to

20. Eugene V. Rostow, The Enforcement of Morals, 1960 Cambridge L.J. 174, 197(1960). Rostow described this common morality as

a blend of custom and conviction, of reason and feeling, of experience andprejudice.... [I]n the life of the law, especially in a common law country, thecustoms, the common views, and the habitual patterns of the people's behaviourproperly count for much .... All movements of law reform seek to carry outcertain social judgments as to what is fair and just in the conduct of society.

Id.21. Wolfgang Friedmann, Legal Philosophy and Judicial Lawmaking, 61 Colum. L.

Rev. 821, 843-45 (1961).

Page 9: Judicial Declaration of Public Policy

THE JOURNAL OF APPELLATE PRACTICE AND PROCESS

standards of conduct which are widely shared in aparticular society, and are to be contrasted with the moralprinciples or moral ideals which may govern anindividual's life, but which he does not share with anyconsiderable number of those with whom he lives.22

This is perhaps the most critical aspect of our inquiry. The judgemust screen out personal bias, passion, and prejudice, andattempt always to distinguish between a personal cultivated tasteand the general notions of moral obligation. Such standards ofconduct reflect an obligation to respect rules of society. Theyare, in Hart's formulation, primary rules of obligation because of"the serious social pressure by which they are supported, and bythe considerable sacrifice of individual interest or inclinationwhich compliance with them involves." 23 And ProfessorWellington said that the way in which one learns about theconventional morality of society "is to live in it, becomesensitive to it, experience widely, read extensively, andruminate, reflect, and analyze situations that seem to call moralobligations into play." 24

The line of inquiry proposed by Rostow, Friedman, Hartand others is similar to that proposed by Wellington todetermine what is "socially desirable" for common lawadjudication. 25 The attempt to base a decision on socialconsensus, however, is fraught with peril and, in theinterpretation of constitutional precepts, may be inappropriate.As Professor Jaffe once inquired:

How does one isolate and discover a consensus on aquestion so abstruse as the existence of a fundamentalright? The public may value a right and yet not believe it tobe fundamental. The public may hold that the rights ofparents are fundamental and yet have no view whether theyinclude sending a child to a private school. There may be aprofound ambiguity in the public conscience; it mayprofess to entertain a traditional ideal but be reluctant to actupon it. In such a situation might we not say that the judgewill be free to follow either the traditional ideal or the

22. H.L.A. Hart, The Concept of Law 165 (Oxford U. Press 1961).23. Id.24. Wellington, supra n. 12, at 246.25. See supra nn. 7-22 and accompanying text.

Page 10: Judicial Declaration of Public Policy

JUDICIAL DECLARATION OF PUBLIC POLICY

existing practice, depending upon the reaction of his ownconscience? And in many cases will it not be true that therehas been no general thinking on the issue? 26

A classic example of judges mistaking the public consensusis the position perennially espoused by Justices Brennan andMarshall in death penalty cases. Their concurring opinions inFurman v. Georgia 7 took the position that the death penaltywas unconstitutional "cruel and unusual punishment" because itwas out of step with contemporary community values.28 Therush of state legislatures to impose the death penalty after their1972 statements, however, showed an unmistakable communityreaction, at least in the immediately following years, that was incomplete opposition to their statements. 29 The tendency forjudges to find society's values in their own is a constant danger.Much adjudication in the federal courts, especially inconstitutional interpretations based on concepts of public policy,moral standards, and public welfare, is little more than theconscious or unconscious imposition of certain judges' personalvalues. Many of us who purport to be objective in identifyingcommunity values, and who are indeed sincere about it, areactually intent on attaining immediate social ends that wepersonally see as moral imperatives.

