Hans Jauss - Interview - Diacritics

10
The Johns Hopkins University Press is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Diacritics. http://www.jstor.org Interview: Hans R. Jauss Author(s): Hans R. Jauss, M. H. Abrams, Herbert Dieckmann, D. I. Grossvogel, W. Wolfgang Holdheim, Philip E. Lewis, Ciriaco Morón-Arroyo and Jacques Roger Source: Diacritics, Vol. 5, No. 1 (Spring, 1975), pp. 53-61 Published by: The Johns Hopkins University Press Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/464722 Accessed: 28-05-2015 12:55 UTC Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at http://www.jstor.org/page/ info/about/policies/terms.jsp JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. This content downloaded from 198.166.233.2 on Thu, 28 May 2015 12:55:57 UTC All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

description

Hans Jauss interview in Diacritics (Spring 1975) with M.H. Abrams and others.

Transcript of Hans Jauss - Interview - Diacritics

Page 1: Hans Jauss - Interview - Diacritics

The Johns Hopkins University Press is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Diacritics.

http://www.jstor.org

Interview: Hans R. Jauss Author(s): Hans R. Jauss, M. H. Abrams, Herbert Dieckmann, D. I. Grossvogel, W. Wolfgang Holdheim, Philip E. Lewis, Ciriaco Morón-Arroyo and Jacques Roger Source: Diacritics, Vol. 5, No. 1 (Spring, 1975), pp. 53-61Published by: The Johns Hopkins University PressStable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/464722Accessed: 28-05-2015 12:55 UTC

Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at http://www.jstor.org/page/ info/about/policies/terms.jsp

JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].

This content downloaded from 198.166.233.2 on Thu, 28 May 2015 12:55:57 UTCAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 2: Hans Jauss - Interview - Diacritics

DIECKMANN Could you recapitulate some of your ideas on esthetics that might serve as a point of departure for this discussion?

JAUSS I will try. One of my interests is to develop categories which no longer refer to what is generally called the history of esthetic ideas. These categories are not esthetic ideas, nor literary history in the manner of Lanson. What I seek is a middle category,

This conversation took place after a esthetic experience. With categories of esthetic experience, one could bridge differ- Cornell in November, 1973. Among

ent fields of art. A bridge could be envisaged between pre-autonomous art in the the participants were M. H. Abrams, Middle Ages, art which had a social function, and post-autonomous art which is Herbert Dieckmann, D. i. Grossvogel, supposed to be free of social functions. The opposition between "serious" and W. Wolfgang Holdheim, Philip E. "trivial" literatures interests me too: the literature of masterpieces versus consumer Lewis, Ciriaco Mor6n-Arroyo and literature. New theories of communication cannot successfully focus their analyses Jacques Roger. Publication in extenso on consumer literature alone. One must begin by exploring what were the models was not possible due to the limita- of "serious" literature that consumer literature was patterned on. Here, I think that tions imposed by the format of Dia- categories, based on the different levels of identification, may be applied to form critics and the quality of our recording another bridge. There is a third opposition one could bridge through an esthetics instruments, of reception. The new science of literature, and the textual linguistics also, are no

longer content with categories that concern only the speaker; they now seek to de- velop categories which concern the person to whom one speaks-intersubjective categories. An esthetics of reception would not be a self-sufficient method. It is a method which must be completed by the esthetics of production and the esthetics of presentation. It would seem that the best hermeneutic approach to artistic phe- nomena lies on the side of reception, because we, the philologists or interpreters, are also situated on the side of reception. We are not involved in the mystery of production; yet all, or nearly all traditional approaches stem from an esthetics of presentation.

DIECKMANN Would you see any difference between what one calls in French "la fortune de Racine, de Corneille, de Molibre" and your esthetics of reception? There seems to be a relation between the two.

JAUSS There is a difference. I alluded to it in a recent polemic argument against the Ger- man Marxist theory of literature.' I distinguish between "efficacy" [Wirkung] and "reception." W. Iser has explained, in an article about the reading process,2 that the significance of the work of art depends on the convergence of the work (the text created by the author) and the code of the receiver (the realization of the reader). This convergence affords an understanding of what German hermeneutics, Derrida and others, call the open structure of signification. And if there is an open structure of signification, then it is not sufficient to represent quantitatively the "efficacy" of, say, a Racine: the changing code of reception must always be respected. Previously, explaining the history of great works of art meant almost always accepting implicitly a Platonic point of view according to which the work generates its effect unfailingly and consistently, with no respect for the changes in codes that change in every age the perceptor's understanding of art.

i "Die Partialitat der rezeptionsasthe- tischen Methode, Nachwort zu: Ra- cines und Goethes Iphigenie," Neue Hefte fur Philosophie, Heft 4 (1973), 1-46. (English translation forthcoming in Yale French Studies.)

' "The Reading Process: A Phenomen- ological Approach," New Literary His- tory, 3 (1971/72), 279.

