Ja Zu Deutschland

download Ja Zu Deutschland

of 14

Transcript of Ja Zu Deutschland

  • 8/3/2019 Ja Zu Deutschland

    1/14Electronic copy available at: http://ssrn.com/abstract=1498527

    PUBLIC LAW AND LEGAL THEORY WORKING PAPER SERIES

    WORKING PAPER NO.170 NOVEMBER 2009

    THEGERMANCONSTITUTIONAL COURTSAYS Ja zu Deutschland!

    DANIELHALBERSTAM AND

    CHRISTOPHMLLERS

    GERMAN LAW J.,VOL.10-8,(2009)

  • 8/3/2019 Ja Zu Deutschland

    2/14Electronic copy available at: http://ssrn.com/abstract=1498527

    TheGermanConstitutionalCourtsays"JazuDeutschland!"DanielHalberstam&ChristophMllers

    UniversityofMichigan,AnnArbor

    UniversityofGttingen,Germany

    AbstractIn announcing the decision of the Bundesverfassungsgericht (Federal Constitutional

    Court or FCC) on the constitutionality of the Lisbon Treaty, the Presiding Justice of theSecondSenatesummedupthejudgmentbyproclaiming: TheGermanBasicLawsaysyestothe Treaty of Lisbon. The decision has since receivedmuch praise from commentators for

    havingstruck

    down

    only

    the

    existing

    version

    of

    an

    accompanying

    federal

    law

    while

    preserving

    GermanysratificationoftheTreatymorebroadly. Thedecisionisthuslikenedtoanotheractofjudicialcooperation,theFCCs1992decisionontheMaastrichtTreaty.

    This short comment explains what is old and what is new about the FCCs current

    decisionaboutEurope. ThecommentexposestheFCCshighlydeceptiveinvocationofhavingtakenaEuropefriendlystanceininterpretingtheGermanBasicLaw. Thediscussionexposesthemyriadcontradictionswithintheopinionandthedecisionsstrangeconsequencesboth in

    terms of the concreteworkings of the EuropeanUnion and in terms of its grand theory of

    democracy. The comment highlights the FCCs mistaken understanding of the EuropeanParliament,theprofoundfailureoftheCourtsreflexiveideaofstatesovereignty,andtheway

    inwhich

    the

    opinion

    condemns

    Europe

    to

    aperpetual

    state

    of

    deficiency.

    In

    all

    this,

    the

    Federal

    ConstitutionalCourtinstallsitselfasthesolearbiterofGermanysconstitutionaldestinyevenabovethepeoplethemselves.

    AsubversiveopinionwithmoretwistsandturnsthaneventheFCCitselfcomprehends,thedecisionultimatelystandsasacrudespeechactassertinglittlemorethanthepoweroftheCourtitself.

    Daniel Halberstam, Eric Stein Collegiate Professor of Law, University of Michigan Law School [Email: [email protected]].

    ChristophMllers,ProfessorofPublicLaw,UniversityofGttingenLawSchool[Email: [email protected]].

    mailto:[email protected]:[email protected]:[email protected]:[email protected]:[email protected]:[email protected]
  • 8/3/2019 Ja Zu Deutschland

    3/14Electronic copy available at: http://ssrn.com/abstract=1498527

    Halberstam&Mllers 2TheGermanConstitutionalCourtsays"JazuDeutschland!"

    ByDanielHalberstam&ChristophMllers

    [in10GERMANLAWJOURNALNo.8(2009)]

    A. IntroductionInannouncingthedecisionoftheBundesverfassungsgericht(BVerfG FederalConstitutionalCourt)onthe

    constitutionality of the Lisbon Treaty,1 the Presiding Justice of the Second Senate summed up the

    judgmentbyproclaiming: DasGrundgesetzsagtJazumVertragvonLissabon.

    B. RepetitionTheGermanCourtrepeatsmuchthathadbeensaidbefore. Mostfundamentally,theCourtexplainsonce

    againthat

    it

    views

    the

    European

    legal

    order

    as

    asecondary

    order,

    derived

    from

    that

    of

    the

    Member

    States. TheCourtcontinuestocomparetheEuropeanUniontointernationalorganizationsbyrepeatedly

    discussing international and supranational organizations2 in one breath. Once states transfer

    sovereignpowerstosuchaninstitution,3thelattermayindeeddevelopindependentlyandshow[]a

    tendency of political selfenhancement.4 And yet, the Member States remain the masters of the

    Treaties.5 ThefunctionalConstitutionofEurope,i.e.theprimarytreaty lawconstitutingthepowers

    of theUnion, simply remains an abgeleitete Grundordnung, i.e. a derivative legal order. So, too,

    EuropeancitizenshipisaderivativestatusthatdoesnotchallengetheexistenceoftheGermanpeople

    (Staatsvolk).6

    As in theMaastrichtCase, theCourtmakesway for theapplicationofEuropean lawwithinGermany.

    European law does not preempt Member State law in the sense of annulment but forces back

    conflicting

    Member

    States

    law

    to

    allow

    for

    the

    application

    of

    Community

    law.

    7

    The

    Court

    pledges

    to

    adheretotheoldSolangecompromiseandrefrainfromreviewingEuropeansecondary lawandactsfor

    theircompatibilitywithfundamentalrightsas longastheEuropeanUnionguaranteesanapplicationof

    fundamental rights that in substance and effectiveness is essentially similar to the protection of

    fundamentalrightsrequiredunconditionallybytheBasicLaw.8

    Daniel Halberstam, Eric Stein Collegiate Professor of Law, University of Michigan Law School [Email:[email protected]]. Christoph Mllers, Professor of Public Law, University of Gttingen Law School [Email:[email protected]]. ThankstoDieterGrimmandtheparticipantsintheSIASSI2009seminarforhelpfuldiscussions,andtoMatejAvbeljforpointingouttheCourtsmisstatement regardingnationalrepresentationintheEuropeanParliament.

    1 Lisbon Case, BVerfG, 2 BvE/08 from 30 June 2009, available at:http://www.bverfg.de/entscheidungen/es20090630_2bve000208.html.2See,e.g.,id.atpara.237.3Id.atpara.231.4Id.atpara.237.5Id.atpara.231.6Id.atparas.34650.7Id.atpara.335.8Id.at191(citingBVerfGE73,339(376,387);BVerfGE102,147,(164)).

    mailto:[email protected]:[email protected]:[email protected]:[email protected]:[email protected]:[email protected]
  • 8/3/2019 Ja Zu Deutschland

    4/14

    TheLisbonDecision 3

    Unsurprising, then, is theCourtselaborationof the impossibility thatGerman state institutionswould

    grant the EuropeanUnion license to determine its ownpowers (KompetenzKompetenz).9 Similarly

    unsurprising isthe insistenceonGermanyspowerto leavetheUnion,which, intheCourts(somewhat

    sloppy) view, would not be an instance of internationally problematic secession, but merely the

    withdrawalfromaStaatenverbundthatisfoundedontheprincipleofreversibleselfcommitment.10

    The

    LisbonTreaty

    presents

    no

    problem

    in

    this

    regard,

    11

    especially

    as

    it

    now

    makes

    the

    previously

    existing

    right

    ofwithdrawalexplicit.12

    C. InnovationDespiteamplerepetitionoftheMaastrichtrefrain,theCourtdidmanagetocoversomenewground

    bothattheconcrete levelof imposinglegalrulesaswellasatthe levelofconceptualizingtheEuropean

    andMemberStatelegalorders.

    I. OperationalMatters

    1. BlockingPasserelle

    Thecentral

    innovation

    of

    the

    Courts

    Lisbon

    Case

    concerns

    the

    so

    called

    passerelle

    clauses,

    which

    allow

    the Council tomove from unanimity to qualifiedmajority voting or from the special to the ordinary

    legislativeprocedure.13

    Theseprovisionsgivenationalparliamentssixmonthstovetoaproposedswitch

    inprocedure. TheCourt,however,fusestherepresentativeoftheGermangovernmentintheCouncilto

    itsnationallegislaturebyholdingthatGermanysrepresentativeintheCouncilmustinnocaseagreetoa

    changeinprocedureunlessanduntilthelegislaturehasvotedonthematter. Silenceonthepartofthe

    BundestagandBundesrat,theCourtexplains,is . . .notsufficient forexercisingthisresponsibility.14

    Moreover,withregardtothegeneral(asopposedtosubjectmatterspecific)bridgeclauses,avotebythe

    legislatureisnotenough. HeretheCourtrequirestheGermanlegislaturetotaketheextrastepandpass

    alawtoratifywhattheCourtdescribesasachangeinprimarytreatylawwithinthemeaningofBasicLaw

    Article23(1).15

    2.The

    Curious

    Case

    of

    the

    Emergency

    Brake

    TheCourtevensubjectsthesocalledemergencybrakesystemtoaforced legislativevoteto instruct

    Germanys representative in the Council. In the course of considering certain legislative proposals

    concerningcriminal law16

    andsocialsecurity,17

    aCouncilmembermayraiseanobjectionthatsuspends

    9Id.atpara.233(citing,amongothers,89BVerfGE155,187f.,192,199).10

    Id.atpara.233.11

    Id.atparas.29899.12

    See,e.g.,id.atpara.329.13

    See,e.g., id.,atpara.316. Seealso,TreatyofLisbonAmendingtheTreatyonEuropeanUnionandtheTreatyEstablishingthe

    EuropeanCommunity,

    Dec.

    13,

    2007,

    art.

    48(7)

    2007

    O.J.

    (C

    306)

    1[hereinafter

    Lisbon

    Treaty]

    (general

    bridge

    clause);

    Lisbon

    Treaty

    art.31(3)(CFSPbridgeclauseCouncil);ConsolidatedVersionoftheTreatyontheFunctioningoftheEuropeanUnion,May9,2008,art.81(3),O.J.C115/47, at78 (2008) [hereinafter TFEU] (family law);TFEU art. 153(2) (social rights);TFEU art. 192(2) (certainenvironmentalprovisions);TFEUart.312(2)(multiannualfinancialframework);TFEUArt.333(2)(enhancedcooperation).

    14 Lisbon Case, BVerfG, 2 BvE/08 from 30 June 2009, para. 413, available at:

    http://www.bverfg.de/entscheidungen/es20090630_2bve000208.html..15

    Id.atparas.319and413.16

    TFEUarts.82(3)&83(3).

  • 8/3/2019 Ja Zu Deutschland

    5/14

    Halberstam&Mllers 4considerationofthemeasureandrefersthemattertotheEuropeanCouncil.

    18 Theseprocedurespushin

    theoppositedirectionasthepasserelleclauses,suspendingthemoreCommunityfriendlyprocedurethat

    wouldbeusedabsentinterventionbyaMemberState. Nonetheless,theCourtsubjectstheseemergency

    brakesalongwiththepasserelleclausestoanaffirmativeinstructiononthepartoftheBundestagand,

    whereappropriate,theBundesrat.

    TheCourts

    decision

    on

    the

    emergency

    brake

    provision

    leads

    to

    arather

    surprising

    result.

    Recall

    that

    in

    theemergencybrakeprovisionsthemoreCommunityfriendlyprocedure isthedefaultprocedure. This

    procedure is only set aside upon the objection of a Member State representative in the Council.

    Nonetheless,theCourtholds:

    [T]he German representative in the Council may only exercise this

    right of the Member States on the instruction of the German

    Bundestagand,totheextentthatthisisrequiredbytheprovisionson

    legislation,theBundesrat.19

    Thishasthreecuriousconsequences. First,theGermanrepresentative intheCouncilcannot invokethe

    emergencybrakeagainstthewishesofparliament. IftheGermanparliamentchoosesnottoinvokethe

    emergency brake, then neither can the German government. This stands inmarked contrast to the

    situationunder

    the

    passerelle

    clauses,

    where

    the

    German

    government

    as

    well

    as

    the

    German

    legislature

    mustagreebeforethemoreCommunityfriendlyprocedureisused. Second,theGermanrepresentative

    in the Council cannot act at all with regard to the emergency brake provision in the absence of

    parliamentary instruction. Thismeansthat iftheGerman legislature isdeadlockedorotherwisefailsto

    act,themoreCommunityfriendlyprocedurewillbeused. Here,too,theCourt,most likelyunwittingly,

    pushesinfavornotagainstintegration.

    Third,theCourtspeaksonlyaboutinstructingtheGermanrepresentativeintheCouncil,sayingnothing

    abouttheGermanrepresentativeintheEuropeanCouncil. ThismeansthattheGermanlegislaturemight

    instruct the German representative in the Council to invoke the emergency brake only to have the

    Germanrepresentative intheEuropeanCounciltothrowthematterbacktotheCouncilthus liftingthe

    brakealtogether.

    3. ImpliedPowers,theFlexibilityClause,andUltraViresReview

    IndiscussingtheUnionsflexibilityclause,theCourtopenswithatendentiousslightofhand. Itsuggests

    that the doctrine of implied powers is, in principle, nothing unusual in the scheme of European

    integration. TheCourt likenstheeffective interpretationofpowers(wirksameKompenzauslegung)to

    theU.S.doctrineofimpliedpowers, (citing the InternationalCourtof JusticecaseonReparationfor

    Injuries suffered in the Service of the United Nations), and to the French doctrine of effet utile in

    internationaltreatylaw.20

    AlthoughtheCourthereaddsaparentheticalcitationtoPierrePescatorefor

    an understanding of the latter concept especially as regards European law, the main gist of the

    17TFEUart.48(2).

    18UnderArticle48TFEU,theEuropeanCouncilmaythenterminatethelegislativeprocess,asktheCommissionforanewproposal,

    orreferthematterbacktoCounciltoproceedwiththe legislativeprocess. UnderArticles82and83TFEU,theEuropeanCouncilmayonlyreferthematterbacktotheCouncilafteraunanimousvoteanddoesnotappeartohavetheoptionofrequestinganew

    proposalfromtheCommission. UnderArticles82and83TFEU,however,nineMemberStates,mayalsochoosetoproceedonthebasisoftheclosercooperationprovisionsoftheTreaty.19

    Lisbon Case, BVerfG, 2 BvE/08 from 30 June 2009, para. 400, available at:

    http://www.bverfg.de/entscheidungen/es20090630_2bve000208.html(emphasisadded).20

    Id.atpara.237.

  • 8/3/2019 Ja Zu Deutschland

    6/14

    TheLisbonDecision 5paragraphsuggestsaninternational,asopposedtoconstitutional,understandingofimpliedpowers.

    21 A

    constitutional understanding of implied powers that invokes the U.S. tradition would have had to

    grapplewiththepowerfulvisionof impliedpowers laidout inJusticeMarshallsopinion inMcCullochv.

    Maryland. TheCourtssimplecitationto international lawassomehowrepresentativeoftheAmerican

    traditionofimpliedpowersisaratherunderhandedwayofavoidingthiscomparison. Weareleft,then,

    withnoargumentfortheCourtswatereddownunderstandingoftheimpliedpowersdoctrineinEurope.

    The Court further subjects any Council decision to resort to the general implied powers provision of

    Article 352 TFEU to a ratification law pursuant toBasic LawArticle23(1). The Lisbon Treaty lifts the

    currentlimitationofArticle308EC(whichdemandsthattheuseofimpliedpowersservethegoalsofthe

    internalmarket) toallow the invocationof impliedpowers in the serviceofallpoliciesdefined in the

    Treaties.22

    IntheCourtsview,thisnewgenerality leavesthescopeofthe flexibilityclause illdefined

    and,thus,tantamounttoaninvitationtosubstantive,fundamentaltreatychanges.23

    TheCourtalsosees

    thisasraisingconcernsinlightoftheconstitutionalprohibitionagainstgrantingtheUnionplenarypowers

    or against delegating to theUnion thepower to determine itsown competences.24

    Accordingly, the

    Courtsays,theflexibilityclausecanonlybekeptwithinconstitutionalboundsbysubjectingitsexerciseto

    aratificationlaw.

    Finally,theopinionhighlightsthepotentialforultraviresreviewintheCourtitself. Afterreiteratingthe

    possibilityof

    such

    review,

    which

    had

    already

    been

    laid

    out

    in

    the

    Maastricht

    Case,

    the

    Court

    elaborates

    significantlyonthisideahere. ItengagesintheratherinterestingargumentthattheEuropeanfriendly

    application of constitutional law demands that the Court engage in ultra vires review itself. More

    importantly,however,theCourtexpresslylaysouteachofthevariouspossibilitiesforsuchreviewunder

    currentprocedures. Anditcloseswithwhatlookslikeaninvitationtothelegislaturetocreateadditional

    typesofproceedingsbeforetheCourtthatareespeciallytailoredtoultraviresreviewandidentityreview

    to safeguard the obligation of German bodies not to apply in Germany, in individual cases, legal

    instrumentsoftheEuropeanUnionthattransgresscompetencesorthatviolateconstitutionalidentity.25

    4. CollectiveSecurityandInternationalRepresentation

    In theLisbondecision, theCourtsuggests for the first time that theEuropeanUnion iscurrentlynota

    systemof

    collective

    security

    within

    the

    meaning

    of

    Basic

    Law

    Article

    24(2).

    It

    says

    that

    even

    ifthe

    EuropeanUnion...weretobedeveloped intosuchasystem,nosupranationaldecisionmakingcould

    control the specificdeploymentofGerman troops.26

    This raises the interestingpossibility thatefforts

    suchasthecurrentGermannavaldeploymentonthecoastofAfrica,whereGermantroopsaresubjectto

    ajointEUcommand,areunconstitutional. UnderArticle24oftheBasicLaw,Germanymayonlyrestrict

    itssovereignpowersoveritsowntroopsinthecontextofasystemofcollectivesecurity. IftheEUdoes

    notcurrentlyqualifyassuchasystem,thenGermanywouldpresumablyhavetomaintaincommandover

    itsowntroopsunlesstheinterventionisauthorizedbytheUNorNATO.

    The Court similarly treads unreflectively into international terrain by suggesting, without warrant or

    argument, that states have to keep their formal status as a contracting party in an International

    21

    Id.

    at

    para.

    237.

    22TFEUart.352(1).

    23 Lisbon Case, BVerfG, 2 BvE/08 from 30 June 2009, para. 327, available at:

    http://www.bverfg.de/entscheidungen/es20090630_2bve000208.html..24

    Id.atpara.328.25

    Id.atpara.241.26

    Id.atpara.255.

  • 8/3/2019 Ja Zu Deutschland

    7/14

    Halberstam&Mllers 6OrganizationsothattheirmembershipwillnotbecompletelymediatedbytheEuropeanUnion.

    27 The

    WTO is thecase inpoint. TheCourt seems toassume thatWTOmembershipmustbeorganizedbya

    mixedagreementunderwhichMemberStatesremainparties. TheCourttellsusthatiftheEUalonewere

    amemberof theWTO, theGerman statewould somehowbedeprivedof itsproper function in trade

    negotiations. But it isfarfromclear,withregardtothepowerstheUnitedNationsSecurityCouncilfor

    example,whatthisdoctrinecouldmeanfortheinstitutionalstructureof international law. Indeed,one

    mightwell

    argue

    that

    the

    Court

    frustrates

    the

    national

    interest

    it

    seeks

    to

    serve.

    Under

    the

    existing

    conditions of a European Customs Union it seems odd that the European member states would be

    inevitablycommittedtofragmentingtheircommonEuropeannegotiatingpower. Inanyevent,thereal

    practicalimpactoftheCourtsdecisiononthispointisdebatable.

    II. ImaginingaUnionofMemberStates

    1. Statehood(re)gained

    FortheCourt,democracy isaconceptthat is limitedtoastatewithapeopleand itsterritory. Without

    eitherdrawingoninternationalorconstitutionallawtomakeitsclaimsexplicittheCourtemphasizesthe

    idea of territoriality. The basic point seems to be to define European territoriality and European

    citizenshipasderivativephenomena. InsodoingtheCourtdoesnotstrugglewithprimaryorsecondary

    lawon

    citizenship,

    borders,

    or

    security.

    Instead,

    it

    immunizes

    itself

    from

    these

    potentially

    burdensome

    considerations. Europe without borders is merely accessory to the state territory of the member

    states.28

    So,thestateisastatebecauseitisautonomous;itisautonomousbecauseitisastate.

    2. TheEuropeanParliamentDismissed

    InordertoensureamonistconceptionofEuropeandemocracyviathenationalpoliticalprocesstheCourt

    mustdeprive theEuropeanParliamentof its legitimacy. Itdoessowithaproblematicbutwellknown

    move,thejuxtapositionofparliamentarismanddemocracy,apatternbelongingtotheworsttraditionsof

    Germanconstitutionaltheory.29

    TheCourtbelittlesthegrowingemancipationofParliamentariansfrom

    their roleasmembersofnationaldelegations and theirgrowing constitutional selfperception aspan

    Europeandelegateson a leftrightdimension.30

    Nordoes it creditParliaments remarkable efforts to

    controlthe

    Commission.

    All

    this

    is

    rendered

    worthless

    because

    of

    the

    European

    Parliaments

    election

    procedure.

    The Court states correctly that the voting mechanisms to the European Parliament do not function

    accordingtoastrictruleofdemocraticequality,one(wo)man,onevote. Asaconsequence,however,the

    CourtdeniesanyclaimonthepartoftheEuropeanParliamenttodemocraticrepresentation. TheCourts

    statist logicassumesthat, ifthere isnopeoplethere isnoparliament. Asthere isnoEuropeanpeople,

    theEuropeanParliamentisnotarealparliament,i.e.apopularrepresentation(Volksvertretung).Itisonly

    a second chamber, a logic that en passant denies the United States Senate as well as the Swiss

    Stnderatitscharacterofdemocraticrepresentation.31

    27Id.atparas.37475.

    28Id.atpara.345.

    29CARLSCHMITT,DIEGEISTESGESCHICHTLICHELAGEDESHEUTIGENPARLAMENTARISMUS(1923).

    30SeeDanielHalberstam,TheBrideofMessina:ConstitutionalismandDemocracyinEurope,30EUR.L.REV.775(2005).

    31 Lisbon Case, BVerfG, 2 BvE/08 from 30 June 2009, para. 286, available at:

    http://www.bverfg.de/entscheidungen/es20090630_2bve000208.html..

  • 8/3/2019 Ja Zu Deutschland

    8/14

    TheLisbonDecision 7Atwin fallacy liesburied inthisargument. On theonehand, thedistinctionbetweena representative

    parliamentandanonrepresentativesecondchamberthatisnotstrictlyapportionedaccordingtoone

    persononevoteisspecifictoGermany. IntheGermanpoliticalsystemthesecondlegislativeorgan,the

    Bundesrat,comprisesrepresentativeoftheLndergovernments. Asabodycomposedofexecutives,itis

    not, strictly speaking, a parliament. But to draw on this distinction to undermine the representative

    quality of the European Parliament belies the Courts assertion that the standards it applies to the

    EuropeanUnion

    do

    not

    reflexively

    repeat

    national

    constitutional

    law.

    Ontheotherhand,theCourt isnotevenabletogiveacoherentdescriptionoftheGermaninstitutions.

    Elsewhereintheopinion,itclearlyidentifiestheBundesratasachamberofanationalparliament.32

    If

    theBundesrat,anonegalitarianrepresentationofthestates executives,istreatedlikeaParliament,then

    theEuropeanParliamentmust,afortiori,betreatedasone,too.

    There is more. The almost FrenchRepublican egalitarian demands the Court applies are especially

    irritatinggiventhefactthattheGermanfederalsystem isoftendiscussedasaprimeexampleofanon

    majoritarian political system.33

    Onemight argue in favor of the Court that it insists on at least one

    egalitarianbody inademocraticorder. But even this isnot convincingbecauseegalitarian legitimacy

    necessarily disappears in thejoint decisionmaking procedure. According to the Courts logic, a law

    makingprocedure that requires the consentofBundestag andBundesrat,which is regularly the case,

    couldeven

    violate

    the

    democratic

    principle

    of

    the

    German

    Basic

    Law

    in

    Germany.

    That

    aGerman

    court,

    operatinginasystemthatisnotoriousforfederaldeadlock,sovigorouslyadvocatesastrictmajoritarian

    conceptionofdemocracymustbeoneofthedecisionsbiggerironies. Andthefactthat,accordingtothe

    decision, the Federal government acting at the European level must at times be controlled by both

    Bundestag andBundesrat, leads to a final shortcircuit. To borrow from thewords of the Court, the

    Germansystemitselfmightbeoverfederalized.

    CaughtinitsowncontradictionstheCourtlooksforcontradictionsintheEuropeanlegalorder. TheCourt

    holds that the electoral law of the European Parliament shows an assessment of values that is in

    contradictiontothebasisoftheconceptofacitizensUnionthat[theUnion]hasofitself.34

    Thealleged

    contradictionstemsfromthefactthattherepresentation intheEuropeanParliamentdoesnottakeas

    its nexus equality of the citizens of the Union (Article 9 TEU Lisbon), but nationality.35

    But this

    assessmentof

    the

    European

    law

    is

    flatly

    wrong.

    An

    Italian

    citizen

    who

    lives

    in

    Lithuania

    votes

    for

    the

    Lithuaniancontingent intheEuropeanParliament. ASpanishcitizenwho lives inGreececanstandasa

    candidateforelectionsoftheGreekcontingenttotheEuropeanParliament. Itisaterritorialnexusthatis

    created by the right to free movement that defines the representative structure of the European

    Parliament. Thatmightnotliveuptoanystrictidealofdemocraticequalitybutitstillhasa logicthatis

    connectedtotheratherprofoundideaofEuropeancitizenship.

    3.AnUnnecessaryTheoryofNecessaryStateFunctions

    Forquitea longtimeastrangecommonplace inGermanconstitutionalscholarshiphasbeenthe lackof

    anyStaatsaufgabenlehre,that is,atheoryofwhatnecessarytasksthestatemustfulfill.36

    Itwashoped

    thatscholarsmightdefinethisfieldinapurelyconceptualeffortwithoutanyreferencetothenecessarily

    32Id.atpara.407.

    33 GERHARD LEHMBRUCH, PARTEIENWETTBEWERB IM BUNDESSTAAT (3d ed. 2000); Fritz Scharpf, TheJointDecision Trap: LessonsfromGermanFederalismandEuropeanIntegration,66PUB.ADMIN.239(1988).34

    Lisbon Case, BVerfG, 2 BvE/08 from 30 June 2009, para. 287, available at:http://www.bverfg.de/entscheidungen/es20090630_2bve000208.html..35

    Id.36

    SeeCHRISTOPHMLLERS,STAATALSARGUMENT146n.67(2000).

  • 8/3/2019 Ja Zu Deutschland

    9/14

    Halberstam&Mllers 8opendemocraticprocess. Thisdreamofa conceptualdeductionof thebeingoressenceof the state

    Wesenanditsagendasnevertookconcreteform. Instead,itremainedanostalgicsentimentaboutwhat

    mighthavebeenacompletetheoryofthestate.37

    It isnoaccidentthatsucha theoryhasneverbeenwritten.38

    Inadifferentcontext, theUnitedStates

    SupremeCourthasalsostruggledwith,and retreated from,comprehensivelydefiningwhatconstitutes

    traditionalareas

    of

    state

    regulation.

    39

    An

    open

    democratic

    process

    makes

    it

    difficult

    to

    define

    in

    any

    comprehensivewaywhatareasof legislation form thestatesnecessary tasks. Tobesure,any such

    theorywould, indeed,helpusdrawmetaconstitutional linesaroundthepowerofthestate. Anysuch

    doctrine could then protect the state from various forms of disaggregation, privatization, as well as

    Europeanizationand internationalization. Still, inGermany,thedreamofaStaatsaufgabenlehreproject

    haslongbeenforgotten.

    Forgotten? Suddenly and without precedent the Courts Lisbon Case develops its own

    Staatsaufgabenlehre. TheCourtdefines five areas inwhich the statemust take a role: Criminal law

    (substantialandprocedural),warandpeace,publicexpendituresandtaxation,welfare,andcultureand

    religion. Thesetasksare,accordingtotheCourt,especiallysensitive fortheabilityofaconstitutional

    state todemocratically shape itself.40

    But is thereany theoryorargumentbehind this list? We find

    none in theopinion. TheCourtmerely refers to itsown imaginationofpastsovereignty. Theopinion

    assertsthat

    seit

    jeher,

    since

    ever,

    the

    state

    has

    fulfilled

    these

    tasks

    as

    an

    expression

    of

    its

    sovereignty.

    This is obviously not the case. The welfare function of the European nation state has often been

    describedasthebeginningoftheendofthe ideaofsovereignty,asthepointofdissolutionofthestate

    into society.41

    Religionwasadecisive topicof theWestphalianTreatySystem that standsat thevery

    beginning of the modern concept of sovereignty in Public International Law, a concept the Court

    otherwise explicitly endorses. Religiondidnotbelong to state sovereignty at the verymomentof its

    invention.42

    Ontheotherhand,whatabouttheomissionofCivilLaw inthe list? Despitethefactthat

    GermanBGB,theCivilCode,wasthecentralcodificationofthenewlyfoundedGermannationstate,the

    Court does not even mention this area of law as being special to the German states identity or

    sovereignty. Andwhat about the controlover currencya field thatoften hasbeenmentioned as a

    classicalprerogativeofthestate? Fromeitherahistoricalorasystematicperspective,thelistmakesno

    sense.

    Then again, why does the Court classify just the five areas on its list as necessary parts to state

    sovereignty? Theanswer is simple. Thetheoryof theCourt isaposthocargument in supportofa

    preordainedresult.

    37Thisfeelingseemstoberathercommon. See,e.g.,CHRISTOPHMLLERS,DERVERMISSTELEVIATHAN(2008).

    38TheclosestbookmaybefromHansPeterBull. SeeHANSPETERBULL,DIESTAATSAUFGABENNACHDEMGRUNDGESETZ(2ded.1977).

    39 Forthedevelopmentoftraditionalcomponentstatepowers,see,e.g.,NationalLeagueofCitiesv.Usery,426U.S.833 (1976);

    Garciav.SanAntonioMetropolitanTransitAuthority,469U.S.528(1985);NewYorkv.UnitedStates505U.S.144(1992);Printzv.UnitedStates521U.S.898 (1997);UnitedStatesv. Lopez,514U.S.549 (1995). In the contextofU.S. federalism, theSupreme

    Courtssubstantive

    distinction

    between

    the

    areas

    of

    state

    and

    federal

    powers

    is

    notoriously

    undertheorized,

    as

    is

    the

    Courts

    proceduralororganizationalunderstandingofcomponentstateautonomy. See,e.g.,DanielHalberstam,Comparative FederalismandtheIssueofCommandeering,inTHEFEDERALVISION213(KalypsoNicoladis&RobertHowseeds.,2001).40

    Lisbon Case, BVerfG, 2 BvE/08 from 30 June 2009, para. 252, available at:http://www.bverfg.de/entscheidungen/es20090630_2bve000208.html..41

    ThepioneeringauthormaybeHaroldLaski. SeeHAROLD J.LASKI,STUDIES INTHEPROBLEMOFSOVEREIGNTY (1924).Butseealso the

    worksofLonDuguit.42

    STEVEND.KRASNER,SOVEREIGNTY:ORGANIZEDHYPOCRISY7980(1999).

  • 8/3/2019 Ja Zu Deutschland

    10/14

    TheLisbonDecision 9The only concrete holding of the decision with its myriad treatiselike passages strikes down the

    Begleitgesetz, the accompanying statute that organizes the participation of the Bundestag and the

    Bundesratwith regard to thepasserelleprovisionsof the treaty. According to the Court, the Federal

    government in certain areas cannot agree to a passerelle procedure that shifts from unanimous to

    majoritydecisionmakinginthecouncilwithoutconfirmationbyparliament. Asaninitialmatter,itseems

    rather questionable whether this mechanism increases the effectiveness of parliamentary control.43

    Whatis

    most

    striking,

    however,

    is

    that

    the

    policy

    areas

    that

    define

    sovereignty

    map

    perfectly

    onto

    the

    subjectmatterofthespecificpasserelleclausesthatareatissueinthiscase.

    OnecannotbutsuspectthattheCourtdesigneditstheoryaroundtheonlyresultitcouldpossiblyachieve.

    Without becoming responsible for the fall of the LisbonTreaty on the one hand, but with the firm

    intentiontoshow itsreadinessto intervene,ontheother,thetreatmentofthepasserellewasaperfect

    target. This small result thus wags a metaconstitutional theory that no proper constitutional

    interpretationcouldcreate.

    Thedeep ironyofthispartofthedecision lies inthefactthattheallegedtheoryofthesovereignstate

    simply stems from a negative reading of the European Treaties. There is no convincing systematic

    argumentwhyotherpolicyareasdonotnecessarilybelongtothestate. WhattheCourtdeemstobe

    protected are merely the leftovers of European integration recycled as necessary elements of state

    sovereignty.A

    more

    devastating

    bankruptcy

    of

    asolipsistic

    theory

    of

    the

    state

    is

    hard

    to

    imagine.

    4. TheConstitutionalDoublebind

    TheCourtleavesEuropeinadoublebindacombinationofmutuallydefeatingcommands.44

    Ontheone

    handwe learnabouttheforbiddenfinalityofaEuropeanBundesstaat. Ontheotherhand,thecurrent

    levelofintegrationissaidtofailminimalconstitutionalstandardsforaEuropeanpolity. ThemoreEurope

    seekstodeepenitspolity,then,themoreitrunsupagainsttheprohibitionsoftheGermanconstitution.

    AtsomepointEuropeanintegrationmuststoportheGermanswillhavetogiveuptheirconstitution.

    The treatment of the European Parliament is a case in point. The Court dismisses the legitimacy

    achievementsoftheEuropeanParliament. But itdoesso inreviewingwhethertheTreatyrespectsthe

    democraticprinciples

    that

    the

    German

    constitution

    demands

    of

    European

    integration.

    But

    why

    does

    the Court examine the European Parliament at all if, as the Court suggests, all democratic legitimacy

    stems from the Member States? The answer is that the Court seems to accept that the European

    Parliament delivers some additional legitimacy to the EU as long as the EP does not become too

    important,i.e.ofequalimportancetotheCouncil.

    The suggestion that theParliamentadds legitimacy to theUnion seems to contradict theCourtsown

    explicit thesis that the frameworkofdemocracy issomethinginviolable thatcannotbebalanced.45

    Moreover,theargumentabouttheEPsadded legitimacycreatesastrangeambivalenceinwhichtheEP

    somehowremainsbothanecessaryelementandathreattotheconstitutionalityofEuropeanintegration.

    TheCourtshowsasimilarambivalenceinreviewingEuropeanSocialPolicy.46

    Ontheonehand,European

    integration cannotbeapurelymarketorientedproject. Thiswould violate theGerman constitutional

    obligationto

    promote

    the

    social

    principle

    in

    the

    EU.

    On

    the

    other

    hand,

    it

    would

    be

    even

    more

    43SeeinfraPartC.

    44GREGORYBATESON,STEPSTOANECOLOGYOFMIND159338(1999).

    45 Lisbon Case, BVerfG, 2 BvE/08 from 30 June 2009, para. 216, available at:

    http://www.bverfg.de/entscheidungen/es20090630_2bve000208.html..46

    Id.atparas.39394.

  • 8/3/2019 Ja Zu Deutschland

    11/14

    Halberstam&Mllers 10dangeroustoerectacompleteEuropeanwelfaresystemandtherebyestablishaEuropeanBundesstaat

    throughthebackdoor.

    These ambiguities, thejuxtaposition of numerous commands pulling in opposite directions, create a

    doublebind. WhateverEuropedoesinwhateverwayitdevelopswouldseemtoviolatethestandards

    setforthbytheCourt. Theremightbetoomuch,andtheremightbetoolittleparliamentarylegitimacy;

    toomuch

    or

    too

    little

    social

    standards,

    and

    so

    on.

    Notwithstanding

    its

    grand

    announcement

    that

    the

    BasicLawhas renouncedall formsof politicalMachiavellianism, theCourt turnsout tobeawicked

    strategistitself. Readcarefully,itsdecisioncondemnstheEUtofinalitinastateofperpetualdeficiency.

    C. TheRoleoftheConstitutionalCourtI. InstructingtheGermanParliamenttoInstructtheGermanGovernment

    TheLisbondecisionurgestheGermanBundestagtocontrolthegovernmentinawaythattheparliament

    itself could have done but did not do. Early commentators of the decision were quick to criticize

    parliament for its failure and to congratulate the Court for its democratic sensitivity.47

    But did the

    BundestagreallynotknowwhatitwasdoingwhenitdecideduponthesocalledAusweitungsgesetz(i.e.

    thenowunconstitutionalstatutethatorganizestheparticipationoftheBundestagandtheBundesrat in

    theprocess

    of

    European

    integration)?

    Political science has taught us that parliamentary control of international negotiations between

    governmentsisanextremelyproblematicandoftenfruitlesseffort. Thetwolevelgameofgovernments

    in the internationalarenahasoftenbeendescribed,48

    andthere isso farnoconvincingremedy toput

    national parliaments in a stronger position in such settings. This is particularly problematic in

    parliamentary systems inwhich themain responsibility of themajority is to back and strengthen the

    government.49

    TheauthorsoftheBasicLaw,evermindfulofthedemiseofWeimar,wereespeciallykeen

    to guarantee the stability of the government. It seems quite improbable that formal obligations of

    parliamentaryconsentwillmateriallyenhanceParliamentspolitical influence intheEuropeandecision

    making procedure. Parliament will not have more substantial influence but it will be explicitly held

    politicallyresponsiblefortheresultsthataredefinedbythegovernment.50

    TheCourtsprofessionofconcernabouttheutterdestructionoftheGermanconstitutionseemsstrange

    in lightof its failure tograpple substantivelywith the singlemost importantprovisionon the subject:

    BasicLawArticle23. Thisprovision,whichbringstheprojectofEuropeanintegrationintotheframework

    of theBasicLaw,expressly requires that theFederalgovernmentadhere to theordersof theGerman

    Bundestag. Theexplicit ideaoftheprovision isthattheGermanparliamentmay,butneednot,commit

    theFederalGovernmenttoacertainposition intheEuropeancontext. Thisnormexpressesrespectfor

    thedemocraticwillofthelegislaturethatseemsespeciallywellsuitedtoaparliamentarysysteminwhich

    theparliamentarymajorityregularlyhasthesamepoliticalagendaastheGovernment. Onewouldthink

    that the framers of Article 23 meant to provide a comprehensive statement of the constitutionally

    requiredrelationshipbetweenParliamentandGovernmentinmatterspertainingtoEuropeanintegration.

    47See,e.g.,HeribertPrantl,Verfassungsgericht zu Lissabon-Vertrag - Europische Sternstunde, SDDEUTSCHEZEITUNG,July1,2009.

    48RobertD.Putnam,DiplomacyandDomesticPolitics: TheLogicofTwoLevelGames,42INT'LORG.427(1988).

    49WALTERBAGEHOT,THEENGLISHCONSTITUTION69(1967).

    50Inadditiontothat,thereisacertainironyinthefactthatinothercasesofforeignrelationslawtheCourttookjusttheopposite

    stance. Inmany cases regarding theparliamentaryparticipation in thedevelopmentofNATO, theCourt didnotonly refrain to

    developconstitutionalduties forparliamentaryparticipationbut,tothecontrary,defined itsconstitutional limits. BVerfGE68,1;

    BVerfGE104,151.

  • 8/3/2019 Ja Zu Deutschland

    12/14

    TheLisbonDecision 11TheCourtdoesnotengagewithanyofthisandsimplyholdsthattheprovisionsoftheAusweitungsgesetz

    violateBasicLawArticle23(1),whichisthegeneralnormrequiringthatGermanyparticipateinEuropean

    integrationaccordingtodemocraticstandards. TheCourtdoesnotseemtoconsiderthepossibilitythat

    Article 23(1) may not be the relevant norm, as Basic Law Article 23(3) provides the definitive and

    comprehensive statementof the constitutionally requiredprocedural standard that shouldgovern this

    case. TurningtoBasicLawArticle23(3),however,wouldbeinconvenient,giventhattheBundestagand

    theBundesrat

    specifically

    adhered

    to

    its

    provisions

    during

    the

    deliberations

    on

    the

    ratification

    of

    the

    LisbonTreaty.

    ThedecisiontosetasidethespecificnormofBasicLawArticle23(3)infavorofinvokingthemoregeneral

    normofArticle23(1)onlymakessenseinlightoftheCourtsmassiveEuroskepticreservationsexpressed

    inthecourseofanalyzingthestatute. BecausetheCourtisconfrontedwithaspecificconstitutionalnorm

    thatseemstogovernthecaseathand,theopinionmustturntoagrandtheoryofdemocraticlegitimacy.

    Italsoneedsasuperconstitutionalnormtotransformthistheoryintolegalargument.

    This iswhereBasic LawArticle79(3)comes in. Thenormativebasis for transforminghigh theory into

    insuperable doctrine is the socalled eternity clause. This norm imposes certain unalterable

    constitutionalstandards, includingtheprincipleofdemocratic legitimacy. TheCourtseemsto interpret

    Article23(1)inthelightofArticle79(3)togivethefirstnormahigherstatusallintheserviceofbypassing

    themore

    specific

    Basic

    Law

    Article

    23(3).

    But

    Article

    79(3)

    was

    not

    meant

    to

    protect

    Germany

    against

    Europe. It was meant to prevent the German state from a new 1933, from a slow slippage into

    totalitarianism without an obviously illegal break. Though nobody in the constituent Parliamentary

    Councilbelievedthatanynormcouldsaveapoliticalorder,thenormwouldnonethelessserveasasign

    fortheidentityofthenewdemocraticconstitution. ItisthushighlydubiousthatBasicLawArticle79(3)

    wasmeanttopreservethesovereigntyoftheGermanstatewithintheprocessofEuropeanintegration.

    TooperationalizethetheorythatEuropeandemocracyisgroundedexclusivelyintheMemberStates,the

    Court conjures up the idea of a modification of treaty law (Vernderung des Vertragsrechts)51

    that

    needstheexplicitconsentoftheGerman legislature.52

    Vernderung isanotherkeyterm intheCourts

    elaborateopinionthatmustbeexaminedwithcare. ItsignifiesthemodificationoftheTreatiesthatisnot

    a formalamendment (whichwouldbe termedaVertragsnderung). Onemight,ofcourse,argue that

    everysubstantial

    reinterpretation

    of

    the

    Treaties

    is

    amodification

    of

    the

    treaty

    of

    the

    former

    kindnot

    allofwhichcandemandafreshroundofratification. Moreover,theTreatyofNiceknowsmanyexplicit

    textualprovisionsthatallowforwhattheCourtwouldnowtermmodifications,suchasthepossibility

    to change the number of European Commissioners or Advocates General on the ECJ by unanimous

    decisionofthecouncil.53

    ButtheCourtdoesnotobjecttothese. Instead, itseemstoobjecttothose

    modifications that were somehow not sufficiently defined in the Treaty. We are generally left to

    wonderwhatthismeansinpractice,butonethingisclear: byintroducingthetermofVernderung,the

    Courtinstallsitselfasthearbitertodistinguishperhapswiththehelpofitsflawedadhoctheoryofstate

    functionsbetweenthemodificationsthatrequireratificationandthosethatdonot.

    PerhapstheCourtsmostplausibleweknowitwhenweseeitobjection istoArt.352TFEU,thenew

    FlexibilityClause. ThenearuniversalapplicabilityofthisclausethreatenstoleavethescopeofEuropean

    competences truly open ended. But to submerge this real concern in a host of unsubstantiated

    judgments,as

    the

    Court

    did,

    obscures

    the

    real

    question

    of

    articulating

    more

    precisely

    and

    more

    usefully

    51 Lisbon Case, BVerfG, 2 BvE/08 from 30 June 2009, para. 409, available at:

    http://www.bverfg.de/entscheidungen/es20090630_2bve000208.html..52

    Id.53

    TreatyEstablishingtheEuropeanCommunity,Dec.24,2002,art.213(1)(3),2002O.J.(C325)33,120[hereinafterECTreaty];EC

    Treatyart.,222(2).

  • 8/3/2019 Ja Zu Deutschland

    13/14

    Halberstam&Mllers 12what should be done about Article 352 TFEU and why. To be sure, Article 352 TFEU may well be

    overbroad. ButifeveryinvocationofArticle352TFEUdemandsratification,eventhemorelimitedresort

    toArticle352TFEU formarketpurposes (which theCourtapproved intheMaastrichtCaseabsentany

    specialnationalratificationprocedure)willnowbemuchharderthanitwaseverbefore.

    TheremainingjudgmentsontheGermanparliamentsrelationwiththegovernmentseemhighlysuspect

    aswell.

    It

    is

    unclear

    why

    the

    specific

    passerelle

    clausesor

    even

    the

    general

    passerelle

    clauseshould

    be

    subjecttonationalratification. Tobesure,theseclausestightenEuropeanintegration. Butthescopeof

    thistighteningisperfectlydefined. Therearenumerousclausesthatprovideforqualifiedmajorityvoting

    andtheordinarylegislativeprocedure. Whattheseproceduresentailisperfectlyknown. Indeed,choices

    betweenthetwoformsofdecisionwithregardtoasinglepolicyareaalreadyexist,asinthefamoustwin

    articlesof94 and95ECor themanyprovisions that allow for a choiceof governancebydirectiveor

    regulation. Moreover,theMemberStatescouldclearlyhaveoptedtosubjectalltheareascoveredbythe

    variouspasserelleclausesdirectly to themore integrateddecisionmakingprocedureon suchmatters.

    ButtheCourtgivesnoreasonwhythisgreaterpowerdoesnotincludethelesserpowerexercisedhere.

    TheCourtsdecisionontheemergencybrakealsomakesnosensewhatsoever. Here,theCourtsubjects

    the invocation of the emergency brake to the prior consent of the German legislature. Although

    integration enthusiasts shouldwelcome the interesting and almost certainly unintended result of this

    holding,54this

    part

    of

    the

    opinion

    does

    not

    safeguard

    Germany

    from

    any

    creeping

    loss

    of

    power.

    II. SuperCounterMajoritarianism

    The idea that the eternity clause of Basic Law Article 79(3) protects German sovereignty (or

    statehood)isanacademicinventionofthe1980s.55

    IntheLisbonCasetheCourtnowusesthisnormto

    createasomewhatirritatingchoicebetweentwoalternatives: ThepeopleofAdenauer,Brandt,andKohl

    whowantcontinuedEuropeanintegrationandempowermentoftheEuropeanparliamentinathoroughly

    democraticspiritmustremainwithintheboundsdeterminedbytheCourtorelsetheGermanpeople

    mustgiveupitsconstitution.

    Inarathersurprisingtwist,theCourtseemstoexpanditsreviewingpowerbeyondalllimitstoreachfor

    judicialcontrol

    even

    of

    the

    pouvoir

    constituant

    of

    the

    German

    people.

    Given

    the

    general

    carelessness

    of

    theopiniononemightthinkthepassagesinquestionsaremerelyaccidental. Butasthereatleastthree

    referencestothisidea,weshouldtaketheCourtatitsword. TheCourtstates,forexample,thatArticle

    23(1)oftheBasicLawdoesnotbindtheGermanstate,buttheGermanpeople.56

    Inotherpassages,

    the Court explicitly leaves openwhether the German people themselvesmight not be bound by the

    eternityclause.57

    If thiswere true,however, therecouldbeno revolutionaryescape intoaEuropean

    federationfortheGermanpeoplewhatsoever.

    Finally,theCourttakesBasicLawArt.146(whichenvisionsthattheGermanpeoplemaygiveitselfanew

    constitution)tocontainarightthatcanbeinvokedbyindividualsinCourt.58

    Thisideaisconceptuallyso

    absurdthateventheCourthasahardtimeexpressingit. Welearnthatthisisapreconstitutionalright

    thattheBasicLawmerelyconfirms.59

    TheCourtexplainstheideainits,bynowcharacteristicmove,of

    54SeesupraSectionB.

    55SeeMLLERS,supranote36,atCh.17.

    56 Lisbon Case, BVerfG, 2 BvE/08 from 30 June 2009, para. 229, available at:

    http://www.bverfg.de/entscheidungen/es20090630_2bve000208.html..57

    Id.atpara.217.58

    Id.atpara.180.59

    Id.atpara.179.

  • 8/3/2019 Ja Zu Deutschland

    14/14

    TheLisbonDecision 13denyingwhatitsupports: ThefactthatArticle146oftheBasicLawdoesnotestablishan independent

    claimthatcanbeassertedbyaconstitutionalcomplaint...isnotcontrarytothepossibilityoflodginga

    constitutionalcomplaintagainstthelossofstatehood. Forthisdoesnotruleoutthataviolationmaybe

    challenged under Article 146 of the Basic Law in conjunctionwith the fundamental rights and rights

    equivalenttothefundamentallaws....60

    Allin

    all,

    the

    revolutionary

    act

    of

    constitution

    making

    is

    down

    sized

    to

    an

    ordinary

    act

    that

    is

    henceforth

    underreviewoftheCourt. Accordingtothedecision,thepeoplewhowantademocraticrevolutionmust

    petitiontheCourt.

    D. ConclusionThe German Federal Constitutional Court has never made true on theMaastricht Cases promise to

    reviewEuropeanactsundertheultraviresdoctrine. InnocasesinceSolange I61

    hasCourtreviewedor

    struck down an act of the European authorities. Maastricht had come to look like a hollow threat,

    especiallyaftertheCourtpassedontheopportunityto intervene intheBananaCase.62

    Thecaseofthe

    LisbonTreaty,therefore,putconsiderablepressureontheCourttoshowitstruecolors. Woulditsoften

    the project of national constitutional review or give some kind of new credibility to its claims in the

    MaastrichtCase.

    AsthenakedjudgmenttouchesonlyuponGermanstatutorylaw,theentiredecisionseemsratherlikea

    performativeutterance inwhich theCourtunderlines itsown importance ina strange combinationof

    rhetoric and verbosity. The Lisbon Case takes over 421 paragraphs tomake several confused points.

    Indeed,theCourtsopinionmightmakeeventhemosthardenedcriticnostalgicfortherelativeclarityof

    theMaastrichtCase,whichtooklessthanhalfasmanywordstoreviewahistorictreatyamendmentthat

    gavesubstantialnewpowerstotheEuropeanpolity,erectedtheEuropeanUnion,establishedaCommon

    SecurityandDefensePolicy,andcreatedanewcurrency.

    HastheCourtsaidJazumVertragvonLissabon? Wethinknot.63

    60Id.atpara.180.

    61

    BVerfGE

    37,

    271.

    62BVerfGE102,147.

    63Thereisonerathernicepointintheopinionatparagraph415. Article1,4(3),cl.3oftheActExtendingandStrengtheningthe

    Rights of theBundestag and the Bundesrat in EuropeanUnionMatters provides that in formulating theGerman governmentspositionwithregardtothegeneralbridgeclause,theBundesratandBundestagcaneachoverridetheothersinvocationoftheveto.As theCourtproperlypointsout,however,only theBundestagcanoverride theBundesratssuggestionofaveto. Toallow theBundesrattooverridetheBundestagsveto,isamisunderstandingofGermanconstitutionallaw. Wecouldnotagreemore.