Fiona Jenkins, Souls at the Limit of the Human

15
This article was downloaded by: [Monash University Library] On: 06 February 2012, At: 22:15 Publisher: Routledge Informa Ltd Registered in England and Wales Registered Number: 1072954 Registered office: Mortimer House, 37-41 Mortimer Street, London W1T 3JH, UK Angelaki: Journal of the Theoretical Humanities Publication details, including instructions for authors and subscription information: http://www.tandfonline.com/loi/cang20 Souls at the Limits of the Human Fiona Jenkins a a School of Philosophy, Research School of Social Sciences Coombs Building Australian National University, Canberra, ACT 0200, Australia Available online: 04 Jan 2012 To cite this article: Fiona Jenkins (2011): Souls at the Limits of the Human, Angelaki: Journal of the Theoretical Humanities, 16:4, 159-172 To link to this article: http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/0969725X.2011.641353 PLEASE SCROLL DOWN FOR ARTICLE Full terms and conditions of use: http://www.tandfonline.com/page/terms-and- conditions This article may be used for research, teaching, and private study purposes. Any substantial or systematic reproduction, redistribution, reselling, loan, sub-licensing, systematic supply, or distribution in any form to anyone is expressly forbidden. The publisher does not give any warranty express or implied or make any representation that the contents will be complete or accurate or up to date. The accuracy of any instructions, formulae, and drug doses should be independently verified with primary sources. The publisher shall not be liable for any loss, actions, claims, proceedings, demand, or costs or damages whatsoever or howsoever caused arising directly or indirectly in connection with or arising out of the use of this material.

description

Fiona Jenkins, Souls at the Limit of the Human

Transcript of Fiona Jenkins, Souls at the Limit of the Human

  • This article was downloaded by: [Monash University Library]On: 06 February 2012, At: 22:15Publisher: RoutledgeInforma Ltd Registered in England and Wales Registered Number: 1072954 Registeredoffice: Mortimer House, 37-41 Mortimer Street, London W1T 3JH, UK

    Angelaki: Journal of the TheoreticalHumanitiesPublication details, including instructions for authors andsubscription information:http://www.tandfonline.com/loi/cang20

    Souls at the Limits of the HumanFiona Jenkins aa School of Philosophy, Research School of Social Sciences CoombsBuilding Australian National University, Canberra, ACT 0200,Australia

    Available online: 04 Jan 2012

    To cite this article: Fiona Jenkins (2011): Souls at the Limits of the Human, Angelaki: Journal ofthe Theoretical Humanities, 16:4, 159-172

    To link to this article: http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/0969725X.2011.641353

    PLEASE SCROLL DOWN FOR ARTICLE

    Full terms and conditions of use: http://www.tandfonline.com/page/terms-and-conditions

    This article may be used for research, teaching, and private study purposes. Anysubstantial or systematic reproduction, redistribution, reselling, loan, sub-licensing,systematic supply, or distribution in any form to anyone is expressly forbidden.

    The publisher does not give any warranty express or implied or make any representationthat the contents will be complete or accurate or up to date. The accuracy of anyinstructions, formulae, and drug doses should be independently verified with primarysources. The publisher shall not be liable for any loss, actions, claims, proceedings,demand, or costs or damages whatsoever or howsoever caused arising directly orindirectly in connection with or arising out of the use of this material.

  • ANGELAKIjournal of the theoretical humanitiesvolume 16 number 4 December 2011

    I eventful life

    Barely hours old, photos of a newborn infantare published. Uploaded onto a Facebookpage, the physical features of the face, if unique,

    are as yet but minutely differentiated from foetal

    anonymity; nonetheless, we have come to mark

    the entry of a life with an image, available to an

    infinite set of points of access and download,

    circling the globe. The circulation of the new-

    borns image, as important as a name, as

    imperative as a sex, establishes a presence

    through its trace.

    This essay concerns the question of how to

    read or understand such an event as the

    marking of a life; and in what way it might

    invite us to think again about the processes of

    humanisation and dehumanisation that are

    increasingly considered to be wrought through

    the global circulation of images. The capacity of

    the photographic image to bring a once distant

    world close, and realist interpretation of such

    images as tracing presence in a sense given by

    what Roland Barthes called the emanation of the

    referent (80) conjoin to suggest a process of

    mediation by which the humanity of subjects

    finds a global impress. The global circulation of

    images of distant lives, their fate and suffering

    has for many contemporary theorists seemed to

    foster a moral cosmopolitan outlook, giving force

    to the claim that all human beings hold equal

    status as the fundamental units of moral concern

    and should thus be extended respect by all other

    human beings. Ulrich Beck in his Cosmopolitan

    Vision (2006), for instance, argues that people

    throughout the world have now all become

    cosmopolitans by default, due to an inescapably

    global form of exposure and witnessing. The

    presumptive relation between a global connectiv-

    ity of the image and responses to those images as

    generative of belief in equality thus operates as a

    powerful aspect of faith in contemporary pro-

    gressive humanism. That this impress often fails

    to bring about a response (as in the phenomenon

    labelled compassion fatigue), or that it is often

    distorted or divisive (as in what Judith Butler

    terms the differentiation of grievable and

    ungrievable lives in media reporting), does

    little to damage a conviction regarding the ethical

    importance of such connectivity. The key ques-

    tion for many moral cosmopolitans becomes how

    distant others may be rendered in their humanity,

    such that their suffering invites a responsiveness

    that promises action on their behalf

    (Chouliaraki). It as though the claim of the

    image conjoins with the discourse of human

    rights to render a kind of representational

    fiona jenkins

    SOULS AT THE LIMITSOF THE HUMANbeyond cosmopolitanvision

    ISSN 0969-725X print/ISSN1469-2899 online/11/040159^14 2011Taylor & Francishttp://dx.doi.org/10.1080/0969725X.2011.641353

    159

    Dow

    nloa

    ded

    by [M

    onas

    h Univ

    ersity

    Libr

    ary] a

    t 22:1

    5 06 F

    ebru

    ary 20

    12

  • egalitarianism, the right of all human lives to

    appear, to be marked, within an ethically

    compelling space of visibility.

    But must such marking or such responsiveness

    be configured in cosmopolitan form? A funda-

    mentally different perspective on the character

    and import of the circulation of images is

    suggested by the work of Jean-Luc Nancy, who

    concerns himself with what, in the showing or

    presenting that is the world, surpasses an older

    understanding of the world as cosmos, a

    world of distributed places, given by and to, the

    gods (Corpus 39; Creation 47). What Nancy

    resists here is the representational framing of the

    world that seems inherent to cosmopolitan vision,

    and within this a tacit understanding of how the

    circulation of images conveys information from

    afar about lives that are thus made familiar to us

    and bear equal moral claims by virtue of the

    humanity they signify. There are many layers to

    this resistance, but central to them all is the

    attempt to do justice (in terms that find some

    summation in Nancys project of a decon-

    struction of Christianity) to the sense of an

    existence that is given in the world, and exceeds

    and overflows all reference to a Subject (even

    such a subject as humanity) standing outside

    it.1 Thus, for Nancy, our being one world is

    first of all not a question of how we represent

    ourselves as belonging in common to one globe

    but rather of how making sense arises as a

    being in the world that gives ontological

    responsibility, prior to moral or juridical

    responsibility.