DIECKMANN If I understand you correctly, what you call the history of reception is still an essen- tial part of our present-day interpretation: we must be conscious of the special way in which the work of art was received at a certain time and take this into account in our present-day interpretation. If this is so, there would be a difference between "la fortune de Racine" and the "reception" of his work because the perspective would have changed.

JAUSS I agree. Questions and answers are necessary in hermeneutics in order to identify the manner in which our contemporary interpretation is determined. Neither the esthetic code of a past work, nor the current code of its understanding, can be grasped through an atemporal descriptive system. Codes of reception are generally not obvious, but depend on unconscious traditions. We can avoid the illusion of a constantly valid descriptive system only when we determine, through question and answer, the difference between past and present codes of understanding. Her-

diocritics /Spring 1975 53 This content downloaded from 198.166.233.2 on Thu, 28 May 2015 12:55:57 UTC

All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 3: Hans Jauss - Interview - Diacritics

meneutics must keep even the new semiotics mindful that every description pre- supposes a question to which this description was or is still the answer. If I don't ask that question, I am dependent on something which is worse (not to say ideolog- ical), because I have not reflected upon it.

ARROYO It seems to me that there are three different levels, when we speak of "la fortune de." If we speak of "la fortune de Cervantes en France," the works analyzed are likely to be inferior imitations, not really artistic works. I would exclude such exemplars as instances of "la fortune de." At a second level of reception, there is the echo of Cervantes in Goethe, who never wrote an imitation of Cervantes. And yet there is a dialogue there. It is perhaps here that we have what you call the "imaginative"- a deeper assimilation of work and interpretation. Then there is a third level-the one you mentioned, the reception of the work of art, by the public, in its norm- creating aspect. At this third level, "reception" is indeed a social phenomenon tied to the concept of esthetic enjoyment: before there is ever any criticism of artistic creation, there must be simple enjoyment by the untutored reader.

JAUSS Yes. I would insist however that it is important to realize that all levels of the history of reception do not simply continue the past as a tradition: tradition is, on all levels, retention as well as omission. An esthetic canon is a consensus omnium which se- lects certain works of art from the past at the expense of others. In this respect it would be wise to reexamine the formation of canons on the reflexive level of esthetic experience (dialogue of authors, imitation of canonic works, canons of the schools of the exemplary authors of each period). The reception of works of art is, in part, a function of reflexive conditioning (through the educational system, cultural institutions, and orientation by the critics), and partly of pre-reflexive norms of social behavior transmitted indirectly through esthetic pleasure. Esthetic pleasure, how- ever, cannot be completely channelled or manipulated. That which our children find interesting in art is not determined solely by the educational system or the conscious canon of parents. The change of interests from generation to generation would be a fruitful topic-one perhaps more rewarding than the traditional pursuit of Comparative Literature that simply compares nations or periods.

GROSSVOGEL I would like to ask you about what you term the consensus omnium. Don't your categories correspond to a learned tradition in which the receptive disposition de- pends on acquiring knowledge? When we slip, as our conversation has so far, into areas of the subjective and the Freudian, we are no longer talking about a consensus omnium, but of a consensus individualis-a tacit agreement between the individual percipient and the artistic object. Am I correct or incorrect in this assumption?

JAUSS Must we not contrast an individual answer or subjective norm on the level of pre- reflexive experience with the consensus omnium as a general esthetic norm in the reflexive tradition? We might speak of a subjective answer or an individual norm on the reflexive as well as on the pre-reflexive level of esthetic tradition. An inter- esting question then arises: how, in esthetic experience, can an objective tradition develop out of subjective reactions?

How. can a general, albeit dynamic, historically

mutable consensus of esthetic judgment arise from individual norms? My answer is supported by Kant's definition of esthetic judgment-judgment directed by the assent of others, and necessarily intersubjective. Esthetic judgment is, then, neither an individual act [parole] nor a statement of universal applicability, but rather an historical norm, which is continually redefined and further developed in the process of interaction between work and public, past art and evolving reception. The es- thetic consensus omnium is a process in which the subjective answer or individual norm becomes effective only as an innovation when others agree with it, raising the individual norm to a general norm and thus further developing the esthetic code. It is also necessary to distinguish, on the pre-reflexive level of esthetic experience, between a system of possibilities of behavior (identification-models) and historical norms or realizations, where a much more limited flexibility is established for in- novations arrived at through subjective answers or individual norms. To admire an artistic model is not to indulge a subjective category: it is something to be admired with others. What I admire personally and alone may be relevant for my biography, but not for the process of esthetic experience. Freudian categories are interesting because they concern intersubjective attitudes.

ROGER You detach the concept of esthetics from any kind of value?

JAUSS Is not the open-ended judgment which develops in the continuous consensus of tradition a kind of "value"? Certainly not in the sense of an esthetic platonism. I doubt, however, whether we could answer decisive questions concerning the esthetic activity of man and the function of art in history by assuming absolute or universal esthetic values which are supposed to be independent of it. Esthetics as

54 This content downloaded from 198.166.233.2 on Thu, 28 May 2015 12:55:57 UTC

All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 4: Hans Jauss - Interview - Diacritics

a scientific method must assume only those values which are developed historically. And the nai've reception of past art can often provide more information concerning the question of the development of esthetic values or norms of taste than the subtle interpretation of a work by a professor of literary history, who exceeds the inter- pretations of his predecessors only by nuances.

