“Emotion, Expressive Qualities, and Nature.” By Emily Brady-Zack Bosshardt.

19
“Emotion, Expressive Qualities, and Nature.” By Emily Brady -Zack Bosshardt

Transcript of “Emotion, Expressive Qualities, and Nature.” By Emily Brady-Zack Bosshardt.

Page 1: “Emotion, Expressive Qualities, and Nature.” By Emily Brady-Zack Bosshardt.

“Emotion, Expressive Qualities, and Nature.”By Emily Brady -Zack Bosshardt

Page 2: “Emotion, Expressive Qualities, and Nature.” By Emily Brady-Zack Bosshardt.

Overview of the Paper

How can we justify attributions of expressive qualities to the natural environment?

Conclusion: The similarity account along with the embodiment account gives us an explanation of expressive qualities in natural environments.

Page 3: “Emotion, Expressive Qualities, and Nature.” By Emily Brady-Zack Bosshardt.

A distinction

Felt emotion - Having some feeling or emotion as a result of aesthetic influence. We discussed this on Monday with Carroll’s article. Example: “We feel exhilarated when taking a morning walk through a forest.”

Expressive Quality - We do not feel any particular emotion, but rather we just find expressive qualities in what we experience. Brady’s examples: “a landscape that is bleak and forbidding”, or a tree that is anguished.

In short, felt emotion is an internal condition, while expressive qualities are external to us. The focus of the article is the latter.

Page 4: “Emotion, Expressive Qualities, and Nature.” By Emily Brady-Zack Bosshardt.

Worries About Subjectivity, Emotion, and Aesthetics

Emotion viewed as too subjective- Emotions can be fickle, differ among people, and be based on false beliefs; thus emotion and expressive qualities derived from nature could possibly be too subjective for appropriate aesthetic judgment.

Page 5: “Emotion, Expressive Qualities, and Nature.” By Emily Brady-Zack Bosshardt.

Cognitive Theory of Emotion

Brady agrees with Carroll: Emotions are “…not subjective projections upon a landscape.” “Justifying the feeling of excitement from the grandeur of a waterfall depends upon the qualities of the waterfall and the beliefs and thoughts that underlie the response.”

Carroll’s Cognitive Theory of Emotion is a solution to the subjectivity worry – We talked about this on Monday. Certain beliefs about the world are appropriate or inappropriate according to their corresponding truth or falsity. And further, an emotion resulting from a belief can be appropriate or inappropriate. People reasonably share the same emotional response given a base level of knowledge and belief. In this way, we can judge emotion resulting from nature as ‘objective.’

Page 6: “Emotion, Expressive Qualities, and Nature.” By Emily Brady-Zack Bosshardt.

Some Clarification on the Cognitive Theory from Brady

1. Brady emphasizes Carroll’s assertions that beliefs that elicit an emotional response are not scientific or specialized beliefs, but common sense beliefs.

2. Although beliefs are important and essential for emotion, “they do not provide the fullest account of the grounds for our emotions.” Imagination and thinking may affect our emotional response as much as belief. Also, “that our affective response reach beyond beliefs for their grounding and context.” Brady gives the cloud example.

3. Overall Brady accepts Carroll's views on emotion and aesthetic response.

Page 7: “Emotion, Expressive Qualities, and Nature.” By Emily Brady-Zack Bosshardt.

Expressive Qualities

Expressive qualities are emotional qualities that we perceive in external objects or environments. There are various ways we could fail to explain how environments and their objects are expressive:

1. Attribute emotional states to inanimate objects.

2. Compare nature to art.

3. Utilize a causal account.

Page 8: “Emotion, Expressive Qualities, and Nature.” By Emily Brady-Zack Bosshardt.

Ways Not to Think of Expressive Qualities

1. Attributing emotional states to inanimate objects - We could say that when an environment or object has a particular expressive quality, then the object or environment actually has the corresponding psychological or emotional state. For example, when we say a loch is somber, we are saying that the loch possess the psychological or emotional state of somber. This fails quickly because, “inanimate objects, objects without minds, do not have emotional states.” She gives another example of the child projecting emotions onto the teddy bear.

2. Comparing nature to art – In the case of art, the artist’s intention of an expressive quality emerges in the painting. Like we’ve said many times, this analogy cannot be applied to nature. Nature does not have an artist, so the intent and corresponding expressive quality do not exist like an art object.

Page 9: “Emotion, Expressive Qualities, and Nature.” By Emily Brady-Zack Bosshardt.

Ways Not to Think of Expressive Qualities3. Causal account – “When we ascribe an expressive quality to something, it is because the thing causes one to feel a particular emotion.” The loch can make a person feel a range of emotions, calm, relaxed, satisfied, or even no emotion at all. Despite this fact, the loch will retain its expressive quality of somberness. So, the causal account cannot explain expressive qualities either.

Example of Winning the Lottery – Even after winning the lottery experiencing the emotion of happiness, one can still recognize the loch as somber.

Page 10: “Emotion, Expressive Qualities, and Nature.” By Emily Brady-Zack Bosshardt.

Expressive Qualities in Nature, and how we ought to think of them: Similarity Theory

Similarity Theory - Identification of non-aesthetic qualities, the way things are arranged or the way things “look or sound”, leads us to a comparison between the identified object and emotions that we experience. This comparison gives us the ability to identify an expressive quality in the object that corresponds, or is similar to, human emotion.

The weeping willow example – We can give the expressive quality of sad to a weeping willow. By this we don’t mean that the tree possesses the psychological state of sadness, but that it is sad looking. “Weeping willow is sad or sad-looking because we recognize in it the posture of someone feeling down.” The reference point to ascribe an expressive quality is human emotion, “but it is possible that the resemblance works both ways.” (The storm example)

Page 11: “Emotion, Expressive Qualities, and Nature.” By Emily Brady-Zack Bosshardt.

Similarity Theory

‘Objective’ Approach – The approach relies on observation of non-aesthetic qualities, or the formalistic ways things appear to us. These non-aesthetic qualities appear more or less the same to everyone, and so I can communicate the corresponding expressive qualities to other people with relative ease.

Stephen Davies elaborating on Carroll – Another explanation of similarity and expressive qualities is in music. Take the example of a sad song. Although I may not feel the emotion of sadness currently, I can nonetheless identify sadness as a quality of a sad song. “The similarity exists structurally, and he describes a piece of music as a sound map of particular emotional expression.” When we hear a song with an expressive quality of sadness, we are recognizing “in music a resemblance to human emotional behavior through speech, gestures, and bodily movement.”

Page 12: “Emotion, Expressive Qualities, and Nature.” By Emily Brady-Zack Bosshardt.

Potential Problems with Similarity Theory

Similar, though not an exact translation or comparison – Given our particular human vocabulary of emotion, there may be some instances in which we cannot accurately describe an expressive quality in nature. “A particular emotional quality can be roughly analogous to some nameable human emotion, desolation for instance; but the precise quality of desolation revealed in some waste or desert in nature may be quite distinctive in timbre and intensity.”

Humans are quite different from nature - Nature can have certain expressive qualities that do not equate to a familiar human emotion. By attempting to equate human emotion with some expressive quality in nature, we can “overly humanize nature” which “overlooks nature’s own distinctive otherness.”

Page 13: “Emotion, Expressive Qualities, and Nature.” By Emily Brady-Zack Bosshardt.

Solution to this Problem?

Problem - We can attempt to describe nature in terms of its expressive qualities according to our human emotions and fail to encompass these qualities accurately.

Solution: Reciprocal Relationships - Reciprocally, nature can determine certain new categories for human emotion? (p.179) “…natural expression will influence our moods or determine them altogether, so that we reflect nature's qualities rather than the other way around.”

Example: We can experience in nature an expressive quality x, which will elicit a corresponding emotional response x in the appreciator. This does not appear to be different from the causal theory we’ve already dismissed. If there is something ‘distinctively other’ about nature, why are we trying to describe it in terms of human emotion?

Another Problem – Expressive qualities in nature whether they are caused or causal, can be ultimately reduced to human origins. The example of the stormy person.

Page 14: “Emotion, Expressive Qualities, and Nature.” By Emily Brady-Zack Bosshardt.

A Second Problem for Similarity Theory

Complexity of the Real World - The similarity theory focuses upon the non-aesthetic properties of an examined object, and thus does not “account for complex chains of association and belief.”

The quarry example – An outsider of the community would view the quarry as ugly in terms of its arrangement, but a community member knowing the appropriate cultural history would regard the quarry as a source of pride. Aesthetic judgments involve complex associations beyond the appearance of non-aesthetic properties which similarity theory does not account for.

Customs and social practices – Cultures can begin to associate particular non-aesthetic qualities (the appearance) of an object or landscape with a particular emotion and thus expressive quality. The quarry example is dependent upon customary associations. The other example is of the falling cherry blossoms in Japanese literature associated with sorrow.

Page 15: “Emotion, Expressive Qualities, and Nature.” By Emily Brady-Zack Bosshardt.

Embodiment Theories Used to Supplement Similarity Theory.

Embodiment account – suggests that environments embody history, emotions, memories and so on. An environment is not simply the configuration or arrangement of objects, but is within a larger context of associations.

The two-term account of expression – “Many instances of our aesthetic appreciation of nature are based upon this fusion between the object's sensuous surface and various associated facts such as scientific facts, historical or literary associations , or practical values.”

Page 16: “Emotion, Expressive Qualities, and Nature.” By Emily Brady-Zack Bosshardt.

“For example, we may appreciate the way in which the fierceness of a battle is reflected in a disfigured landscape with poor vegetation.”

Page 17: “Emotion, Expressive Qualities, and Nature.” By Emily Brady-Zack Bosshardt.

More on embodiment

Subjectivity and Individual vs. Community Associations – This is mentioned briefly and potentially is a worry. If an expressive quality in an environment is tied to associations, and since my associations may differ from someone else’s, then an expressive quality may be dependent upon the individual appreciator’s particular associations.

Carlson on embodiment – “For an object to express a quality or life value, the latter must not simply be suggested by it. Rather the quality must be associated with the object itself; that is, what Santayana meant by saying that the object must seem to embody that which it expresses. Clarified in this way, expression is not typically due to the unique associations resulting from an individual's own personal history.”

In short, associations are not found in the individual but are embodied in the object. The object of appreciation has factual associations that an individual may or may not be aware of.

Page 18: “Emotion, Expressive Qualities, and Nature.” By Emily Brady-Zack Bosshardt.

Criticism of Embodiment

My Criticism – which associations are appropriate, or most important in aesthetic appreciation? The environmentalist viewing the quarry vs. a community member viewing the quarry.

Brady’s Criticism - Although the embodiment account helps us address problems with similarity theory, like the quarry example, Brady says it may be too vague.

“What exactly does it mean to say that environments or objects are ‘drenched’ with emotions or images?” Brady concludes that although drenched and embodiment are metaphorical concepts, they give us a better way to understand expressive qualities in nature.

Page 19: “Emotion, Expressive Qualities, and Nature.” By Emily Brady-Zack Bosshardt.

Conclusion and Implications

Conclusion: “I have argued that the similarity account provides part of the answer to the problem of expressive qualities in nature but that it needs to be supplemented by the embodiment account.”

Practical Implications in Environmental Planning – Brady explains that her blending of similarity and embodiment theory to explain expressive qualities, combined with other aesthetic qualities that we’ve mentioned of imagination, emotion, and perception, give us a good vocabulary in discussions regarding conservation. (p. 182)