I Criminal Justice and Legal Reparat ions as an...

14
PHILOSC)PHICAL ISSUES, 11 Social, Politicd, and LcgaI Philuuophy, 2001 Criminal Justice and Legal Reparat ions as an Alternative to Punishment ' I. Introduction Consider n just society, with reasarrable laws, fairly enforced by an appropriate authority. In this context, how should society re- spond to those legitimately determined to have broken the law?2 Marly have thought the right answer is: "with punishment." In support of this answer, t,hree sorts of justification fos pun- ishment are comnlonly offered. Some justifications appeal to the demands of justice and consjderations of desert t o th~ criminal deserving punishment or to the victims or other rizembers of society deserving state sanctioned retribution. Somp justjfica, tions appeal instead to utility and especially to the prosprct of deterrence-to the thought that the threat of punishment, or pull- ishrnent itself, will work io prevent crime. Finally. some appeal to purlishment 's role in establishing, expressing, or affirming soci- e ty's commitment to the (frequently moral) judgments embodied in the law. Often enough one or another- such justification is advanced by itself as both necessary and sufficient for determining when-and . - 19. CRIMINAL JUSTICE AND LEGAL REPARATIONS 503 the extent to w]filicl~-criminuls may or rn~ist be punished. Yet they are also often cornbilled in the attempt to fashion a theory that appeals to considerations of justice and desert as well as to the importance of deterrence and the role punishment can play in expressing moral disapproval and contributing to moral educatjvn. XIy purpose in thia paper is to argtle that these familiar justi- fications of punishment, taken either individually or in combina- ! tinn. all (to thp dent, they are plausible) recommend a practice I i~rlportantly different from punishment. I call the alternative Legal Reparations, and will, in the course of this paper, (i) dist;ingnish I it horn punishment, (ii) sketch the institutiollal form it might; take, and (iii) argue thal Lhe jubtifications traditiondly offcrcd in favor of punishment actually instead favc)r legal reparations. I won't spend a lot of time sorting through the variety of ways one might ;ry to combine the three sorts of justifications hnt will instend focus on each kind considered alone. Nonetheless, my preferred mix of the three will. I suspect, become evident. Some such mix of all three considerations is, I think, essential to any defensible state response to violations of its laws. Only a prartice that ad- dresses ~onsidera~tions of all three kinds can be such * to secure the reasonable agreement of those who would be subject to the practice-and that is itself crucial .lo the practice being justmi- ijcd. 1 won't here defend this last claiui. I riler~tiotl it now only to acknowledge the role it will play-perha,ps, in places, only surreptitiously-in the version of Legal &parations T sketch. 11. Punishment asld Legal Reparations: The contrast Pmlishrneut, as Staniey Benn observed, is "inflicted on an of- fender becamuse of an offense he has committed; it is delihpratcly imposed, not just the natural consequence of a person's action (like a hang-over), and the unpleasantness is essential to it, not an accidentd awompaalimenf to some other treatment (like the paill of the dentist's cirill)." Similarly, H.L.A. Bart notes that punishment <'must involve pain or other consequences normally conside~ed unpleasant" and '*rust be for an offense against. iegal rules." Along the same lines, Richard Wasserstrom emphasizes that "the point of t h e imposition of a deprivation wllen it is un- mistakably a punishment is that il is being in~posed bccauac it is s deprimtion, because the person upon whom it is being imposed should thereby be made to s~tffer and in that respect be worse off

Transcript of I Criminal Justice and Legal Reparat ions as an...

Page 1: I Criminal Justice and Legal Reparat ions as an …gsmunc/reparations/Legal_Reparations.pdfPHILOSC)PHICAL ISSUES, 11 Social, Politicd, and LcgaI Philuuophy, 2001 Criminal Justice and

PHILOSC)PHICAL ISSUES, 11 Social, Politicd, and LcgaI Philuuophy, 2001

Criminal Justice and Legal Reparat ions as an Alternative to Punishment '

I. Introduction

Consider n just society, with reasarrable laws, fairly enforced by an appropriate authority. In this context, how should society re- spond to those legitimately determined to have broken the law?2 Marly have thought the right answer is: "with punishment."

In support of this answer, t,hree sorts of justification fos pun- ishment are comnlonly offered. Some justifications appeal to the demands of justice and consjderations of desert t o t h ~ criminal deserving punishment or t o the victims or other rizembers of society deserving state sanctioned retribution. Somp justjfica, tions appeal instead to utility and especially to the prosprct of deterrence-to the thought that the threat of punishment, or pull- ishrnent itself, will work i o prevent crime. Finally. some appeal to purlishment ' s role in establishing, expressing, or affirming soci- e ty's commitment to the (frequently moral) judgments embodied in the law.

Often enough one or another- such justification is advanced by itself as both necessary and sufficient for determining when-and

. -

19. CRIMINAL JUSTICE AND LEGAL REPARATIONS 503

the extent to w]filicl~-criminuls may or rn~ist be punished. Yet they are also often cornbilled in the attempt to fashion a theory that appeals to considerations of justice and desert as well as to the importance of deterrence and the role punishment can play in expressing moral disapproval and contributing to moral educatjvn.

XIy purpose in thia paper is to argtle that these familiar justi- fications of punishment, taken either individually or in combina-

! tinn. all (to t h p d e n t , they are plausible) recommend a practice

I i~rlportantly different from punishment. I call the alternative Legal Reparations, and will, in the course of this paper, (i) dist;ingnish

I

it horn punishment, (ii) sketch the institutiollal form it might; take, and (iii) argue thal Lhe jubtifications traditiondly offcrcd in favor of punishment actually instead favc)r legal reparations. I won't spend a lot of time sorting through the variety of ways one might ;ry to combine the three sorts of justifications hnt will instend focus on each kind considered alone. Nonetheless, my preferred mix of the three will. I suspect, become evident. Some such mix of all three considerations is, I think, essential to any defensible s ta te response to violations of its laws. Only a prartice that ad- dresses ~onsidera~tions of all three kinds can be such * to secure the reasonable agreement of those who would be subject to the practice-and that is itself crucial .lo the practice being justmi- ijcd. 1 won't here defend this last claiui. I riler~tiotl it now only to acknowledge the role it will play-perha,ps, in places, only surreptitiously-in the version of Legal &parations T sketch.

11. Punishment asld Legal Reparations: The contrast

Pmlishrneut, as Staniey Benn observed, is "inflicted on an of- fender becamuse of an offense he has committed; it is delihpratcly imposed, not just the natural consequence of a person's action (like a hang-over), and the unpleasantness is essential t o it, not an accidentd awompaalimenf to some other treatment (like the paill of the dentist's cirill)." Similarly, H.L.A. Bart notes that punishment <'must involve pain or other consequences normally conside~ed unpleasant" and '*rust be for an offense against. iegal rules." Along the same lines, Richard Wasserstrom emphasizes that "the point of the imposition of a deprivation wllen it is un- mistakably a punishment is that il is being in~posed bccauac it is s deprimtion, because the person upon whom it is being imposed should thereby be made to s~tffer and in that respect be worse off

Page 2: I Criminal Justice and Legal Reparat ions as an …gsmunc/reparations/Legal_Reparations.pdfPHILOSC)PHICAL ISSUES, 11 Social, Politicd, and LcgaI Philuuophy, 2001 Criminal Justice and

g M

d,

* .G

U4

-d

8 x

.sg

8; %

i F:-

a,,

MG

5 2

.? f? * -

E Fj

a3 % g

5 2

0 4

.z 22% g

rn .3

+

3%

u 5

*s

8 &

2 83 a

2.22-

g 53 A

a,

$*.a

07

"-a

a ag-?