DIECKMANN Am I right in seeing in your conception of the history of receptivity two different functions? First, it is interesting simply to know how a work was once received. But it seems to me that you also consider in your concept of receptivity what you call the reflective approach to the work of art, and the reflecting in the work of art. Could there not be a conflict between the two? The first is an historical inquiry. It seems to me that you stress more the function of a work in making us more re- flective in our own appreciation. Do we really have a fully developed, fully reflec- tive receptivity for the work of art, if we do not know its history?

JAUSS Certain hermeneutics-Gadamer's, for example-are of the opinion that to arrive at the plain understanding of our present codes, we cannot but analyze previous positions of past experience on which we rely. This may be true, but one has the feeling that one cannot, in a single existence, see or analyze all tradition. That is why we-and each generation anew-must achieve a critical viewpoint in reference to the "thesaurus" of past art. This critical viewpoint demands that we discover the pre-history of our contemporary experience in the tradition of past art. We must find the exemplary works and esthetic norms which determine, overtly or covertly, our contemporary relationship to art. To achieve such a critical viewpoint demands a critical hermeneutic reflection which must avoid two dangers: the harmonization of tradition and the actualization of past experience to serve the present.

HOLDHEIM Do you lump together the past, which is a datum of the collective memory, and the critical act or judgment on the work, which selects certain aspects of this past, do you lump these under the same concept of receptivity? Do you make any distinc- tion?---or do you see a relationship between the two?

JAUSS These questions describe a difficulty which affects not only my own theory. At this point I would like to recall the recent esthetic debate in West Germany between Gadamer and Habermas-between classical hermeneutics and the critical theory of the Frankfurter school. In my view, this debate led to the conclusion that herme- neutic reflection and an ideological and critical methodology contain no irrecon- cilable opposition (Paul Ricoeur had already anticipated this in his book on Freud and the concept of interpretation). Hermeneutic reflection can integrate the postu- lates of ideological criticism, if it admits that all tradition-especially in the realm of art-retains as well as omits, extols and represses man's experience. The develop- ment of tradition in the esthetic experience does not conform to Bergson's model of Zeit-philosophie. But neither can the history of esthetic experience be described according to the model of collective recollection (Maurice Halbwachs), which pre- serves from the past only what is of current interest. Ideological criticism, which traces all historical manifestations of art back to the veiled interests and material needs of the ruling classes, ought not to limit itself to the unconscious-collective processes and should accept the fact that the history of art always goes beyond the reductions of collective recollection.

ROGER What distinguishes esthetic communication from other forms of communication?

HOLDHEIM Also, can one speak about the ironic denial of esthetic identification? Isn't irony at least the primary characteristic of every esthetic identification-as opposed to a non-esthetic one?

JAUSS The difference between esthetic and non-esthetic identification lies in the mediating role of the imaginary. When the imaginary is involved, there is esthetic experience. The esthetic theory of German classicism explained the function of the imaginary through the concept of "the beautiful illusion." Sartre also described the change between imagination and perception, between the object in esthetic and emotional attitudes. Similarly, the Prague School of structuralism describes esthetics as an "empty function": the imaginary object is not a specific object; rather, each object of our everyday experience can be organized, according to Mukarovsk--it can be isolated, elevated, and idealized through the esthetic function, and thereby raised to the level of esthetic pleasure. In contrast to an esthetic attitude or to the beautiful illusion, irony has an apparently disturbing function: it interrupts the pre-reflexive esthetic enjoyment, abolishes the power of esthetic identification, and compels re- flection. Only a disciple of Kierkegaard, who must judge ironic behavior on the basis of ethical principles as being "merely esthetic," can dispute this.

HOLDHEIM But is the ironic syndrome not necessarily connected with the concept of the miss- ing hero or the anti-hero? What about tragic irony?

diacritics /Spring 1975 55 This content downloaded from 198.166.233.2 on Thu, 28 May 2015 12:55:57 UTC

All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 5: Hans Jauss - Interview - Diacritics

JAUSS I think that irony-the idea of omnipotent fate toying with the weakness of man- can allow for a positive hero. The levels of esthetic identification that I propose are not necessarily an historical succession of steps. There may be a synchrony in each period of literature, or in a single work (when it leads the spectator through various attitudes such as wonder, pity, amazement, fear or compassion).

ABRAMS Concerning the adequacy of your typologies: you comprehend heroes in frequently recurring literary types; what about the kind of story in which the hero is largely a transparency, where the nature of the hero is secondary to a focus on, let us say, the solution of a mystery?