    In this essay I propose to explore what

    marking a life might mean on such terms,

    and how it may shift understanding not only of

    what is done through the circulation of images

    of suffering human life, or of life exposed to

    violence, but also as the evidence of life that is

    given in the simple act of posting the image of a

    newborn to a Facebook page. This is not to

    displace from consideration the emphasis placed

    by cosmopolitan vision on images of suffering

    human life, or life exposed to violence; rather, it

    is to make the ontological question of how the

    image presents existence prior to the issue of

    what images present. Photographic media, film

    particularly, are read by Nancy as giving

    evidence of existence, marking it in this

    sense.2 In his treatment of cinema, for instance,

    the image becomes a matter of evidence, a force

    of evidence that imposes and carries away

    something more than a truth: [that is,] an

    existence (Evidence 44). Ontologically speaking,

    the image does not belong to the subject as its

    representation or projection; rather, it is this

    outside of the world where the gaze loses itself to

    find itself as gaze (regard), that is, first and

    foremost as respect (egard) for what is there, for

    what takes place and continues to take place

    (64). Although the images of concern to moral

    cosmopolitanism most often take for their

    content human suffering or exposure to violence,

    these are not the only sorts of images we should

    consider, supposing it might matter to raise

    fundamental questions about how existence may

    be marked in and through the image. Thus the

    photo of a newborn, or a cinema that, as Nancy

    claims, continues life, will be important in

    approaching a way of thinking images that, I shall

    suggest here, we might read productively as a de-

    centring of the locus of the human subject from

    what gives meaning to the image.

    Indeed, in view particularly of the marking of

    new life, a comment Nancy makes in an essay

    On the Soul will also prove to warrant

    consideration: for when a baby is born it is not,

    as he puts it, that a soul comes down into the

    body from on high (and it is not that man is made

    in the image of God, the creator). Rather, with

    the event of birth there is simply a new there,

    space, extension in general, is extended and

    opened (Corpus 132).3 Regarded thus, the

    newborn infants lack of truly distinctive features,

    a face that would allow one without hesitation

    to pick this individual out, indeed does not affect

    the force of an image that is given as respect for

    what takes place. What matters is the event of

    birth, as a beginning without further ground, a

    coming out of nothing, which can only avoid a

    metaphysical construal through being rendered in

    the tense of the future anterior: as Nancy puts it,

    the subject in its first moment will always

    already have been born (Birth 13).

    There is, certainly, another way of construing

    what the image of a newborn marks, one that

    would lay emphasis on the person now

    at the limits of the human

    160

    at the limits of the human

    Dow

    nloa

    ded

    by [M

    onas

    h Univ

    ersity

    Libr

    ary] a

    t 22:1

    5 06 F

    ebru

    ary 20

    12

  • revealed before us, an individual soul whose

    time of existence readily appears to precede birth

    and to exceed death; and it is perhaps this way of

    reading that makes our images of foetal life so

    powerful in debates on the right to life, images

    through which a face appears, and the foetus

    takes on the human form that would confer

    protection. Nancys resistance to such a picture,

    however, is precisely based in a thinking of birth

    and death as taking place without being

    subtended by the ground of identity that the

    name soul would suggest. The childs existence

    does not precede birth, it has its birth as the

    past of its differentiation. It is not born, it is not

    . . . Rather it was born (Birth 13). Another way

    to put this is that soul is not a name, not some

    thing, but the fact that there is a body, a coming-

    to-presence, the emergence of distinctness, self-

    difference (Corpus 63). More than the beginnings

    of a face, we could say the image marks existence

    as the opening that is the birth-event (and thus

    perhaps gives face as facing, or exposure, more

    than as a distinctive property of a given

    individual).4

    Rather than conveying information, or even

    bespeaking humanity, the image that would mark

    a life as coming-to-presence might be thought as a

    non-representational image, or imaging; as an

    exposure that is shared out, given place, in its

    circulation; or as that which continues life, as

    lifes very continuation. It is such an interpreta-

    tion of the images that circulate amongst us that

    shapes Nancys reading of an Abbas Kiarostami

    film, titled And Life Goes On; a film that tracks a

    quest through the landscape of post-earthquake

    Iran, finding everywhere survivors who conduct

    their mourning while continuing to watch and be

    riveted by the World Cup an event which is

    being screened in public, in the open, on the edge

    of devastated villages. It is a scene that might well

    lend itself to reflections on global spectatorship.

    What proves critical to Nancys reading of the

    film, however, as it explores the interweaving of

    image and life, is the sense he seeks in film of

    giving evidence of existence: life presented or

    offered in its evidence (Evidence 58). It is this

    that Nancy calls justice. Thus a body, writes

    Nancy,

    first of all is displayed as its photo-graphy (the

    spacing of clarity [lespacement dune clarte]).

    Only this, to begin with, does justice to the

    body: to its evidence . . . Bodies are evident

    and thats why all justice and justness start and

    end with these. Injustice is the mixing,

    breaking, crushing and stifling of bodies,

    making them indistinct (gathered up in a

    dark corner, piled up to eliminate the space

    between them, within them, assassinating even

    the space of their just death). (Corpus 47)

    In ways that might undo the cosmopolitan

    discourse on generic and general humanity

    (93), and as I explore in more detail in section III

    below, Nancy reaches toward a thinking of

    images as a writing of existence in light

    (a photo-graphy); as a distinction that is non-

    representational, not subordinated to the task of

    signifying a referent but rather tasked with

    exposing the singularity of a body, as its

    being-there or Da-sein.5

    II grievable and ungrievable life

    Alongside Nancy, I also want to set another

    approach to thinking the marking of life and

    death. Although this may seem to evoke a

    different set of terms, I want rather to argue for

    the usefulness of seeing the proximity of the two

    accounts. In Frames of War, Judith Butler

    specifies her project as a response to the

    conditions of contemporary war that is enabled

    by a selective and differential framing of

    violence (1). War becomes easier to wage when

    its violence is targeted against lives that fail to

    appear as such, and the exclusion from visibility

    that takes place is fundamental: for lives cannot

    be apprehended as injured or lost if they are not

    first apprehended as living (1). There are

    profound global differences in the way in which

    lives and deaths are marked with or without a

    media image, an obituary, a memorial that

    Butler tracks as evidence of the differentiation of

    grievable and ungrievable life which so

    smoothes the path to global violence.6 Read as

    marking life as being of value, this distinction

    seems to bear a perhaps too obvious ethical and

    political salience and to be readily assimilated

    into the cosmopolitan concern to find an

    jenkins

    161

    jenkins

    Dow

    nloa

    ded

    by [M

    onas

    h Univ

    ersity

    Libr

    ary] a

    t 22:1

    5 06 F

    ebru

    ary 20

    12

  • adequately expansive representation of the

    human, that no life be overlooked or go

    unmarked. This way of presenting the political

    division of worlds is indeed most readily under-

    stood as if it ethically posed an issue of

    recognition, as the mode whereby a body is

    invested with a protective significance. For within

    human rights-based cosmopolitan thinking it is

    taken for granted that such recognition confers

    some level of protection against violence; that to

    bring a body within the borders of sanctity is to

    see that it is like one of us, enjoying the moral

    status of humanity. This construction makes the

    process of humanisation and dehumanisation that

    is worked through the image, the capacity of

    media stories to give face to victims of

    violence, or to efface them, an urgent site

    of intervention.