3 w

.-

0

"3

3

1%

s 4 cl a

8

$"

Es 3

" "d M

F1 9 h

22

3 8 O

cH

0

5%

O L5

>-

+

g-w

%-

G

. c

2 C

U o

W

U:

32

2°C

Page 3: I Criminal Justice and Legal Reparat ions as an …gsmunc/reparations/Legal_Reparations.pdfPHILOSC)PHICAL ISSUES, 11 Social, Politicd, and LcgaI Philuuophy, 2001 Criminal Justice and

19. CRIMINAL JUSTICE AND LEGAL REPARATIONS 507

ing, is not achieved merely by compensating the victim. Mere com- pensation, after all, might be secured in a number of ways that leave the criminal's standing vis-h-vjs society unchanged, as, for instance, when the compensation is paid by snrne third party or by the criminal himself in a way that leaves the offense (even if not the harm) unaddressed. Whatever might effect the repair, arid so the relevant rehabilitation, must do so by restoring the crimi- nal's standing within society.

What is crucial to restoring the standing? I think there is no single substantive answer to this question. Society, in effect, needs to settle what it will, in practice, take as sufficient for rehabilit+ tion. features of human psychology no doubt limit and shape what might he seen as appropriately addressing the breach an offense constitutes. St ill, whatever limits there are evidently ieave open a strikingly broad range of possibilities. No doubt, what- ever is expccted, by way of efforts at repair, should reflect the relative seriousness of the offenses, with the more serious offenses cal l j~g for more sig~iificitnt efforts. Yet what sort of efforts might be deemed appropriate, artd how their significance might be mea- sured, is a matter of convent ion. Same crimes, of course, will be so serious that no amount of effort will count as sufficient. In sucb cases. efforts at making itmerids can never be successfilf on their own and will need to be met with some sort of institutional forgj-\~eness. But not all crimes will call for forgiveness once a ger- petrator has made efforts t o make amends. There can be a point at which the criminal has in fact paid his debt to society and is hinlself owed good standing. To bar him still is, 1 believe, to do h in~ an injustice. What is it, then, that can repair t he breach a crime introduces? The answer offered by reparations is: the crimi- nal's effort towards repair-not because that effort is painhll (though it may be), but because it addresses dirert.1~ and posi- tively the damage (the harm and the offense) done 1)y tIlr crime.

Legal reparations aim to enforce efforts at making nanends for thc offense committed, not to inflict pain for that offense. Still! any state response to crime-other than passive acquiescence-is bound to involve pain for the criminal, since it is bourld often t.o rely on coercion. This does not mean, however, that a system of reparations is really one of punishment after all. Treatment prw grams and restitution schemes, no less than a system of legal rep- arations, will involve sometimes forcing people to do what they would rather not. Even so, there is an important moral difference between making someone act in a certain way, where so acting happens to be painful for them, and intentionally inflicting pain.

Punishment is in place only when the infliction of pain is part of the point of the practice.

Of course, knowingly causing pair1 requires justification, even when the pain caused is unintended. So a system of reparations, which will sometimes cause people pain, stands (as does punish- ment) in need of justification. The burden facing reparations, how- ever, is reasonably thought to be different from and less than that facing a system of criminal punishment. If there is some- thji~g right about the doctrine of double effect--so that intention- ally inflicting paill or harm is worse in itself than merely knowingly causing p a j ~ ~ or haam-then purlishiuent ( d i k e reparations) stands on the wrong side of the contrast requires special consider- ations in order to be justified, if it can be justified at all. And even if the difference between intending and merely knowingly causing pain i~ not morally significant in itself, the difference can make a huge difference in how much pain is actually produced. For t,here will likely be many situations in which a call for pun- ishment will require the infliction of pain where a parallel call for reparations will require much less (if any).13

system^ of punishment and reparation alike can, and surely must, recogrlizc a limit on how much pain might legitimately be pro- duced in response to a given crime, so that both might reash such a Iirnit and have to stop. Still, in aiming at the infliction of pain. a system of punishment is, one may suppose, more likely to reach that limit than will be a system that lacks that aim. This is wen more likely if the system of reparations views the pain felt not just as a side effect, but as an unfortunate one that is reasonably alleviated so long as alleviating it does not work against the sys- tem's aims.14

The underlying idea of a system of reparations-that a person who commits an offense has a duty to make amends-eems t o m e appropriate not only for crirninaI offenses but more generally whenever someone violates a justified prohibition. My concern in this paper, however, is with the state's response to crime. In its irlstitut ional incarnation, as a part of a criminal justice system, reparations will, I am supposing, take on a structure that has the fruits of a criminal's efforts contribute to a state fund that vic- tims can, in turn, call upon for at least partial compensation. Decisions as to what should be required of people for various of- fenses will be independent of the actual darnages caused by par- ticular instances of that kind of offense and will instead ref1ec.t an ordinal ranking of various kincls of offense in terms of their seri- ousness (though that ranking of ser io~~ness will likety be sensitive

Page 4: I Criminal Justice and Legal Reparat ions as an …gsmunc/reparations/Legal_Reparations.pdfPHILOSC)PHICAL ISSUES, 11 Social, Politicd, and LcgaI Philuuophy, 2001 Criminal Justice and

19. CRIMINAL JUSTICE ANU LEGAL REPARATIONS 509

to the usua.1 damages offenses uf the variuus kjilds impose)). Thus, barring extenus Ling circumstances and aggravating conditions, of- fenses of one kind will predictably be counted as Inore wrious than others and will ttcwrtlinglj It: rrlel wikh rt dernand for greater effort at making amends. The effort, in turn, wil! (1 a m irnagin- in^) be measured in work time, so that in having committed an offense a crizninal wjll br held it.c.countable for working (to al&e amends) an appropriate amount of time. Thus labor (not punish- ment. '~ pain) will serve as the comrllon coi11 in which one "pays urle'rj deb^," with the market value of that labor paying iuto a victi~n eornpe~lsatiofi fund, so far as there is an excess m r and above enforcement costs.

It is worth emplmsizing that a system of legal reparations that responds to crime not with punishment but with demands for efforts at making amends is fully compatible with maintaining the distinction between criminal md civil actions. Civil proce- dures already. and 1 think a.ppropriately, provide an avenue for victims t c ~ collect compensation for damages. The criminal proce- dures that would ep wit.11 a syptertl of reparations would not du- plicate nor replace nor rely on these civil procedures. Their focus would not be c x i cornpensable damage but on offense and the dernmds that would be made of criminals would not be propor- tioned to the kctual damages caused (as they are in civil cases) but to the nature of the offense comnlitted (as they are in crim- inal caws). The efforts at making amends, not the monetary value of those effort.^, are what matters in this corltext. Along wi th this difference in focus will go a variety of procedural differences con- cerning, say, burGen of proof and the relevance of intent, that are already more w less in place now a t ~ d that are crucial to the difference between criminal and civil cases. At the same time, though. to the extent the efforts demanded by n sysbem of repa- rations do contribute positively t.o the statme fund, extra resources will be available to address damages suffered.I5 And a significant advanta.ge of such a system is that there is hope at least of com- pounding benefits a system of criminai justice might offer.

Wheil the offe~iders are not dmgerous, and are emplr~yed, the aims of a system of reparations might be well met by having them work in their current jobs, count-ing some of their work time towards reparations (with the actual payments into the com- pensation fund being a function of their salaries), while those who are not dangerous but not gainfully employed would be put to work on putdic works projects. Those crinlina,ls who are danger- ous would, I think legitimately, be incarcerated, not with the aim

of inflicting pair1 but so as to ensure efforts towards reparations and, until reparat.ions are made, to insulate them frorn society. In addition to the genuinely dangerous there are, of course, a variety of crimi~lals who would not, absent supervision aud enforcement, make reparations. So within a system of legal reparations there will no doubt need to be a variety of more or less restrictive hous- ing arrarlgernents (some surely being very similar to current pris- ons) and work options that might well be modeled on various alternative sentencing programs. In each case, the criminals would have their freedom Ijmited not, with the aim of inflicting pain (or some other harm) but rather on the grounds that an unwilling- ness t,o work towards making anlends forfeits one's right to pa- licipate fully in society.lc

When a, person is willing but, unable to wmk effectively, the focus of the system should be on effort, not effect, and it would I>r+ reasonable too to instibute v a i o ~ ~ s training programs (e,.g., that teach trades) that put offenders in n better position to have their effort,s genuinely be effective and also improve their chances of contributing positively to society. Within a system of punish- merit., snch proposals preciictatdy run afoul of the objection that the training programs help rather than hurt the offenders, whjc11 is antithetical to the point cuf punishment. Within a system of reparations, no sue11 objection gets traction, and the fact that, tiles? programs may help the offenders more effectively 1na.k~: amends counts in th.eir favor. Indeed, across the board, with Dotb dangerous and non-dangerous offenders, with those employed and those basely able t-o work, the focus of the institationd respnnsp to their crimes should be on their responsibility to make anlends for their offense, not on making them suffer pain nor (for that matter) shame except, as these are involved in or follow from hold- ing them responsible for- their crimes. That a system of repara- tions demands making amends and efforts at repair., and not shaming, is important, I think. It leaves room for someone to maintain his dignity, and insist that what he did was neither wrong nor properly the cause of shame, even as he acknowledges the offense and works t.o make amends.17

There are. of course, a range of obvious quesijuns t.hat need t.o be addressed concerning, for instance, victimless crimes and crimes that cause irreparable harm or involve unspeaka.hl~ nff~rlse, as: well as issues relahirig to the specification of appropriate sen- tences, equalizing burdens, and effectively speaking to victims' concerns. Before turning to these, however, I will survey the stman- dard justifications for punishnlent and argue that, t.0 the extent

Page 5: I Criminal Justice and Legal Reparat ions as an …gsmunc/reparations/Legal_Reparations.pdfPHILOSC)PHICAL ISSUES, 11 Social, Politicd, and LcgaI Philuuophy, 2001 Criminal Justice and

19. CRJM~NAL JUSTICE AND LEGAL REPARATIONS 511

they are plausibIe, they all actually favor legal reparatio~la over punishment as a uray for society to address crime. I should em- phasize that T wiIl not be arguing that punishment is unjustified but that the various con.iderations that might successfully justify punishment recommend the alternative offered by a system of le- gal reparations.

111. The Familiar Justifications for Punishment

The familiar justifications of punishment fall into three groups, accordirlg to whether they appeal prirtv~rily to considerations of justice and desert,'' or to utility and the prevention of crirne,lg or to the role of punishment in expressing moral condemnation and contributing to moral education.'* The division is, of course, more than a little artificial; members of society rnight deserve to have institutions that work to prevent crime, and respecting con- straints of justice rnight coiltribute significantly to overall utility, and hot h justice and utility might require mechanisms that force- fully condemn certain behavior an d work effectively towards the moral education of actual and potential ~ffenders.~' Nonetheless, I will discuss them as if they were separate and independent.

A. APPEALS T O JUSTlCE AND DESERT

Often, argunlents offered in defense of puilishrnent take the proper focus of considerations of justice to be the criminal and what he deservcs for having cotllmitted the crime. Sometimes, the thought is that in committing a crime the criminal has acted immoraIly and, because the immoral deserve to suffer, criminals deserve to suffer. Punishrnerlt is jiistified! then, because it invo1ves giving the criminal what he deserves. As H.L.A. Hart puts the view, "the justification for punishing ... is that the return of sufferin for moral evil voluntarily done, is itself just or morally If this is the argument, one might of course question the clairri that those who com111it crimes have @so fact0 done something evil, or the claim that those who do something evil deserve to suffer, or the daim Dhat those who deserve to suffer (because they have done evil) are rightly made to suffer by the state. I have my doubts on all three fronts, but here will simply assume that even if crim- inals are morally defective and therefore deserve to suffer, it is not the state.'s role to make them suffer for that r e a s u r ~ . ~ ~ I an1

not saying that a state never rightly makes someone suffer. As-

suming the state's coercive power is sometimes just-ified it will all~ldst surely sonletimes justifiably coerce in circumstances where someone is thereby made to suffer. Wha.t seems mistaken is the suggestion that the ju~tification of such coercion rests directly on thc state's determination of moral defect. Making people suffer hecauvc of their immoral acts- i8 not legitimately within t,I.le state's purvjear.24 Moreover, to the extent one holds that those who act immorally deserve to suffer and that the state is properly in- $*olved in distributing that suffering in proportion to the immo- rality, such a distribution of suffering urould it seems have to take into account not just how immoral the criminal is, but also how much he has already

Other times, the thought is that punishing a criminal is a way of acknowledging him as a responsible agent and he deserves this acknowledgment (whatever he has done) .2"his line of thought does not depend on holding that the criminal js evil or in~rnoral at all, but instead sees t,renting him a certain way, within a pub- lic system of justice, as part and parcel of recognizing his stmd- ing u a responsible agent. Here a system of reparations and a system of punishment can agree that a criminal a.ct uaZly deservcs to be treated as a responsible agent-to do otherwise is to com- mit an offense against him. But agreeirlg on this is not yet to find grounds for punishing the criminal as opposed to responding t o his crime in some other way, as long as the alternative c0nstitut.e~ a way of a~~kt~owledging his standing as a responsjble agent. In- deed, it is a bit puzzling why anyone would think punishment per se is imporbant to this nch~owledpent , except incidentally as its legitimacy is seen as presupposing a finding to the effect that the criminal is respo~~sible for the crime for which he is be- ing punished. Of course this link to responsibility is nlaintained within a system of reparations that derna.nds efforts toward mak- ing m e n d s only from those who have been found to be respox~si- ble for the crime in question.

Still other ;,imps, a syst,enl of punishment is seen a justified to the extent, and on the grounds, that it would (under the appro- priate circumstances) secure the consent of those subjected to i t . Here the idea is often thxt people have a right to have their stand- ing as moral agents recognized and that this is done properly only when one's treatment of them is such that they thenlselves would (under the appropriate circumstances) give their consent to it. Yet if a system of punishment might secure such consent, it seems pretty clear that a system that demanded reparations in plwe of prmishrnent would likcwise secure the relevant consent

Page 6: I Criminal Justice and Legal Reparat ions as an …gsmunc/reparations/Legal_Reparations.pdfPHILOSC)PHICAL ISSUES, 11 Social, Politicd, and LcgaI Philuuophy, 2001 Criminal Justice and
Page 7: I Criminal Justice and Legal Reparat ions as an …gsmunc/reparations/Legal_Reparations.pdfPHILOSC)PHICAL ISSUES, 11 Social, Politicd, and LcgaI Philuuophy, 2001 Criminal Justice and

imposed or shirked by crirni~lals hy imposing new burdens on them aud thereby establishing the balance of burdens demanded by fair- ness. Reparations too, though, can courltenance shifting burdens in the name of justice. Yet it would do the shifting not by intro- ducing a brand new burden-the pain of punjshment-but by de- manding that criminals (who hiwe either imposed or shirked burdens) compensate others fur the burdens even as it also ac- knorvlcdges, and focuses on, the fact that in committing the crime they have done more and worse than simply imposing or dodging a burden-t,hey have failed to treat others with the respect they are due. This aspect of their crimes calls not for the imposition of pain or some new burden, but rather an effort. at reparations on t,hc part of the crimitlals.