JAUSS Our pleasure in problem-solving does not exclude an enigmatic interest through identification. Let me add, however, that the models of identification with a hero which I propose comprise only the beginning of an analysis of esthetic experi- ence. I am aware that there are also levels of identification which are expressed not in the third, but in the first person. Freud had already distinguished among three categories of identification: being like someone (admiring identification); a relation based on having (to have somebody as a father, for instance); a relation no longer with a person but with a situation: I may read a love story and not identify with the person, but might wish to be in the same situation. The pragmatics of such situational models are of prime importance to me.

GROSSVOGEL If I understand you correctly, you accept the Freudian only at its point of juncture with categories that are susceptible of such universality as would allow esthetic evaluation. But how do you square a "receptive disposition" with, say, alienation? Laughter, for example, supposes such a radical destruction of that which is being laughed at, that the organism is, in a sense, separated from its head-where the categories are. It is a visceral response; if you remain at the level of esthetic clas- sification, are you not talking of a "head" response, which I would understand as more befitting a category like "admiration"?

JAUSS Indeed, laughter can be understood primarily as an act of separation (rupture) which destroys every admiring or sympathizing identification. But this does not mean that all laughter must therefore have its roots in greater psychic depths than those identification-models which you want to dismiss as mere cerebral reactions. It was Freud, in fact, who explained the admiration of a hero as more than a super- ficial enjoyment of an imaginary escape-dream. In a 1908 article on the relation of the poet to day-dreaming, he says that the increment of pleasure which is offered us in order to release yet greater pleasure arising from deeper sources in the mind is called an "incitement premium" or, technically, "for-pleasure." He has in mind the esthetic shock of the recognition of those desires assimilated during childish play, but whose fulfillment had been denied us by life. This theory of recognition links Freud and Proust; both deal, not with cerebral reactions, but rather with the understanding of a depth psychology far more important for the esthetics of recep- tion than much of what Freud said about the biographies of poets.

GROSSVOGEL My question remains, at least to this extent: is something like laughter not an emo- tion whose psychic roots lie buried deeper in the reader than the recognition of childhood patterns-the infantile residuum which you preserve in your balance? Is not laughter deeper and does it not subvert more immediately?

JAUSS Bakhtin has described what he termed "a grotesque laughter"-with deeper roots than the mere "laughter about something or someone," because it originates in the moment of victory over all types of fear---of the hereafter, of death, of power or authority. But this grotesque laughter is only one of the various functions of laugh- ter. We can laugh at something (say, at a comic hero), but we can also laugh with someone (with a humorous person who is able to laugh at himself). Laughing at can occasionally change to laughing with. There is first what you have described as a phenomenon of rupture. This pertains also to the beginning of a group solidarity. If you observe laughter at political meetings, there are two possibilities: one party may laugh at the other; but it may be that both parties, that didn't agree, laugh at the same event. Nobody likes to laugh with his enemies at the same subject. There is an interesting moment in political meetings when you can often sense that this may be the beginning of a new understanding. In a discussion I had with Roland Barthes at Lille, he defended the thesis that where there is sense there must be conflict. If Barthes is right, then the interest of a new semiotics in rhetoric must be to explain how to resolve the conflict. I proposed as a subject of investigation the phenomenon of laughter-a phenomenon of rupture, but which can interrupt con- tention and be the beginning of an understanding that would not be attainable without this element of rupture. In laughter there is rupture, but this rupture can be the beginning of solidarity of the group that "laughs with" the other at (some- thing else).

56 This content downloaded from 198.166.233.2 on Thu, 28 May 2015 12:55:57 UTC

All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 6: Hans Jauss - Interview - Diacritics

GROSSVOGEL Pity is another one of your classifications that I find problematic. For me, Aris- totelian pity is an emotion as deeply perturbing (as deeply visceral, that is to say, subjective) as laughter. But I think that admiration or sympathetic laughter unbal- ances the organism much less than would genuine pity. I believe that when Aris- totle speaks of pity and fear he is speaking of the two outermost poles of going towards-pity-and moving away from-fear-that he could envisage. Viscerally, in the Freudian sense, these were the two most disruptive forces that he could think of in the theater, as opposed to the "mentalizing" virtues of admiration, under- standing, irony-everything that is controlled by the mind.

JAUSS It is difficult to contradict you here, since you have assumed the classical definition of catharsis. To that I can only oppose the Christian redefinition of this classical doctrine. In the Christian era, it was no longer understandable that pity had to be something of which the spectators must be purified. Pity was the beginning of readiness for action and it was a good thing. Fear may still be a subjective emotion, but pity turns the subjective mood to readiness for action, and the entire history of catharsis shows the transformation of pity running counter to the Aristotelian tradi- tion. I would conclude that all esthetic experience, including laughter, involves an act of removal. I differ from you in that I interpret this removal not only as rupture, but also as providing the possibility of a new attitude. The analysis of esthetic be- havior must take into account that which follows the extreme moments of pity and fear, as well as that which follows the moment of laughter. Wonder, too, contains a moment of rupture-specifically astonishment. But wonder, too, elicits a response which goes beyond the moment of rupture.