    Yet although the visual conditions of con-

    temporary mediation under which a face is

    given and those in which effacement takes

    place are without doubt amongst Butlers con-

    cerns, she is chary of invoking recognition of

    humanity as the ground of protection. For the

    human is itself a norm that works to give face

    and to efface, a norm that deserves to be

    regarded as separating us from awareness of

    conditions of existence as often as it directs our

    attention to them; thus a norm that demands

    critical reading rather than embodiment and a

    strategic appropriation or deployment rather than

    faith (77). To be recognisable, to have a face, may

    indeed confer protections. But this having a

    face is not something originary; it is the result of

    a social crafting that not only delimits or

    frames the sphere of the visible (77) but also

    narrows and controls the terms of mutual

    exposure in social space, as if the face might

    as well be a kind of mask. The human face is what

    is socially acceptable, and functions normatively;

    in part through the requirement of a conformity

    that individualises responsibility for being what

    we are; in part through a social and political

    violence that is licensed against the unrecogni-

    sable or inhuman. The body is invested with

    significance through norms of gender, race, or

    position in a global hierarchy, in ways that

    constantly intersect with discourse on the

    human, rendering humanity a site of the

    differential distribution of protection of life

    and exposure to its precarity.

    As such, however, normative framing of the

    human necessarily lacks coherence or consis-

    tency. Butlers intervention in this field does not

    seek to secure expansion of membership in the

    category of the human but to do justice to what

    troubles such a project. This demands a loosening

    of the grip of the idea that recognisability is

    indexed to a referent, and that its trajectory is

    clear, rather than being a process of invention

    and becoming within a field of meaning that is

    not only conflicted but also makes demands in

    excess of recognition:

    How then is recognizability to be understood?

    In the first instance, it is not a quality or

    potential of individual humans . . . If we claim

    that recognizability is a human potential and

    that it belongs to all persons as persons, then,

    in a way the problem before us is already

    solved. We have decided that some particular

    notion of personhood will determine the

    scope and meaning of recognizability . . . [W]e

    have in effect already recognized everything

    we need to know about recognition. (Frames 6)

    Recognition, Butler suggests, must become open

    to un-knowing. Not only must the frames of

    recognition be acknowledged to be partial and

    incoherent but there must also be attentiveness to

    what escapes or troubles them.

    The term Butler turns to here is appre-

    hension, a mode of knowing that is not yet

    recognition, or may remain irreducible to

    recognition (6). This should not be read as if

    it were a capacity to reach behind existing norms

    to discern some kind of truth beyond the

    existing distribution of human identity. Although

    a way of knowing, apprehension has to do with

    a sensing that leaves the body exposed to alterity,

    to whatever comes to disturb the norms of

    recognisability, lacking the defences of a subject

    viewing the world. Apprehension is itself

    exposure, being-beyond protection, being

    exposed; it registers the profound disturbance

    that is given by the spectral character of what is

    not already recognised as a life, a sense attentive

    to what disturbs the given understanding of what

    is real (12). It is at this ontological level of

    at the limits of the human

    162

    at the limits of the human

    Dow

    nloa

    ded

    by [M

    onas

    h Univ

    ersity

    Libr

    ary] a

    t 22:1

    5 06 F

    ebru

    ary 20

    12

  • awareness that Butler suggests a critique of the

    differential norm of humanity must begin, or at

    least in which it must be rooted. Although, she

    argues, there is no life and death without a

    relation to some frame, nonetheless when life

    and death take place between, outside, or across

    the frames by which they are for the most part

    organized, they still take place, though in ways

    that call into question the necessity of the

    mechanisms by which norms are organized (7;

    my emphasis). What I shall seek to find in

    Nancys reflections is a fuller rendering than

    Butler gives us of how ontology and ethics grow

    together here; and thus what this taking place

    between, outside and across frames might lead us

    to think not only concerning spectral life but

    within this, the haunting life of images. In

    Butlers reflections, however, there is an impor-

    tant focus on how violence comes to inhabit the

    structure of moral recognition, through the

    occlusion of existence in ungrievable life, life

    which is not recognized as life (12) because,

    prior to this, it is not apprehended as such.

    What emerges from Butlers discussion is the

    inadequacy of supposing the frames which

    determine the recognisability of the human

    to be more or less adequate forms of representa-

    tion through which the world is seen. The

    conception of framing, instead, is of a reiterative

    process, to be thought as the temporalising and

    spacing operation of norms. Rather than simply

    securing the relationship of representation to a

    referent (as in the visual presentation of a face

    indexed to the human person) the norms of

    framing can be considered as constituting a

    practice of management of context, a separation

    of inside from outside, before and after, that is

    never wholly successfully determined; indeed,

    which entails that the sense of the inside is

    forever haunted by what is outside (Frames 9).

    The operation of the norm, one might say, is

    inherently open, not because it can apply to all

    future proper instances (for instance, of the

    human) but conversely because its re-iteration

    resists fusion into a continuum.7 This is both the

    condition of functioning of the frame and the

    condition of the impossibility of its determining

    meaning. The global circulation of the image is

    thus one crucial locus at which this excess over

    the already-recognisable (this taking place

    beyond an original context or framing intention)

    may be registered. Images, such as those of

    torture at Abu Ghraib, are caught up in this work

    of normative framing; nonetheless, they repeat-

    edly fracture the stability of any determined

    context. Not only do the images find unforeseen

    contexts of reception but also the images in

    circulating generate new contexts beyond

    any intention by which they were made or

    published (77).

    The point of a critique that begins ontologi-

    cally, then, will not simply be to establish the

    functioning of media images as aspects of a

    normativity that circulates in space and time,

    differentially marking the human and inhuman

    according to narratives that justify or condemn

    violence; but more fundamentally, to draw

    attention to the exposure of the image as an

    opening to sense, as what is always already out of

    context, or as the force of the spectral. It is for

    this reason, I suggest, that Butler resists the idea

    of compassion fatigue as an effect of exposure

    to global mediation, alongside the idea that this

    circulation can successfully determine any

    response, whether to give human faces or to

    efface distant lives. For although real enough in

    their immediate effects, both the numbing

    exposure to images and their way of functioning

    to reproduce normative framings of the human

    do not exhaust what an image is, nor how it

    continues to give evidence of what was. Thus,

    considered ontologically,

    the Abu Ghraib photographs neither numb

    our senses nor determine a particular

    response. This has to do with the fact that

    they occupy no single time and no specific

    space. (78)

    The photographs, shown and circulated, consti-

    tute a public condition, in excess of the

    original context, and one under which outrage

    has the chance to find a voice (78). But the image

    generates this opening only on condition of

    rupturing the continuum of meaning; and it is

    an opening incited less by the quest to recognise

    the human than by the necessity of discerning the

    remnants of the recognisable a mark [of

    humanity] . . . not registered through a norm, but

    jenkins

    163

    jenkins

    Dow

    nloa

    ded

    by [M

    onas

    h Univ

    ersity

    Libr

    ary] a

    t 22:1

    5 06 F

    ebru

    ary 20

    12

  • by the fragments that follow in the wake of the

    abrogation of the normatively human (94).