Adherence to the principle of neutrality in judicialdecisionmaking provides a check against the temptation tosubstitute personal for social values. As Professor Greenawalt

26. Louis L. Jaffe, Was Brandeis an Activist? The Search for Intermediate Premises, 80Harv. L. Rev. 986, 994 (1967).

27. 408 U.S. 238 (1972).28. Id. at 295-300 (Brennan, J., concurring); id. at 360-69 (Marshall, J., concurring).29. In Opinion Writing 1990, I noted that a Gallup Poll taken in November 1985

disclosed that three out of four Americans favored the death penalty, seventeen percentopposed it, and eight percent were undecided. See Opinion Writing 1990, supra n. 2, at 42,n. 25 (citing Gallup Poll Finds Sharp Rise in Support for Death Penalty, 134 N.Y. TimesA20 (Nov. 28, 1985)). Analysis of a Gallup Poll taken in October 2007 notes that althoughsixty-nine percent of Americans were then still in favor of the death penalty for a murderconviction, over the years support for the sentence of life without parole as an alternative tothe death penalty has steadily increased. When the Gallup question provides the respondentwith an explicit alternative to the death penalty ("life imprisonment, with absolutely nopossibility of parole"), support for the death penalty typically has registered in the range offorty-seven percent to fifty-four percent. See Frank Newport, Sixty-Nine Percent ofAmericans Support Death Penalty, Gallup News Release (Oct. 12, 2007),http://www.gallup.com/poll/101 863/Sixtynine-Percent-Americans-Support-Death-Penalty.aspx (accessed Oct. 14, 2009; copy on file with Journal of Appellate Practice and Process).

Page 11: Judicial Declaration of Public Policy

THE JOURNAL OF APPELLATE PRACICE AND PROCESS

has observed,[s]erious moral choices typically involve some conflictbetween an action that would serve one's narrow self-interest and an action that would satisfy responsibilitiestoward others. The dangers of bias are extreme; either wevalue too highly our own interest or over-compensate andundervalue it. The discipline of imagining similar situationsin which we are not involved or play a different role morenearly enables us to place appropriate values on competingconsiderations.

30

Similarly, a consideration of the first principles of legalphilosophy may place a particular issue of public concern in abroader, more principled context and may force us to recognizeany inconsistencies between our intuitive moral values and themore general philosophy of law to which we may subscribe.Indeed,

[w]e may discover that some of our intuitive moral viewsare not consistent with other intuitive views or withgeneralized principles to which we subscribe. As we testour intuitive reactions to particular situations against ouraccepted principles, both may give a little, until we arrive atwhat John Rawls calls a "reflective equilibrium," in whichour sense of right for particular issues matches ourprinciples.

31

An important component of our jurisprudentialtemperament is the threshold at which judges are willing to actin disregard or contravention of prevailing social norms, theextent to which they are willing to confront the antimajoritariandifficulty. 32 In those instances in which social consensus is

30. Kent Greenawalt, The Enduring Significance of Neutral Principles, 78 Colum. L.Rev. 982, 997 (1978).

31. Id.32. Professor Laurence Tribe contends that this problem is inherent in constitutional

government:Whether imposed by unelected judges or by elected officials conscientious anddaring enough to defy popular will in order to do what they believe theConstitution requires, choices to ignore the majority's inclinations in the nameof a higher source of law invariably raise questions of legitimacy in a nation thattraces power to the people's will.... In its most basic form, the question in suchcases is why a nation that rests legality on the consent of the governed wouldchoose to constitute its political life in terms of commitments to an originalagreement-made by the people, binding on their children, and deliberatelystructured so as to be difficult to change. Since that question would arise, albeit

Page 12: Judicial Declaration of Public Policy

JUDICIAL DECLARATION OF PUBLIC POLICY

asserted as an appropriate basis for judicial declarations ofpublic policy, how should a judge reconcile what ProfessorFuller called the "inner voice of conscience ' 33 with prevailingcommunity standards?

II. JUDICIAL DECLARATION WHERE THERE Is No CONSENSUS FOR

PUBLIC POLICY

In seeking an answer, I first distinguish betweencircumstances in which there is a consensus and those in whichthere is not. We should agree that free societies will changebecause it is their nature to do so. New ideas can gather strengthin the social or intellectual marketplace and achieve theconsensus. When these ideas are admitted and so absorbed, thelegal system should expand to hold them. Conversely, the legalsystem should contract to squeeze out old policies that have lostthe consensus they once held. The expansion or contraction ofthe legal system to reach these goals is what we call judiciallydeclared public policy. So perceived, social consensus demandssympathy from the court.

Where the legislature has not acted in accordance withchanging social policies and seemingly does not so intend to act,the courts have not only the authority, but possibly the duty, tokeep pace with the change in consensus. Individual legislatorsthen function in only one direction: to ensure their own re-election with the kind of Darwinian instinct that tells animalsthey must fight to preserve their genetic stocks. The prevailingtendency among most legislators is to avoid a vote on anycontroversial issue likely to produce differences in opinionamong their constituents back home. Richard Neely, a formerjustice of the West Virginia Supreme Court and a former state

less dramatically, even without the institution of judicial review, its answer mustbe sought at a level more fundamental than is customary in discussions of whyjudges, appointed for life, should wield great power. For even without suchjudges, it must be stressed, lawmakers and administrators sworn to uphold theConstitution must from time to time ask themselves, if they take their oathseriously, why its message should be heeded over the voices of theirconstituents.

Laurence Tribe, American Constitutional Law 10 (2d ed., Found. Press 1988).

33. Lon L. Fuller, Positivism and Fidelity to Law--A Reply to Professor Hart, 71 Harv.L. Rev. 630, 635 (1958).

Page 13: Judicial Declaration of Public Policy

THE JOURNAL OF APPELLATE PRACTICE AND PROCESS

legislator, is more blunt:[A] legislature is designed to do nothing, with the emphasisappropriately placed on the word "designed." The value ofan institution whose primary attribute is inertia topoliticians who wish to keep their jobs is that a majority ofbills will die from inactivity; that then permits legislators tobe "in favor" of a great deal of legislation without everbeing required to vote on it. When constituents seek to holda legislator responsible for the failure of a particular bill, hecan say, plausibly, that it was assigned to a committee onwhich he did not serve and that he was unable to shake thebill out of that committee. If he has foreseen positiveconstituent interest, he can produce letters from thecommittee chairman in answer to his excited pleas to reportthe legislation to the floor; correspondence of this sort isthe stock in trade of legislators. Notwithstanding theearnest correspondence, it is quite possible that when thelegislator and committee chairman were having a drinkbefore dinner, the legislator indicated his personal desire tokill the bill in spite of the facade of excitedcorrespondence.34

But this does not mean that the judge must act only whenpublic opinion reflects a majoritarian viewpoint, or even aplurality viewpoint. Had the Supreme Court waited for publicconsensus we might never have had Brown v. Board ofEducation;35 in 1954 there was no national consensus for thecompulsory integration of the public school system. This wasone of those times that call for judicial intervention-or moreproperly, judicial operation-in advance of the consensus,which the judge may therefore properly outrun. In doing so,however, he or she must tread delicately.

III. FOUR CONCERNS TO BE ADDRESSED IN JUDICIALDECLARATION OF PUBLIC POLICY

I suggest that judges must address the following concernswhen declaring public policy:

34. Richard Neely, How Courts Govern America 55 (Yale U. Press 1981) (emphasis inoriginal).

35. 347 U.S. 483 (1954).

Page 14: Judicial Declaration of Public Policy

JUDICIAL DECLARATION OF PUBLIC POLICY

1. Judges must be impartial and independentin both the decisionmaking process andthe process of justification.

2. Judges must convey the distinctimpression and appearance ofimpartiality.

3. Judges must fulfill the obligations ofneutrality and the obligations of bothjustice in rem, socially desirable becauseit is based on some pre-eminent moralprinciple, and justice in personam,individually desirable because it yieldsjustice for the parties to a given lawsuit.

4. Judges must identify and evaluate therelevant private, social, public, andgovernmental interests. These must be notonly evaluated, but compared, accepted,rejected, tailored, adjusted and, ifnecessary, subjected to judicialcompromise.

Judges must be especially careful to cleave to the firstprinciple of the reasoning process, which starts the march to thespecific conclusion (or declaration of public policy): It must be aconcept universally held and uniformly respected. It must berelated to at least one of what I have described elsewhere assupereminent principles of the law: creating and protectingproperty interests; creating and protecting liberty interests;fulfilling promises; redressing losses caused by breach or fault;and punishing those who wrong the public. 36

36. Cf Ruggero J. Aldisert, House of the Law, 19 Loy. L.A. L. Rev. 755 (1985).

Page 15: Judicial Declaration of Public Policy

THE JOURNAL OF APPELLATE PRACTICE AND PROCESS

IV. WEIGHING OF INTERESTS IN JUDICIAL DECLARATION OFPUBLIC POLICY

More often than not, public policy derives from a sub-process of the judicial process now popularly known as"balancing interests." With a seemingly inexhaustible inventoryof social interests pressing upon judges and jurists for attention,judicial "balancing" seeks a reasoned accommodation of thecompeting interests and the resolution of their conflicts. Perhapsmost critical to this process, judges and jurists must first identifyand categorize the various individual, public and social interests.As Dean Pound recognized, the validity of the techniquedepends, in the first instance, on whether all relevant identifiableinterests are placed on the scale.37

The expression "balancing interests" is useful, perhaps, butseriously misleading. It implies that the subject matter of thejudicial process is somehow quantifiable. It is not subject tosuch quantification, notwithstanding the itch in this computerage to put numbers to every phenomenon. The best that can behoped is that all the interests at stake in a case are identifiable.Having identified the interests at stake, judges can at leastconsider them, as I doubt that they can ever really be"balanced." Before the accommodation takes place, however,like types of interests must be identified. As there are fruits andfruits, e.g., apples and oranges, so are there interests andinterests.

37. Roscoe Pound, A Survey of Social Interests, 57 Harv. L. Rev. 1, 4 (1943).38. See Ruggero J. Aldisert, The Judicial Process 478-81, 524-28, 604-13 (West 1996).

It seems appropriate to note here that although courts frequently use the expression"interests," there is little judicial explanation of the word. This is very unusual, for allcurrent judicial decisions involve a recognition, stated or unstated, of certain interests. Infact, most decisions involve a weighing of competing interests that have beenunquestionably identified and recognized. For myself, I have gone through an evolvingprocess that now leads me to define an interest as a social fact, factor, or phenomenonreflected by a claim, demand, or desire that human beings, either individually or as groups,seek to satisfy and that has been recognized as socially valid by authoritative decisionmakers in society. Compare my earlier formulation in id. at 489, where I stated that "[alninterest is a social fact, factor or phenomenon reflected by a claim or demand or desirewhich human beings, either individually or as groups or associations or relations, seek tosatisfy and which has been recognized as socially valid by authoritative decision makers insociety."

Page 16: Judicial Declaration of Public Policy

JUDICIAL DECLARATION OF PUBLIC POLICY

We then get to the question of how judges identify thegroupings of behavior and values that will influence theirdecisions. Justice Cardozo recognized that

[t]he whole of the judicial function . . . [involves] thesubjective sense of justice inherent in the judge, guided byan effective weighing of the interests of the parties ... andin weighing conflicting interests, the interest that is betterfounded in reason and more worthy of protection should behelped to achieve victory.39

Other than by an exercise of a threshold value judgment oncertain factual phenomena, either in the record or in the judge'sexperience, I can find no other point at which judicialdecisionmaking can begin. This threshold judgment continues tocolor a judge's thinking as he or she gropes toward a decision inthe case.

Once judges designate an interest, they then make a valuejudgment as to whether it is worthy of protection. If that is thetentative inclination, they then summon relevant precepts thatcommand a definite legal consequence. If specific rules in thenarrow sense are found wanting, the judges range further to thegeneralized precept of legal principle or a still more abstractprecept known as a doctrine or dogma. If rules of law,principles, or legal doctrines fail to provide an answer, the courtsthen look to a moral principle and make a judgment as towhether it should be converted into a legal precept.4 0 Where asatisfactory legal precept is then found or articulated on the basisof these facts, the courts have wrapped legal protection aroundthe designated social facts or factors.

I believe that this accurately characterizes the anatomy ofthe judicial decisional process. I believe also that a criticalcomponent of the process is the interest identified or favored bya given judge in a given court reaching a particular result in aparticular case. In consequence, one primary responsibility of

39. Benjamin Cardozo, The Nature of the Judicial Process 73-74 (Yale U. Press 1921)(quoting Jcharm Georg Gmelin, Sociological Method).

40. Examples of this process in constitutional law are plentiful. See e.g. Roe v. Wade,410 U.S. 113 (1973); Griswold v. Conn., 381 U.S. 479 (1965); Fay v. Noia, 372 U.S. 391(1963); Monroe v. Pape, 365 U.S. 167 (1961). The classic example in state tort law is theadoption of Restatement (Second) of Torts § 402A (1965) (providing for strict productsliability), now superseded. See also Ruggero J. Aldisert, The Nature of the JudicialProcess: Revisited, 49 Cinn. L. Rev. 1, 39-40 (1980).

Page 17: Judicial Declaration of Public Policy

THE JOURNAL OF APPELLATE PRACTICE AND PROCESS

the appellate advocate is the identification of the interests beingweighed today by the courts. This, alas, often does not takeplace. Too often, briefs simply recite the various leading casesand attempt to bring the particular dispute within the boundariesof the decisions thought to be controlling. They address toobriefly, if at all, the interests implicated in the decision. Suchbriefs are of little aid to the court. To be a success, JusticeBrandeis wrote in his notebook, a lawyer must "[k]now not onlythe specific case, but the whole subject .... Know not only thosefacts which bear on direct controversy, but know all the factsand laws that surround.' 1

Referring to his notable survey of social interests, in amagnificent abstraction of the nature and ends of law, Poundsaid:

Looked at functionally, the law is an attempt to satisfy, toreconcile, to harmonize, to adjust these overlapping andoften conflicting claims and demands, either throughsecuring them directly and immediately, or throughsecuring certain individual interests, so as to give effect tothe greatest total of interests or to the interests that weighmost in our civilization, with the least sacrifice of thescheme of interests as a whole.42

The process derives from the writings of the German juristRudolf von Jhering, who designated the method asInteressenjurisprudenz, a jurisprudence of interests.43 Under thismethod of dispute resolution, according to Professor Antieau,the court identifies the opposed societal interests, reconcilesthem if possible and, if reconciliation is not possible, rules thatone societal interest under the circumstances must prevail overanother, with an explanation of why this is so." The process is

41. Melvin I. Urofsky, Louis D. Brandeis and the Progressive Tradition 6 (LittleBrown & Co. 1981).

42. Pound, supra n. 37, at 39.

43. See generally Rudolph von Jhering, Law as a Means to an End (Isaac Husik trans.,Boston Book Co. 1913).

44. Chester James Antieau, The Jurisprudence of Interests as a Method ofConstitutional Adjudication, 27 Case W. Res. L. Rev. 823, 829 (1977) (quoting illustrativepassages from Cantwell v. Conn., 310 U.S. 286 (1940), Thomas v. Collins, 232 U.S. 516(1945), and Saia v. N. Y, 334 U.S. 558 (1948)).

Page 18: Judicial Declaration of Public Policy

JUDICIAL DECLARATION OF PUBLIC POLICY

very much at work today in many aspects of adjudication,especially in tort and constitutional law.45

V. CONCLUSION

I believe that judges today do consider the pragmaticeffects of alternative courses of decision. In their declarations ofpublic policy, they attempt to accommodate the social needs ofall who would be affected by their decisions, irrespective ofwhether those affected were the litigants before them. They lookto the general state of contemporary legislative policy and thefelt needs of the society-insofar as they can discern those needsin an increasingly pluralistic society. They consider economicforces, scientific developments, and identifiable expressions ofpublic opinion. To be sure, this decisional process hasdeontological as well as axiological overtones. It bears aremarkable resemblance to classic natural law.46

45. But of course not every judge and scholar endorses the method. See e.g. LouisHenkin, Infallibility Under Law: Constitutional Balancing, 78 Colum. L. Rev. 1022, 1022-23 (1978) (noting that "[s]ome have seen a tendency toward 'lawlessness' . . . in thegrowing resort by the courts to 'balancing' in constitutional adjudication," and notingfurther that the author is here "reflecting on different uses of balancing in constitutionaldiscourse" and attempting "to distinguish two kinds of balancing in constitutionaljurisprudence"). For examples of how competing interests are weighed and reconciled intwo antitrust cases, see Tose v. First Penn. Bank, N.A., 648 F.2d 879 (3d Cir. 1981), andUnger v. Dunkin Donuts ofAm., Inc., 531 F.2d 1211 (3d Cir. 1976).

46. See Ruggero J. Aldisert, The Role of the Courts in Contemporary Society, 38 U.Pitt. L. Rev. 437, 445 (1977) (recognizing that "contemporary American courts areresorting more and more to the method of sociology as a primary decisional tool," that"[t]his decisional process has deontological as well as teleological overtones," and that it"bears a remarkable resemblance to classical natural law").

Page 19: Judicial Declaration of Public Policy