DIECKMANN How would you relate your theories of admiration, etc., to the problem of identifi- cation in the theater?

JAUSS The classical theater and its audience have been explained by cathartic identification. In the history of literature, after a period of autonomy of art, there often arises a new desire for a more engaged comprehension of literature. In the eighteenth cen- tury, the importance of Enlightenment literature was to induce in the bourgeois audi- ence solidarity of action. The novel did just that and it was the intention of the genre serieux in the theater to do the same. But we know that the genre bourgeois was not as successful. Melodrama was a concession to more subjective feelings, but remained within the realm of the larmoyant and path6tique alone, without any didactic attempt, with the exception, perhaps, of liberating through subjective feel- ing a solidarity necessary for the formation of a new middle-class consciousness.

DIECKMANN The ideal purpose of the Enlightenment theater is definitely education through the performance on the stage. The idea is to create within the spectator a love of virtue, instead of teaching an abstract moral concept. Thus we cannot speak of only a sentimental identification. The result to be obtained is really a setting free of the inherently virtuous nature of man.

JAUSS Yes. But isn't it interesting that this theater is no longer understandable later on?- as we now find it difficult to understand the moral painters of the eighteenth cen- tury (like Greuze), because of other esthetic norms which emerged subsequently. In the nineteenth century, the melodramatic form is so much perverted into mere enjoyment of sentimentality that we no longer understand the emancipatory func- tion which it had at first.

DIECKMANN But the means are entirely different. The process of catharsis in classical French tragedy is obtained by means of words and concepts. Perhaps the break in the line of the alexandrine had a direct effect, a kind of awakening effect on the audience, because they knew that something was going to happen. A good example is the violation of the cesura in Iphig6nie, where Achilles deliberately destroys the normal alexandrine break: the intent is to shock the audience enough for them to realize that something very serious is at stake. But this remains within the domain of words whereas the new effect of catharsis is in its enactment on the stage. In Le Pare de famille, for instance, take the sharp contrast in the stage presentation between the first scene and the last: the first scene shows immediately, to a sensitive audience, the total destruction of bourgeois life. In the very staging which Diderot devised, there is the immediate suggestion that something catastrophic has happened, that the family is torn apart. And the final tableau (and both are called tableaux) is the reunion and the renewal of the bourgeois family. These are ways of suggesting ideas, and they are new: visual impression, stage enactment, the very bearing of the actors, the placing of the various persons achieve the same effect as a tableau-a picture. This would seem to raise the whole question of identification in a new way because the means are so different: the direct appeal is to unknown factors in the human personality, factors which you cannot define in terms of mind, in terms of thought, in terms of thought content, which society shares, to which you appeal, which then activate the percipient.

ciocritics /Spring 1975 57 This content downloaded from 198.166.233.2 on Thu, 28 May 2015 12:55:57 UTC

All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 7: Hans Jauss - Interview - Diacritics

JAUSS You are right saying that the first reception of cathartic classical theater was, as you described it, at the level of surprise and shock. But for a post-classical audience, there often remained only the pleasure of classical language. And the moment we appraise a work of art only at the level of pleasure in the perfection of language, moral identification is no longer realizable. Was not the bourgeois theater in France, from the start, in opposition to a perfect hero as well as to a purely esthetic pleasure in perfect language? This opposition is perhaps articulated in the desire of the new bourgeois drama to present conditions rather than characters as models of iden- tification.

DIECKMANN Isn't distance involved? Classical distance is suppressed by the technique of the tableau; genuine identification is achieved through the action of the sympathetic nervous system.

JAUSS The tableau, seeking to abolish the distance between spectator and stage through an impression of reality, poses a special problem of identification. We can no longer speak of admiring or sympathizing identification with a person. We must think, rather, of that which Freud has described as identification with a situation: the spectator is expected to be gripped by the pathos of the tableau and is thus directed towards a new solidarity of behavior.

DIECKMANN I've always been struck by how much the eighteenth century was surprised by Rousseau's reaction to Berenice. He says that, at the moment when Titus decides to break with B'r'nice, the whole audience marries her. Is there any record of iden- tification, or even of the question and problem of identification, before the eigh- teenth century? You use identification as such a fundamental category: did anyone actually identify at the time? Do we have any information that the problem of identification existed? It is raised by Rousseau, and it was considered shocking in the eighteenth century. Should we not discuss a genealogy of identification?

JAUSS There has been little collected evidence regarding the reception of classical theater by its contemporaries; it would have to be sought in biographical sources or in letters. Some indirect evidence is provided by the Church's criticism of classical theater. It is not surprising that the enlightened Rousseau is, in this respect, on the side of the Church fathers, with whom he had otherwise little in common.

DIECKMANN Still it seems to me you start from what you consider to be a "fact"--not an empir- ical fact-that identification is an attitude towards a work of art which is fairly con- stant throughout history. How can we know about modes of identification in the Middle Ages where an esthetics of this kind didn't exist? How can we know that a medieval reader identified with Roland and Olivier? The fact that people are called Roland and Olivier is not proof of actual identification. Can we take it as a constant of the spectator's attitude-or the reader's?