    Apprehension would be the aspect of sense

    attuned to this spectral life, and attested to in

    the capacity of the image to bear witness to what

    took place, but only in so far as the immediacy

    of presence is ruptured by separation, distance, a

    circulation that creates discontinuity. The impos-

    sibility of giving a determined meaning to the

    event here gives way to the necessity of

    responding to the disturbance it presents.

    The image presents a challenge to the success-

    ful re-instatement of the normatively human (94

    95); it gives evidence against it by exposing

    what the norm forecloses, what it must push to

    the outside in order to function (9). Butler calls

    ungrievable life, this specter that gnaws at the

    norms of recognition, an intensified figure

    vacillating at its inside and its outside (12).

    Yet we should be careful not to redeem this figure

    by giving the spectre a face or human name; for

    ungrievable life, read ontologically (or perhaps

    better, and as Derrida put it, hauntologically) is

    what testifies to a break with the name and the

    order of representation. To read the figure of

    ungrievable life as an element in hauntology, and

    as a place of challenge mobilised by the opening

    of the image, differs fundamentally from a

    reading that would render the term as one

    posing a problem of recognition, and ethically

    presenting the task that falls upon spectators of

    bringing a hitherto exposed body within the

    protective fold of human community. Butler cites

    Sontag exclaiming Let the atrocious images

    haunt us! (Sontag 65 cited in Frames 96); and it

    is in the domain of haunting that grievability

    emerges.8 Paradoxically, Butler argues, it is what

    haunts us that gives us access to the evidence the

    photographic image is. Drawing on Barthess

    reading of the photograph in the tense of the

    future anterior, and as I shall explore more fully

    in section IV below, it is the photographs

    anticipation of the past (98), its rupture of a

    space-time continuum, that establishes the prior-

    ity of sense over knowledge, making grievability

    the condition of a knowable human life (98). To

    affirm a life as existing is to be haunted by its

    presentation in the image; to refuse to be

    haunted, even in the presence of the image, is

    to render life ungrievable; if we are not haunted,

    there is no loss, there has been no life that is lost

    (97). Conversely, to confirm that a life was, even

    within the life itself, is to underscore that a life is

    a grievable life (Frames 97).

    What is established here is a fundamental

    relation between apprehension and the being

    of the image. Apprehension of life can be

    foreclosed and refused; but the image insists (or

    haunts) as the mark of a potential for re-opening.

    Conversely, the image gives itself to apprehen-

    sion, as the demand for sense. We might in this

    way conceive grievability as the precondition of

    life, one that is discovered retrospectively

    through the temporality instituted by the photo-

    graph itself (98), or as life that is accomplished

    in being given to sense:

    The apprehension of grievability precedes and

    makes possible the apprehension of precarious

    life. Grievability precedes and makes possible

    the apprehension of the living being as living,

    exposed to non-life from the start. (15)

    Here I am deliberately weaving together the

    terms Butler uses with terms derived from

    Nancys ontology of the non-representational

    image, as, to cite again, the outside of the

    world where the gaze loses itself to find itself as

    gaze (regard), that is, first and foremost as respect

    (egard) for what is there, for what takes place and

    continues to take place (Evidence 64). The

    apprehension of precarious life, regard for

    existence in its being born and dying, demands

    thinking in terms of the image that goes beyond

    the name (paradoxical as that might seem when

    we think of the obituary or memorial as recording

    names). This is, at several levels, a fundamental

    break with any view of the moral work of images

    that consists in bringing what is distant close, or

    making what is strange familiar. It is also a break

    with the quest for all members of humanity to

    find equality in being equally represented.

    On Butlers terms, precariousness, as apprehen-

    sion of lifes sheer exposure, as the condition of

    being conditioned, exceeds the individual,

    exceeds, indeed, the human and the very terms

    of recognition (Frames 13); yet the irrefutable

    generalizability of this condition (23) is for

    Butler the basis of egalitarian considerations, in

    at the limits of the human

    164

    at the limits of the human

    Dow

    nloa

    ded

    by [M

    onas

    h Univ

    ersity

    Libr

    ary] a

    t 22:1

    5 06 F

    ebru

    ary 20

    12

  • so far as these may be conceived as an obligation

    to the living that arises not through sovereign

    decision about what lives are worth living and

    which deserve to be destroyed, nor by super-

    seding this arbitrariness in the name of an

    expansive and inclusive humanism, but as

    ontological responsibility, precisely to (re)gener-

    ating the conditions of lifes liveability (23).

    This responsibility, as I have been following

    Butler in arguing, turns on sense engaging the

    haunting work of images. Further, it resists the

    terms of a representational egalitarianism that

    arises from certain cosmopolitan precepts, nota-

    bly the conception of the cosmos as a single

    representational universe and the sympathetic

    imagination as the means to expand its territorial

    reach. But to further articulate the kind of claim

    that might be at work in thinking the terms of

    justice and equality ontologically, it is worth

    returning to consider Nancys reflections on this

    theme.

    III mundus corpus

    If moral cosmopolitanism concerns itself with the

    relay of distant suffering (Boltanski) and with

    extending the inclusiveness of representation in

    universal humanity, what is the significance of an

    ontological project that insists, as Nancy does, on

    taking a distance from globalisation by setting in

    motion a world-forming or mondialisation,

    a making sense (Creation 29)? Certainly,

    Nancy speaks of justice; but might such justice,

    indexed as it is to the work of the image, prove

    merely to be an aesthetic category, one indifferent

    to properly ethical concerns?

    An answer to these questions would need to

    pass through several vectors, including reflection

    on how far the moral cosmopolitan project,

    bound as it is to globalisation, proves insensitive

    to the problematic of place, remaining thor-

    oughly centred on the priority of First World

    forms of consciousness and understanding of

    global relationships.9 First and foremost, how-

    ever, what I want to consider here is how a

    deconstruction of cosmopolitan precepts is set in

    motion by conjoining a thinking of the image

    with a thinking of how life is marked; how a

    body comes to matter, without this signalling that

    human life is invested with a significance that

    comes from above (as the immaterial soul

    enters the body, or as reason connects the human

    with a higher realm); a bestowal of significance

    which would, no doubt, find its law in the truth of

    human form. To deconstruct this attribution of

    soul to humanity, in the present context, will

    be to follow Nancy in elaborating instead the

    presentation of a body as itself the stake of

    justice; the soul given in extension, a name for

    the experience that the body is (Corpus 134).

    By asking what it is for a life to be marked, as the

    event of birth or death is marked, I am also

    asking after the mode of distinction that Nancy is

    thinking as the giving-to-be-sensed of the sensing

    body (another name for which might be

    apprehension).

    Nancy treats equality as a giving distinction

    that is irreducible to signification, or the

    determination of meaning (value). This is directly

    set against what he takes to be the production by

    Capital of the absolute value of the human

    (pricelessness, dignity in Kants sense). The

    dignity of man toward which moral cosmopoli-

    tanism reaches represents the absolute value

    that capitalism exchanges for itself, and indicates

    one vital aspect of the concomitance between the

    globalization of the market and that of human

    rights (Being Singular Plural 74). In effect,

    Nancy deconstructs the very idea of value in

    itself or dignity on the basis of the exchange

    or sharing it presupposes, so that its absolute

    becomes that of singular-plural existence:

    There is a common measure, which is not

    some one unique standard applied to everyone

    and everything. It is the commensurability of

    incommensurable singularities, the equality of

    all the origins-of-the-world, which, as origins,

    are strictly unexchangable. (Being 75)

    Nancy does not seek to mystify us with these

    terms. He is saying that equality, the common

    measure, is not given by the incommensurable

    value of a human dignity which a being might

    possess or of which it falls short. Rather, what is

    common is the singularity of existence, which

    shares out equality as distinction without further

    ground. Here, the most common (banal) is

    common for each as such (Corpus 93) just as

    jenkins

    165

    jenkins

    Dow

    nloa

    ded

    by [M

    onas

    h Univ

    ersity

    Libr

    ary] a

    t 22:1

    5 06 F

    ebru

    ary 20

    12

  • birth is common, and yet extraordinary.

    Moreover, it is worth noting that this does not

    intend to be an anthropocentric principle. The

    formulation resists the idea of there being on the

    one side an originary singularity and on the

    other a simple being there of things, more or

    less given for our use; rather, a singularity is a

    body, and all bodies are singularities (Being 18).

    Or, as he also phrases it, humanity is the

    exposing of the world; it is neither the end nor

    the ground of the world; the world is the

    exposure of humanity; it is neither the environ-

    ment nor the representation of humanity (18).

    To maintain a concern for equality is to be

    interested by the fundamental alterity that is each

    origin of the world, whether an other is

    another person, animal, plant, or star, it is above

    all the glaring presence of a place and moment of

    absolute origin, irrefutable, offered as such and

    vanishing in its passing (21). It is not a matter of

    making all these curious presences equal, but

    rather of a concern for the renewal of alterity as

    such, that is, concern for the condition of equality

    as dis-position and co-appearance. That concern

    is destroyed in the desire to appropriate the

    origin, to look for the unique and exclusive

    origin, in order either to accept or reject it (21)

    which can also be put in terms of the annihilation

    of being in place, seeking a position outside

    the world, that would fix the origin as a

    metaphysical ground of being. Such a gesture also

    refuses the exposure that co-appearance, or

    being-with constitutes.

    It is for all these reasons that the recourse to an

    absolute value of humanity is said by Nancy to

    refuse existence and become mutilation, the loss

    of distinction, the annihilation of the plurality of

    bodies. Affirming that the translation of all

    bodies into a mass, or indistinction, can be

    opposed even from within an existence that is

    suffering, and without recourse to the idea that

    these bodies all represent individual members of

    humanity, Nancy writes:

    The exceptionality of a body is common as

    such: substitutable for every other as

    unsubstitutable.

    This is what makes the idea that images

    banalize more or less false or ideological.

    Of the thousands of corroded, suffering,

    reduced bodies that television can show, it

    also shows that each one, each and every time

    again, an each one is suffering.

    But this is visible only in the space of bodies,

    to an eye attentive to bodies not to a

    discourse about generic and general humanity.

    (Corpus 93)

    What is an eye attentive to bodies? No longer a

    cosmopolitan vision, it is an eye attuned to

    whatever comes. The each one that Nancy

    refers to is a singularity; however, singularity

    rests in the generalised contingency of ex-isting,

    being ex-posed, that is, existing as a body without

    ground. The each one is each one, just this

    time (Being 97), so that one might say it is

    eventuality rather than the unique subjectivity

    of a bearer of human life that is at stake for

    Nancy in the way the image resists the banality

    that it is, inevitably, also given over to. To

    present suffering is to give the demand that

    arises as ontological concern for singular-plural

    existence.

    In a sense what is to be marked here is

    precisely lifes exposure to its own contingency,

    and the problem and question become how that

    does not, on the one hand, collapse into

    indifference, the banality of utter substitutability

    that also renders all suffering that belongs to the

    mass of bodies, to be of no account; or on the

    other, be countered with the desire to redeem all

    suffering, to make it meaningful in a way that is

    indexed to humanity. There are many forms

    that sheer being-without-reason can take; for

    instance, it can take the form of capital

    (Creation 110). Yet Nancy also maintains that

    that the world happens is the law of its justice,

    justice to birth and death.

    The question then is how to take up con-

    tingency as the without ultimate reason for being

    so. The without reason of the world is not just

    the absence of necessity (not just what Nancy

    terms the absentheism of a disappearing God).

    Rather, it is the ex nihilo from nothing that is

    the opening or birth of sense. The originary

    ethics called for in this context by Nancy

    is engaged on the basis of nihilism as the

    general dissolution of sense but as the exact

    at the limits of the human

    166

    at the limits of the human

    Dow

    nloa

    ded

    by [M

    onas

    h Univ

    ersity

    Libr

    ary] a

    t 22:1

    5 06 F

    ebru

    ary 20

    12

  • reverse of nihilism: as the bringing-to-light of

    making sense as action requested in the

    essence of being. (Finite Thinking 180)

    Although the remark is made in exposition of

    Heidegger, it may stand to explicate what is most

    fundamentally at issue for Nancy in thinking the

    contingency that exposes bodies: the question to

    each gesture . . . How do you engage the world?

    How do you involve yourself with the enjoyment

    of the world as such and not with the appropria-

    tion of a quantity of equivalence? (Creation 53).

    The demand of making-sense is not to find a

    rationalisation of existence as it is but calls for

    the creation of meaning, as the touching of

    material limits (something Nancy contrasts with

    the capitalist production of value). Sense here

    is at once responsiveness and agency, the sense by

    which we touch the world and by which it touches

    us. This, indeed, is a passage toward a different

    world, an access access itself; and art is

    privileged as a way of remaining within the

    coming world by remaining within the passage,

    towards the coming world, by beginning ex

    nihilo (Birth 44).

    But this is not only a matter for art to address,

    although the images generated by aesthetic

    practices will prove exemplary. It is also on the

    basis of this thinking that, as bodies are presented

    in ever more insistent ways through the media of

    the worlds interconnectivity, Nancy seeks to

    figure the condition of plurality, as the non-

    generic nature of an existence comprising more

    than five billion human bodies (Corpus 83). This

    crowd of bodies will seem to press toward a banal

    and indifferent mass if the differentiation or

    distinctness of the body, its place or extension, its

    mattering in this sense, is levelled as equiva-

    lent value (124). The problem or opportunity that

    Nancy poses as arising from the circulation of

    images is thus one of making sense, or of

    rendering worlding as distinctness, without

    appeal to any higher end or principle of

    comparability, that is, to render soul as the

    form of a body:

    Our billions of images show billions of

    bodies as bodies have never been seen

    before. Crowds, piles, melees, bundles, col-

    umns, troops, swarms, armies, bands,

    stampedes, panics, tiers, processions, colli-

    sions, massacres, mass graves, communions,

    dispersions, a sur-plus, always an overflowing

    of bodies . . . the world taking place as a

    prodigious press of bodies. (3941)

    The impetus of moral cosmopolitanism is to

    retrieve from this threatened massification the

    humanised individual subject of a general

    humanity; and its privileged form of the image

    would therefore aim to certify the truth of an

    identity, a face. The body it depicts is

    humanised if it represents the interiority of

    subjectivity, the human soul to which moral

    value can be attached. If the equal consideration

    that here inflects the marking of human lives,

    near or far, might also be said to concern the

    distinctness of an image, this is in the sense of a

    representation, distinctly rendering the condi-

    tions or appearance that secure membership

    within the category of the human and thus

    confer rights.

    In Nancys thinking, however, the image itself

    is freed from this end; mundus corpus, his

    name for a world given to its singular bodies, is

    neither cosmos, nor pure immanence, nor

    spectacle, but rather whatever images show

    us (39). This shift of focus not only breaks with

    the idea of the cosmos as the representation of a

    universe, a cosmos that presupposes a perspective

    outside the world it surveys, a globe

    (Creation 42); in addition, the image itself is

    being thought in terms that break with the logic

    of representation, as Nancy seeks to elaborate the

    being distinct of an image, its standing out

    against a ground, not as an appearance behind

    which a reality lies but as a being-there wholly

    other than the availability of objects (Ground 2).

    Whatever images show us should be read with

    stress on a whatever that is a question, a

    passion, a regard for the distinct posed as a

    welcome to whatever comes.

    In terms that might be contrasted wholesale

    with the idea of the media image as an element of

    transport that represents the lives of one side of

    the globe to the other, Nancy insists that the

    image should be thought in terms of being

    distinct, being a thing that is not a thing,

    without this proving secondary to the identity of

    the referent. The image is that which tears being

    jenkins

    167

    jenkins

    Dow

    nloa

    ded

    by [M

    onas

    h Univ

    ersity

    Libr

    ary] a

    t 22:1

    5 06 F

    ebru

    ary 20

    12

  • from itself simply because the image is that

    within which what is presents itself. The image in

    withdrawing from the thing gives the thing

    itself distinguished in its sameness (Ground 11)

    that is, precedes it, even as the thing thereby

    comes to resemble itself (24). Here, images and

    the evidence they give participate in a movement,

    in the without ground of creation, or world-

    making. Such is the demand of distinction, or of

    being brought to distinction. The image is

    whatever distinguishes itself from the thing, to

    give place to the thing; and as such it implies a

    rupture with the continuity and homogeneity

    proper to the order of things. The distinct is the

    heterogeneous and what it transports to us . . . is

    its very unbinding, which no proximity can pacify

    and which thus remains at a distance (34). This

    coming to distinction is being-singular-plural,

    and it posits a continual creation which is the

    equality of all origins, as arising without

    reason, as birth itself. Giving place and taking

    place configure the generosity of existence, the

    sharing out of distinction prior to the possession

    of any property. Worldhood (mondialisation),

    which contrasts globalisation, then demands to be

    created, a demand given by existence beyond all

    ends (beyond the ends of man or God) (Creation

    52). Nancy also calls mundus corpus the world

    that is coming (Corpus 39) and we might think of

    this as a futurity exceeding representation,

    including the representation of ends, or read as

    the prescience, the futural thrust of the tearing

    away that is presentation as such.

    IV from ontology to hauntology

    In Butlers reflections on what it is to mark a

    life, that is, to apprehend it, I have suggested that

    we also find such a deconstruction at work, and

    that it is again one that not only calls for

    invention beyond what is recognisable but also

    does so out of a concern for existence in common

    that goes beyond the human.

    A new life, according to Butler, is attended by

    anticipation of its mortality; it is regarded as a

    life only in so far as its death would matter

    (Frames 15). This might seem to make each one

    of us dependent on recognition in a sense that

    gives us over entirely to the values and concerns

    of others. It is just such contingent vulnerability,

    one would think, that the idea of inherent human

    dignity (a dignity that transcends local context)

    resists. On such grounds, too, one might give

    welcome to the global circulation of images that

    break with the locality of place and time precisely

    as the means to transcendence of whatever is

    arbitrary and cruel in the context a being is born

    to. It is important, then, to note that Butler has

    distinguished this order of regard for life

    grievability from recognition; and that the

    dependency posited does not ultimately rest on

    the sheer contingency of local social valuations,

    although it will sometimes seem to do so.

    Although we could read the claim of newborn

    life to care, in terms simply of the vulnerability of

    the infant, its human need for a social network

    of hands (14) to guarantee survival, it is the

    necessity of caring for this life, the obligation to

    do so, that has prior conditions and demands an

    account. If that depends solely on human

    valuation and decision then the issue would

    indeed seem to be one that calls for an invocation

    of universal humanity as the highest order of

    concern for individual life. The question that I

    have in an indirect way been exploring here,

    however, is how otherwise to phrase the nature of

    a demand that exceeds an immediate or given

    context. It is this demand, I am suggesting,

    that is given in the non-representational image,

    the presentation of precarious life; and its force is

    the force of evidence, conjoining the imme-

    diacy and the distance through which the image

    gives distinction. This is captured, I suggest,

    when Butler binds the apprehension of lifes

    mattering to a grievability that precedes and

    conditions knowing, and that finds its model in

    the treatment of photographic portraiture given

    by Barthes and, after him, Derrida and Nancy.10

    In evoking precisely the haunting nature of

    photography, the particular suspension of

    normal temporal and spatial relations that

    cast the photographic image of a person as the

    mark of a life, Butler links the apprehension

    that rests on grievability to the temporality of the

    future anterior this will have been a life. It is as

    such an apprehension (and apprehension is

    precisely the mood of the future anterior, bearing

    an element of anxiety) that grievability is a

    at the limits of the human

    168

    at the limits of the human

    Dow

    nloa

    ded

    by [M

    onas

    h Univ

    ersity

    Libr

    ary] a

    t 22:1

    5 06 F

    ebru

    ary 20

    12

  • condition of lifes emergence and sustenance;

    for, Butler writes, there can be no celebration

    [of new life] without an implicit understanding

    that the life is grievable, that it would be grieved

    if it were lost, and that this future anterior is

    installed as the condition of its life (Frames 15).

    The photographic image, characterised by the

    mood of the future anterior, figures as the

    privileged site of the apprehension of existence,

    not because it represents a human subject, but

    due to its expression of a tense that presents the

    fact of the body as without further ground than

    its taking place.

    The tense of the future anterior inscribes the

    life of the image with a meaning that defeats

    linear time and looks from the ungroundedness of

    all being to touch on what is real: This will be a

    life that will have been lived signals the

    eventfulness of an existence that has always

    already begun and whose transcendence is not

    that of a soul hovering before or after

    incarnation but of the taking place that the

    birth-to-presence is. This reflection leads us to

    another conception of how the image in claiming

    us might lend distinction to the life. Rather than

    being a gift or discretion of the human, mattering

    haunts the image of the living, and inhabits the

    very tense of existence, registered in exposure to

    loss. Apprehension does not concern what or

    who a being is, so much as respond to what

    Barthes describes as a vertiginous experience of

    the image as a defeat of Time (Barthes 96). It is

    facing, not face, which is presented by exposure

    within the image itself; and this bespeaks an

    opening which cannot be contained by the frame

    and resists the assumption that what concerns us

    most is the content of the image, the face it

    depicts. Rather, the image anticipates a whole (a

    life) that is touched by mortality, yet cannot

    close that whole, as if by representing a life

    from the outside. The photograph, as exposure,

    as facing, thus always presages a death. In

    Barthess words I observe with horror an

    anterior future of which death is the stake (96);

    in Butlers:

    The photograph relays less the present

    moment than the perspective, the pathos, of

    a time in which this will have been . . . But

    every photographic portrait speaks in at least

    two temporal modes, both a chronicle of what

    has been and a protentive certainty about what

    will have been. (Frames 97)

    The photograph in this temporal mode gives

    evidence or marks a life. It is worth noting,

    indeed, that although the photograph as portrait

    is certainly a privileged instance here, there need

    be no face as such in this sort of image, but only

    some trace of facing. This is implied by one of

    Barthess illustrations of the punctum of the

    image (that in it which exceeds any frame or

    determination of content):

    In 1850 August Salzmann photographed, near

    Jerusalem, the road to Beith-leham (as it was

    spelled at the time): nothing but stony ground,

    olive trees; but three tenses dizzy my con-

    sciousness: my present, the time of Jesus, and

    that of the photographer, all this under the

    instance of reality and no longer through

    the elaborations of the text, whether fictional

    or poetic, which itself is never credible down

    to the root. (97)

    Jacques Rancie`re, reading Barthes, criticises

    what he believes the latter accords to the

    privilege of photographic or pictorial silence

    (Rancie`re 125), that is, the capacity of the image

    to register a mortal presence in excess of all

    contextualising explanations; and views the

    attention paid to the punctum of the image in

    Barthes as an extension of the ethical regime of

    images whereby a portrait or statue is always

    an image of someone, and derives its legitimacy

    from its relationship with the being or god it

    represents (113). Yet this seems to miss the

    profound experience of apprehension that regis-

    ters in Barthess account, and in a sense that

    exceeds the idea of the transcendence inherent in

    individual life. For Barthess image presents

    existence at a limit of the very availability of

    language, as landscape, without any visual

    appearances of faces as such. The presentation

    of the image, whose force displaces text and its

    credibility, collapses the representational

    regimes frame of space and time. That is not

    because the auratic face, or soul inhabits the

    image; rather, the image is a marker of eventful-

    ness; that it happened, certainly, but, further,

    jenkins

    169

    jenkins

    Dow

    nloa

    ded

    by [M

    onas

    h Univ

    ersity

    Libr

    ary] a

    t 22:1

    5 06 F

    ebru

    ary 20

    12

  • and more fundamentally, that it will have

    happened, thus, the affirmation of the happen-

    ing of the event, its being, which is its

    presentation in the image beyond all immediate

    context.

    Nor does Butler think of the image as breaking

    with context in the sense of transcendence. The

    breaking with context is, rather, an aspect of

    circulation; put quite formally, it concerns a

    rupture in the continuum of space-time that is

    other than individual transcendence. Likewise, I

    suggest that the nature of exposure that Butler

    renders here as the condition of being condi-

    tioned goes wider than that given by the

    sociality of humanity, whether given locally or

    universally. As the locus of the human subject is

    displaced from its position of privilege as what

    gives meaning to the image, so too the locus of

    universal humanity proves inept for registering

    the demand arising from the image. The image

    gives evidence of the living as exposure; its

    demand is for the invention of forms of

    liveability, such that the differentiation and

    distinctness of the body, its taking place or

    mattering becomes a place of existence upon

    which we might touch. This, I suggest, is how to

    read the egalitarian condition of grievable life, or

    of concern for the fundamental alterity that is

    each origin of the world; the welcome to

    whatever comes, the event of birth, the

    repeated advent of the strange, as a demand of

    world-creation.

    For a life to be marked might mean to be

    remarked, or represented in a way that suggests

    at least the possibility for concern, care or

    compassion. There is, however, another dimen-

    sion that deconstruction opens up within the

    mark. If we suspend the priority of a life over

    what pictures or represents it to a distant

    audience, we might enter thinking about the

    marking of life instead on the terms in which

    Jacques Derrida frames his hauntology; as a

    ghost-work, exceeding ontology and reworking it

    from the inside, or as the re-mark of performa-

    tivity that is the opening of a time-out-of joint, or

    the to come (Specters of Marx). The mark in

    this sense does not come after the life, as

    representation refers to presence; rather, the

    mark inhabits life, bespeaking the death that

    de-centres it and the temporality of the trace.

    This might not only invite a thinking of the work

    of images on terms that again break with their

    special status as representations that bring close

    distant lives, but also challenge the progressive

    understanding of the movement of time char-

    acteristic of moral cosmopolitanism. By linking

    the problematic of the marking of a life to the

    general structure of the mark as haunted by

    the mechanical repetition of what happened once,

    the pure reproducibility of a pure event

    (Margins 194), we might evoke at once certain

    characteristics of photographic portraiture and

    the movement of the to come as a repetition

    and inauguration that turns experience toward

    the question of how to welcome the other or

    the strange. Derridas treatment of this ques-

    tion inspires his sense that an absolute law of

    hospitality in excess of cosmopolitanism would

    welcome the spectral, the soul at the limit of the

    human, remaining open to

    what is coming, that is, to the event that

    cannot be awaited as such, or recognized in

    advance therefore, to the event as the foreigner

    itself, to her or him for whom one must leave

    an empty place [. . .] the very place of

    spectrality. (Specters 65)

    So, too, we might read Butlers reflections as

    moving beyond a cosmopolitan vision when she

    writes that over and against an existential

    concept of finitude that singularizes our relation

    to death and to life, precariousness underscores

    our radical substitutability and anonymity in

    relation to death and to life (Frames 14). For it

    is only on the basis of anonymity and substitut-

    ability that, she argues, a bond of obligation can

    be formed among strangers, constituting a

    collectivity on another basis than identity or

    intimacy (3435). It is not the presence of a

    face that secures obligation, except on terms

    that extend the intimacy of a human family whose

    members are already known to one another,

    already recognisable. Rather, the demand to

    which the photographic image attests claims us

    on the basis of the opening or facing of a

    futural and unknowable transcendence. Butlers

    reasoning, I have argued here, is thus proximate

    to that presented by Nancy in terms of a way of

    at the limits of the human

    170

    at the limits of the human

    Dow

    nloa

    ded

    by [M

    onas

    h Univ

    ersity

    Libr

    ary] a

    t 22:1

    5 06 F

    ebru

    ary 20

    12

  • thinking community without ground, the being-

    singular-plural or being-with; a we that is given

    as a common exposure, not a property of

    beings (the property of vulnerability, say) but

    occurring as the dis-posing of being, giving place

    to whatever comes.

    Here the response to and obligation to the

    strange, even to that strange alterity of the

    newborn, issues from a precariousness that is, as

    Butler puts it, co-extensive with birth itself

    (14) and is given in the future anterior tense of

    the body-as-image, the body that matters. To

    affirm the existence of such a body is to affirm

    life as exposure; and to offer hospitality to such a

    life is a hospitality to whatever

    comes, to the advent of singu-

    lar-plural existence beyond

    all given ends, or to a

    mondialisation.

    notes1

    Aworld viewed, a represented world, is aworld dependent on the gaze of a subject oftheworld. A subject of theworld . . . cannotitself be within the world. Even without areligious representation, such a subject,implicit or explicit, perpetuates the positionof the creating, organizing, and addressingGod (if not the addressee) of the world.(Nancy,Creation 40)

    2 See James for an excellent discussion ofevidence in Nancy.

    3 The crucial point is that whereas on thePlatonic-Christian understanding of human beingit is as though soul animates the body, in such away that signification (or representation) givessense to the body, Nancy holds that to make abody a sign in this way is to refuse how a body ishere, at the here or there of a place.The termsoul is thus retrieved from the thinkingof the philosophical tradition as nothingother than the experience of the body or asthe extension or expanse of the body(Corpus134).

    4 To be born, Nancy writes, is the name ofbeing, and absolutely in excess of representation(Birth 2).

    5 For further discussion of this point in Nancy,see both Armstrong and Balfour.

    6 See also Butlers Precarious Life.

    7 This argument depends, of course, on the treat-ment of context in Derridas Signature, Event,Context (Margins).

    8 It should be noted that Butler takes Sontag tomake a less ambitious claim, treating the photo-graphic image as an invitation to reflection,rather than engaging photography at the level ofsense proposed here. See Frames 98^99.

    9 The problem of worlding is ignored when theself-designated First World purports to stand ina spectatorial relation to distant others, whilethoroughly integrating a global market economyunder the rubric of human rights. Thus, forinstance, despite Becks nod to an inclusivity ofdifferent perspectives in constructing a post-colonial cosmopolitanism (Beck and Sznaider2006), it remains the case that, as Martell argues,the ideologyof a co-operative humanitarian globalpolitics relies on a moral optimism that fails totake sufficient account of how world politics isstructured by conflict and power, rather than bycommon consciousness and collaboration andfails, for structural reasons, to move smoothlyalong ideal progressive lines. My specific sugges-tion here, however, is that if moral cosmopolitan-ism typically glosses over conflicts, inequalitiesand injustices in world society and harmonises[. . .] contradictions within a benign and optimisticview of international relations (Martell 254) thishas a lot to do with the account given of how thecontemporary global world is rendered in imagesand the kinds of claim these imagesmake.

    10 See Barthes; Derrida,Work of Mourning. Seealso bothWike and Kaplan for an excellent discus-sion of howNancy takes up and extends Barthessand Derridas insights.

    bibliographyArmstrong, Philip. From Appearance toExposure. Journal of Visual Culture 9.63 (2010): 11^27. Print.

    Balfour, Ian. Nancy on Film: RegardingKiarostami, Re-thinking Representation (with aCoda on Claire Denis). Journal of Visual Culture 9.63(2010): 29^43. Print.

    jenkins

    171

    jenkins

    Dow

    nloa

    ded

    by [M

    onas

    h Univ

    ersity

    Libr

    ary] a

    t 22:1

    5 06 F

    ebru

    ary 20

    12

  • Barthes, R. Camera Lucida: Reflections onPhotography. Trans. Richard Wang. New York: Hill,1981. Print.

    Beck,Ulrich.CosmopolitanVision.Cambridge: Polity,2006. Print.

    Beck, Ulrich, and Natan Sznaider. UnpackingCosmopolitanism for the Social Sciences: AResearch Agenda. British Journal of Sociology 57.1(2006):1^23. Print.

    Boltanski, Luc.Distant Suffering:Media, MoralityandPolitics.Cambridge: Cambridge UP,1999. Print.

    Butler, Judith. Frames of War:When is Life Grievable?NewYork and London:Verso, 2009. Print.

    Butler, Judith.Precarious Life:The Powers ofMourningand Violence. New York and London: Verso, 2004.Print.

    Chouliaraki, Lilie. The Spectatorship of Suffering.London and Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage, 2006.Print.

    Derrida, Jacques. Margins of Philosophy. Brighton:Harvester,1983. Print.

    Derrida, Jacques. Signature, Event, Context.Margins of Philosophy. Brighton: Harvester, 1983.308^30. Print.

    Derrida, Jacques. Specters of Marx: The State of theDebt, the Work of Mourning, and the NewInternational.NewYork: Routledge,1993. Print.

    Derrida, Jacques.TheWorkofMourning.Ed.Pascale-Anne Brault and Michael Naas. Chicago: U ofChicago P, 2001. Print.

    James, Ian. The Evidence of the Image. LEspritCre ateur 47.3 (2007): 68^79. Print.

    Kaplan, Louis. Photograph/Death Mask:Jean-Luc Nancys Recasting of the PhotographicImage. Journal of Visual Culture 9.63 (2010): 45^62.Print.

    Martell, Luke. Global Inequality, Human Rightsand Power: A Critique of Ulrich BecksCosmopolitanism. Critical Sociology 35.2 (2009):253^72. Print.

    Nancy, Jean-Luc. Being Singular Plural. Trans. R.Richardson and A. OByrne. Stanford: StanfordUP, 2000. Print.

    Nancy, Jean-Luc.The Birth to Presence. Trans. BrianHolmes. Stanford: Stanford UP,1993. Print.

    Nancy, Jean-Luc. Corpus. Trans. Richard A. Rand.NewYork: FordhamUP, 2008. Print.

    Nancy, Jean-Luc. The Creation of the World orGlobalization. Trans. Franc ois Raffoul and DavidPettigrew. Albany: State U of New York P, 2007.Print.

    Nancy, Jean-Luc. The Evidence of Film: AbbasKiarostami. Trans. C. Irizarry and V. AndermattConley.Brussels: Gevaert, 2001. Print.

    Nancy, Jean-Luc.AFiniteThinking.Ed. Simon Sparks.Stanford: Stanford UP, 2003. Print.

    Nancy, Jean-Luc. The Ground of the Image. Trans.J. Fort. Stanford: Stanford UP, 2005. Print.

    Rancie' re, Jacques.TheEmancipatedSpectator.Trans.Gregory Elliott. London:Verso, 2009. Print.

    Sontag, Susan. Regarding the Pain of Others.NewYork: Picador, 2003. Print.

    Wike, Lori. Photographs and Signatures:Absence, Presence and Temporality in Barthesand Derrida. Invisible Culture: An Electronic Journalfor Visual Studies 3. 2000.Web. 5 June 2011.

    Fiona Jenkins

    School of Philosophy

    Research School of Social Sciences

    Coombs Building

    Australian National University

    Canberra, ACT 0200

    Australia

    E-mail: [email protected]

    at the limits of the humanat the limits of the human

    Dow

    nloa

    ded

    by [M

    onas

    h Univ

    ersity

    Libr

    ary] a

    t 22:1

    5 06 F

    ebru

    ary 20

    12