Hyman 1997_Words and Pictures

27
8/12/2019 Hyman 1997_Words and Pictures http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/hyman-1997words-and-pictures 1/27 Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement http://journals.cambridge.org/PHS  Additional services for Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement: Email alerts: Click here Subscriptions: Click here Commercial reprints: Click here Terms of use : Click here Words and Pictures John Hyman Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement / Volume 42 / March 1997, pp 51 - 76 DOI: 10.1017/S1358246100010183, Published online: 12 April 2010 Link to this article: http://journals.cambridge.org/abstract_S1358246100010183 How to cite this article: John Hyman (1997). Words and Pictures. Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement, 42, pp 51-76 doi:10.1017/S1358246100010183 Request Permissions : Click here Downloaded from http://journals.cambridge.org/PHS, IP address: 89.206.117.139 on 15 Sep 2013

Transcript of Hyman 1997_Words and Pictures

Page 1: Hyman 1997_Words and Pictures

8/12/2019 Hyman 1997_Words and Pictures

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/hyman-1997words-and-pictures 1/27

Royal Institute of PhilosophySupplementhttp://journals.cambridge.org/PHS

 Additional services for Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement:

Email alerts: Click here

Subscriptions: Click hereCommercial reprints: Click hereTerms of use : Click here

Words and Pictures

John Hyman

Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement / Volume 42 / March 1997, pp 51 - 76

DOI: 10.1017/S1358246100010183, Published online: 12 April 2010

Link to this article: http://journals.cambridge.org/abstract_S1358246100010183

How to cite this article:John Hyman (1997). Words and Pictures. Royal Institute of PhilosophySupplement, 42, pp 51-76 doi:10.1017/S1358246100010183

Request Permissions : Click here

Downloaded from http://journals.cambridge.org/PHS, IP address: 89.206.117.139 on 15 Sep 2013

Page 2: Hyman 1997_Words and Pictures

8/12/2019 Hyman 1997_Words and Pictures

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/hyman-1997words-and-pictures 2/27

Words and Pictures

J OHN HYMAN

Pictures have always played  a prom inen t role  in  philosophical spec -ulation about  the mind ,  but the concept  of a picture  has itself be enthe object  of  philosophical scrutiny only intermittently.  As a  matterof fact,  it  was studied most intensively  in the  course of a theologicalcontroversy   in  the Eastern Rom an E mp ire, dur ing the eighth c entu-ry  -  which  is a  sufficient ind icati on  of its marginal place  in the his-

tory  of  philosophy. Perhaps this  is because pictures have never p ro -duced  in us the theoretical paralysis wh ich Au gu stin e famously a sso-ciated with time,  but  have  on the  contrary generally seem ed  too

unproblematic  to  deserve much tim e from philoso phers. Even today,after several decades  of  accumulating theory, philosophers with  no

stake   in the matter  are often imp ervious  to its  charm.  I  feel somesympathy   for this att i tude , because  the task of  explaining  the natureof depiction  is, I  believe,  one w hich calls  for the refinement ratherthan refutation  of our first thou gh ts ab out  it. But a precise und er-

standing  of  depiction  is both  a necessary prolegomen on  to a  signifi-cant part of  aesthetics, and a useful prop hylac tic against confusion  inthe theory  of the ima ginatio n. B esides, ther e  is also  the pleasure of

the chase, which  J. L.  Austin nonchalantly appealed  to  many yearsbefore  the Research Assessmen t Exercise was ina ugu rated.

Introduction

Although abstract paint ings  are som etimes called pictures,  I  shall

follow   the restrictive convention w hich stipulates th at every pictu redepicts,  is a picture  of, someth ing  or   other.A picture  is a  kind  of  artefact.  In  general, kinds  of  artefact  -

clocks, lamps , knives, cha irs — are distinguished  by their function. Aclock  is a device  for keeping t ime,  a lamp  for sheddin g l ight ,  and so

on. Of  course clocks  and lamps  can serve m any different pu rpo ses .For example,  a  clock  can be  used  to  decide whether  a  record  has

been beaten and   a lamp can be used  to attract insects; and either canbe used   as a door-stop.  But a clock  or a  lamp  can be  used for a cer-

ta in purpo se because it  is a  clock or a lamp  if, and only if, it serves thispurpose  by  keeping time  or   sheddin g l ight . Henc e, these  are  theirdefinitive func tions.  In m any cases an artefac t's function will dictatethe kinds  of  material  it can or cannot  be  made  of, and its form  or

shape.  For example,  a  knife cannot  be spherical  or  made  of  sponge,

51

Page 3: Hyman 1997_Words and Pictures

8/12/2019 Hyman 1997_Words and Pictures

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/hyman-1997words-and-pictures 3/27

John Hyman

and a sail cannot be made of chicken-wire. There are also manykinds of artefact which are distinguished by form or size, distinc-tions which may correspond to differences in function, but need not

do so - for example, kinds of spear or sword: halberds, pikes andbills,  cutlasses, sabres and scimitars. Finally, simple machines aredistinguished not only in terms of their function, but also in termsof their manner of operation - not only what they do, but also howthey do it. Pulleys and capstans, for example, are both machines forlifting w eights , bu t they w ork differently. A pictu re is not a machin e;but the definition of a picture, like the definition of a pulley, willneed to explain what a picture does and how it does i t .

The philosophical l i terature contains answers to both questions.Answers to the first - What do pictures do? - include the following:They show us things. They give us the i l lusion of seeing things.They make us think of things. They stand for or denote things.Historically, the most common answer to the second question -H ow do they do it? - has been: by m eans of resem blance. However,in  Languages of Art,  N elson Go od m an rejects this answer, andargues instead that pictures depict by means of semantic and syn-tactic rules.  Languages of Art  dese rvedly rem ains a focus of deba tethree decades after its publication, partly because of its rhetoricalpanache, but principally because its arguments are ingenious and itsconclusions original, not to say perverse. It may be helpful to layout some representative answers to the two questions in a table, inorder to display the route which led to   Languages of Art:

What do pictures do?

Beardsley A picture   shows the latestmodel Chevrolet, a plaid

shirt...something thatexists or might existoutside the pictureframe'.  (1981, p. 267)

Hospers A picture is a symbol andtherefore  refers  to  or

stands for  the objects itrepresen ts. (1946, p. 29)

Goodm an A picture stands for ordenotes its subject.  (1981, p. 5)

How do they do it?

By means of a closeresemblance in shape and

colour; for in order todepict a  Y,  a picture mustmust contain an area'that is more similar tothe visual appearance ofYs  than to objects of anyother class', (ibid., p. 270)

By means of a 'closenatural relationship,

namely likeness orresemblance, betweensymbol and thingsymbolized', (ibid., p. 40)

By means of a system ofsemantic and syntactic rules.

52

Page 4: Hyman 1997_Words and Pictures

8/12/2019 Hyman 1997_Words and Pictures

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/hyman-1997words-and-pictures 4/27

Words and Pictures

The table is not arranged chronologically. Beardsley's Aesthetics  wasfirst published about a decade after Hospers' Meaning and Truth in  theArts.  But it conveys a schematic picture of the relationship between

the three theories more effectively than a chronological arrangementwould. For as we can see, Beardsley and Hospers disagree about the'what' of pictures, but agree about the 'how'; whereas Hospers andGoodman agree about the 'what', but disagree about the 'how'.

In order to see which way philosophy has moved since Languagesof Art,  it is best to take a long step back, and to consider howDescartes fits into the picture:

Descartes  A picture 'enables the soul By the operation of

to have sensory perceptions mechanisms which physiologyof the various qualities of can investigate,the objects to which itcorresponds'. (1985, p. 166)

Descartes' idea is that the function of a picture is to produce psy-chological episodes of a certain sort, namely, 'sensory perceptionsof the various qualities' of the things it depicts. So instead of sup-posing that the distinctive nature of the experience of looking at apicture - what makes this experience different from the experienceof looking at visible things of other kinds - is simply a function ofthe distinctive nature of pictures themselves, he makes the oppositesupposition: that the distinctive nature of pictures should beunderstood in terms of the distinctive character of the experienceof looking at them. And what is distinctive about this experience isthat it is not, or not exclusively, a sensory perception of the variousqualities of the picture  itself,  but of the forest or battle or stormthat the picture represents. A picture is therefore something whose

essential nature is disguise: a flat pattern of ink or pigment, con-trived with the express purpose of frustrating the desire to see itsimply for what it is. This is, in effect, an illusion theory of pic-tures: the function of a pictu re, in Descartes ' view, is to produ ce anillusion.

Today almost everyone with an opinion agrees that the illusiontheory is not viable; but the general approach that Descartes pio-neered is more popular today than any other, partly because of theinfluence of Ernst Gombrich's  Art and Illusion,  which has done

even more than Languages of Art  to make pictorial representation alively topic in philosophy, and partly because Goodman won fewconverts, but persuaded many that the resemblance theory wasirreparable. There isn't a consensus about how exactly the experi-ence of looking at a picture should be defined, but there is wide-spread agreement that defining this experience is the key to the

53

Page 5: Hyman 1997_Words and Pictures

8/12/2019 Hyman 1997_Words and Pictures

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/hyman-1997words-and-pictures 5/27

John Hyman

theory   of  pictorial representation. Paradoxically,  the m ost faithfulCartesian  in  the twen tieth ce ntury w as Gilbe r t Ryle, who was there-fore  - in a sense -  ahead of his time.1

In what follows,  I  shall begin  by  discussing  the  doctrine thatdepict ion  is  explained  by  resemblance,  and two main argum entsagainst  it, the  first pro po un ded  by  Descar tes,  in his  treatise  on

optics, and the second  by G o o d m a n ,  in  Languages   of Art.  Secondly,I shall examine   and crit ic ise G ood m an's  own theory  of  depiction.Finally,  I shall defend  a positive proposal ab out the n ature of  depic-tion  -  although  it is m uch less than  a  complete answer  to the  theo-retical problems raised by pictoria l a rt —  and examine  its connectionwi th Descar tes '  and  Goo dm an ' s a rgumen ts  and conclusions, and

with   the doctr ine they opposed.

The Resemblance Theory

T h e t ru th m ay be s imple to express b ut difficult to exp ou nd; an d wesometimes discover,  in the  course of   expounding  it, that the simpleformula we began with   is as a pt  to misle ad as to inform. T he propo -

sit ion that resemblance explains how pictures depict will turn out  tobe of   this sort; and whether  we  stick  to it, as the best epitom e  of a

subtle matter,  or  prefer  to be  less economical with  the tru th, willmatter relatively little, once we  are  able  to provide  a more substan-tial explanation.

One reason for  treating the s imple formula with caution is that weoften believe  the right thing  for the wro ng reasons;  and what mayseem   to be a  good reason  for   believing that resemblance explainsdepict ion  is actually no reason at all . Wh at  I have in  mind  is the fact

that some pictures  are   good likenesses. Th is  is how the train  ofthought might  run : a  por t ra i t  is one paradigm  of a  picture, and

al though   a por t ra i t  can be  used  in  various ways — to  comm emora tethe dead,  to negotiate  or celebrate  a marriage,  to express allegianceor  to reinforce auth ority  - it cannot  be deemed  a successful po rtra itunless  it is a   good likeness, that  is,  unless  it  resembles  its  subject.And wha t  is  true  of  portrai ts  is true  of  other pictures too. A   suc-cessful picture  of a  girl looks like a girl,  and a successful pic ture of

an apple looks like   an apple. Th es e resemblances,  no less than the

1  Ryle's comments about depiction occur  in a  chapter devoted  to the

imagination, and although the two philosophers make strange bedfellows,these com ments mark a point of congruence between Descartes' theory ofperception and Ryle's theory of  imagination. See Ryle (1949), ch. 8,  esp.pp. 253-4.

54

Page 6: Hyman 1997_Words and Pictures

8/12/2019 Hyman 1997_Words and Pictures

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/hyman-1997words-and-pictures 6/27

Words and Pictures

resemblance between Smith and his portrait, will be obvious to any

spectator who knows what girls or apples or Smith look like.

If these thoughts seem plausible, it is because we find it easy to

misidentify the things which resemble each other when pictures

are good likenesses.2  If, for example, I am struck by a close like-

ness or resemblance between Renoir s  Girl with a Falcon   and the

postman s daughter, the resemblance which strikes me is not

between the postman s daughter and a canvas smeared with pig-

ment, but between the postman s daughter and the girl in Renoir s

picture. Similarly, Frans Hals s portrait of Johannes Hoornbeek

resembles his portrait of Herman Langelius more closely than it

resembles its subject; but the man we can see in the picture resem-

bles Hoornbeek, or so we believe. It may be tempting to object

that the man in the picture cannot be said to resemble Hoornbeek,

since he is Hoornbeek; but this objection betrays an important

confusion, for the phrase the man in the picture can be used in

two different ways: to describe a picture , what it shows us and

what we see or fail to see in it; or to refer to a man whom a picture

portrays.3 Thus, The man in Hals s picture is dead is false if the

phrase is being used in the first way, to describe Hals s picture, but

it is true if it is being used in the second way, to refer to Johannes

Hoornbeek. It is normally clear in which of these two ways a

phrase like the man in the picture is being used. For example,

 The man in the picture has a book in his hand normally means

 The picture  depicts  a man with a book in his hand , in which case

the phrase the man in the picture is being used in the first way;

but The man in the picture was a professor of Theology at the

University of Utrecht means The picture portrays  a professor of

Theology at the University of U trecht , so here the phrase the

man in the picture is being used in the second way. Needless to

say, we can imagine circumstances in which it might be difficult to

be sure how such a phrase was being used, but it would be a sim-

ple matter to find out.

We can call the first way of using the phrase the man in the pic-

ture ,  the one which corresponds to the paraphrase using the verb

 depicts ,   internal ,  and the use of the same phrase which corre-

sponds to the paraphrase using the verb portrays ,  external .  And

now it should be obvious that Hals s portrait is a good likeness, not

if the canvas resembles Hoornbeek, but if the man in the picture, inthe  internal  use of the phrase, resembles him. This resemblance is

2  This and the following paragraph draw substantially on and modify

Hyman(1992).3 Cf. Anscombe (1965), p. 159.

55

Page 7: Hyman 1997_Words and Pictures

8/12/2019 Hyman 1997_Words and Pictures

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/hyman-1997words-and-pictures 7/27

John Hytnan

not what makes  the picture  a por t ra i t  of  Hoornbeek;  bu t it is whatmakes the por t ra i t  a good likeness. For conve nience, w e can say tha ta por trai t  is a good likeness  if its  internal subject resembles  its   exter-

nal subject.*

In sum, we need  to take care not to confuse  the marks on the sur-

face  of a  picture  and its  internal subject.  T he resemblance whichentit les us to  describe  a por t ra i t  as a  good likeness  is not a  resem-blance between  the man or wom an por t rayed  and the  marks  on the

surface   of the picture,  but between  the man or  wom an portrayedand  the  pictu re's intern al subject;  and if an  apple  in a  picture  isunmistakably   a Cox's O range Pipp in,  it is the picture 's internal s ub -ject ,  the apple  we can see in it, and no t the patch  of  canvas whichdepicts  the apple, tha t m ust resemble other C ox's Orange Pipp insmore closely than  it   resembles Bram leys. M agr itte 's celebratedpaint ing  he   Trahison des Images  illustrates  the confusion.  The artistseems  to be  claiming tha t every pictu re,  by its  very nature,  is a

deceiver, a false friend. Bu t the tr ut h  is less dram atic: 'Ceci n 'est pasune p ipe '  is true  if the pro no un refers  to the  paint ing,  and false if itrefers   to its internal subject . Wh ethe r M agri t te knew  it or not, the

pain t ing tu rns  on an equivocat ion,  not a paradox .This a rgument does  not disprove  the  resemblance theory;  but it

removes  one unsatisfactory reason  for  endors ing  it, and it also  sug-

gests that  a  more explicit statement  of the theory than  the simpleformula  we  began with  may be useful:  not resemblance  tout court,bu t a resemblance  in  shape or colour betwe en th e disposition of  pig-m e n t s  on a  picture's surface  and the   pictu re's intern al subjectexplains depiction,  if the resemblance theory  is  right.

There have been  two major attacks  on the resemb lance theory:one  by  Descar tes ;  the  other  by   Go odm an. B oth make  use of an

analogy between pictures  and words  in a language.Descar tes was not especially interested  in the  nature of  depictionin  its own  right.  He  denied th at resem blance explains dep iction

4 The distinction between pictures that have an external subject and pic-

tures that don't  is drawn by many philosophers who write about the sub -ject. However, it is  commonly thought that  the  external subject  of a pic-ture must  be  someone  or  something which actually exists,  and  thereforecannot be a fictional character or thing. For example, Malcolm Budd, whocalls pictures which have an external subject 'relational p ictures ' (1995, pp.66ff.),  claims that  a [relational] picture must stand  in a certain relation toan  actual thing', describes relational pictures as pictures of   real individu-als'  (ibid., pp. 66, 73, italics added), and  argues that pictures  of  fictionalcharacters  -  to put it more crudely than Budd does - merely pretend to berelational pictures (ibid., p. 72). The idea that the external subject of a pic-ture cannot be  a  fictional character is, I  believe, mistaken; but it is a diffi-cult issue, and I shall not examine it here.

56

Page 8: Hyman 1997_Words and Pictures

8/12/2019 Hyman 1997_Words and Pictures

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/hyman-1997words-and-pictures 8/27

Words and Pictures

because he believed that this doctrine was implicated in a theory ofvisual perception which he was bent on undermining. Nevertheless,his argum ent is worth examining carefully. Thi s is what he says:

in no case does an image resemble the object it represents in allrespects, for otherwise there would be no distinction between theobject and its image. It is enough that the image resembles itsobject in a few respects. Indeed the perfection of an image oftendepends on its not resembling its object as much as it might. Youcan see this in the case of engravings: consisting simply of a littleink placed here and there on a piece of paper, they represent to usforests, towns, people, and even battles and storms; and although

they make us think of countless different qualities in theseobjects, it is only in respect of shape that there is any real resem-blance. And even this resemblance is very imperfect, sinceengravings represent to us bodies of varying relief and depth ona surface which is entirely flat. Moreover, in accordance with therules of perspective they often represent circles by ovals betterthan by other circles, squares by rhombuses better than by othersquares, and similarly for other shapes. Thus it often happensthat in order to be more perfect as an image and to represent an

object better, an engraving ought not to resemble it. (Descartes1985, pp. 165-6).

Descartes makes three poin ts here. The first is that an image can-not be a perfect facsimile of the things it represents; the second isthat an image need only resemble what it represents in a fewrespects; and the third is that even this resemblance is often imper-fect. Then he illustrates the second and third points with the exam-ple of an engraving.

The first point has often been made. Socrates argues for it with anice example in Plato's  Cratylus  (432b-c): 'An image', he says toCratylus, 'which reproduced all the qualities of the thing imitatedwould no longer be an image.' And he continues as follows:

Suppose tha t some god makes not only a representation such as apainter would make of your outward form and colour, but alsocreates an inward organisation like yours, having the samewarmth and softness, and into this infuses motion, and soul, andmind, such as you have, and in a word copies all your qualities,

and places them by you in another form. Would you say that thiswas Cratylus and the image of Cratylus, or that there were twoCratyluses?

Although it is obvious which answer Socrates expects, it is less obvi-ous that either is satisfactory. However, what matters more is that

57

Page 9: Hyman 1997_Words and Pictures

8/12/2019 Hyman 1997_Words and Pictures

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/hyman-1997words-and-pictures 9/27

John Hym an

the general proposition about images has not been demonstrated,and seems to be false; for many pictures depict other pictures, andin such a case, part of the depicting picture will resemble the

depicted picture in i ts ' inward organization' as well as in i ts 'out-ward form and colour', as long as the same sorts of materials areused in both cases. Perhaps we can accommodate this exception bymodifying the general proposition, for i t seems plausible that anentire  image cannot resemble an object i t represents in all respects.But since many parts of images depict objects or parts of objects,the modified proposition will not shed much light on the nature ofdepiction, at least until some further work is done to tease out itssignificance.

Descartes' second point is that an image need only resemble whatit represents in a few respects. Socrates' argument has a bearing onthis point also, because it implies what was proposed earlier — thatthe few respects in which an image must resemble what i t repre-sents,  if the resemblance theory is right, are 'outward form andcolour'. However, it is noticeable —  although not surprising, givenhis theory of colour - that Descartes chose to illustrate the pointwith the example of an engraving, ignoring colour altogether.5

Descartes' f inal point is that even in respect of shape the resem-blance between an image and the object it represents is oftenimperfect . He supports th is with two observat ions, one concerningthe shapes of bodies and the other, two-dimensional shapes. First ,he points out that 'engravings represent to us bodies of varyingrelief and depth on a surface which is entirely flat ' . So, for exam-ple,  the parts of an engraving which depict a cylindrical tower andits conical roof cannot possibly resemble these things in shape,because a figure on a plane cannot be cylindrical or conical. And

then he adds that ' in accordance with the rules of perspective[engravings] often represent circles by ovals better than by othercircles. . .and similarly for other shapes' . Thus, even part of anengraving which depicts some thing with a two-dim ensional shape- say, the facade of a building or the surface of a table - will nothave exactly the same shape as the thing it depicts, if the artist hasused foreshortening.

I think this criticism is interesting, and rather effective. Just howeffective it is will become clear in the sequel.

I turn now to Goodman. Goodman tr ies to disprove the resem-blance theory by attacking a theory of vision which he believes itpresupposes. Following Gombrich, he calls this theory the 'myth ofthe innocent eye' . I t is propounded by Berkeley in his   New Theoryof Vision  and defended by Russell in  Our Knowledge of the External

5  On Descartes' theory of colour, see Hacker (1987), ch. 1.

58

Page 10: Hyman 1997_Words and Pictures

8/12/2019 Hyman 1997_Words and Pictures

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/hyman-1997words-and-pictures 10/27

Words and Pictures

World: w hat we see imm ediately  and  directly, the visual appearancesthat things present  to us, are always sim ply  a patchwork  of  colours.We identify  the  things themselves  and  their various qualit ies,  by

interpreting this bril l iant panorama  in the light  of  experience. (AsBerkeley (1975, sec. 130) pu t it: in a  strict sense,  I see noth ing but

lights  and colours,  and the ir several shade s  and v ariations.. . ')Goodman argues that if, as the resem blance the ory implies,  a pic-

ture were a copy of the visual app earance  of the things  it depicts, an

artist would need, somehow   or   other,  to   strip away  the varnish  of

thought  and interpre tation which clothes  his —  as everyone's — per-

ception  of things, in order to  record the pristin e patchw ork of  colourswhich lies beneath   it. But  since this operation, which G ood m an(1981, p. 8) caustically desc ribes  as 'purification rites'  and 'methodi -cal disinterpretation',  is impossible,  the resemblance theory  is false.

I f ind this argument unsatisfactory because  it   imputes gui l t  by

association.  The theory  of  percept ion Goodman at tacks  is  definite-ly confused.  It  implies that perceptual judgements  -  such  as the

judgement that there  is a book before yo ur eyes, or a window to one

side  of you - are the results  of  inferences,  and a faithful re po rt of

the evidence  on wh ich the se inferences  are based wou ld ne ed  to be

couched  in a  vocabulary restricted  to  terms which refer  to  shapesand colours. Hence  it   implies that every reasonable perc eptu aljudgemen t  we  m ake arises out of a visual experience wh ich  we are

able  to   describe faithfully  in   these austere terms, since  the evidencefor the judgement would otherwise  be beyond  our grasp. B ut we are

not generally able   to prov ide this sort  of  descr ipt ion  of our visualexperience; hence  our  experience  and the judg em ents which ar iseout  of it cannot  be related  in the way the theory implies.  It is easyto miss this point,  if we  imagine that  a  visual experience  itself,

rather than  a description  of  what  we  see, co uld  be the  data  or evi-

dence   on   which  an   inference  was   based.  But in  fact  the  phrase'sense-data '  is misleading. A  visual experience  is not the premise of

an argument, which  can be  taken  as  true  and argued from: hence  itcannot  be  evidence  in the  requ ired sense.

6

O ne  can of  course imagine  the  resemb lance theo ry being com-

bined with this patchwork theory   of  vision,  the myth  of the inno-cent eye. Indeed there   is no  need  to imagine  it , because  it   was untilrecently quite common,  not  only am ong theorists  but  among

painters  too.  Monet ,  for  example, offered  the  following advice:'When  you go out to   paint ,  try to  forget what objects  you  havebefore you,  a tree,  a house,  a field,  or  whatever. Merely thin k, hereis a little squ are of blue, here an  oblong of  pink, here a streak of yel-

6Cf. Ryle (1971), p. 346.

59

Page 11: Hyman 1997_Words and Pictures

8/12/2019 Hyman 1997_Words and Pictures

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/hyman-1997words-and-pictures 11/27

John Hyman

low, and pain t  it  jus t as it looks  to you,  the exact colour  and shape,unt i l  it   gives your own naive impression  of the scene before you '.

7

Nevertheless, Goodman fails  to show tha t one cannot end orse the

resemblance theory without implicit ly accepting   the  myth  of theinnocent  eye, and it is  doubtful w heth er this  can be  shown. An

advocate  of the  resemblanc e theo ry nee ds  to say   something  aboutappearances.  But why  are we  entitled  to sup po se that this confuseddoctr ine about appearances  is all tha t he w ill find  to say? Since ther eis   no  obvious reason, since none  is  given,  and  since —  as   will  be

shown  in the  sequel —  there  is  much else that  can be  said aboutappearances , Goodman 's a rgument  is  unconvincing.  The  resem-blance theory  and the  m y t h  of the inno cen t eye dovetail neatly, and

have often been combined,  but one  cannot condem n  a  theorybecause  it  has been seen  in bad  company.

Goodman s Theory

N o w   I  shal l examine Goodman 's  own theory  of  depict ion.  The

philosophers Goodman reacted against were Susanne Langer ,Char les Morr is , John Hospers .  As we have seen, they prop ose d  a

novel answer  to the  quest ion  of   what  pictures  do, although theyaccepted  the orthodo x answer  to the quest ion  of how they  do it.

Ins tead   of  producing i l lusions,  or  making  us  think  of  things,  or

presen t ing  us w ith the appea rances  of  things, they argued th at p ic-tu res  are symbols  or   signs which stand  for or  refer  to the  objectsthey represent . (Hospers (1946,  p. 29)  does  not  explain wha t' s tand ing   for is, beyond me nt ion ing ,  as an  examp le, that  the wordchair  'refers  to or  stands for. . . the kind  of  object that  I am  now sit-

t ing  on .  M orris (1946) explains what s tandin g  for is in   behav-

iourist terms.)If both pictures  and words  are  signs or  symbols, we shall have to

distinguish between them by distinguishing between different kindsof signification. Drawing partly  on  Peirce's taxonomy  of  signs,

7 Quoted  by  Gage (1993), p.  209. Unfortunately, there is no record of

this remark   in the original French; but it seems very likely that the phrasethe translator rendered  as  'naive impression'  was meant  to   refer  to thecolourful mosaic which   was widely imagined  to be the raw material ofvisual experience.  In   England, Ruskin and Fry  expressed similar views.

Indeed, Ruskin expressed   it in the passage  in   The Elements of   Drawingwhich gave Gombrich the phrase 'the innocent eye': 'The whole technicalpower of  painting', Ruskin wrote, 'depends on our recovery of what maybe called  the  innocence of  the eye;  that is to say, of a sort of childish per-ception  of  these flat stains of  colour, merely  as such, without conscious-ness of what they signify...' Quoted by G ombrich (1977), p. 250.

60

Page 12: Hyman 1997_Words and Pictures

8/12/2019 Hyman 1997_Words and Pictures

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/hyman-1997words-and-pictures 12/27

Words and Pictures

Morris (1946, p.  190) describ ed  a picture  as a  visual  and  iconic sign,that is, a 'visual stimulus .. .which  is similar  in  some respects  to whatit denotes'.

8  Hospers argued that  a  picture  is a   natural  symbol ,

whose significance does  not depend ,  as the significance  of a  worddoes, on stipulation  or   convention.

O ne  of the problem s with  the  semiotic theory  is that  too  m a n ydifferent kinds  of  thing were said to be  iconic signs: onomatopoeicwords; sentences which are similar  in  struc ture  to the  circum stancesthey describe, like   T he  fork  is to the  left  of the  knife' (w rittendown)  or T he   Sanctus  comes before  the   Agnus   Dei (spoken);graphs; maps; paint ings; photographs; shadows; footpr ints; coloursamples of the  sort one finds  in  catalogues  of  artists ' materials; and

so on. M oreover,  it becam e clear that th e term s  symbol and  stands forwere being used   too  generously  to retain m uch m eaning.  For exam-ple,  nimbus clouds were held  to  stand  for  rain  and a car  comingstraight towards another  car was descr ibed  as a  symbol meaning' s top ' ,  although these were  not of  course supposed  to be  iconicsigns.  But even  if it was thou ght possible  to  tighten this  up, and

thereby toss out some of the motley things  in the  rag-bag  of  iconicsigns,  degrees  of  iconicity still seemed  too crude  a  device  to  drawsignificant distinctions between   the things that remained .

Languages of Art   is an avowedly heterodo x p rodu ct  of the semi-otic tradition  in  aesthetics. G oo dm an accep ts that picture s  are visu-al signs -  they are signs because they stand for or refer  to the  objectsthey represent; they   are visual signs because w hat they repre sentdepends on how they look. But he denies categorically that pictu resare natural  or iconic sign s; and that ,  he  says complacently, 'adds up

to open heresy'  (1981,  p. 230).Instead  of  explaining depiction  in  terms  of a  'close natural rela-

t ionship ' between  a picture and w hat  it represents ,  Languages  of Artdefends  an   elaborate analogy between  the manufacture  and  enjoy-men t  of  pictures  and the use of  language. This analogy has existedin   one form  or   another since Plato.  It  received  its m ost influentialexpression   in the letter G rego ry  the  Great wrote  to the  Bishop of

Marseilles  in   about 600:  For the  u nle t te red ,  and in  part icular  for

the heathen,  a  picture takes  the place  of a  book. '  As I  ment ionedearlier, Descartes drew attention   to it in his  Optics.  And of  course itwas implicit  in the doctr ine  of the  iconic sign.  But nob ody before

8 Morris also claimed that an iconic sign 'denote[s] any object which hasthe properties  (in practice, a selection from the properties) which  it itselfhas'  (1939-40), p. 136; but  this implies that  if a portrait  of  Smith  is aniconic sign which denotes Sm ith, then  it denotes his twin brother, and thatif  a picture of an apple is an iconic sign, it denotes every other picture ofan apple that it  resembles sufficiently closely.

61

Page 13: Hyman 1997_Words and Pictures

8/12/2019 Hyman 1997_Words and Pictures

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/hyman-1997words-and-pictures 13/27

John Hyman

Goodman supposed that the analogy is sufficiently close to discon-nect depiction and resemblance entirely.

G ood m an begins with a por trai t of the Du ke of W ell ington. T he

portrait , he argues, l ike the proper name 'Arthur Wellesley' and thedefinite description ' the victor at Waterloo' ,  denotes  the man it por-trays.  Like Hospers, Goodman does not explain what he means bydenotation. It is the relation between a label and the thing or thingsit is attached to, a name and its bearer, or a predicate and the sever-al members of the corresponding class - and that is all there is to besaid about i t . Holbein 's portrait of Erasmus denotes Erasmus, and aview of the Matterhorn denotes the mountain .

However, a painting of a satyr, although it may be said, with per-

fect propriety, to depict or represent a satyr, denotes nothing at all,for no satyrs exist to be denoted. In this sort of case, Goodmanargues, the verb 'dep ict' does not signify a relation betwee n two inde-pe nd en tly ex isting thin gs; it is pa rt of a com plex one-place p redicate.A painting of a satyr is not something, a painting, which stands in acertain relation, depiction, to another thing, a satyr. It is merely acertain kind of painting, a satyr-representing-painting, so to speak. 9

I f Holbein 's por trai t of Erasmus, l ike the name 'Erasmus' ,denotes him, whereas a painting of a satyr, l ike the word 'satyr ' ,denotes nothing, what is i t that makes the two paintings, each ofthe m an intr icate disposi t ion of p igm ents u pon a canvas, examplesof p ic tor ia l represen ta t ion , whereas the two s t r ings of le t te rs ,'E-R-A-s-M-u-s' and 's-A-T-Y-R', are linguistic symbols? Not, asHospers and the other semioticians supposed, a 'close natural rela-tionship, namely likeness or resemblance' , or for that matter anyother sort of relationship, between the pictures and what theydepict: 'Descriptions are distinguished from depictions not throughbeing more arbitrary but through belonging to articulate ratherthan to dense schemes; and words are [no] more conventional than

9 In Languages of Art, Goodman (1981), p. 21 injudiciously claimed that

'F-representing-picture' is an unbreakable predicate, i.e. that its meaningis not a function of the meanings of its parts and the way in which they arecombined. ('Red' and 'round' are trivially unbreakable, because they donot have significant parts; 'red and round' and 'red or round' are notunbreakable. Figurative predicates are often unbreakable, despite havingsignificant parts: for example, one cannot deduce the meaning of 'blue-chip'  or 'copper-bottomed' from the meaning of their parts.) This claim

was criticised by Wollheim (1973) and Scruton (1974), pp. 193-97, and itis certainly false. For if 'sloop-representing-picture' were an unbreakablepredicate, it would not be possible to deduce that a sloop-representing-p ic-ture is a boat-representing-picture from the fact that a sloop is a boat.Goodman (1972, p. 122) has since conceded that F-representing-picture isa complex one-place predicate, and not an unbreakable one.

62

Page 14: Hyman 1997_Words and Pictures

8/12/2019 Hyman 1997_Words and Pictures

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/hyman-1997words-and-pictures 14/27

Words and Pictures

pictures...if conventionality is construed in terms of...artificiality'(Goodman 1981), pp. 230-1). The manufacture of pictures,Goodman argues, like the use of language, is a symbolic activity

governed by a complex system of semantic and syntactic rules; andit is the distinctive character of the system of rules which guide themanufacture and the use of pictures, rather than a special kind ofrelationship, such as resemblance, between pictures and what theydepict, which makes the difference between a picture and a desc rip-tion in words.

A symbolic system is representational, Goodman explains, if anychange to a character in any one of various respects, however smallthe change is, will effect a change in what it represents. This, in anutshell, is the difference between pictures and written descrip-tions.  One example will suffice. Compare a drawing of a man witha long nose with the corresponding written phrase (figs. 1 and 2). Ifwe change the drawing slightly, say by elongating the part whichrepresents the nose, it will represent a man with a longer nose thanit did before; whereas the corresponding change to the phrase willnot have the same effect (figs. 3 and 4). Of course, a small change tothe written phrase  might  change its meaning (fig. 5); but only if it

Fig 1

  man w ith a long noseFig. 2

Fig 3

63

Page 15: Hyman 1997_Words and Pictures

8/12/2019 Hyman 1997_Words and Pictures

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/hyman-1997words-and-pictures 15/27

John Hyman

A man with a long n o s eFig 4

A man with a long hoseFig 5

affects the classification of one or more characters, so that an 'n'becomes an 'h ' , for example. There is no respect —  the thickness orcolour of the line, the size or shape of any part of the inscription —in which any change, however small, will change the significance ofa wri t ten phrase. Turning from wri t ten to spoken language, we cansee tha t if En glish we re modified in such a way that every differencein intonation, volume and pitch corresponded to a difference inmeaning, i t would become a representational language, or rather, i twou ld have ceased to be a language an d would have become insteada means of making audible representations, distinguishable frompictures only by the fact that they would be constructed out of

sounds rather than colours. Hence the distinctive character of a pic-torial symbolic system depends essentially upon the 'syntactic andsemantic relationships among [its] symbols'  (1981,  pp. 227-8), andhas nothing whatever to do with any putative resemblance betweenpictures and their subjects.

Turning now from exposition to crit icism, I shall concentrate onthe propinquity Goodman's analysis confers on words and pictures;in fact, I shall focus on one fundamental defect, although I shallappro ach it by a circuitous route. Th e struc ture of the a rgum ent

will be complicated; so I shall explain it in advance. It has threesteps.First , I shall consider one of the two most common objections to

Goodman's theory: that i t severs the connection between being vis-ible and being depictable. I shall argue that Goodman can meet thisobjection, but only by conceding that if pictures 'function in some-wh at the same way as des criptio ns' (G oo dm an 1981, p. 30), thedescriptions that pictures are somewhat l ike are descriptions whichare couched purely in terms of form and colour. Second, I shall con-

sider the other of the two most common objections to Goodman'stheory: that if I can recognize a certain sort of object then I can beexp ected to recognize a pic ture of tha t sort of object, w hereasGoodman's theory implies, on the contrary, that I cannot be expect-ed to recognize a picture of something unless I also know the rele-vant syntactic and semantic rules. Again, I shall argue that

64

Page 16: Hyman 1997_Words and Pictures

8/12/2019 Hyman 1997_Words and Pictures

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/hyman-1997words-and-pictures 16/27

Words and Pictures

Goodman can meet this objection, but only by making the sameconcession: that if pictures 'function in somewhat the same way asdescriptions', these descriptions must be ones which are couched

purely in terms of form and colour. Finally, I shall argue that theconcession is fatal, because it implies that we can only identify thesubject of a picture by means of an inference. This approach is basi-cally a matter of asking what kind of rule Goodman's theory postu-lates, or rather, what its nearest linguistic equivalent would be; andwhether seeing what a picture represents could be the result ofapplying rules of this kind.

According to Alberti, 'No one would deny that the painter hasnothing to do with things that are not visible' (1966, p. 43). If this

seems plausible, then it will be tempting to argue as follows: byinsisting tha t the relation between a picture and its subject is whol-ly conventional, Goodman loses the resources he would need inorder to explain why it is impossible to depict sounds; for it is cer-tainly possible to devise a representational scheme which usescolours arranged on a plane surface to represent sequences ofsounds, and where a small modification in the symbol (it would bea kind of graph) affects what it represents. For example, the  x  axismight represent time; the y  axis, pitch; hue might represent timbre;

and saturation, volume.If the objection is stated in exactly these terms, it seems to be

open to a decisive rejoinder, namely, that it  is   possible to depictsounds. For example, the drawings by Saul Steinberg which theadvertising campaign for Classic FM radio made famous unmistak-ably depict the sounds of various musical instruments.Furthermore, whatever makes it true that the delicate filigreedepicts the sound of a harp, it cannot be a close resemblancebetween them in shape or colour, or the fact that the drawing pro-

duces the illusion of hearing a harp, because there is no such resem-blance and no such fact. Hence, far from indicating a weakness inGoodman's theory, the question of whether it is possible to depictsounds reveals a weakness in its principal rivals.

Perhaps there is a better way of stating this objection toGoodman's theory. For whereas it is perfectly possible to describe asound without employing a synaesthetic metaphor, any depiction ofa sound will need to be metaphorical; and that is a fact whichGoodman's theory cannot accommodate. Once again, an advocateof the resemblance theory can take heart, for if  X  and  Y  resembleeach other in appearance, the resemblance between them may be aliteral one; but if the appearance of X  resembles the sound of  Y,  theresemblance can only be metaphorical.

There is, I believe, one way in which, Goodman can meet this

65

Page 17: Hyman 1997_Words and Pictures

8/12/2019 Hyman 1997_Words and Pictures

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/hyman-1997words-and-pictures 17/27

John Hyman

objection, and that is by conceding that the language in which pic-tures speak to us is only capable of  literal descriptions of things withshapes and colours. This would not imply that pictures cannot rep-resent landscapes, men and angels; bu t tha t they could only do so ina vocabulary confined to shape- and colour-terms. In Goodman'sown terminology, the compliance-classes (or classes of denotata) ofcharacters in a pictorial system of representation would be definedby shape and colour alone. If this concession were granted, the factthat a picture of a sound cannot fail to be a metaphor would ceaseto be an embarrassment. For although colour-terms can be used todescribe sounds —  Messiaen was famously fond of giving colourfuldescriptions of his chords - these descriptions are bound to bemetaphorical.

Now for the other popular objection to Goodman's theory. Theability to recognize something by its appearance seems intuitivelyto be connected more closely with the ability to recognize a pictureof it than with the ability to recognize a description of it; whereasGoodman's theo ry implies, on the contrary, that neither connectionis closer than the other. This objection surely has some degree ofplausibility, bu t it is difficult to tur n it into a compelling argum ent.

It would be nice if we could claim, straightforwardly and unequiv-ocally, that if I can recognize something by its appearance then Imust be able to recognize a picture of it; for if depiction isexplained by semantic and syntactic conventions, I may be able torecognize something by its appearance without knowing the rele-vant conventions, and hence without being able to recognize a pic-ture of it. But the straigh tforward claim is, as it so often is, too boldto be convincing. For example, a dog may be able to recognize itsmaster without being able to recognize his portrait. And if the

straightforward claim is false, it isn't easy to modify it sufficientlyto make it plausible without weakening it to the point where it isconsistent with Goodman's theory. A few critics have tried to dothis,  and failed. Richard Wollheim, for example, put the objectionas follows:

it is a grave objection to [Goodman's theory] that it cannotaccount for the evident fact of transfer. By the term 'transfer' Imean, for instance, that, if I can recognize a picture of a cat, andI know what a dog looks like, then I can be expected to recognize

a picture of a dog. But on [Goodm an's] view this ought to be baf-fling. It should be as baffling as if, knowing that the French word chat means a cat, and knowing what dogs look like, I should, onhearing it, be able to understand what the word  Men means.(Wollheim 1987, p. 77)

66

Page 18: Hyman 1997_Words and Pictures

8/12/2019 Hyman 1997_Words and Pictures

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/hyman-1997words-and-pictures 18/27

Words and Pictures

Wollheim's argument  is  admirably concise,  bu t it is not a  cogentobjection  to   Goodman 's theory because  the the ory does  not  implythat pictures  are like n am es. On the contrary, Go odm an argues thatthe rules which determine what pictures represent   are significantlydifferent from the rules which  fix the m eanings of  'chat '  and 'chien ' ,and  as we have seen, he is quite clear abou t w hat  the difference  is.

So  it  would  be a  fairer test  of  Goodman 's theory  to ask  whethe rtransfer would  be a  surprising feature  of a  symbolic system  or, in

particular,  of a  representational  symbolic system — in  other w ords, asymbolic system   in   which m inute changes  of  various kinds  to a

character will change what  it   represents .In fact, there  are  ma ny sym bolic systems  in  wh ich transfer

occurs.  For example,  the diagram ma tic no tat ion devised  for  musi -cally illiterate guitarists represents  the fingering  for   each chord by

marking  a grid w ith dots,  and it  seems obvious that  if I can recog-nize  the sign  for a G   major chord  and I  know  the  fingering  for a

diminished seventh  on D, then  I can be   expected  to  recognise  the

sign   for a  diminished seventh  on D. So, would  it be surpr is ing  iftransfer occurred  in a  representational system?  I can see no   reasonto think that  it  would;  and  since  he  fails  to  provide  a  reason,

Wollheim's argument  is unconvincing. He seems to have m istaken adisanalogy between pictures  and  words  for a  disanalogy b etw eenpictures  and symbols  in  general.

But if  transfer  is an 'evident fact' a bou t pictures, as it seems to be,and if  pictures 'function  in  somew hat the sam e way as descr ip t ions ' ,as Goodman says they   do  (1981,  p. 30),  thes e will hav e  to be

descriptions  of a  special sort, since transfer will have  to be a  factabout them too.  If I can recognize this sort  of  descr ipt ion  of a cat,

and  I  know what a dog looks like, th en  I can be  expected  to  recog-

nize this sort  of  descr ipt ion  of a dog.  But the  only sort  of  descr ip-tion  I can be expected  to recognize becau se  I know w hat a d og  lookslike   is a  description  of a  dog's appearance;  and the  only sort  of

description  of a  dog's appearance  I can be   expected  to  recognizebecause  I can recognize  a  certain sort  of  descr ipt ion  of a cat is a

description which makes  use of the  same vocabulary  as this sort of

description  of a cat.  In short ,  if  pictures 'function  in  somewhat the

same way   as descr ipt ions ' , these descr ipt ions m ust  be couched  in a

vocabulary which   has a  sufficiently broa d com peten ce  in the

description of appearances to m atc h the full ex tent of transfer  in therecognition  of  pictures; and which is fully eng age d  in  every de scrip -tion,  so  that  if I  under s t and  one descr ipt ion,  I can be   expected  tounderstand another . When  we consider how far  transfer extends  -

from pictures  of  clouds  to pictures  of  cuckoos —  it is obvious thatthis could only  be a vocabulary  of  colour-  and shape- terms. So, if a

67

Page 19: Hyman 1997_Words and Pictures

8/12/2019 Hyman 1997_Words and Pictures

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/hyman-1997words-and-pictures 19/27

John Hyman

picture is like a description, it must be like a description couchedpurely in terms of form and colour.

As we have seen, Goodman says that pictures are like descrip-

tions. If my argument is correct, his theory implies that they are likedescriptions of a particular sort, namely, ones which only make useof colour- and shape-predicates. It follows that the theory isdemonstrably false; for if pictures were like descriptions of thissort, any attempt to say what a picture depicts which goes beyond adescription of their colours and shapes would have to be the resultof an inference; but this is false.

Goodman  (1981, p. 36) explicitly denies that we need be 'aware...of making any interpretations at all' when we perceive what a pic-

ture depicts. But in fact his theory implies that we should be awareof making interpretations when we perceive that a picture repre-sents the sun, as opposed (roughly) to something round and yellow,or a girl with a falcon, as opposed to som ething with such-and-suchcolours at such-and-such places, just as we would be if we realisedthat a verbal description in terms of shape and colour was in fact adescription of the sun or a girl with a falcon. Once we know a lan-guage well, we come to hear or see words, phrases and sentences ashaving the meaning they do. So there is no obstacle to Goodman'smaintaining that we need not be aware of interpreting pictureswhen we perceive what they represent, despite the fact that they arecharacters in a symbolic system,  so long as we do not outstrip theirmanifest signification. But as soon as we perceive that a picturedepicts something of such-and-such a kind, where 'such-and-such'involves more than shapes and colours, he is bound to admit that wehave left behind what visual experience can present us with, bymeans of an explicit inference.

Goodman criticises the resemblance theory for implying that visu-al experience can only ever present us directly with shapes andcolours. Following Gombrich, he calls this doctrine the myth of theinnocent eye. But the proposition that perceiving what a picturedepicts depends on making inferences is tantamount to applying themyth to pictures; for it is no more plausible to deny that we can seewhat a picture depicts immediately and directly than to deny that wecan see the visible objects in our environment immediately anddirectly, rather than mere patterns of light and colour. In the final

analysis, this is the cardinal principle which Goodman's theory con-tradicts. If his theory were correct, we would need to be capable ofdescribing what a picture depicts purely in terms of shape and colourin order to be capable of describing it at all. But we don't, any morethan we need to able to describe the visible things that su rround us inthe same austere vocabulary, in order to say what they are.

68

Page 20: Hyman 1997_Words and Pictures

8/12/2019 Hyman 1997_Words and Pictures

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/hyman-1997words-and-pictures 20/27

Words and Pictures

Art and Occlusion

If  the  relationship betw een p ictures  and wh at they depict  is not ,

after all, a purely conventional on e; and if  Descartes was right  to saythat even  in   respect  of  shape,  the  resemblance between  an   imageand  the  object  it   represents  is  often imp erfect,  is it  possible  to

explain precisely what sort of  relationship must exist between  a pic-ture  and its  subject?  Or is  there perhaps  - as  Descar tes seems  tohave believed  - no answer  to be found, until experim ental p sych ol-ogy has discovered whatever correlations exist between  the forms of

images and the  'sensory percept ions  of all the various qualit ies of

the objects  to which they correspon d '?

I think  it is possible  to provide  an  answer,  if we make  use of the

concept  of  occlusion shape.  T he  occlusion shape  of an  object  is

what some philosophers have called  its  'apparen t shape '  - in   otherwords, an  object 's outline or  silhouette.  I prefer  the ter m 'occlusionshape' because it is less tenden tious, since  it  does not carry  the  sug-gestio falsi  that  a  contrast  is  being m ade im plicit ly between  an

object's  occlusion  shape  and its  real shape,  and hence that  an  object 'socclusion shape  is not a  perfectly objective visible feature  of our

physical environment.  A  circular plate viewed obliquely  has an

elliptical occlusion shape:  it will occlu de or be  occluded  by an ellip-tical patc h on a plane perp endicular  to the  line of  sight. An object 'socclusion shape  is a  function  of its  actual shape  (I   shall  use the

phrase, despite misgivings)  and its orien tation relative to the line of

sight.  We can be   mistaken about  the  occlusion shape  of an  object,and  a mistake of  this kind can be corrected by m easurem ent and cal-culation.  An object's o cclusion sh ape can also be affected  by  refrac-tion.  A  straight stick that  is  half- immersed  in   water will have  acrooked occlusion shape. Again, this  is a  perfectly objective m atter.

The concept  of  occlusion shape plays  the following role  in the

theory  of  depiction. Consider  an   engraving  of a  m an 's head .W h e t h e r  the  picture  shows   its  internal subject  (as   Beardsleythought) ,  stands  for   it (as Ho spers thought) ,  or  produces  a  specialsort  of  psychological episode which  is  related  in   some distinctiveway   to the  psychological episode wh ich occu rs when som eone seesa man's head,  it does so  because  the shape (the actual shape , that is)

of  the smallest pa rt  of the pictu re w hich dep icts  the m an's nose or

chin  is identical  to the   occlusion shape of the nose or the c hin in thepicture, relative  to the  spec tator 's l ine of  sight.  T he general pr inc i-ple,  which  I  shall call  the  Occlusion Sha pe Princip le,  is  easilyproved  by   means  of a  though t -exper imen t .  In  fact,  the  though t -exper iment is an unu sual one, because  it  can actually be  performed.The exper iment  is to try to trace  the shape  of the par t  of a  picture

69

Page 21: Hyman 1997_Words and Pictures

8/12/2019 Hyman 1997_Words and Pictures

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/hyman-1997words-and-pictures 21/27

John Hytnan

which depicts something - whether it's a house or a tree or a man ora part of his body - by running a finger across its surface, withoutsimultaneously tracing the occlusion shape of the correspondingpart of the pictu re's internal subject - the house or the tree or what-ever. Alternatively, one might try to trace the occlusion shape ofpart of a picture's internal subject without tracing the actual shapeof the part of the picture that depicts it. It only takes a moment'sreflection to see that neither thing is possible. Hence the occlusionshape of  a part of  a picture s internal subject (/), relative to the spec-tator's line of sight, and the actual shape of  the  smallest part o f thepicture that depicts  that part of its  internal subject  (D ) must be iden-tical.

It is important to notice how modest the Occlusion ShapePrinciple is. First, it tells us nothing about what  kind  of thing theinternal subject of a pic ture is, as opposed to its occlusion shape rel-ative to the spectator's line of sight. For example, if part of a pic-ture represents a duck 's bill or a rabbit's ears, the principle does nottell us which; although it does tell us that if the picture can be seeneither as a picture of a duck or as a picture of a rabbit, the duck andthe rabbit must have the same occlusion shape, relative to the spec-tator's line of sight. Second, it says nothing about the relationshipbetween the surface of a picture and its  external subject, if it hasone.  Finally, it does not imply that each part of the internal subjectof a picture must have a fully determ inate occlusion shape; althoughit does imply that any such indeterm inacy will be precisely matchedby a corresponding indeterminacy in the shape of the correspond-ing part of the picture's surface. But although the Occlusion ShapePrinciple is modest, it marks a fundamental difference between pic-tures and inscriptions, for the shape of an inscription alone does not

tell us anything whatever about its meaning.Mention of meaning brings me to an objection which might wellhave been raised when the concept of a picture's internal subjectwas introduced. T he objection may as well set out from a remark inLanguages of Art:

From the fact that  P  is a picture of or represents a unicorn wecannot infer that there is something that P is a picture of or rep-resents... Saying that a picture represents a so-and-so is thus high-ly ambiguous as between saying what the picture denotes and

saying what kind of picture it is. (Goodm an 1981, p. 22)

The objection is that unless talk about a picture P's internal subjectis interpreted as talk about what kind of picture P is, it is bound toinvolve, at least implicitly, the 'fallacious existential inference'(ibid., n. 19) that there is something that P is a pictu re of, something

7

Page 22: Hyman 1997_Words and Pictures

8/12/2019 Hyman 1997_Words and Pictures

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/hyman-1997words-and-pictures 22/27

Words and Pictures

that actually exists; and that  the Occlusion S hape Pr inciple implic-itly commits this fallacy.  If the internal subject  of a picture  is anal-ogous  to the  sense  or meaning  of a de scr ipt ion  in  words,  the claim

that  it has a  certain occlusion shape  or  that  it  resembles S m ithinvolves  a blatant h ypostatisation  of  meanings .

The reply   to  this objection  is that a t t r ibut ing  an  occlusion shapeto  a part  of the  internal subject  of a  picture need not be taken  toamoun t  to som ething m ore than saying what kind  of  picture  it is.

The Occlusion Shape Principle allows us to infer from

(i) D  depicts something which  has the  occlusion shape  5

that

(ii) D  has the  actual s hape  S

although   of  course this must not be taken  to  imply that  any  infer-ence is necessary  in  order  to perceive that either  (i) or (ii) is the case.But  if  P  represents  a  unicorn '  can be  unders tood  as  saying whatkind  of  picture P  is, rather than  as expressing  a  relation between  Pand something else which exists independently   of   P,   as it  surelycan, then  so can P (or   D)  represents something which  has the

occlusion shape S .  Hence , ne i the r ' / has  the occlusion shape S nor

' / resembles Smith ' implies that  / is som ething w hich exists inde-pendently   of  P,  and which m igh t therefore su rvive  its  destruct ion;any more than 'Jones  is imagining som ething w hich  has the  occlu-sion shape  S or  'Jones  is imagining  a man who  resembles Sm ith 'carries  the corresponding  and equally fallacious im plica tion.

A second objection   to the  Occlusion Shap e Principle  is that por-

trait caricature disproves it, for surely  the physiognomy  of a carica-turist 's subject may be wildly d istorted  on the   picture's surface, and

moreover  the distortio n need  not  conform  to any fixed rule . T he

objection  is a weak one , becau se  it  turns on a confusion betw een theinternal subject  of a picture  and its  external subject.  T he  internalsubject  of a  portrait caricature  is a  recognisable distortion  of its

external subject ;  but the   cor responde nce p resc r ibed  by the

Occlusion Shape Principle, between   the  pic ture 's surface  and its

internal subject,  is not  breached.A more telling objection   has to do with distor t ions  of a  different

kind, namely anamorphoses: 'perspectives which, r ightly gazedupon ,  /  Show nothing  but  confusion,  - ey d  awry,  /  Dist inguish

form'.10   The best know n anam orphoses include  the famous depic-tion of a  skull at the bot to m of H olbein 's  French Ambassadors  (in the

National Gallery, London)  and a  portrai t  of  Edward  VI (in the

National Portrait Gallery),  but the technique  was  commonly  and

10 Shakespeare, Richard II,   II.ii.18f.

71

Page 23: Hyman 1997_Words and Pictures

8/12/2019 Hyman 1997_Words and Pictures

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/hyman-1997words-and-pictures 23/27

John Hym an

less playfully exploited by the artists responsible for Byzantinechurch decoration, to compensate for distortions which would oth-erwise appear in pictures as a result of the spectator's eccentric line

of sight, or the curvature of the picture's surface. For example, inthe Pentecost depicted in the main cupola of the Haghia Sophia inThessalonica, the legs of the Apostles are deliberately elongatedbecause, whereas the upper parts of the figures l ie almost perpen-dicular to the spectator's line of sight, their lower parts are morenearly vertical, and so the anamorphosis ensures that the apostles 'bodies will appear to be well-proportioned when the cupola is seenfrom below.

Examples of this sort seem to disprove the Occlusion Shape

Principle, because the occlusion shape of an Apostle 's leg,   relativeto the spectator s line of sight,  is not identical to the actual shape ofthe smallest part of the mosaic that depicts it, precisely because thespectator 's l ine of sight is eccentric. Anamorphosis therefore seemsto recom m end a different principle , namely that the occlusion shapeof / and the occlusion shape of   D,  both relative to the normal orintended line of sight, must be identical. The phrase 'normal orintended' is of course vital, since the occlusion shape of / will notchange merely because the spectator 's l ine of sight, and hence theocclusion shape of  D,  chang es. For exam ple, if a circular part of apicture's surface represents a sphere, it will not cease to do so if thespectator moves to one side of the picture. But whereas the occlu-sion shape of a sphere can only be a circle, the occlusion shape of acircular part of a picture's surface will become elliptical if the spec-tator moves to one side.11

But the same phrase - 'normal or intended' - also indicates whatis wrong with the new principle. I t simply isn 't plausible that a nor-mal or intended line of sight which is sufficiently precise to under-write the principle is associated with every picture: there would, forexample, need to be a normal reading posture precise enough toshame the sternest aficionado of the Alexander Technique, andacknowledged since the invention of the illustrated book. And it ismanifestly absurd to suppose that a distinct line of sight is specifi-cally associated with each part of every large picture which is not ananamorphosis. Is it feasible to add a rider to the new principle, stat-ing that the default line of sight is orthogonal to the picture plane?

Perhaps; but this would simply amount to a return to the OcclusionSha pe Principle , disguised by a cu m bro us circum locution, for theocclusion shape of a two-dimensional form, relative to the line ofsight that is orthogonal to the plane on which the form is drawn, is

11  On some related matters concerning the spectator's line of sight, see

Gom brich (1977), pp. 215-16.

72

Page 24: Hyman 1997_Words and Pictures

8/12/2019 Hyman 1997_Words and Pictures

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/hyman-1997words-and-pictures 24/27

Words and Pictures

identical to its actual shape. It is better, therefore, to stick to theOcclusion Shape Principle, and to acknowledge the exceptionalnature of anamorphoses - somewhat as the theory of meaning can

acknowledge irony and hyperbole, without being stymied by them.Anamorphosis  is   exceptional; for whereas we normally perceive apicture's internal subject by perceiving shapes and colours on itssurface, anamorphosis requires us to mzsperceive D , in order to per-ceive / as we are meant to. Anam orphoses are, in effect, pictures tha tdon't mean what they say.

What goes for occlusion shape goes equally for relative occlusionsize. If I hold out my hands in front of me, and extend one arm fur-ther than the other, my hands will not appear to differ in size, but

the greater occlusion size of the nearer hand will be evident: thenearer hand will occlude or be occluded by a larger patch on a planeperpendicular to the line of sight. The relative occlusion size of twoobjects is a function of their relative size and their relative distancefrom the spectator, and is, no less than occlusion shape, a perfectlyobjective feature of the visible objects in our environment. And justas the occlusion shape of /, relative to the spectator's line of sight,and the actual shape of  D   must be identical, so the relative occlu-sion size of  I,  and I 2 relative to the spectator's point of view, and the

relative size of  D,  and  D 2  must be identical. I shall call this theRelative Occlusion Size Principle.

The two Occlusion Principles disprove Goodman's doctrine thatthe difference between a picture and a description in written wordsis wholly attributable to the distinctive pattern of 'syntactic andsemantic relationships among [its] symbols'. They also explain thefact on which - as we have seen - Goodm an confers a crucial signif-icance, namely, that a small change to a picture may effect a changein what it represents although a similar change to an inscriptionwould not have a similar effect. For if the Occlusion ShapePrinciple is true, any change to the actual shape of  D   will,  eo ipso,change the occlusion shape of /, relative to the spectator's line ofsight; and if the Relative Occlusion Size Principle is true, anychange to the relative size of  D,  and  D 2  will change the relativeocclusion size of  I,  and  I2,  relative to the spectator's point of view.The resemblance theory —  in its cruder forms at least —  impliessomething more than this, as Beardsley acknowledged: 'if two rep-resentational designs differ as designs,' he claimed, 'no matter howlittle, they must differ in what they depict, even if only trivially'(1981,  p. 295). But this is false, for if two paintings differ only inabsolute size, and not at all in the relative proportions of their parts,then in the absence of any explicit convention to this effect, therewill not be a difference in what they depict. (Although of course it

73

Page 25: Hyman 1997_Words and Pictures

8/12/2019 Hyman 1997_Words and Pictures

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/hyman-1997words-and-pictures 25/27

John Hym an

does not follow that they will not differ aesthetically).12

  T h eOcclusion Principles, by contrast , do not imply that a change inabsolute size, large or small, will have a corresponding effect on the

size of the picture 's internal subject.The Occlusion Principles also reveal how much truth there was in

Descartes' f inal objection to the resemblance theory. The objectionwas this:

Indeed the perfection of an image often depends on its not resem-bling its object as much as it might. You can see this in the case ofengravings...although they make us think of countless differentqualities in these objects, it is only in respect of shape that there is

any real resemblance. And even this resemblance is very imper-fect, since engravings represent to us bodies of varying relief anddepth on a surface which is entirely flat. Moreover, in accordancewith the rules of perspective they often represent circles by ovalsbetter than by other circles, squares by rhombuses better than byother squares, and similarly for other shapes. Thus it often hap-pens that in order to be more perfect as an image and to representan object better, an engraving ought not to resemble it.

Since an engraving represents objects on a flat surface, the actual

shape of / and the actual shape of   D   cannot be identical if the shapeof / is three-dimensional; and the example of perspective showsthat the actual shape of / and the actual shape of   D  need not beidentical even if the actual shape of / is two-dimensional. Thismuch is undeniable. And we can add two further points, both in thespirit of Descartes' argument: first, as we have seen, the occlusionshape of / and the occlusion shape of   D   (both relative to the spec-tator's line of sight) need not be identical; and second, / and   D  neednot resemble each other in colour, for the internal subject of a gri-

saille or an engraving (whatever the colour of the ink) need not andgenerally will not have a determinate colour.

Descartes was therefore right to reject the resemblance theory, ifthe term 'resemblance' is taken   au pied de la lettre.  But having saidthat, if the Occlusion Principles are true and truth can be mixedwith falsehood, then the idea that resemblance explains depictionsurely has some truth in it - which is why my first remarks about theformula were equivocal. More importantly, Descartes was wrong toconclude that experimental investigation alone can determine what

regu lar corres po nde nce s in sha pe exist betw een the surface of a pic -ture and its internal subject. Whether the same is true of corre-spondences in colour is another matter, and one which I shall dis-cuss elsewhere.

12 On the aesthetic significance of scale, see Wind (1985), pp. 65 and n. 124.

74

Page 26: Hyman 1997_Words and Pictures

8/12/2019 Hyman 1997_Words and Pictures

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/hyman-1997words-and-pictures 26/27

Words and Pictures

I  cannot claim that  the  Occlusion Principles  are an  original idea,for something very similar appears   in  m any places.  In  book xxxv of

his  Natural History,   for exam ple, Pliny insists patriotically tha t the

claim  of the Egyptians  to have discovered the art of paint ing  is spu-rious,  but apart from this he tells us little abo ut th e o rigins of  pain t -ing -  except that  he  claims that  it is generally agreed tha t p aint ingbegan 'with  the outl ining  of a ma n 's shadow ' .  In  fact,  the analogybetween   an  image and a   shadow makes  its  first appe arance  in the

Odyssey  (xi.204-8) , when Odysseus encounters  his mo ther ' s image{eidolon):

As my mother spoke there came  to me out of the confusion  in m y

heart  the one desire,  to embrace  her spirit , dead th ou gh  she  was.Thr ice ,  in  my eagerness  to clasp he r  to m e,  I  started forward withmy hands outstretched. Thrice, l ike   a  shadow  or a  dream,  she

sl ipped through   my  arms  and  left  me  harrowed  by an   evensharper pain.

Sometimes indeed ' learning philosophy   is  really recollecting'.13

References

Alberti, L . B. 1966. On  Painting,  revised edition, trans. J. R. Spencer. NewHaven: Yale University Press

Anscombe,  G. E. M. 1965. The  Intentionality  of  Sensation:  AGrammatical Feature',  in R. J.  Butler (ed.),  Analytical Philosophy:Second Series. Oxford: Basil Blackwell

Beardsley, M. C. 1981. Aesthetics:  Problems in the  Theory of  Criticism,  2ndedition. Indianapolis: Hackett

Berkeley,  G. 1975.  An   Essay Towards   a New   Theory   of   Vision, inPhilosophical  Works,  ed. M. R. Ayers. London: J. M. Dent

Budd, M. 1995. Values of  Art.  London: Allen LaneDescartes,  R. 1985.  Optics,   in   The  Philosophical  Writings of   Descartes,

Volume I, trans. J. Cottingham et al. Cambridge U niversity PressGage, J. 1993. Colour and  Culture. London: Tham es HudsonGombrich, E. H.  1977. Art  and Illusion, 5th edition. Oxford: PhaidonGoodman, N. 1972. Problems  and Projects.  Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill

1981. Languages of  Art,  2nd edition. Brighton: HarvesterHacker, P. M. S. 1987. Appearance  and Reality.  Oxford: Basil Blackwell.Hospers, J. 1946. M eaning and Truth in  the Arts.  Chapel Hill: University

of North Carolina Press

Hyman,  J. 1992. 'Language  and  Pictorial  Art , in D.  Cooper (ed.),  ACompanion to Aesthetics.  Oxford: Basil BlackwellMorris,  C.  1939-40. Aesthetics  and the  Theory  of  Signs',  Journal of

Unified Science (Erkenntnis) 8, 131-501946. Signs, Language and  Behaviour. New York: Prentice-Hall

13 Wittgenstein (1993), p.  179.

75

Page 27: Hyman 1997_Words and Pictures

8/12/2019 Hyman 1997_Words and Pictures

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/hyman-1997words-and-pictures 27/27

John Hytnan

Ryle,  G. 1949.  The  Concept  of Mind. London: Hutchinson1971.  'Sensation', in his  Collected Papers, Volum e 2.  London:

Hutchinson

Scruton, R. 1974. Art   and Im agination. London: Routledge  Kegan PaulWind, E. 1985. Art and  Anarchy.  London: DuckworthWittgenstein, L. 1993.  Philosophical  Occasions,  ed. J. Klagge and A.

Nordmann. Indianapolis: HackettWollheim, R. 1973. 'Nelson Goodman's  Languages  of Art in his Art and

the Mind.  London: Allen Lane1987. Painting  as an Art.  London: Tham es Hudson