GROSSVOGEL If we refer to tradition, is there not another factor that intrudes-the object itself? Before the sophistication of the reader-critic, the poet's word may have been closer to the Word of God. But when we speak of a subsequent tradition, it seems to me that the "recognition" of the hero is the recognition of the whole tradition that goes with the hero, so that the hero is no longer an immediacy-he is already an artistic object. Don't your categories presuppose the kind of immediacy that antedates the tradition? To respond to Professor Dieckmann's question, I believe that since there was a Roland, and there was a war in Spain, it is not unlikely that the audience at the time responded more directly to the "reality" of Roland than they did to the form that gave a particular dimension to that reality. But thereafter, when you have only a tradition within which to respond, are you not responding to the-hero-as- part-of-the-tradition-a fiction, a work of art?

JAUSS You are describing the transition from immediacy to tradition, when reflection en- ters. It is true that one cannot remain in the realm of absolute immediacy, but I think that there remains always a need for heroic models, and generations will seek immediate possibilities of identification by honoring incarnations of this need. We find in Heidegger, for instance, that the mass always seeks a hero. In prereflexive esthetic experience, the heroes of our fathers are replaced by new heroes. On the reflexive level, on the other hand, there is actually a process in which the hero as behavioral model disappears more and more behind the author. We admire the author because of his originality, in contrast to our children, who admire Don Quixote and Sancho Panza without being interested in the author Cervantes, whose name they may not remember. I concede to Mr. Dieckmann the fact that my sys- tem of identification-models assumes certain anthropological constants. Why should we not assume that admiration or pity, amazement or sympathy, laughter or irony have defined, under changing motivations, the esthetic behavior of man in his everyday experience, since the production of art freed itself from ties to the religious cult? We might agree more easily in this matter if I add that such anthropological

58 This content downloaded from 198.166.233.2 on Thu, 28 May 2015 12:55:57 UTC

All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 8: Hans Jauss - Interview - Diacritics

constants are interesting to me chiefly because of their hermeneutic function. Whether or not I can determine empirically how the public of the twelfth century identified with Roland appears of minor importance when the access of the modern reader to the distant world of this heroic epic depends obviously on esthetic experi- ences which he can still share with the public of that time. What allows us to understand Roland in a world where heroic virtues and Christian conception are no longer valid, is our feeling of admiration: it allows us to understand the heroic attitudes in the Middle Ages even if we no longer understand the Christian ideology.

DIECKMANN Even though history is what we recreate in our minds, history is also a number of other things. History is all that actually happened, which is not reconstructed in our minds but which we perceive, as we perceive objects outside of ourselves. I think that a certain objectivity is possible; and the complete subjectivity of what we recreate in our minds should, perhaps, not be taken so much for granted. A certain differentiation seems necessary to me. I wonder whether we can speak of a generally valid esthetics for large segments of history.

JAUSS An esthetics which remains completely on the reflexive level and is related to the concept of the work of art and limited to a history of the beautiful is certainly not suited to all the historical manifestations of art: it fails not only in regard to non- European traditions, but even in regard to the greater part of medieval art and literature. That is why I am attempting to compare a history of esthetic experience with the history of esthetic ideas, a theory of the reception of works of art with ontological esthetics, identification-models of the collective consciousness on the prereflective level with the development of models on the reflective level. Not all manifestations of art exist in a perceptible historical continuity. When this continuity is interrupted or non-existent, even classical diachronic hermeneutics are of little use to us, and we must employ systematic approaches, or that which I should like to call "synchronic hermeneutics." In a recent book on the old-French epic, Alfred Adler illustrates how a semantic anthropology can be utilized as an hermeneutic instrument. Levi-Strauss' "logique du sensible" achieves an hermeneutic function when it concerns itself with tracing genetically unrelated epics back to mirror-image or contrastive-image relationships that illuminate a past intellectual horizon which is obscure to the modern reader. (The ambivalent relationship of Charlemagne to Roland, for instance, is explained when we understand that Roland is allowed to be only a nephew of the Emperor, although he is in reality the latter's incestuous son.) That which cannot be explained by diachronic understanding supplied by tradition can be explained by synchronic hermeneutics through combinations of symmetrical, asymmetrical, or reversible relationships among contemporary works. Hermeneutics and structuralism no longer appear here as inimical methodologies.

LEWIS Could we elaborate the polemical side of some of your remarks on the contempo- rary scene? One concept, in particular, seems to be crucial in your own work and has also become prominent in some of the work of the French semioticians, or post- semioticians-the concept of pleasure. Could you, in the first place, discuss the sense of a kind of revalorization of the concept of pleasure in your work? And then, if it seems pertinent to you, distinguish your own attempt to analyze pleasure as a part of the esthetic experience from another sort of revalorization of pleasure that seems to be taking place precisely within the Tel Quel group that you have crit- icized? I'm thinking there of the notion of plaisir du texte as articulated, for exam- ple, by Sollers and Barthes.