Pu t t,ing aside t.1le-I think indefensibleclairn that punishment by the state is justified and demanded directly and simply hy the immorality a criminal's n.cts exhibit, the various arguments for punishment that appeal to what the criminal, or the victim, or society at large, deserve all capture something important. Yet they al, also, mobilize considerations that are not essentially tied to punishment. In fact., it seems to ine that a system of reparations c1ea.r)~ speaks to these considerations more directly and effec- tively than does punishment.

B. APPEALS TO UTILITY AND THE PRECrENTION OF CRIME

Of course appeals to justice and desert are often not the primacy justificatjor~s offered for punistlme~lt , even if such consideratiatls are often seen as constraining wbttt sort of punishment might be justified by other considerations. Long ago, Protagoras argued that "he who desires to inflict rational punishment does not punish for the sake of a past wrong which cannot, be undone; he has regard to the future and is desirous that the man who is punished, and he who secs him punished, may be deterred from doing wrong again." '' Ever since. one of the main justifica.tions for punish- ment has been found in its serving as an effective deterrent- thanks either to punishment effectively reducing recidivism or to the prospect of punishment working as a disincenti-ve. This justi- fication plays right to the core of punjshrnent by claiming that the pain punishment inte~ltionally inflicts keeps people from conl- rnitting crimes they otherwise would commit.

There are of course familiar moral worries a.bout this sort of just.ification that arise unless it is combined in some way with effective constraints on who might be liable to punishment and

19. CRIMINAL JUSTICE AND LEGAL REPARATIONS 515

on just how much punishment migllt. be administeredh3" Absent such constraints a direct appeal to the benefits one might secure by int~ntionally inflicting pain on people risks countenancing the 'punishment' of innocent people and the torturing of people, in- nocent or not, for rilinor as well as major crimes.

Yet even with appropriate constraints in place, the plausibility of a deterrence justificatior~ of punishment is seriously under- mined by the evidence avt~ilableevidence that seerns to show that the prospect of pain (and punishment in general) is an inef- fective deterrent (at least as Iong as the punishinerlt is not draco- nian), especially amorkg those disposed to be criminals in the frst place." Witness the high recidivism rates among offenders who have been punished and the extrmrdinary failure of programs like Scared Straight that are aimed at making vivid the prospect of pain as a consequence of

Any justification of punishment that speaks to what motivates criminals needs to recognize that a great deal other than the pros- pect of pain is in play-including impulsiveness, perceived injus- tice. desire for excitement, apparent lack of better options, the need to establish one's standing, honor...33 Threatening pain, as a system of punishment does, speaks to none of these, nor does it. seem likely to have much impact on what, down the road, might come to motivate those who have been subjected to punishment. All it does is try to shift the balance of considerations by intro- ducing o n e t h e prospect of pain-that evidently does not figure very beavily when it comes to criminal behavior. Of course pun- ishment can, under the rubric of inflicting harm, impose costs on criminals other than the costs of pain. Presumably a system of punishment that takes into account the extent to which criminals seem not to give signific.mt weight to the prospect of pain would devise punishments that, speak to depriving criminals of what they do value. Even then, though, evidence suggests that, to a large extent, long term and uncertain prospects of the imposition of a cost do not figure prominently in deterring crime.34 Rather, the near term perceived certainty of some penalty or other-pretty much regardless of severity-appears t o have a significantly greater deterrent effect. Indeed there is some evidence that increasing the severity of penalties actually increases crime rate^.^.^ The very fact that the severity of the penalty (given equal certainty) has at most little effect suggests that the importance of certainty c€ pen- alty is found not in its providing a cost (the imposition of which is central to punishment) but in something else. Plausibly, the relevant something else is, at least in part, its providing a clear

Page 8: I Criminal Justice and Legal Reparat ions as an …gsmunc/reparations/Legal_Reparations.pdfPHILOSC)PHICAL ISSUES, 11 Social, Politicd, and LcgaI Philuuophy, 2001 Criminal Justice and

19. CRIMINAL JUSTICE AND LEGAL REPAR.ATI~NS 517

message that the behavior is forbidden. This, however, is a me+ srxge easiIy-and well-conveyed by a system of reparations .3"

There is at least some additional evidence that what, nnlatters to deterrence is the message that the violation of the 1a.w is t,o be taken seriously. A number of studies suggest that pdjce "cau- tions" a,s opposed to court probation as opposed to conviction and and being discharged as opposed tJo be- itlg charged and fined,39 all. showed significant increases in sub- seqiient criminality. When the authorities do not take the crime seriously, neither do the criminals. Yet there was no decrease in crirnirlality when the serious responses were augmented by more severe penalties. It seems that once it is clear that the crime is being taken seriously, increasing the severity of the penalty has no positive impact on recidi~isrn.~' A reasonable hypothesis is that what is crucial, when it comes to an institutiorlal response to crime, is that the significance of the offense be urlambiguously conveyed. In any case, however much people thitlk it. a matter of common sense thn,t punishment deters, the evidence shows fairly convincingly that t-lle relationship between crime and the pros- pect of punishment is neither as simple nor as reliable as many would suppose.

C. APPEALS TO THE EXPRESSIW AND EDUCATIVE

ROLE OF PUNISHMENT

That society must convey the sigrljficance of criminal offenses is one of the main ideas behind the suggestion that punishment is justified by its expressive or educative role. The t,hought is that a society can effectively mark jt.s condermation of certain behav- iors, and thus conveys that they are wrong, only by backing pro- hibitions with threats of At the same time, society's willingness to follow througb on the punishments and enforce cit- izens rights is a way of affirming both that the violation of the rights will not be tolerateci and that the person whose rights were violated has standing in the community. To let violations go by, to offer only cautions or merely sentence someone to probation is to send the message that the violation, and by implication the person violated, is not to be taken very seriously. Punishment, so the' argument goes, is society's way of not letting such things go

I do think there is si~bstantia~l evidence (cited above) that a light touch of the law will engender disregard both for it and for

what it claims to protect. However, the evidence does not show that punishment is the best, let alone the only, way for society to indicate the significance it attaches to respecting the law. The expressive function of punishment, as important as it is, is pretty clearly a function that can he played by something other than punishment-and tu better effect, I suspect. Indeed, to the extent there are grounds for thinking increasing the severity of penalties has no deterrent effect there is reamn to thitlk the important and effective message is not cent,rally conveyed by the punishment it- self even when punishmei~ts are in place, but rather by society palpably taking the offense seriously. And conveyitlg that the of- fense is to be taken seriously i s so~nething enforcing efforts at reparations would seemingly do effect jvely.

In addition to thinking yunishn~ent can play a crucial espres- si1-e role, when it comes to collveying condemnation, many have thought punishment works (either via the expressive role, or in some other way) to reform t,he criminal morally, to make him a better person. On this view, as Jean Haxnpton presents it, "there is a concrete moral goal which punishment should be designed to accomplish, and that goal includes the benefiting of the criminal himself. The state, as it punishes the lawbreaker, is trying to pro- mote his moral personality ..." 42 To the extent this goal is legiti- mately adopted by the statme, the question remains as to whether punishment is the best way of achieving it. Hampton appeals to

capacity to communicate a rnord message in defend- ing its educative role. And surely to the extent punishment does actually advance the cause, it is partly by being a means of effec- tive communication. But, as I have already suggested, there is every reason to think that a system of reparations could pla,y the same communicative role. Of course, punishment might also serve the goal of moral irrlprovernent in some other way. It might be, for instance, that 11y altering incentives for available actions, pun- ishment works to change what people choose to do, and thus what habits (and so, character) they develop. Again, though, the evi- deilce suggest^ that whatever irnpact punishment might have on iinlcent.iveu, it works poorly as a deterrent (and therefore cannot be working posjtively to change character by leading people away fro111 crime). Most strikingly, it seem that increasing severity (which presumably jncrr- disincentives) is often cnunter-productive. Still, if punishment does work to promote a criu~inal's "moral persyl- aljty" either by getting him to act in certain ways or by forclng him to take responsibility for his actions, a system of reparations could justifiably claim the same advantages.

Page 9: I Criminal Justice and Legal Reparat ions as an …gsmunc/reparations/Legal_Reparations.pdfPHILOSC)PHICAL ISSUES, 11 Social, Politicd, and LcgaI Philuuophy, 2001 Criminal Justice and

This has been, I realize, a whirlwind tour Bhrougll xv11a.t a.re. in point of fact, highly complex and subtle arguments. I have not even come dose to doing them justice. My purpose, t.houg11, has not been to evaluate the arguments or to refine t,hem to t,he point where I might fully endorse one or the other. The st,mtegy has been, instead, to convey the extent to wliich a.rgunents that are offered in defense of punishment regularly leave unexplored an important and attractive possibiIity-legal reparations. The quick discussion of the various familiar j ~stificat~ions of punishment are thus offered primarily as an invitation to t.hose who find one or another attractive to ask whether reparations might actually speak to the morally legitimate purposes of the criminal law more effec- t ively than does punishment.

No doubt just how attractive legal reparations proves to be de- pends not only on its answering to traditional justifications for punishment but on it addressing well problems that might seem its own alone to face. I will, in wtrat follows, just briefly mention some of these apparent problems and suggest how a defender of legal reparations might speak to them.

IV. Some Worries

The system of reparations puts a lot of weight on the idea that in holding people resporlsible for what they do we should see them a.s owing not just cornperlsat ion but amends-genuine efforts a t repair-to others (victims and society at large, to the extent the 1~x17s m e genuinely just). However, society is surely in no place to force people t o make amends, since genuinely making amends is a.s much a matter of one's state of mind as one's actions. I think, a.s the worry suggests, that in bteitking a just law a criminaI un- dertakes a duty that no one else can force him to fulfill-that is the duty of arknowledging others as deserving better. This duty is most naturally met hy sincere efforts to make amends for the offense constituted by the crjnle. And, as the worry highlights, sincere efforts are just the sort of thing no one can force another to make. Nonetheless, a society can arrange its institutions so as to acknowledge that this is what is in fact owed a d can then work-wit hin the bounds of respecting those involved, including the criminals-to encourage genuine respect of this debt and to enforce actual (if not always sincere) efforts at repair. The first aim is in large part met by pursuing the second. In enforcing efforts at repair-rat her than simply inflicting pain-a system of

19. CRIMINAL JUSTICE AND LEGAL REPARATIONS 519

reparations would be publicly and clearly acknowledging that t.hing is owed to those against whom an offense has been commit- t,ed. And that is, it seems to me, a proper primary focus for a criminal justice system-one that it can accomplish without be- ing objectionably intrusive.

In concentrating on efforts at repair, however, it might seern that a system of reparations would find no grounds for respond- ing; to victimless crimes. How would a system of legal wpara~ons legitinlately see such crimes as within its purview? Well, even when crimes are "victimless," if they are crimes in a just society there is both a harm and an offense to society a t large in their commis- sion. The harm is a t least the marginal costs each criminal adds to the criminal justice system. But the harm is often much more than that, since many "victimless" crimes are criminalixed pre- cisely because t.here is a real, albeit diffuse, harm caused by the act. Consideration of harm aside, an ofEense comes with any vio- lation of a prohibitjoil t,hat society has reayonably deemed impor- tant enough to make a matter of law and the offense starids as grounds for a duty of repara.tions. I should emphasize; though, that acknowledgi~ig t11a.t. w offense is irlvolved in cr~rnrnit t u ~ g crimes is not the same as thinking coininitting the crimes are immoral. Sometimes one is moraJly ju~t,ified in committi~ig an offense. And this is true even when t,h,zt. jjut,ificat.ion has no startditlg as a legal justification or excuse. Whether or not, a nmral justification is present, however, a system of repara.tions will (I think appropri- ately) see the offense and what.ever harm it causes (even 'if dif- fuse) as properly calling for eff0rt.s at repair on the p a t of the offender.

To go to the other extreme. where the victims are clear and both the harm and the offense are large, i t might seem as well that a system of repara.t.ions woilld be at, a loss. Some crimes (e.g. murder, rape, etc.) are such that it is out of place-perhaps even abhorrent-to talk of repair or making amends. These crimes in- volve offenses and harms so great, arid of such a nature, that neither hope nor sense should be attached to the idea that the victim might be made whole. Any response to crime must recog- nize the distinctive standing of such offenses. Within a system of reparations this should be done, I believe, by seeing those who commit such crimes as having, through their actions, incurred debts that no amount of effort throughout the remainder of their lives will count as having made amends. They never have a legidhate claim to having earned reinstatement. Moreover, it is reasonable to see those who commit such crimes as having, through their

Page 10: I Criminal Justice and Legal Reparat ions as an …gsmunc/reparations/Legal_Reparations.pdfPHILOSC)PHICAL ISSUES, 11 Social, Politicd, and LcgaI Philuuophy, 2001 Criminal Justice and
Page 11: I Criminal Justice and Legal Reparat ions as an …gsmunc/reparations/Legal_Reparations.pdfPHILOSC)PHICAL ISSUES, 11 Social, Politicd, and LcgaI Philuuophy, 2001 Criminal Justice and

ish~nent or enforcing efforts at repair. Nonetheless, if some sort of preventive detention or other preemptive reaction is sometimes justifiable in the context of a systern of punishment, i t seems it would likewise be justifiable, on the same grounds, in the runtext of a system of legal reparations." As practicallv important, and morally complicated, as the issue may be, corning to terms with it will (I believv) not have significant implications for the choice between punishn~ent and reparations.M

In contrast, the ubiquitous desire for revenge seems to caH clearly for punishment rather {,ban reparations. After all. punishment, but not reparations, can speak directly to the desire-by satisfy- ing it. So one might see punishment as justified on the grolinds that putting it into place both controls and satisfies a desire that othern-ise would cause mayhem. James Fitzjames Stephen gives voice to this argument when he claims that, in additioll to being an effective deterrent ("it prevents crime by terror"), the criminal law "regulates, sanctions, and provides a legitimatr satisfaxtion for the passion of revenge; the criminal law stands to the passion of revenge in much the same relation as marriage to the sexnal appetite." 47 Bentham advances a similar argument when he cites "vivindjctive satisfaction" as an important advantage of .48

Thought of in these terms, as appeasing the desire for revenge, punishment's relevant advantages are simply unavailable to repa- rations. Only punishment provides this vindictive satjsf;~ction and only punishment speaks directly to the desire for revenge by sat - isfying it. However, it is at least not, clear that sntisfging the cle- sire is the best way of dealing with its presence. Indeed, there js reason to worry that public institutions of revenge actually ericour- agc the desire by legitimizing it,. In any case, it is clear that at least somet imes apologies, and efforts at making amends, and recogni- tjun of another's right to take offense, alI work to extinguish (rather than satisfy) the desire for revenge. So it would he a mistake to assume tha t the desire simply cannot be addressed otherwise than by punislment (or revenge in sollie other form). Needless to say, it is reasonable to suppose that the rnore serious the offense-and es- pecially the more directIy the offense was an attack-the more likely the desire for revenge will remain. Surely what would work to eiirn- inate the desire when it is provoked by minor offenses will not be sufficient when the offense is more significant. Yet it is a serious over-simplif cation to hold that what the more significant offenses caH for is direct satisfaction of the desire for revenge rather than, say, more extensive efforts at making amends and other public ac- knowledgnlents of the significant nature of the offense.

19. CR~MINAL JUSTICE AND LEGAL REPARATIONS 523

Just how successfully a svstem of reparations might address the desire for revenge remains, it seems to me, an open question. But it is plausible to think victims and criminals and society ti3 a whole might be better served if satisfying the desire for revenge were to be remowd from center stage.

Against this suggestion, some will argue that the desire for re- venge, and its appropriate satisfaction! are ineliminable features of a healthy moral comrn~mity. On their view, to do without pun- ishment "would be a sign," as John Cottingham puts it, "that the network of moral responses that defines civilized life had col- lapsed." 49 On this view, a proper appreciation of a crime is sup- posed to travel with a recognition that it calls for punishment. To do anything else, it is commonly suggested, is to fail to recognize the crime for t i e offense it is. I share the view that serious of- fenses are not properly ignored-that one should not simply let them go. Yet I wonder why reacting with punishrncnt would seem the only appropriate response. Punjshment , I suspect, will stem the only appr~priat~e-and only appropriately serious-rerpouse to serious crime as long as people overlook the alternative a sys- tem of reparations offers. But that alternative, it seems to me, presents a framework within whlch society's response to serious crime can be given the necessary significance.

The plaustbilty of reparations as an appropriately serious r e sponse to serious offenses depends upon appreciating that the efforts it calls for can range in their significance and car1 he made proportional to the crime, so that more extensive efforts at repair are delnarlded of those who commit more serious crimes. At the same time, it is important to appreciate that a system of reparations imposes non-optional demands upon criminals. The denland for efforts at repair, the insistence that in com- mitting a crilne one acquires an obligation to make amends, is crucial to reparations' standing as WI acknowledgnent of the rights of all.

Of course, this very feature of reparations (which is so impor- tant to its respecting the seriousness of some offenses) makes it easy for people to miss the difference between wlch a system, on the one hand, and punishment, on the other. The fact that repa- rations are demanded and enforced, not optionaI, may lead some to think that in makirlg the demands such a systemm~ould be actually, if only covertly, punishing those subject to it. No doubt, reparations, like any coercive response to crime (mandatory treat- ment pragrama no less than punishments), will inevitably some- times impose costs, and be unwelcome.

Page 12: I Criminal Justice and Legal Reparat ions as an …gsmunc/reparations/Legal_Reparations.pdfPHILOSC)PHICAL ISSUES, 11 Social, Politicd, and LcgaI Philuuophy, 2001 Criminal Justice and

19. CRIMINAL JUSTICE AND LEGAL REPARATIONS 525

Yet two things especially distinguish reparations frclnl punish- ment. First, reparations in no way aims at causing the criminal pain or harm. It stands fully successful, on its own terms, whether or not someone subject to its demands welcomes the opportunity to make amends. A welcome punishment, in contrast, is no real punishment at all.50 Second, reparations, unlike punishment,, aim directly, and positively, at redressing crimes in a way that takes the victim into account. Unlike punishment, it naturally focuses attention on the fact that in committing a crime one is commit- ting an offense against other members of society.

I have tried, in this paper, to describe and defend a system of Iegrtl reparations that might serve as a genuine, and genuinely attractive, alternative to the current practice of subjecting crjm- inals to punishment.

I have not addressed the practical problems that might conle with changing over from a system of punishment to one of repa- rations. I suspect, though, that the change might be effected wit.h- out drama by gradually introducing alternative sentencirlg progranls that embrace reparations (rather than punishment or t,ren bment) as their underlying aim. Nor have I explored the prwtical com- plexities involved in the actual workings of a system of repara- tions. Most significantly, I have pretty much passed over the question of how appropriate reparations for specific ufftlr~~es might be determined. There. are, undeniably, serious issues here. Yet these problems havc identical twins that stand as problems for any jus- tifiable system of punishment. So they do not represent distinc- tive problems for a system of reparations. Moreover, hy and large whatever solutions work in one system can (I believe) be fairly easily adapted to the other.

What I have done is argue that the most plausible justifications for punishment-whether they appeal t o justice and desert, or t o utility and deterrence, or to moral expression and education-all act~ially recommend a system of legal reparations. If this is right, then the best justifications of purlishnlent are not justifications of punishment a t all hut are instead elements in a justification for an important alternat~ve. This alternative, I maintain, has the signal advantage that, by enforcing efforts at making amends, it steers clear of the n~orizlly problematic practice of intentionally

inflicting harm while publicly, clearly, and productively mknowl- edging crimes as offenses that ca,ll for redress.

1. I have hencfited from discusaiona of this materid at University of Rich- mond, Thc Australian National University Law Program, the h e a r c h Tki- a d e Ethics Circle, and the 1999 Sociedad Z'ilosoJhm Ibem drnevimna (SOFIA) Conference CJn Legal and Pulitical Philosophy, in Maxatlm, Mexico. I am especially grateful F<,r cumments from dolui Breithwaite, Valerie Braith- wait?, Geoffrey Brrntlerl, David Ektlunli, Claire Finkebtein, Don Garrett, Gerald Gaus, Ceoff Gotfrl~l. Livin Guirwres , Jirn Hdl, Torn Hill, Jr., Chris tnpher K i ~ t z , Loren Lonlmky. Larry h,Iavqy. Joan McCord, Gerald Postema, and Peter Vallentync

2. For purpose of this paper. I bracket the problems that come with trying to dwidc what is rcquircd it1 ilrdcr tor a dctcrmination to bc lcgitimatc. What t h i s (by assut~~ption legitimate) dctertnitlation comes t e w h e t h c r a judg- ment of guilt, or of respotisibility. or of efficient causation, will presumably both itlfluet~ce and be ir~tlner~ced by the institutional response to such cleterrniuatio~is.

3. Stanley I. Berui, '.P~~nislinierit." The Bacyclopsdia of Philosophy (Macmillan P~>l)lishing Co., 1967). Vo1. 7 k 3, p. 29.

4. H . L A . Hart, "Prcllegc~meuon for thr Principles of Punishment ," Presidential Address to the Aristotelia~n. Socie-, 11959; reprinted in his PunGhment and Respr,nszbilitu (Oxford: C lxu~~do t i Press, 1968).

5 . Richard W~ss.srstsotn, "Capital Ftiilishment as Punishment: Some Theoret- jral ISRUEE and Dk>jections," hiidwret Studies in PhiIosoph,g, 7 (1982)' p. 476.

C Although thcrc is rootn to worry about, subtle diffcrcnccs bctwccn unplcas- antncfis, pain, deprivatiotl. suffering, and harm, such differences won't, 1 think, havc an imput on the argunletlt that, hllows.

7. Sec R m d y Bmnett's "Restitution: A New Paradigm of Criminal Justice," Ethics, vol. 87 (.July, 1977), pp. 279-301.

8. Gerald Gaus, "Does Cornpensatioll Restore Equality?" in John W. Chap man, ed., Nomos XXXJII: Compen.snt~>r~ J u t i c e . (New York: New York Uni- versity Press, 1991), PI). 45-81, p. 72.

9. Gaus mentions that even when compensation is accompanied t y punishment there may be cases in which ' t he aggressor is not fully squared away with the victim." I am challenging the idea thatt the punishment in it.self ever works to square things away, cxcept in so far anciety accepts a conven- tional arrangement whereby undergoing a acr t~jn xnlount. of prlr~ishment is counted as sufficient.

10. Of course, some who commit crimes arc genuinely not mspons))llc: for what they do. These people no doubt need to be dedt with in lome other way- just how they should be dealt with will presuinably t.urn on how dangerous they are and on whether they can, through trreat,meut, or education, hecarne responsible agents.

Page 13: I Criminal Justice and Legal Reparat ions as an …gsmunc/reparations/Legal_Reparations.pdfPHILOSC)PHICAL ISSUES, 11 Social, Politicd, and LcgaI Philuuophy, 2001 Criminal Justice and

11. Neither sort of rchabilitatian need be pcimxrily a matter ot' waking the crim- inal a morally better person; but both are, of course, miltally constrained, and insofar as they effect a minimal amount of moral decetlcy in one's treat- ment of others there will be (pot.cnt.jally) a luord &mge iuvolved.

12. Edgardo Rotman explores some of t.he romplexitjes of the concept of reh* bilitation in Begond Punishment (New York: Greenwood Press, 1990).

13. Of course, it is possible that a litt,ir int.vntiond infliction of p i n might, over all, cause less pain than would acting dways without that j~rtention. Indeed, a claim to this effect underwrites the fmilirtr uti l i tuim justification of pun- ishment. The idea is that a system that steers clear of intentionally inflict- ing pain (as opposed merely to knowingly causing it) will, thanks t,u its not producing directly the extra wno~int of pain the intentions bring in, prothlce indirectly more pain t)y failing to deter criminal behavior. Obviously, this i b

a t huttom XI empiric~l iusue, but the evidence, it seems to me, does not suppurt the idea that tile pain the system might introduce intentionally carries with it the sort of tuarginal benefit this argument supposes. I wen suaspert, t,het, the Icvcl of pain that wotild come with either punishment. or reparat.iolls is likely to secure most of the deterrent effect there is and the ext.ra pain intentionally id ic ted serves more to raise a sense of injustice and rescnt.nlent on the p-t of criminals than to deter them--and so may actu- ally i n c r e a rr~idivism and crime in general. I cite some relevant (albeit not eonrltlsjve} evidence later in thc paper, in the section concerning deterrence.

14. Whether a system of repartritti0r.s should take this view, or shorild instead see the pain as neither here nor therc, given that it accuu~panies an agent doing what he should, is something ahout which I am ambivalent.

IS. Presumably, those who successfully rollcct civil damages will not also be eligible for stlpport from the state fund^ and many who c.otiId not s u c c c s ~ fully collect using civil procedures might, still have a rlaim on some state fund comperluation.

Iti. In extreme cases, where a person has rulnnlit.ted an eepec.inily heinous of- fense and is unwillirig to work to make amends (presumably not ntl unusual combination), it might be legitimate to co~~s ider forcing such people to eon- tribute in ways that don't require their willing participation. They might, I suppose, be coerced t o participate in mpdical trials, assuming resonable constraints are placed on what is being testcd. Here the idea would he to substitute such criminals into triak that are currently approved as safe enough to allow participation by volunteers, though the criminals' participation would not be, in the cases in qiiestion, voluntary.

17. See John Braithwaite's G'nme, Shntne, and Reinteption (Cambridge: Cam- bridge University Preys, 1989) for a discussion of responses to crime tkat rely on shaming.

18. See, for example, Imn~anuel Finnt's The Metaphysical Elements of Jwtice (Indianapolis: Bobbs Merrill, 1965); Jeffrie Murphy's "Marxism and Retri- bution," ill Rvtribufion, ,hrattcc, tlttd Thempy (Dordrecht: D. Reidel, 1979); and David E. Cooper's "Hegel's Theory of Punishment," in Hegel's Political Philosophgl, di tcd by 2. A. Pelczyuski (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1971).

19. CR~MINAL JUSTICE AND LEGAL REPARATIONS 52'7

10. See. fur a clmsir, example, Jeremy Bentham's An Introduction to the Pnn.- caplrs of Afo~nls arid Legdslntion, edited by J.B. Burns and H.L.A. Hart (Lon- don: At.hlone Press, 1970).

20. See. for example, Joel Feinberg's "The Expressive Function of Puniuhnlent." in Doing and DestrPring (Princeton: Princeton Univt!rsity Prcss, 19701, pp. 9:- 118; Herbert Morris's "A Paternalistic Theory of Punishment," A l n e ~ c a n Philosophic-ad Quor-terly 18 (l981), pp. 263-71; and Jean Harnpturl's "The Moral Education Theory of Punishment," Philosophy and Publxc -4ffair.s 13 (19841, pp. 208-38.

21. Most attempts to justify punishment, niuc these various cousiderations in some way or other, which seems only reasunable in that they all appear to capture something both relevant and import.ant., John Rawk' "Two Con- cepts of Rules," Philosophical Review 64 (1955). pp. 3-32, h especially con- cerned with sorting out the mix, as are H.L.A. Hart's "Prolegdtuenon to the Principles of Punishment," op. cat. and Thomns Hill's "Kar~t ou P~misl- ment: A Coherent M i of Deterrence and Retribution?" irl Rcsprt%t. Plaml- ism, and Jastice. (Oxford: Oxford Universit,~ Press, 2000), pp. 173 -199.

2'1. Punishment and Responsibility, pp. 231. 23. There are all sorts of remons for rejecting this as the state's role, not least

being that the state is in no position to determine how immoral people are over-dl, and such a determination would presumably be necessmy in ordrr to sett,le how much punishment a particular person deserves. See Gertrude Eaorskv: "The Ethics of Punishment," in Gertrude Ezorsky (ed.) Philosoph- ical Perspectives on Paadshmet~t (Albany: State Univ~mity of New York Press, 1972), in which she argues that m appeal to a criminal's deserving punish- mcnt bwause of his mord defects would require balancing "all of his moral wrongs against the sufferit~gs of his entire life" (p. xxvi) in ordcr to deter- mine whether: for ir~$tar~cr, he hiu already suffered enough.

24. See Jeffrie hlurphy, "Retri1,iitivism and the State's Interest in Punishment," in NOJfOS .y,l-VII: Crtrnznal Justirc, edited by J.R. Pennock and J. Chap man (New h r k : New York Univer~ity Press, 19851, pp. 156-64.

25. At the same f,iule, this view seems &o t o encourage the idea that the law should expand to cover all immorality or at least that all such immorality is properly within the domain of the state as it exercises its puwr to rlistrib- ute suffering. See Gcrtrude Ezorsky's "The Et,llics of Punisl~rrl~rtt," irk PhiL oat~phical Perspectives on Punishment, op. czt., pp. ~ i v - m i .

26. See Herbert Morris's "Persons and Punishmrnt." in Pur~eshrn~s~t (snd Reha- brl~tation, edited by Jeffrie Murphy (Belnlont: JTadswort.h Ptihlishing Corn- pmy, 1973), pp. 40-64.

27. see Phillip Montague's "Punishment and Societ,d Defpnse" in Ciitnirinl JILS- tice Ethacs, 2 (1983), pp. 3 S 3 6 .

2d. See Herbert Morris's "Punishment and Fairness," The Monest, 6 (196d). pp. 476-79.

29. P1at.o. Protragow, 324b, translated by 3. Jowett, revised by Marart 00st wdd, 1956 (Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill, 19561, p. 22.

30. See H. L. A. Hart's L'Prolegomcnon to thp Principles of Punishment," op. cet.

Page 14: I Criminal Justice and Legal Reparat ions as an …gsmunc/reparations/Legal_Reparations.pdfPHILOSC)PHICAL ISSUES, 11 Social, Politicd, and LcgaI Philuuophy, 2001 Criminal Justice and

31. Scc David far ring tor^, "Social, Psyrhol~~gicaI and Biologicd Influences on Juvenile Delinque~lcy and Adult Crime," i11 Expla?nirlg C~rr't~~inal Beharliour, edited by W. Buikhuiscn and S.A. IvItidnick (New Sork: E.J. Brill, 1988), pp. 68--89; J.H. Sattcrfield, "Ct~ildhood Diag~lostic and Neurilphysiological Prerlictors of Teenage Arrest Rates: An Eight-ycar Prosper:tivr Study," in T ~ P C a w e s of C ~ m e : New Biologzcak Ayj)roaches edited by S.A. M e h i c k , T.E. hloffitt, and S.A. Stack (Cambridge: Cambridge University Prcss, lsY7), pp. 1-lGj-167; 6. Hinton, M. O'Neill, S. Hamilton, and M. Burke, "Ps?-&u- phyiillogicsl Differentiation Between Psychopathic and Schizophrenic Ab- normd Offenders," British ,Journal (q Sucaal and GZiaiml Psychology, 19 (1t)PO). pp. 257-269; and D e t e m n c e and Irst-apacatataon: Estimating the EffecLs o j C ~ m i n a k Sa?~ctPons on Crime Rutrn edited by Alfrcd Blumstein, Jacqueli~lc Cohen, and Daniel Nagin, (Wa.4lington, D.C.: Nationd Academy of Sci- ences, 1978).

32. See A.C. Petro~inu, C. Turpin-Pet rosino, and J.O. Finckenauer "Wrll- ~neaning programs ran have hnsn~f i~ l effccts! Lessons from experiments of prugrams such as Scared Straight." C~rtra~, & Delinquency 46 (2000), pp. 354- 379; J.C. Buchner and M. Chesney-Lind, '-Dramatic Cures for J~lvcaile Crime: An Evaluation of a Prisoner-run Dclinquency Prevention Program," fr~rnr- nal Justice and B ~ h a v t o ~ , 10 (1983), pp. 227-247; and R.V. Lewis, l'S(bnred Straight-Californib Style," Criminal Justice and Behavior, 10 (I933), pp. 284-289.

33. Sec Joan McCurll, "He Did It Because He Wanted To ...," W. Osgotnd (ed.) Nebraska Syn~ptlhium on Motivation: Motivation a~rd DcFnqzit.r~c~, (Lincoln: University of Nehraska Prcss, 19971, pp. 1 4 3 .

3-1. Scc T. E. hlofLtt., "The Lcarning Theory Model of Punishment: Inlplica- t.ions for Delitulurncy Deterrence," C~iminal Jzkshce rand Bthwueor, 10 (19831, pp. 131-158.

35. See G. Antunes ~ i r i A.L. Hunt, "The Impwt of Certainty and Severity of Punishment on Levels of Crimc in American States: An Extended Analysis," Juurr~al 01 Cri~fiz~aal L,aw and Criminology, 64 (1973), pp. 489 -493.

36. Thmc arc, of course, 0 t h possibilities. It, may be, for instance, that cer- tainty offsets all otherwise dramatic discount crindnals might place on fu- ture costs.

37. David P. Farringeon and T. Brnnett.. "Police Cautioning of Juveniles in Lon- don," British Journal of Ce?ni~zol(?yy. 21 (198 1)- pp. 123-135.

38. D. Glaser and M.A. Gordon, "PrufIt,able Penalties for Lower Level Courts: Judicature, 73 (1990), pp. 248-152.

39. David P. Farrington, S.G. Osborn, and D.3. West, "The Pcssistence of Labeling Effects," Brit~sh J o ~ ~ m a l of Crinzinology, 18 (1978), pp. 277-284.

-111. This fits nicely with the research concerning the impact of ccrtaint,~ to the extent low certainty is due to lack of enforcement or casual or illcon~i~tent t.reatmcnt of offenders that would convey the meusage that thr offens~s in question are not being takw very seriously.

41. Fur an account of plmishnier~t that emphasizes its expressive rolc: Fcr ,loci Feirlt~erg's "Thv Expressive Function of Punishrr~ent," in his Dozng and Desewzug (Priucstc~r~: Princeton University Press, 1070), pp. 95-118; and

Robert Nozick's Philosophical Eqlnnntions (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1981), pp. 363-397.

42. "The Moral Education Theory of Punislwent," in Punishment , edited b y A.J. Simmons, M. Cohen. J. Cohen, md C. Beitz, (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1995), pp. 112-132, p. 119. See also Herbert Morris' "A Paternalistic Theory of Punis l~n~r~l t , " Antericur~ Philosophical Quaderly, 18 (1981), pp. 263-271; and R .A. Duff's Trials urad Punishments (Cambridge: Cambridge University P re~s , 1986).

43. Within certain bounds, though, it may be both fair and rea.snna.hlc to let decisions concerning institutional forgiveness be signifirant !y infl~~snccd by the victims or thcir familics.

44. These general issues arc: nicely raised by Thomas Nagel's "hloral Luck," iu his Mortal Ques t~onq (Cambridge: Cambridge University Prrss, 1979). pp 24-38. . .

45. It is worth noting that the very fact that we expect someorlp to commit a crime after having srnwd his sentence often seems evidence bhat we think Le has not prnrlirlely ~nade amends. (Sometimes, of course, recidivism is trace- able ~ ~ v t t o a failure to r cge t an offense. It might, for instance, be due to peop1,pl~ having, at least they see it, counterbalancing rcasons to offend again or t.o the acts being due to something for which the criminal is not fillly rulpatlc.) Still, the state cannot legitimately hc in the business of de- termining genuine regret and should not be irnpa~ine senteuces the limits of which arc set by the state7s being ~at,isfied that the crituinal regrets his actions. It is in society's interest ay a whplc to keep the state out of that arena and so to settle for sentences that, const,it,ute public artd ptiblicly en- forceable efforts at making amends in proport.jon tcr the offense. It should steer clear of m&iug actual reget thc bcnrhnlark. Nonethelrsu, one hope of A system of reparations is that the forus on rnalu~~g ~ l l l e n d ~ rather than causirlg pain, and the insisting on people taking reponsibility for thcir x- tior13 in the form of working to repair the dmlage they have done, is that, in fact the practice will encourage genuine regret and repair, and not nlrrrly synlholic reprcscntations of those.

46. Fox an attempt to spell out when ant1 why preventive dctcntion and ot.bcr preemptive strikes might he justiLed, see Norval Morris' " 'Dangerousncss' and Incapacitation," frurr~ R w ~ d of the Associateon of the Bur of the City elf New York, 39 (1982). pp. 102-28. See also Andrew von Hirsch, Past o r Fzi- k r e Crimes (Ne- Brunswlrk: Rutgct.s University Press, 1985).

47. J m c s Fit~janes Steplphen, A Get~ertal Kicw of the Cnmznal La711 of E n g l a d (London: Macrnill,iull, IfiGj), p. 99.

48. Jeremy Bentham, Air Infrodu~tdon to tht. Amczples of MOT& and Leg~slc& tion Chapter 13, footuoto 1, p. 158, o p . cnl.

0 49. John Cottiugham; "Just Punishment," Proceedrrlgr of the Anstot?lzcan Soci-

ety, Supplcmelltarx Volume 61, (1987), pp. 41-55, p. 53 50. More accurately, the fact that some punishment is welcnme and clot r imed

a burden will mean that, in an important rwpect.. it. 1m.s nliufired.