JAUSS For art history today, that experience of art worthy of theory usually begins beyond pleasurable behavior, which, as the subjective side of art-experience, is generally left to psychology (that has little interest in it). The sharpest criticism of all pleasur- able art experience is in the posthumous esthetic theory of Theodor W. Adorno, who attacks all enjoyment of art as false consciousness of the late-capitalistic con- sumer culture. Adorno, and the currently popular esthetics of negativity, stand in a long tradition of puritanical hostility towards art, which connects such mighty names as Plato, Augustine, Rousseau, and Kierkegaard. It is possible to conclude indirectly from this secular polemic that esthetic pleasure in the history of esthetic experience has not been perceived as a mere sign of adaptation but, again and again, as an element of anarchy and rebellion against order or domination. According to my theory, pleasurable behavior, which art releases and makes possible, is therefore the primordial esthetic experience. But I think it is important to regard esthetic pleasure as release from as well as becoming available for something. Pleasure in the esthetic object assumes the negation of everyday practice: the acting subject must become spectator, listener, observer, reader, in order to achieve esthetic en- joyment; he must loose himself from the constraints of habits and interests in order to perceive an object esthetically, or to identify with the represented action.

clicrtiCS /Spring 1975 59 This content downloaded from 198.166.233.2 on Thu, 28 May 2015 12:55:57 UTC

All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 9: Hans Jauss - Interview - Diacritics

LEWIS I suppose this means that, among other things, you would be using the concept of esthetic pleasure polemically in opposition to a strictly formalistic reading of litera- ture or analysis of art?

JAUSS In this opposition I am on Barthes' side and approve, in particular, of his criticism of those who believe that all esthetic pleasure is ideology. I doubt, however, whether the difference Barthes describes between plaisir and jouissance can be upheld as an actual opposition of affirmative and negative esthetic pleasure. Barthes seems inter- ested in only the "real" negative pleasure of "rupture," which he separates from merely affirmative or cultural enjoyment (plaisir) as an elite attitude, without recog- nizing that this latter enjoyment can also have an intersubjective and social func- tion. This explains why, although Barthes wants to project an esthetics that is based on the enjoyment of the recipient, he is not able to honor this claim. He stresses the "insular character" and the "asocial nature" of pleasure in the reading process so simplistically that the activity of the reader-and with it the dialogue between reader and text-is lost. The "plaisir du langage," which stands in the center of Barthes' apologia, seems to me to be merely the typical pleasure of the lonely philologist who has forgotten the possible social function of art. I should like to expand the apologia of esthetic pleasure to a theory of esthetic experience which comprises the three origins of esthetic pleasure: the productive consciousness cre- ating the world as its own work; the receptive consciousness grasping the possibility of comprehending the world differently; and finally, the agreement with a judgment demanded by a work or the identification with predetermined and further-to-be defined norms of behavior.

LEWIS If I understand the kind of criticism that you're addressing to the contemporary avant-garde, you seem to be saying that the activity of the avant-garde would tend to be essentially destructive rather than creative?

JAUSS Destruction would not be an objection, if it did not end as the sanction of isolated esthetic pleasure which is good only for a lonely spectator. This esthetics of neg- ativity cannot require that art achieve a communicative, let alone a revolutionary, function. As long as an esthetic theory such as that of Adorno or of the Tel Quel group is not in the position to describe esthetic activity within intersubjective cat- egories, it will remain individualistic and idealistic from the onset, even if it ac- knowledges materialism.

LEWIS You have spoken of your own polemical position in terms of a general opposition- one exceedingly vast in its implications-between hermeneutics and semiotics. You appear to see both a clear-cut opposition between semiotics as we have come to know it over the past few years, as a study of what we might term covert struc- tures, and a hermeneutic position which is seeking to uncover the covert structures that are simply inaccessible to a rudimentary semiotics oriented around language. At the same time, you also spoke of a certain possibility for conciliation of semiotics and hermeneutics. I wonder if the meeting ground which you envisage would be the opening on to Freud that you were speaking of. It would appear that in what recent French semiotics terms the "expansion of semiotics," semiotics as a discipline is try- ing to open up its own enterprise, not simply to a Freudian discourse, but to include a broadly conceived field of communication as well. The kind of semiotics to which you have objected may be disappearing, and semiotics, as it expands, propelled in the main by a rereading of Freud (in and outside of France), may well be opening up to questions which you consider vital. I wonder if you can elaborate on the potential for such a reconciliation between semiotics and your own hermeneutics?

JAUSS Your suspicion is correct. In discussions at Columbia with Julia Kristeva, I agreed that the gap between semiotics and hermeneutics could be bridged through a new reception of Freud. If a new semiotics wants to open itself up to the intersubjective aspects of communication, it need not begin its work at point zero. It would need, first of all, to recognize the excellent interpretation of Freud by Paul Ricoeur, who has taken decisive steps to mediate the argument that is being waged in France be- tween semiological and hermeneutic exegesis, as well as the argument that has flared up in Germany between ideological criticism and hermeneutics. Semiotics could take over from Ricoeur the theory of ambiguous language (a differentiation of the relationship of meaning to thing and the relationship of meaning to mean- ing). On the other hand, the Frankfurt School of criticism and the Marxist ideolog- ical critics could learn from Ricoeur how the two "interpretations of interpretation," specifically the reconstruction of meaning and the destruction of illusions of con- sciousness, complement each other methodologically in an overlapping hermeneu- tic reflection. Like Ricoeur in France, Alfred Lorenzer in West Germany has intro- duced a new reading of Freud, of which our French friends have apparently taken no notice as yet. This new "German Freud," especially Lorenzer's theory of "the

60 This content downloaded from 198.166.233.2 on Thu, 28 May 2015 12:55:57 UTC

All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 10: Hans Jauss - Interview - Diacritics

understanding of the scene," appears to me to be no less important than the "French Freud" (Lacan). If the new semiotics is serious in its desire to reestablish the subject within the structure or, as Julia Kristeva put it in an Hegelian formula- tion, to recreate the substance as subject, it should consider such research.

LEWIS Another way of stating the opposition might be simply to consider the object of a so-called new semiotics. The current expansion of semiotics seems to embrace the study of polyvalent meanings and even evidences interest in the "genesis" of mean- ing. Yet there would seem to remain a significant difference between a semiotic outlook and an hermeneutic outlook, if only because the semiotician feels that he has to protect in his enterprise something that was acquired at an earlier stage. What is being sustained derives from the critique of consciousness, the critique of the notion of origins, and the critique of structures of power to which you re- ferred a moment ago. Some semioticians appear to maintain a suspicious attitude toward hermeneutics on the basis of an assumption that the hermeneutician must be protecting a heavy investment in the notion of human subjectivity and in origins as such. Perhaps this opposition has to do with an absolutely fundamental concep- tion of language or expression, with the status of the subject in relation to language. In any case, as hermeneutics and semiotics grapple with the problem of the subject, the question arises as to which of these two disciplines is ultimately capable of in- cluding the other. Which discourse used to expose what is hidden in the work of art will ultimately be able to claim epistemological priority? Do you perceive the hermeneutic discourse as primary, as one that will be ultimately in a position to provide an account of the semiotician's work, whereas the semiotician will not be in a position to provide an account of yours?

JAUSS Your questions touch upon the central misunderstandings which inhibit the open- ing of the new semiotics to the new hermeneutics. The first thing to be said is that the new hermeneutics is no longer primarily interested in the subjectivity of under- standing (the relationship of the interpreter to the other ego of the author), but rather in the intersubjectivity of communicative processes. Secondly, it is an old and apparently indestructible misunderstanding of hermeneutics that it is corrupted by the myth of "origins." Gadamer has explained, in his theory of the fusion of horizons, that the concern of hermeneutics is precisely not the reconstruction of the original or "first" meaning of the text; rather it is the establishment of the difference and the temporal interval between the code of the author and the code of the recipient, i.e., between the code of the first reader and that of the current one. It seems to me, moreover, that the myth of "origins" has become the prey of that semiotics which establishes the text or the 6criture as the first and unques- tionable beginning. Last, in answer to your question concerning a primary discourse of hermeneutics, it cannot be anything other than that dialectic of question and answer to which I referred earlier. Semiotics must also avail itself of this dialectic if it wishes to comprehend the text as a dialogical structure and no longer as a causa sui.

LEWIS One last question. To what extent do you see the hermeneutic tradition to which you were referring turning back upon itself and constituting a critique of its own enterprise? What kind of changes in the orientation of hermeneutic research might you anticipate as your enterprise proceeds to assimilate the tools of other enter- prises that you are able to dominate conceptually? I have in mind both psycho- analysis and semiotics.

JAUSS I see, above all, three interesting possibilities for a future development of a theory and for empirical research which uses semiotic as well as hermeneutic methods: (1) Hermeneutics has been developing new methods to examine overt and repressed traditions since the Gadamer-Habermas debate. I hope that ideological criticism- which to date has itself remained ideological-will admit its so far unacknowl- edged hermeneutic assumptions and include them in self-reflection. (2) The pro- gression from the classical hermeneutics of texts to a new hermeneutics of inter- subjectivity could lead to a new area of research in the still inadequately developed theories of the act of speaking and linguistic games, in "new rhetorics," and also in the barely explored field called "Pragmatics," with which linguistics has recently concerned itself. (3) My personal interest as a literary scholar is directed towards the progression from classical esthetics to a modern theory of experience. This includes the attempt to return from conventional literary history to the still undescribed history of esthetic experience-an endeavor for which this discussion at Cornell

(Translated by Marilyn Sibley Fries) has provided many new ideas, and for which I should like to thank all participants.

dlocrltlcs /Spring 1975 61 This content downloaded from 198.166.233.2 on Thu, 28 May 2015 12:55:57 UTC

All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions