EJKM Volume 11 Issue 2

67
 Editorial for EJKM Volume 11 Issue 2 This is my first editorial, as I have just recently become the editor of the Electronic Journal of Knowledge Management, following a long period as a paper reviewer. I feel very honoured to be able to contribute to the continued success of our journal at a challenging time for t he KM discipline. While the field has evolved s ignificantly since its emergence in the early 1990s and attracted a high level of interest across both the academic and the practitioner communities, any comprehensive review of recent publications across the discipline might produce some sense of déjà vu, as many are concerned that limited progress is being made in the broader recognition of the discipline in the academic community and in the adoption of good KM practices. Thus, while we continue to solicit papers on any aspect of KM, we would especially encourage authors to consider contributing papers that can add rigour to the many theories in the discipline as well as those that can demonstrate successes in the practical application of theory in the field In this issue, we have six papers that provide interesting and contrasting insights. We have two theoretical papers (one revisiting the tacit explicit dimension, the other knowledge governance frameworks) three interesting case studies (examining graduate students personal knowledge, air force incident reporting and manufacturing firms’ external knowledge search) and a survey of the perspectives of more than 500 Basque CFOs on valuing intangible assets. Ilkka Virtanen’s In Search for a Theoretically Firmer Epistemological Foundation for the Relationship between Tacit and Explicit Knowledge  is an insightful revisitation of one of the most frequently used (and often abused) concepts in KM. Following a re- examination of the original work of Polanyi (1958) and the perspective provided by Nonaka and Takeuchi (1995), he proposes an improved epistemological model for tacit knowledge that should be of interest to most KM researchers. In another theoretical paper, David Johnson’s Governing Frameworks for Sharing  Actionable Knowledge  discusses the importance of context in KM activities and examines four alternate governance frameworks (formal, informal, markets, and professional) for interaction within organisations. Elaiza Benitez, David J Pauleen and Tony Hooper’s From Information Gatherers to knowledge creators: The evolution of the post-graduate student  examines the evolution of graduate students’ skills in personal information and personal knowledge management. It should be of interes t both to students en tering postgradua te studies and those who supervise graduate students. In  A Form to Collect Incident Reports: Learning from Incidents in the Swedish Armed Forces, Ulrica Pettersson provides an excellent and detailed case study in an unusual 116 

description

Knowledge management in post graduate

Transcript of EJKM Volume 11 Issue 2

  • Editorial for EJKM Volume 11 Issue 2

    This is my first editorial, as I have just recently become the editor of the Electronic

    Journal of Knowledge Management, following a long period as a paper reviewer. I feel

    very honoured to be able to contribute to the continued success of our journal at a

    challenging time for the KM discipline. While the field has evolved significantly since its

    emergence in the early 1990s and attracted a high level of interest across both the

    academic and the practitioner communities, any comprehensive review of recent

    publications across the discipline might produce some sense of dj vu, as many are

    concerned that limited progress is being made in the broader recognition of the

    discipline in the academic community and in the adoption of good KM practices.

    Thus, while we continue to solicit papers on any aspect of KM, we would especially

    encourage authors to consider contributing papers that can add rigour to the many

    theories in the discipline as well as those that can demonstrate successes in the

    practical application of theory in the field

    In this issue, we have six papers that provide interesting and contrasting insights. We

    have two theoretical papers (one revisiting the tacit explicit dimension, the other

    knowledge governance frameworks) three interesting case studies (examining graduate

    students personal knowledge, air force incident reporting and manufacturing firms

    external knowledge search) and a survey of the perspectives of more than 500 Basque

    CFOs on valuing intangible assets.

    Ilkka Virtanens In Search for a Theoretically Firmer Epistemological Foundation for the

    Relationship between Tacit and Explicit Knowledge is an insightful revisitation of one of

    the most frequently used (and often abused) concepts in KM. Following a re-

    examination of the original work of Polanyi (1958) and the perspective provided by

    Nonaka and Takeuchi (1995), he proposes an improved epistemological model for tacit

    knowledge that should be of interest to most KM researchers.

    In another theoretical paper, David Johnsons Governing Frameworks for Sharing

    Actionable Knowledge discusses the importance of context in KM activities and

    examines four alternate governance frameworks (formal, informal, markets, and

    professional) for interaction within organisations.

    Elaiza Benitez, David J Pauleen and Tony Hoopers From Information Gatherers to

    knowledge creators: The evolution of the post-graduate student examines the evolution

    of graduate students skills in personal information and personal knowledge

    management. It should be of interest both to students entering postgraduate studies

    and those who supervise graduate students.

    In A Form to Collect Incident Reports: Learning from Incidents in the Swedish Armed

    Forces, Ulrica Pettersson provides an excellent and detailed case study in an unusual

    116

  • and interesting environment, but one from which lessons can be generalised to many

    other situations where there is a need to capture experiential knowledge to improve

    subsequent performances of complex activities, such as incident reporting.

    In The Search for External Knowledge, Rebecca Purcell and Fergal McGrath take an

    Interpretivist approach in examining three Irish manufacturing firms to determine how

    they carried out external knowledge search, developing a practical framework for

    external search activities.

    Finally, Real Options in the Valuation of Intangibles: Managers Perception, by Beln

    Vallejo-Alonso, Gerardo Arregui-Ayastuy, Arturo Rodriguez-Castellanos and Domingo

    Garca-Merino, examines the challenges in financial valuation of intangible resources

    and examines a specific method for such an evaluation. Focusing primarily on SMEs in

    the Basque Country, they demonstrate the relevance of the method examined, while

    highlighting the very limited capacity of firms and their CFOs to under stand and apply

    the concept.

    These articles are a robust demonstration of the good work that is being done in the KM

    discipline. I trust readers will find them of interest and encourage all those interested in

    the KM field to consider our journal as a useful outlet for their work and would very

    much like to hear from those of you interested in making additional contributions to the

    journal, perhaps by acting as one of our paper reviewers.

    Ken Grant

    Ryerson University

    [email protected]

    117

  • ISSN 1479-4411 118 ACPIL

    V I In Search for a Theoretically Firmer Epistemological Foundation for the Relationship Between Tacit and Explicit Knowledge The Electronic Journal of Knowledge Management Volume 11 Issue 2 (pp118-126) available online at www.ejkm.com

    In Search for a Theoretically Firmer Epistemological Foundation for

    the Relationship Between Tacit and Explicit Knowledge

    Ilkka Virtanen

    School of Information Sciences, University of Tampere, 33014 University of Tampere,

    Finland

    [email protected]

    Abstract. Tacit knowledge has become one of the most used buzzwords in many scientific areas, especially in the area of

    knowledge management, during the past twenty years. In the mainstream of contemporary KM literature the concept of

    tacit knowledge has been brought in a relatively rough way alongside the traditional conception of knowledge (explicit

    knowledge) without further analysing the theoretical coherence of the resulting epistemology. Moreover, tacit knowledge

    T factors have led to puzzling or even internally contradictory epistemological views. We critically analyse the predominant

    epistemological views in the knowledge management literature from the theoretical perspective. We outline a

    P W although knowledge management is relatively new scientific area, its roots should be firmly grounded in the philosophical

    problems concerning knowledge if it is expected to present credible theories that could support knowledge management

    practices.

    Keywords: epistemology, explication, explicit knowledge, Polanyi, tacit knowledge, theory of knowledge

    1. Introduction

    For over two decades tacit knowledge and its relation to explicit knowledge have been widely discussed topics

    in the fields of management studies, information system science and particularly in knowledge management

    KM I P KM literature to the widely supported claim that organizations could achieve competitive advantages by using

    effectively their unique knowledge (see e.g. Nonaka and Takeuchi 1995). As a result, the focus of KM literature

    shifted from explicit forms of knowledge to softer and more complex resources of knowledge that were not

    stored in information systems but held in human minds. Since then hundreds of scientific papers and reports

    have presented possible procedures, models and theories for making tacit knowledge representable by

    converting it to explicit knowledge. The innermost aim of these suggestions is to harness valuable personal

    understanding and insights to common benefit in organizations.

    However, analysis of epistemic views discussing the relation between tacit and explicit knowledge, and

    particularly the ones that stress the importance of making tacit knowledge explicit, shows that the concept is

    often used in inconsistent, even misleading ways. According to Cowan et al (2000), very often the meaning of

    the concept itself remains literally tacit. Various authors (e.g. Grant 2007; Wilson 2002; Tsoukas 2003) have

    argued that the fundamental content of the concept has been misinterpreted. This suggests that the subject

    area is still inadequately studied.

    Conceptual clarity is not important only from the perspective of internal theoretical consistency of KM; KM is a

    multidisciplinary field of science, which means that it should communicate with other relevant fields of

    science. This naturally becomes difficult if central concepts adopted outside the field are redefined. Instead,

    theoretical statements from different disciplines should refer to the same set of phenomena (Bunge 1967).

    The focus of KM is evidently on the management and use of knowledge, which means that the area is above all

    practical. In this sense it may seem doubtful to introduce profound epistemological considerations to the

    practices of the field. However, the moment we begin to discuss theories of knowledge creation and

    explication of tacit knowledge we cannot avoid epistemological consideration because we have to know what

    we are theorizing about; from the scientific perspective the problem is significant because theories based on

    vague concepts are themselves vague and hence close to meaningless.

  • Electronic Journal of Knowledge Management Volume 11 Issue 2 2013

    www.ejkm.com 119 ACPIL

    The question about the relationship between tacit and explicit knowledge is important because it lies in the

    very heart of the KM theory. Although N T iginal theory has been revised and modified (see e.g. Nonaka and Peltokorpi 2007), the epistemological foundation (namely the classification of knowledge

    into tacit and explicit) of their original theory has gained a dominant role as the basis for epistemology in the

    KM theory (Maasdorp 2007 M N T the epistemological distinction between tacit and explicit knowledge has been so influential that even the

    whole field of KM has been defined basing on it. For example, according to different authors KM means

    ed process for acquiring, organizing, and communicating both tacit and explicit knowledge (Alavi and Leidner 1999: 6); T of explicit knowledge held in artefacts or as tacit knowledge possessed by individuals or

    S 63); knowledge asse C-Carrin 2006: 34).

    Theories can be considered as a systemization of practice, and as such they serve as a framework for making

    sense of the subject area. Respectively, indefinite theoretical frameworks may cause wider problems for the

    practices of the field by directing research to wrong lines. For example, technology developed to mine tacit

    knowledge of the users is of little value if it is unclear what exactly should be mined. Grant and Qureshi (2006)

    remark that many KM projects have stated as their aim the conversion of tacit to explicit knowledge, and

    storing and sharing it by developing proper ICT-systems for the purpose. These projects, however, often have

    had very limited success (Grant and Qureshi 2006). As Grant (2007) suggests, this might have very negative

    effects on organizations.

    Tacit knowled opposed to articulate, explicit knowledge (e.g. Nonaka and Takeuchi 1995; Baumard 1999; Steward 1997).We

    argue that one key factor behind the conceptual vagueness of the concept of tacit knowledge is the lack of

    profoundly studied epistemological foundation of the relation between tacit and explicit knowledge.

    Generally, the meanings of theoretical concepts are determined by the scientific theories in which they occur

    (Tuomela 1973). Accordingly, to attain a better theoretical understanding of tacit knowledge and its relation to

    explicit knowledge we have to go P and not just for picking up one concept but to assess the theory as a whole because not only the expression providing a definition of the concept but that

    entire theoretical context signifies the concept to be defined (Tuomela 1973).

    W P gical foundations upon which the theories of application of tacit knowledge rest-- P mentioned and referred basically by every author. The concept has been brought alongside with the

    traditional conception of knowledge, which leads to theoretical confusion as will be shown. We critically

    analyse the two epistemological theories (knowledge as tacit and explicit categories; knowledge as spectrum)

    that seem to have wide influence in the contemporary KM literature. Based o P sketch an epistemological model that aims to conceptual clarification of tacit and explicit knowledge and the

    relationship between the two. We examine in this work the components of which different conceptions of

    knowledge consist in order to compare them and to assess their internal consistency. The aim of this work is to

    point some flaws in the mainstream epistemic view of KM and present more coherent epistemological model,

    P

    2. Epistemologies of KM literature P Based on the foundations of positivist epistemology, the majority of the contemporary knowledge literature

    develops typologies that distinguish between different types of knowledge (Hislop 2005). The most common

    distinction, and also the one that we are interested in, is between tacit and explicit knowledge. This view can

    be considered significant because the most cited authors of knowledge management and intellectual capital

    literature1

    (e.g. Nonaka and Takeuchi 1995; Davenport and Prusak 1998; Steward 1997) embrace it, and many

    1 A B -review of knowledge management and intellectual capital literature that surveyed all

    citations of the topic (about 60 publications in total) in three major knowledge management journals (Journal of Intellectual Capital,

    Journal of Knowledge Management and Knowledge and Process Management.

  • Ilkka Virtanen

    www.ejkm.com 120 ISSN 1479-4411

    authors after them have adopted it (e.g. Johannessen et al 2000; Kikoski and Kikoski 2004; Seidler-de Alvis and

    Hartmann 2008). The tacit/explicit distinction came to prominence in KM literature through the work of

    N T M N T express the foundation of their epistemology clearly:

    I O s explicit knowledge, which can be articulated in formal language including grammatical statements, mathematical expressions,

    specifications, manuals and so forth. This kind of knowledge thus can be transmitted across

    Hever, we shall argue, a more important kind of knowledge is tacit knowledge, which is hard to articulate with formal language. It is personal knowledge

    embedded in individual experience and involves intangible factors such as personal belief,

    perspective, This view treats (explicit) knowledge in a traditional way, namely defining it as justified, true belief. For

    N T I adopt the tradit A view makes is that (explicit) knowledge is objective and discrete entity (Hislop 2005). As tacit knowledge is

    seen convertible into explicit knowledge, the most crucial KM process is to identify the sources of significant

    tacit knowledge and codify that tacit knowledge to explicit (Nonaka and Takeuchi 1995; Steward 1997; Kikoski

    and Kikoski 2004).

    However, this view has some theoretical problems, and we next discuss briefly the two most significant of

    them.

    First, Polanyi never said that there existed two types of knowledge ontologically although many authors claim

    so (e.g. Baumard 1996; Spender 1996; Jasimuddin et al. 2005). I P knowledge are related to two different kinds of awareness, subsidiary awareness and focal awareness respectively. The

    things that we are attending to and that we are consciously aware of (e.g. propositional belief, mental image,

    external object, read sentence etc.) belong to focal awareness. However, all focal awareness is dependent on

    subsidiary awareness that consists of variety of clues, elements and processes (personal knowledge structures,

    emotional processes, past experiences, motor responses etc.) that enable focal awareness giving rise to the

    personal meaning of its contents. This is the structure of all acts of knowing (Polanyi 1969). Hence, the focal

    object is always identifiable and in this sense explicit, whereas subsidiary content is unidentifiable, tacit. In

    addition, the two kinds of awareness are mutually exclusive; when the attention is switched to something

    hitherto subsidiary, it becomes focal losing its subsidiary meaning (Polanyi 1964). Most importantly, this tacit-

    explicit structure concerns all acts of knowing; tacit knowledge is not a separate category of knowledge but an

    integral component of all knowledge. Hence, to divide knowledge into two categories is not only

    P to knowledge. Also other authors have H W T G P L M which I P theory of knowledge, whose vital component the tacit dimension is. Tacit dimension is present in all knowledge.

    Second, the categorisation of knowledge into tacit and explicit and the idea of conversion of tacit knowledge

    into explicit knowledge leads to puzzling, even internally contradictory, overall epistemology. For example,

    Nonaka and Takeuchi (1995) originally saw rather unproblematic that something subjective and intangible (as

    they characterised tacit knowledge) became converted justified, objective and true belief. However, the

    process of explication (or externalization) does not explain how tacit knowledge becomes justified and true.

    T P hat specifically due to the tacit dimension of knowledge it could never be objective or fully justified.

    The epistemology that divides knowledge into two categories has also one practical constraint that does not

    coincide with our everyday experience. For example, I might be able to articulate reasons why I choose one

    option over another being, however, unable to exhaustively explain all the factors that have affected my

    choice. In this sense the described epistemological view is a rather rigid because knowledge is defined either

    - A definitions of these two categories of knowledge become unavoidably vague in the case of borderline

    instances of knowledge.

  • Electronic Journal of Knowledge Management Volume 11 Issue 2 2013

    www.ejkm.com 121 ACPIL

    It has been argued (e.g. Hislop 2005; Tsoukas 2003; Brown and Duguid 2001) that tacit-explicit dichotomy

    P I in a sense that it is a compromise between polanyian epistemology and traditional definition of knowledge,

    which leads to non-realistic epistemic view. Supposedly for these reasons this perspective has been afterwards

    modified to more workable theory of knowledge that recognizes the inseparability between tacit and explicit

    knowledge better but still supports the idea of sharing of tacit knowledge.

    The modified view is based on the idea that all knowledge exists on a spectrum (or continuum) that runs from

    tacit (uncodified) knowledge at one extreme to explicit (codified) knowledge at the other (Leonard and

    Sensiper 1998; Hall and Andriani 2003; Jasimuddin et al 2005). Leonard and Sensiper (1998) remark that most

    knowledge exists in between these two extremes, which is the main modification compared to the tacit-

    T P namely the idea that knowledge has both tacit and explicit dimensions. The position of knowledge on the tacit-

    explicit spectrum is then determined by its tacit-explicit mix (Jasimuddin et al 2005). This epistemic

    perspective2

    is described (as we understand it) in figure 1.

    Figure 1: Knowledge seen as a spectrum. According to this view knowledge-spectrum has tacit and explicit

    ends. Hence, any given instance of knowledge has a tacit part and an explicit part unless not taken from either

    of the ends

    However, as a theory of knowledge this view also has some illogical or at least unexplained features. First, the

    explicit pole of the knowledge P P of wholly explicit knowledge (because all knowledge is tacit or based on tacit knowledge, see Polanyi 1966).

    However, it would be obviously simple to modify the model and figure 1 so that in the explicit end knowledge

    only approached explicitness but the continuum ended before total explicitness. In fact, Leonard and Sensiper

    A ompletely H MA K as a spectrum where one extreme is seen as completely tacit and implicit knowledge and the other as

    completely explicit or codified knowledge It is an interesting question how different instances of knowledge then are situated in the continuum. For

    H A end. It might be possible to present scientific theories are anything but explicit; the theory of gravitation probably represents very different kind of

    things to a novice compared to its meaning to an experienced physicist based on their experiences and existing

    2 T -view, only described in a different manner. For example, Edwards (2009) presents

    knowledge as two circles with the tacit part as a smaller circle within the bigger, explicit circle. The size of the inner circle (tacit part) varies

    depending on the level of tacitness/explicitness of the particular instance of knowledge. Hence, the relational amounts of tacit and explicit

    parts of any instance of knowledge can be presented with this model in an analogical way to the way an instance of knowledge is

    T E um-view.

  • Ilkka Virtanen

    www.ejkm.com 122 ISSN 1479-4411

    knowledge structures, among others. Exactly this is the significance of the tacit dimension that enters into

    every act of knowingand why completely explicit end of the spectrum is not very realistic. Second, spectrum-view of knowledge also seems to lead to relatively sharp tacit-explicit dichotomy as many

    authors apply it as a background theory for sharing of tacit knowledge (e.g. Leonard and Sensiper 1998; Hall

    and Andriani 2003; Jasimuddin et al 2005). Let us observe any given instance of knowledge on a knowledge

    spectrum; it has a tacit and an explicit part. In order to share tacit knowledge we should codify it first (Nonaka

    and Takeuchi 1995; Hall and Andriani 2003). The process of codification means that tacit knowledge is

    converted explicit. Hence, a certain amount of the tacit part of that particular instance of knowledge would be

    replaced by explicit knowledge. This means that the proportion of explicit part to tacit part grows and hence,

    that particular instance of knowledge must shift towards the explicit end of the spectrum if the codification

    succeeds.

    Consequently, the same knowledge can exist in various points in the spectrum. In a logical sense this means

    that the same instance of knowledge can exist in various forms in the knowledge spectrum. Thus, a

    presupposition of the process of explication/externalization/codification of tacit knowledge always

    presupposes also two different forms (or categories) of knowledge. For example, Hall and Andriani (2003: 146)

    U C H C C T more or less the same knowledge of music can exist in two different forms of knowledge, tacit and explicit.

    Basically this leads back to categorization of knowledge and some kind of knower-independent, objective ideal

    of knowledgewhich, again, are issues that Polanyi wanted to criticise with the concept of tacit knowledge. Third, even if it were assumed that some tacit knowledge could be traced, supposedly most of it would remain

    hidden. This means that it is impossible to specify the amount of tacit knowledge that a given instance of

    knowledge includes. Following from that, it is also impossible to specify the location of any given instance of

    knowledge on the kn T - C view it takes into account that there nowledge. Besides that it does not seem to - M view makes it rather clear that tacit knowledge is dependent on knower and explicit knowledge is independent

    of knower, the spectrum-view does not provide very clear explanation of the role of the knower in the process

    of knowing. Evidently, tacit end and explicit end represent knower-dependent and knower-independent

    knowledge respectively, but what about the instances in between? Accordingly, the spectrum-model is argued

    to provide a unified conception of knowledge but it cannot explain what knowledge is. Hence, although it covers different types of knowledge, no supporters of this view have

    provided further explication of the nature of knowledge in general suggesting that the view has not been

    considered completely.

    3. Towards theoretically firmer epistemology

    We base our understanding of the nature of knowledge on the polanyian argument that knowledge requires

    active participation of the knower and is hence knower dependent. Knowing is an act of a particular individual.

    The claim that there is knowledge in itself, without a concrete knowing subject, is fantastic (Bunge 1974).

    Whenever however, carry for the most part information, which only a knowing mind can assimilate, understand and

    incorporate into its own knowledge structures (Wilson 2002). Despite the various ways to codify and store

    someone). When we know something, we engage in that what we know and cannot be neutral or indifferent

    in relation to it; we have no means to abstract the knowledge from our life and experiences by the means of

    which we understand that knowledge.

    If the knower dependency of all instances of knowing is accepted it means that the tacit dimension of knowing

    also enters in all types of knowledge as Polanyi argues; knowledge is represented in the mind of the knower

    and it is thus necessarily dependent on the processes and elements that take part in the forming of that

    representation. In this sense even an instance of knowledge that is presented in an explicit form (e.g. a note

    written on the paper) has a tacit dimension. The conscious representation in turn forms the explicit dimension

    of knowledge.

  • Electronic Journal of Knowledge Management Volume 11 Issue 2 2013

    www.ejkm.com 123 ACPIL

    It is important to bear in mind that knowledge presented in an explicit form can only be originated from a

    relatively clear representation in the mind; we can articulate and describe only things that we are conscious of

    L I P processes in subsidiary awareness. In this sense for example any proposition is equally explicit whether we

    read it, hear it said by another person or come to think it spontaneously by ourselves. The main point is that

    explicitness of knowledge does not refer only to the form in which a given instance of knowledge is presented;

    the clarity of knowledge and the way we regard it is not dependent on the form of presentation of that

    knowledge. Hence, in the epistemic sense explicitness refers to the coherence of knowledge, which in turn

    refers to origins and justifiability of the belief in question.

    In sum, given that knowing occurs within a human knower, all knowledge has necessarily a tacit dimension

    that refers to subconscious or otherwise subsidiary processes and elements that reflect the experiences of that

    particular knowing subject, but are also typical to any human cognition. As a result of the tacit factors the

    knower forms a focal conception of the matter, which represents more or less explicit knowledge. Hence, all

    instances of knowledge have tacit and explicit parts (Polanyi argued that all knowledge can be tacit, that is, an

    instance of knowledge that does not have an explicit part. However, in this case even the knower does not

    consciously know that he is knowing something tacitly and such a situation can be considered as a special case

    of knowing that simply cannot be commented on much). When this basic structure of knowledge is taken into

    account, knowledge can be further divided into categories in a suitable way (for example in a way adopted

    from psychological memory research: conditioned knowledge, semantic knowledge, episodic knowledge,

    procedural knowledge). Importantly, all categories in the model should manifest this structure. The basic

    structure of knowledge is described in figure 2.

    Figure 2: The structure of knowledge. Knowledge has a tacit part upon which the possible explicit part is

    founded.

    All instances of knowledge manifest this structure, even if knowledge is further categorized in a suitable way

    depending on the context. In this figure is presented an example of categorization adopted from the

    psychological memory research

    It is useful to relate this conception to the traditional definition of knowledge (knowledge as justified, true

    belief) in order to clarify it. The starting point of knowledge in the traditional definition is the belief; knowing

    something posits that the thing being known must be believed. However, according to this definition we must

    distinguish correct beliefs from incorrect ones. Thus, the belief must somehow correspond to the state of

    things in reality in order to be considered knowledge. This, however, is still not enough because for example a

    lucky guess could be interpreted to be knowledge. Therefore there has to be some grounds for holding a

    certain beliefthe belief must be justified. Indeed, traditional theory of knowledge as a branch of philosophy is most basically a theory about epistemic justification (Pollock and Cruz 1999).

    Whereas the traditional analysis of knowledge described above starts from the belief and the analyses

    P form the belief. In P . This idea is described in figure 3.

  • Ilkka Virtanen

    www.ejkm.com 124 ISSN 1479-4411

    Figure 3: T P K I P ief represent explicit knowledge. Tacit knowledge refers to belief forming factors that cannot be fully traced. In this sense tacit

    knowledge can be understood as an internal justification for the focal belief. Instead, the traditional approach

    to knowledge studies justification and truthfulness of propositional beliefs

    This view suggests that knowledge has two types of justification. External justification refers to justification in

    the traditional sense; the requirement to objective explanation/argumentation of how that belief has been

    attained. It is specifically related to the ability to publicly present evidence supporting a claim (Niiniluoto

    1999). Thus, (external) justification is directed at the belief or other form of representation that the knower

    holds. But all evaluations of beliefs derive from belief-forming processes (Goldman 1986). In this sense the

    idea of internal justification comes close to the basic argument of naturalized epistemology according to which

    epistemic status of a belief state depends on psychological processes that generate and sustain it (Kitcher

    1992). Accordingly, natural cognitive and physiological processes involved in the process of knowing refer to

    internal justification of the formed belief and cannot be bypassed in an analysis of knowledge. Instead of being

    particularly interested in the norms that justify human knowledge, Polanyi stressed the importance of

    confidence in human cognitive capacities in understanding reality.

    The epistemological conception presented above has considerable strengths compared to the two models

    predominant in the KM literature discussed in the section four. First, instead of simply picking up the concept

    P logical environment, P T P mainly because of considerably different conceptions of the requirement of justification of knowledge. Second, we express clearly the knower-

    dependency of knowledge. Every individual knows in his own way, from his basis. Interestingly, this has been

    originally the starting point of knowledge sharing but from the theoretical perspective the idea seems to get

    lost somewhere en route. Third, as other critics have also suggested tacit knowledge is narrower phenomenon

    that KM literature intimates in the sense that our narratives, beliefs, impressions etc. do not represent tacit

    capacity.

    4. Conclusions

    The predominant epistemological conceptions behind the relationship between tacit and explicit knowledge

    and the idea P theory. As a result, the epistemological foundations behind the tacit knowledge discussion tend to wake more

    questions than provide answers. This has led to confusion and inconsistency in the discourse concerning tacit

    knowledge and its relation to explicit knowledgeeven up to a point that some critics (e.g. Wilson 2002; Grant 2007) have claimed that the concept of tacit knowledge has become meaningless nonsense.

    The origin of the problem of conceptual vagueness is that the concept of tacit knowledge is taken from an

    epistemological environment that differs radically from the theoretical environment that it has been brought

    to. In order to get the concept function in the new context it has been interpreted very loosely. Moreover,

    given that one of most important functions of theoretical models (for example the models of explication of

  • Electronic Journal of Knowledge Management Volume 11 Issue 2 2013

    www.ejkm.com 125 ACPIL

    tacit knowledge) is to make predictions, it is obvious that models including poorly defined concepts make

    wider amount of predictions--up to a point at which the made predictions are anything but accurate, reliable

    or even very clear. Therefore not surprisingly, in the case of tacit knowledge it is somewhat simple to report

    positive results in the experiments concerning explication or externalization of tacit knowledge because some

    subjects regardless of the used method. Instead, a little attention seems to have been paid on the question, in

    T P KM understood traditionally as justified true belief simply is too narrow to explain human way to know and act in

    O P consideration of pre-logical phases of knowing that unavoidab P broadens the scope of knowledge as he accepts feelings and intuitions not only as valid but also as necessary

    P -dependency of knowledge (that knowledge is necessarily dependent on the subjective processes and elements that take part in the forming of the focal

    part of knowing) is also well justified from the psychological perspective.

    We have suggested a simple epistemological model that is in line with polanyian theory of knowledge. We

    argue that this model provides more coherent foundation for KM theory than the two epistemological views

    that are predominant in the contemporary KM literature. Given that tacit knowledge is inarticulate and

    inaccessible by definition, we suggest that in attempts to classify knowledge the focus should be on different

    crystallization of (focal) knowledge that is difficult to articulate. Hence, we would like to stress that our aim is

    not to criticize the goals and methods of knowledge sharing in general but to develop the aspects that are

    shown to be inconsistent in the present KM theory.

    References

    Alavi, M., Leidner, D. (1999) K M I C B Communications of the Association for Information Systems, vol 1, pp. 1-37.

    B P O F A I D K M B d Edmondson, A. (eds.), Organizational Learning and Competitive Advantage, London: Sage Publications Ltd.

    Baumard, P. (1999) Tacit Knowledge in Organizations, London: Sage Publications.

    B J D P K O A -P P Organization Science, vol 12, pp198 213.

    Bunge, M. (1967) Scientific Research I: The Search for System, Berlin: Springer-Verlag.

    Bunge, M. (1974) Treatise on Basic Philosophy, volume 1. Semantics I: Sense and Reference, Dordrecht: Reidel Publishing

    Company.

    Capeda-C G C A K M D Encyclopedia of knowledge Management. Hershey: Idea Group Reference, pp. 34-43.C D P F D T explicit Industrial and Corporate Change, vol 9, pp. 211-252.

    Davenport, T., Prusak L. (1998) Working Knowledge: How Organizations Manage What They Know. Cambridge: Harvard

    Business School Press.

    Edwards, J. (200 B P K M K-Pour, M. (ed.) Encyclopedia of Information Systems and Technology. Hershey: Idea Group Reference (second edition) pp. 471-476.

    Goldman, A. (1986) Epistemology and Cognition. Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1986.

    G K T W P The Electronic Journal of knowledge Management, vol 5, pp. 173-180.

    G K Q U K M W M F Innovations in Information Technology, November 2006, pp. 1-5.

    H A P M Journal of Business Research, vol 56, pp. 145-152.

    H T W E W I M T Knowledge: Towards a Better Understanding of the Shape of A Conference proceedings, 8th European Conference on Information Systems, Vienna, pp. 46-51.

    Hislop, D. (2005) Knowledge Management in Organizations A Critical Introduction. Oxford: Oxford University Press. J K J C C T

    Management Decision, vol 43, pp. 102-112. J J O J O B Mt of tacit knowledge: The importance of tacit knowledge,

    International Journal of Information Management, vol 21, pp. 3-20.

    Kikoski, C. and Kikoski, D. (2004) The Inquiring OrganizationTacit Knowledge, Conversation, and Knowledge Creation: Skills for 21st-Century Organizations, Portsmouth: Greenwood Publishing Group.

  • Ilkka Virtanen

    www.ejkm.com 126 ISSN 1479-4411

    K P T The Philosophical Review, vol 101, pp. 53-114. Ledoux, J. (2002) Synaptic Self: How Our Brains Become Who We Are, New York: Viking Penguin.

    L D T T K G I California Management Review, vol 40, pp. 112-132.

    Maasdorp, C. (2007) Concept and Context: Tacit Knowledge in Knowledge Management theory Schreinemakers, J., van Engers, T., (eds.), 15 Years of Knowledge Management: Advances in Knowledge Management, vol 3, Wrzburg:

    Ergon, pp. 59-68.

    MA M B MC J E Journal of Knowledge Management, vol 1, pp. 43-59.

    M N T KM Journal of Knowledge Management, vol 9, pp. 104-113.

    Niiniluoto, I. (1999) Critical scientific realism, New York: Oxford University Press.

    N I K N T B B F K C California Management Review, vol 40, pp. 40-54.

    N I P V T K A I J E T 15 Years of Knowledge Management, Advances in Knowledge Management, vol 3, Wrzburg: Ergon, pp. 68-82.

    Nonaka I. and Takeuchi H. (1995) The Knowledge-Creating CompanyHow Japanese Companies Create the Dynamics of Innovation, New York: Oxford University Press.

    Polanyi, M. (1964) Personal Knowledge: Towards a Post-Critical Philosophy (second edition), New York: Harper and Row.

    Polanyi, M. (1966) The Tacit Dimension, Garden City: Doubleday & Company.

    Polanyi, M. (1969) Knowing and Being, London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.

    Pollock, J. and Cruz, J. (1999) Contemporary Theories of Knowledge. Lanham: Rowman and Littlefield Publishers Inc.

    Refaiy, M. and L A T maintenance performance: an empirical study of UK A Knowledge Management Research & Practice, vol 7, pp. 277-288.

    Seidler- A H E T ledge management in Journal of Knowledge Management, vol 12, pp. 133-147.

    A B N M-Review of Knowledge Management and Intellectual Capital Literature: Citation Impact and Research Productivity Rankin Knowledge and Process Management, vol 11, pp. 185198.

    D C A K P D - Journal of Knowledge Management, vol 6, pp. 100-111.

    J C A T K M B E A Organizational Learning and Competitive Advantage, London: Sage Publications Ltd.

    Stacey, R. (2001) Complex responsive processes in organizations: Learning and knowledge creation. The introduction of the

    tacit-explicit distinction in the KM. London: Routledge.

    D T T K T Conference proceedings, 33rd Hawaii International Conference on System Sciences, Maui, pp.3020-3029.

    Stewart, T. (1997), Intellectual Capital: The New Wealth of Organizations. New York: Doubleday.

    T H D W U T K E-Smith, M. and Lyles, M. (eds), Handbook of Organizational Learning and Knowledge, Oxford: Blackwell.

    Tuomela, R. (1973) Theoretical Concepts, Wien: Springer.

    W T T Information Research, vol 5, paper no. 144.

  • ISSN 1479-4411 127 ACPIL

    J D Governing Frameworks for Sharing Actionable Knowledge The Electronic Journal of Knowledge Management Volume 11 Issue 2 (pp127-138) available online at www.ejkm.com

    Governing Frameworks for Sharing Actionable Knowledge

    J. David Johnson

    University of Kentucky, Lexington, USA

    [email protected]

    Abstract: A fundamental necessity for the transfer of actionable knowledge is that it must occur within a context. This

    essay suggests that governing frameworks provide the medium within which it becomes possible to share actionable

    knowledge. To support this claim the notion of governing frames is first explicated. Frameworks provide the basic support

    structures for sharing knowledge within organizations through the development of an inextricable linkage between context

    and meaning often found in the underlying foundation for governance structures. Each of the classic governing frameworks

    discussed, formal, informal, markets, and professional, has different manifestations of key structural elements,

    relationships, elements, context, configurations, and temporal stability and thus different implications for sharing

    knowledge. The strengths and weakness of the various frameworks for understanding the sharing of knowledge in

    organizations are exemplified by focusing on two exemplar problems: information seeking and clinical and translational

    science. In conclusion, the concept of governing frameworks offers a new way of looking at the often intractable problem

    of sharing knowledge in our ever more complex organizations. A compelling focus of future research is how these

    frameworks are negotiated in an increasingly professionalized world where specialists must integrate their activities in

    interprofessional teams.

    Keywords: organizational structure, governing frameworks, actionable knowledge, sharing, information seeking and clinical

    and translational science

    1. Governing frameworks for sharing actionable knowledge

    The absence of a role for context in organizational behavior not only leads to inadequate explanations for

    individual attitudes and behavior, but also makes it impossible to develop a common paradigm for micro and

    macro organizational research (Cappelli and Sherer, 1991, pp. 55).

    A fundamental necessity for the transfer of actionable knowledge is that it must occur within a context. In

    general, in conceptualizing our world, we have a tendency to focus on objects rather than their grounds

    (Stocking and Holstein, 1993), focusing on messages or individuals, for example, rather than the contexts

    within which they are embedded. We concentrate on the processes we are interested in rather than on the

    more diffuse social contexts that frame, embed, and surround them. This essay will focus, then, on the

    relationship between governing frameworks, one instantiation of context, and structure in shaping the sharing

    of actionable knowledge in organizations.

    Traditionally three senses of context have been used in organizational research (see Johnson, 2003, for more

    detail). First, context is seen as equivalent to the situation in which an individual is immersed, with situations

    viewed as more important in determining behaviors than individual traits or dispositions. Second, contingency

    approaches move toward specifying active ingredients that have specific, predictable effects on various

    processes. Third, major frameworks for meaning systems or interpretation are increasingly seen as critical to

    various processes. Since the first two of these senses have been extensively explored in the literature (e.g.,

    Johnson, 2003), here we will focus on the more recent developments concerning frameworks and governance

    structures, the mechanisms by which contexts are operationalized, and become real for organizational

    participants.

    Increasingly generating and manipulating knowledge is seen as a core function of our econ (MacMorrow, 2001, pp. 381). Greater knowledge intensity leads to greater profitability for commercial firms, higher levels of

    innovation and, ultimately, knowledge has become the source of wealth creation and economic growth

    (Florida and Cohen, 1999, Leonard, 1995, Stewart, 2001). This is critical for organizations, since knowledge

    becomes something you can do something with. As a result it often leads to strategic advantages since

    organizations who have the best understanding of their environment and then act on them accrue competitive

    advantages.

    Knowledge runs the gamut from information, to explicit knowledge, to tacit knowledge, to wisdom, with a

    variety of distinctions made between these terms in the literature. While there is a generally recognized

  • Electronic Journal of Knowledge Management Volume 11 Issue 2 2013

    www.ejkm.com 128 ACPIL

    ordering among these terms, with wisdom having the least coverage of the other sets, they are often used

    interchangeably and in conflicting ways in the literature, resulting in some confusion (Boahene and Ditsa,

    2003).

    experience (Leonard and Sensiper, 1998, pp. 113, italics in original).

    Knowledge is also something that is inherently social (Brown and Duguid, 1998, Barnett, 1988, Orlikowski,

    2002), bound to particular contexts (Barnett, 1988, Swan, 2003, Tsoukas and Valdimirou, 2001), and something

    that can be communicated to others, even if it may take considerable effort and require the development of

    mutually agreed upon symbols which is greatly facilitated by governance frameworks.

    Knowledge sharing (also termed diffusion, dissemination, transfer, and adoption) has been a compelling issue

    in a variety of areas including technology transfer between developed and developing nations, between

    organizations, and within organizations. Here I primarily focus on internal organizational transfer. Since

    knowledge transfer among organizational units can provide opportunities for learning, cooperation and

    creativity, it has been directly related to organizational innovation (Tsai, 2001), as well as a number of other

    organizational processes (Reagans and McEvily, 2003). To be effective, transfer implies a level of

    understanding that enables action (Jensen and Meckling, 1995). In this essay it is suggested that governing

    frameworks provide the medium within which it becomes possible to share actionable knowledge. Innovation

    diffusion is ultimately a social process of information seeking and transfer of ideas perceived as new such as in

    clinical and translational science problems discussed in concluding this essay.

    2. Frameworks as governance structures

    A frame, or the act of framing, usually refers to putting a perspective into words when one encodes a message

    (1979) providing, for example, a definition, meaning, or conceptualization of an issue in a conflict situation

    (Putnam and Holmer, 1992). The concept of framework has a long history in the social sciences (e.g., Schon

    and Rein, 1994, Tversky and Kahneman, 1981), especially in relation to discourse processes (Goffman, 1974).

    Frames have been viewed as inherently delimiting, providing individuals with a situated context for action and

    for interpretations of particular 'strips of activity' (Goffman, 1974).

    The concept of frames is most commonly used to indicate both a way of viewing the world and of subjectively

    interpreting it, acting as sense-making devices that establish the parameters of a problem (Gray, 1996). A

    fundamental property of communication is that interpretation depends on context. Frameworks are both

    windows on the world and lenses that bring the world into focus, at the same time they filter out some stimuli

    (Bolman and Deal, 1991). Often understandings attributable to various frameworks assume a taken-for-

    granted reality among interactants. Indeed, frameworks perform a number of critical functions for

    interactants: they are shared conversational resources; they provide a common emotional tone; they insure

    quicker responses; and they also provide a basis for temporal stability by insuring more continuous responses

    (Collins, 1981, Benson, 1975).

    Here the focus will be on governance frameworks that provide a more encompassing context for interaction

    within organizations. A framework for interaction is the set of interrelated conditions that promoting certain

    levels of shared understanding of meanings, orient interactants to the nature of the event, and establish the

    ultimate purpose of continuing interaction (Johnson, 1997b, Johnson, 1998). A framework, then, is the ground

    that opens doors to social worlds of situated knowledge and governing rationalities. Frameworks provide the

    basic support structures for sharing knowledge within organizations through the development of an

    inextricable linkage between context and meaning often found in the underlying foundation for governance

    structures.

    3. Governance structures

    Governance implies the imposition of order by a common authority by allocating legal or quasi-legal

    entitlements and obligations (MacKechnie & Donnelly-Cox, 1996, pp. 46).

    Structural research has been a primary focus of research on transfer and it has been centrally concerned with

    F social systems whose members are more closely linked by communication networks have a stronger diffusion

  • David Johnson

    www.ejkm.com 129 ISSN 1479-4411

    (Rogers, 2003, p. 235). Structure determines what is possible in large organizations since it enables action within a governance framework. Without a predictable

    pattern of recurring relationships, coordinated activity, such as knowledge transfer, within the organization

    would be impossible. The more constraints that exist, the more things occur in predictable patterns; the more

    people know about their organization. Extensive reviews of the prior literature on structure has identified five

    common elements in most of its definitions; relationships, entities, configurations, context, and temporal

    stability (Johnson, 1992, Johnson, 1993) H configuration of communication relationships between entities within an organizational context" (Johnson,

    1992, pp. 100).

    As Table 1 details each of the governing frameworks we will discuss, formal, informal, markets, and

    professional, has different manifestations of these key structural elements. As detailed below, each of these

    frameworks has been separately developed within different theoretical traditions. Johnson (1997b, 1998,

    2009) has then integrated them by developing scales associated with them for empirical tests, applied them to

    case studies, and articulated their relationships to managing knowledge networks.

    Table 1: Relationships between structural elements and governance frameworks

    Governance Frameworks*

    Structure

    Elements

    Formal Informal Markets Professional

    Relationships Hierarchical Sentiments Exchanges Normative

    Entities Positions People Traders/Brokers Professionals

    Context Rules System Social/Personal/

    Climate

    Embeddedness Practice Standards

    Configuration Organizational

    Chart

    Sociogram Bazaar Guild/clan

    Temporal

    Stability

    Equivalent to

    O Limited Dynamic Generations,

    Common Law

    Knowledge Rules Emotional

    Intelligence

    Explicit Tacit

    *(Johnson, 2009, pp. 62)

    A formal approach was the earliest systematic specification of the underlying basis for interaction within

    organizations and in many ways the other frameworks were established in opposition, or counterpoint, to it

    (Johnson, 1993). In fact, informal communication studies, the precursors to the modern interest in

    communication networks, became a residual category including a wide array of potential frameworks (e.g.,

    sentiments, informal influence, and so on) for interaction. Thus, exchange rests on individuals pursuing their

    rational self-interest common to markets, while normative frameworks depend on operations of larger

    collectivities most clearly represented in the professions. The introduction of tacit knowledge also suggests a

    need for the more explicit introduction of culturally related normative elements captured most clearly in the

    professions. Let us know turn to a more explicit discussion of these four governing frameworks.

    3.1 Formal

    Administrative rationality in the Weberian sense has always been a central concern of the formal approach

    (e.g., Thompson, 1967) and with it has come the assumption that structures are designed to control behavior

    in such a way as to produce efficient/effective operations (Pfeffer, 1978), controlling competitive instincts to

    produce cooperative behaviors. Thus structures are conceived as fitting into a rational plan, rather than

    viewed as representing rationality after the fact (Weick, 1969).

    Formal frameworks essentially represent the bureaucratic world of the organization, with its specification of

    patterns of super- and sub-ordination and other hierarchical relationships between positions in a relatively

    permanent system of rules (Weber, 1947). An hierarchy provides a framework for action by specifying control

    patterns, routinizing production, and implementing plans (McPhee, 1988). The kinds of behavior individuals

    can engage in are specified in company manuals and output targets are detailed in formal performance reports

  • Electronic Journal of Knowledge Management Volume 11 Issue 2 2013

    www.ejkm.com 130 ACPIL

    (Baliga and Jaeger, 1984), laying the ground work for much of the common explicit knowledge with the

    organization. Usually formal frameworks require only a limited form of knowledge, based on system rules,

    training, and a legalistic understanding of relationships between positions best exemplified by the

    configurations embodied in the organizational chart. Actors are presupposed to be driven, or motivated, by

    the requirements of the positions they occupy within a specified organizational chart.

    Knowledge transfer in formal structures is best accomplished if couched within this relatively limited frame

    which is especially conducive for sharing explicit, organizationally sanctioned knowledge. Often formal

    structure codify in rigid rules who is responsible for sharing knowledge and how it can be transmitted.

    3.2 Informal

    Often interaction results in collective sentiments; thus, friendship and other more emotional bases for

    relationship then provide the underlying basis for ties between people. Traditionally this has been cast as a

    primary basis for informal communication structures. The shared understandings characteristic of these

    relationships are often dependent on the depth of emotional involvement. Sentiments recognize the often

    neglected place of emotions (Mumby and Putnam, 1992) and the desire for affiliation in organizational life.

    The degree of affiliation felt between interactants determines the temporal stability of relationships which can

    be fleeting and the degree to which parties' sentiments may override other bases for relationships, such as

    exchange.

    Knowledge transfer within this governing frame often depends on sophisticated understanding of the climate

    of the social system embodied in a high level of emotional intelligence. This level of understanding is essential

    to minimizing resistance and overcoming the uncertainty that is often associated with the change that

    knowledge sharing entails.

    3.3 Markets

    Recently, yet another view of structure, a market approach, which shares much with both network and formal

    approaches, and rests on economic and exchange assumptions, has emerged. Markets focus on exchange

    relationships between traders or brokers (see Table 1) and the paramount importance of trust often emerging

    from actors embedded in social systems in characterizing them (Kirman, 2001, Granovetter, 1985, Johnson,

    1996) which has led to social capital perspectives on brokerage relations (Sawyer et al., 2003). In this view

    individuals are seen as driven to maximize rewards through their interaction with each other.

    Obviously, an exchange relationship can rest on extremely rudimentary understandings of others, based on

    such fundamental issues as fair price and trust that the other party will follow through on bargains.

    Relationships are seen from a utilitarian perspective, with the primary bases for continued relationships

    resulting from a perception of mutual gain creating dynamic changes in social systems depending on changing

    rewards. Indeed, we may seek exchanges with others because they are not like us and they have resources

    that we do not possess.

    Networks of explicit information exchanges, which also contain market elements, are particularly useful

    structures for organizations composed of highly skilled work forces who possess knowledge not limited to

    particular tasks (Powell, 1990). Indeed, more generally it has been argued that knowledge sharing may be best

    accomplished by market-like structures because of problems in recognizing the significance of information and

    communicating it effectively and efficiently (Gupta and Govindarajan, 1991). This form of decentralization

    often reduces the possibility of information overload within these organizations, and attendant delays and

    imperfect planning orders. Thus, in organizations like universities it may be better to minimize intrusive formal

    structures and promote wide-ranging interactions, while providing a framework in which trading relationships

    can occur, much like ancient bazaars.

    3.4 Professional

    Modern expertise comes partly at the expense of narrowness, and of ignorance about what other people do

    (Becker and Murphy, 1992, pp. 1146).

  • David Johnson

    www.ejkm.com 131 ISSN 1479-4411

    I T e (Polanyi and Prosch, 1975, pp. 204). These professions come together in organizations to pursue loosely defined larger objectives (e.g., universities and the pursuit of knowledge). Relationships

    between and among professions are often governed by such normative expectations (Cheney and Ashcraft,

    2007). Professionals reinforce normative isomorphism in institutional theory terms, where all firms come to

    act in the same manner, especially under conditions of uncertainty where mimicry is often the safest course

    (Mizruchi and Fein, 1999). Unfortunately little theoretic attention has been focused on professionals (Lammers

    and Garcia, 2009, Pratt et al., 2006), especially on their interrelationships and micro level processes in

    organizations (Chreim et al., 2007), such as knowledge transfer, so we will discuss them in somewhat greater

    detail than the other frames here.

    Most work on the professions has focused on how they establish (and protect) their jurisdictions and maintain

    their status within broader social systems. Knowledge is seen as a key tool in these processes (Lammers and

    Garcia, 2009, Abbott, 1988, Macdonald, 1995) bodies of knowled (Larson, 1977, pp. xi), and thus is an incidental focus of traditional research. Knowledge is intimately related with credentialing and training and

    the formal (and often legally, state enforced) differentiation of specialties in societies generally and

    organizations specifically (Macdonald, 1995). Relatedly, the development of tacit knowledge plays a key role in

    distinguishing professionals (Larson, 1977) and their relative competence (Schon, 1983). So, intraprofessional

    status often results from the ability of a profession to do non-routine work (Abbott, 1981) to apply old knowledge in new ways to solve novel or unforeseen problems.

    Over the last three decades cultural factors, which norms encapsulate, have assumed a central place in our

    theories of organizations. Culture is seen as providing an interpretive framework within which communication

    is possible; a macromedium for interaction (Johnson, 1993). Perhaps nowhere in our society is socialization

    more intensive than in the preparation of a professional with societies often delegating enforcement of

    practice standards to professional bodies. They, in turn, jealously guard their prerogatives, especially in

    relation to knowledge claims in specific areas (Cheney and Ashcraft, 2007), since these claims often define

    what the profession is and its relative status (Abbott, 1988). Their natural reluctance to share professional

    knowledge is further exacerbated by the more general reluctance to share knowledge with others if they are

    thought incapable of understanding it (Hew and Hara, 2007).

    A key element of this socialization is the development of elaborate semantic systems of tacit understandings

    (von Hayek, 1945) that are difficult to share. The more elaborate and refined the framework, the more

    effective the communication within the profession (and that much more difficult outside of it). An advantage

    of strong cultures is their enhancement of shared understandings between actors and a norm of adjustment

    through consultation within a system of mutual authority that governs competition (Polanyi and Prosch, 1975).

    Clan controls result in high goal congruence and common interests, most appropriate when transformation

    processes are imperfect and measures of outcomes are low (Turner and Makhija, 2006). Interaction

    configurations are also provided with a normative base that expresses the underlying cultural values. This

    strong emphasis on socialization of succeeding generations reinforces the temporal stability associated with

    professions on a near common law accretion of knowledge.

    Nonaka (1991) developed a more dynamic, interactive approach to these issues focusing on the implications of

    the spiral of knowledge and its articulation (converting tacit to explicit) and internalization (using explicit to

    T ion to develop insights into deeper problems (e.g., financial trends) then articulate them, as financial brokers do, to specific

    buy and sell recommendations for their clients. However, once true expertise is developed, the professional

    may have a very difficult time translating it for the novice or generalist (Hinds and Pfeffer, 2003). Professions

    (Abbott, 1981).

    Expert knowledge does depend on the application of traditional knowledge to which the seeker is in many

    ways a servant. The freedom of members of these communities rests on certain obligations and systems of

    mutual authority that also entail personal judgments (e.g., scientists making hypotheses, lawyers preparing

    briefs). This process is accorded respect by society and certain things are left to communities of specialists to

    pursue; the mutual adjustment of these specialists then determine the ultimate directions of the societies of

  • Electronic Journal of Knowledge Management Volume 11 Issue 2 2013

    www.ejkm.com 132 ACPIL

    which they are a part. Mutual adjustment depends in turn on consultation or, in the case of business,

    competitive forces. However, this system of spontaneous order has several limits: one, the public good can be

    surrendered to these personal judgments; two, society is ruled by a privileged oligarchy; and, three, it can drift

    in directions determined by no one (Polanyi and Prosch, 1975).

    Some more cynical observers of the professions suggest that perhaps the most powerful motivation for

    doctors and lawyers to keep up-to-date is the ever present threat of a malpractice suit (Paisley, 1993). Most

    other professions do not have similarly compelling external motivations to keep current; they do not have

    sanctions for 'remediable ignorance,' for actions which duplicate or overlook existing knowledge (Paisley,

    1980). These professions can in effect conspire to say it is pointless to try to keep up. They also have

    substantial interests in the preservation of personal knowledge unique to their professions by insuring there

    are heavy information costs to memberships in their priesthood, discouraging intermediation. However, never

    has secret knowledge been more accessible to those who are interested in it.

    3.5 Negotiated order

    The forgoing frameworks are ideal types. It is possible for an individual to act with others with their unique mix

    of the forgoing frames, to choose among themselves what frame (or combination of frames) will govern their

    interactions. It is also possible for two interactants to decide mutually on an idiosyncratic basis for interaction

    (Nathan and Mitroff, 1991). This possibility creates the underlying conditions for change (Strauss, 1978).

    Indeed, the absence of a dominating frame, or the lack of rigid specification when one or another applies,

    creates the possibility of flexibility within an organization.

    So two parties communicate with each other to arrange the nature of their future interaction by mutual

    agreement. This negotiation is designed to establish a stable ordering of the relationship governing

    interactions within it, to move to a state where the underlying base for the interaction is taken-for-granted. At

    times this negotiation might be explicit, verging on contractual terms, at other times it might grow out of

    ongoing interactions.

    4. Discussion

    Within organizations, governance frameworks differentially impact knowledge transfer. Formal structures tend

    to lessen contact and contracting costs, but may not be very efficient at finding the optimal price. There is also

    a quite natural human tendency to exercise ever more control when performance problems are experienced,

    which may (Williamson, 1994, pp. 91). Informal approaches focus on the emotional impact of knowledge sharing focusing

    on issues such as potential points of resistance. Strong professional norms can severely restrict the content

    and interactants available to individuals, but interestingly, because of the increased sophistication of shared

    understandings, they can enhance the effectiveness of knowledge transfer. They also can improve efficiency

    by clearly delineating roles and relationships. In contrast, exchange based transfer have few barriers, but

    limited breadth and only moderate levels of effectiveness and efficiency, in part because of the differential

    understanding levels of the parties.

    In general, it has been argued that there are three approaches to organizational phenomenon (Lee et al., 2004,

    Ferratt et al., 2005): universalistic; contingency, and configurational which focuses on bundles of attributes

    that exhibit synergestic, nonlinear effects on outcomes. This focus on commonly occurring clusters of

    attributes which can be linked to performance (Lee et al., 2004) is also linked to the classic system concepts of

    equifinality (Gresov and Drazin, 1997). By focusing on sets of practices, with the adoption of one limiting the

    adoption of others because of complementarity/fit/gestalt issues. Gestalts are feasible sets of internally

    consistent configurations, with research findings suggesting configurational approaches are more predictive of

    outcomes than others (Lee et al., 2004). For example, Andersen and Segars (2001) found that IT enhancing

    communication supported a decentralized decision structure that was associated with higher financial

    performance. Each of the governance frameworks can be seen as relating as a configuration to a variety of

    different organizational outcomes such as knowledge sharing. In this section we will focus on the issues of

    what types of knowledge can be shared and where it might come from, then we turn to two exemplars of

    these processes, clinical and translational science and information seeking.

  • David Johnson

    www.ejkm.com 133 ISSN 1479-4411

    The critical knowledge that is the focus of transfer in formal settings is a set of rules and routines that can form

    the basis for information processing. In informal governance structures knowledge of personal affiliations and

    coalitions is critical to determining the political acceptance of different types of knowledge. Markets are best

    suited for the transference of knowledge as a commodity that most often takes on explicit, limited forms,

    although in certain situations it may have special significance, somewhat akin to insider trading, because of the

    ability of one of the parties to use it for their unique benefit. Finally, professional knowledge is often tacit

    based on years of experience and as a result difficult to transfer. In addition, professionals often jealously

    guard their secrets and are reluctant to share them with outsiders.

    This quick sketch also raises some interesting issues of where new perspectives come from and what is the

    nature of the knowledge that is transferred. Interestingly, the first three frameworks focus on the processes by

    which knowledge might be shared, while professional knowledge is also concerned with this in developing a

    unique approach to problems, it also deals with content more directly. So, fundamentally, these frameworks

    provide the overall institutional frame in which knowledge can be shared. One of the reasons why transfer has

    proved so difficult is that they must all be operating in concert with each other. Thus agents are needed to

    facilitate transfer of tacit knowledge who operate simultaneously within several frames, a key role for

    management in the modern organization (Postrel, 2002).

    One of the basic problems with relying exclusively on what goes on within an organization is that there is a

    finite limit to the number of new ideas that can be produced from the same elements of a knowledge set

    (Katila and Ahuja, 2002). Professions play a unique role in determining where is it substantive change within

    organizations comes from. In many ways strong professions transcend particular organizations and make their

    boundaries more permeable. Membership in a profession provides access to a much larger, scalable tacit

    knowledge community outside the organization (Lammers and Garcia, 2009). These much broader tacit

    networks, especially associated with professional institutions, become the primary vehicle for external learning

    (Lammers and Garcia, 2009, Van der Krogt, 1998). This is a key shortcoming of the other approaches to

    governance which primarily focus on what happens within the firm

    Professionals seek answers to their questions wherever they may easily be available, whether inside or outside

    the organization. Indeed, professional membership is likely to diminish organizational identification (Lammers

    and Garcia, 2009). Sophisticated search agents and brokers only accelerate this trend. This is a unique

    advantage of a professional framework - they are scalable, they bring the world outside in (Newman et al.,

    2006), becoming a more modern version/extension of the classic cosmopolitan/local distinction (Gouldner,

    1957).

    The relationships between diverse professional groupings, who jealously guard their domains, is an

    increasingly critical problem, particularly in health care settings (Clark, 2006, DA ). P onal autonomy and (Sicotte et al., 2002). However, balancing cooperation and competition must be achieved, most notably in sharing information that is in the

    interest of the collective, in spite of individual motivations to hoard (Kalman et al., 2002). The greater effort

    that is devoted to specialization, which implies you benefit from the work of others, the more reluctant

    someone will be to give up what they know, especially to perceived free riders. Some have suggested that the

    best motivator for knowledge sharing is a sense of collectivism and reciprocity (Hew and Hara, 2007).

    4.1 The clinical and translational science problem

    There is a widely held view that the U.S. is not receiving the full value for its investment in biomedical research

    (Colditz et al., 2008, Real, 2008, Lee, 2007). While there are over 10,000 randomized trials of new intervention

    approaches every year, very few innovations are ever widely adopted (Grol and Grimshaw, 2003). Drug

    companies have also expressed concern about the length of time it takes for their investments to pay off and

    their low success rate, with only 1 in nine compounds eventually achieving government regulatory approval

    (Berelson and Steiner, 1964). While there has been growth in evidence reviews that inform practice there also

    is a growing gap in their implementation (Colditz et al., 2008). Of course, this is emblematic of a larger problem

    in translating research into professional practice common to many disciplines including communication,

    management (Reay et al., 2009), and information science (Garnett, 2011).

  • Electronic Journal of Knowledge Management Volume 11 Issue 2 2013

    www.ejkm.com 134 ACPIL

    Clinical and Translational Science Institute's began to be funded by NIH in 2006. They were established to be

    the home for clinical research within Academic Health Centers and to improve their resource base by

    establishing linkages to industry and other health care organizations enhancing the level of community

    engagement, while at the same time increasing the control of NIH over their direction (Robertson and

    Williams, 2009). They are also designed to provide the critical infrastructure needed for traditional academic

    training and linkages to clinical research resources (Robertson and Williams, 2009). The key problem faced

    AHC

    The reasons why it takes nearly two decades to transfer knowledge into routine medical practice are complex

    and still poorly understood (Sussman et al., 2006). Changes in practice are rarely easy and require

    collaborations between disciplines in very complex systems (Grol and Grimshaw, 2003). In the 1970s and 80s,

    in recognition of the difficulties in knowledge translation, the dominant conceptual model came to focus on

    the inherent differences between research and policymaking communities with the two communities theory

    stressing that the inherent differences between them were often intractable (Jacobson et al., 2003).

    Translational research often demands that there be communication across disciplines, which often runs into

    basic problems that scientist have in communicating well with people from the practice community (Sussman

    et al., 2006).

    If we apply the framework of governance structures to this problem we can easily see why it has proved so

    intractable. First, AHC have a layering of formal bureaucracy that constrains many research processes (e.g.,

    human subjects protections, animal usage, and so on). Then, we have an informal structure governed by

    sentiments and political coalitions that can prove difficult to negotiate and which is particularly important

    traditionally for physicians who often place more weight on reputational standing of their colleagues in

    adopting new practices than on bureaucratic dicta. Next, we have market exchanges and the inevitable

    question of what is in it for me and who can I trust. Finally, we have the strong, compelling normative interests

    of a multiplicity of professions. In some ways, all of these forces need to be aligned for successful

    implementation, although adoption and creation may only depend on one. So new ideas are created, but it

    may take nearly two decades to align all the frameworks.

    When moving from the bedside to the community we face the additional problem that these factors become

    even more diffuse, since the formal structures of government regulations and insurance guidelines is not

    bolstered by the bureaucracy of the AHC. Further market relations and sentiments become much more diffuse

    and fractured, so the only constant is the professional framework within which practice is embedded. All this

    makes the information sharing and seeking components more critical for widespread practice implementation.

    4.2 Information seeking

    Not only to people initiate sharing of information they possess with others, which has been the primary focus

    of the literature on knowledge sharing, but individuals often initiate sharing on their own based on their

    perceived needs. In doing this they must decide on the objects of their searches. Will a health professional

    who needs information seek it from the formal structure of the organization, will they depend on friends, will

    they exchange their knowledge with other health professions in teams, or will they rely on the advice of

    colleagues in their own profession.

    Sadly, in a series of studies, Hersh has demonstrated that the information seeking practices of health

    professionals are very problematic which further impedes effective sharing. So, an experimental study by

    Hersh, Crabtree et al. (2002) showed that students of medicine and nursing were only partially successful in

    applying the results of medical database searches to clinical questions. Subjects did the best in interpreting the

    implications of medical literature for prognosis, and worst in applying retrieved documents to questions of

    diagnosis and potential harm to the patient. An earlier analysis by Hersh (1998) of existing studies concluded

    that literature searches exhibit poor recall of potentially relevant items, their results typically address only a

    small port retrieval for medical doctors are unclear.

    Johnson (1996, 1997a) has summarized the basic approach to information seeking of individuals with Case

    (2012) in a more recent review making very similar arguments. First, people seek out information that is the

    most accessible. However, second, having access to information means very little if an individual does not have

  • David Johnson

    www.ejkm.com 135 ISSN 1479-4411

    the proper information seeking skills and training to retrieve it. Third, people follow habitual patterns in their

    information seeking. Fourth, face-to-face, interpersonal communication is the preferred mode of

    communication for information seeking. This creates some real problems of scale when people move outside

    of the physical proximate setting of AHC. Fifth, different types of persons use different sources of information.

    This is further reinforced in medical setting by professional norms and standards of care which may differ

    somewhat from profession to profession in a health care team. Finally, there are cognitive limits on the

    amount of information individuals can process, especially in short term memory. All of this is further

    complicated by the near chaotic framework typical of modern health care with multiple frameworks and

    players within each of them coming into play (Lawrence, 2002).

    5. Conclusion

    The corporations take on the task of putting appropriate specializations together to exploit the synergistic

    advantages thus accruing. The business executive becomes (Fuller, 2010/1962, pp. 80).

    As this quote suggests the problem of bringing together different professions to share knowledge has been

    with us for a long time with Fuller maintaining that Alfred North Whitehead early in the 20th

    century traced it

    to the increasingly specialized training of professionals at our universities. This created what was termed the

    Whitehead Dilemma of ever deepening problems. So, a compelling focus of future research is how these frameworks are negotiated in an increasingly

    professionalized world where specialists must integrate their activities in interprofessional teams.

    Managers need tacit knowledge, deep understanding for fundamental change, but this knowledge is

    supported by existing frameworks and various inertial forces. This can result in coalitions and power struggles,

    which often are a by-product of tacit knowledge. A key social outcome of more specialized tacit knowledge is

    the problems of concertative control resulting in conformity and influence within groups which makes

    intergroup action much more difficult. While we need the support of others, they also limit our action.

    References

    1979. American Heritage Dictionary Of The English Language, Boston, Houghton Mifflin.

    Abbott, A. 1981. Status And Strain In The Professions. American Journal Of Sociology, 86, 819-835.

    Abbott, A. 1988. The System Of Professions: An Essay On The Division Of Expert Labor, Chicabo, University Of Chicago

    Press.

    Andersen, T. J. & Segars, A. H. 2001. The Impact Of It Decision Structure On Firm Performance: Evidence From The Textile

    And Apparel Industry. Information And Management, 39, 85-100.

    Baliga, B. R. & Jaeger, A. M. 1984. Multinational Corporations: Control Systems And Delegation Issues. Journal Of

    International Business Studies, 14, 25-40.

    Barnett, G. A. 1988. Communication And Organizational Culture. In: Goldhaber, G. N. & Barnett, G. A. (Eds.) Handbook Of

    Organizational Communication. Norwood, N. J.: Ablex.

    Becker, G. S. & Murphy, K. M. 1992. The Division Of Labor, Coordination Costs, And Knowledge. Quarterly Journal Of

    Economics, Cvii, 1137-1160.

    Benson, J. K. 1975. The Interorganizational Network As A Political Economy. Administrative Science Quarterly, 20, 229-249.

    Berelson, B. & Steiner, G. A. 1964. Human Behavior: An Inventory Of Scientific Findings, New York, Harcourt, Brace &

    World.

    Boahene, M. & Ditsa, G. 2003. Conceptual Confusions In Knowledge Management And Knowledge Management Systems:

    Clarifications For Better Kms Development. In: Coakes, E. (Ed.) Knowledge Management: Current Issues And

    Challenge. London: Irm Press.

    Bolman, L. G. & Deal, T. E. 1991. Reframing Organizations: Artistry, Choice, And Leadership, San Francisco, Jossey-Bass.

    Brown, J. S. & Duguid, P. 1998. Organizing Knowledge. California Management Review, 40, 90-111.

    Cappelli, P. & Sherer, P. D. 1991. The Missing Role Of Context In Ob: The Need For A Meso-Level Approach. Research In

    Organization Behavior, 13, 55-110.

    Case, D. O. 2012. Looking For Information, Bingley, Uk, Emerald Group Publishing.

    C G A K L C T P I C tudies: Implications For Theory And Research Within And Beyond The Boundaries Of Organizational Communication. Communication Theory, 17, 146-

    175.

    Chreim, S., Williams, B. E. & Hinings, C. R. 2007. Interlevel Influences On The The Reconstruction Of Professional Role

    Identity. Academy Of Management Journal, 50, 1515-1539.

    Clark, P. G. 2006. What Would A Theory Of Interprofessional Education Look Like? Some Suggestions For Developing A

    Theoretical Framework For Team Work Training. Journal Of Interprofessional Care, 20, 577-589.

  • Electronic Journal of Knowledge Management Volume 11 Issue 2 2013

    www.ejkm.com 136 ACPIL

    Colditz, G. A., Emmons, K. M., Vishwanath, K. & Kerner, J. F. 2008. Translating Science To Practice: Community And

    Academic Perspectives. Journal Of Public Health Management Practice, 14, 144 -- 149.

    Collins, R. 1981. On The Microfoundations Of Macrosociology. American Journal Of Sociology, 86, 984-1014.

    D D F-Videla, M., Rodriguez, L. S. M. & Beaulieu, M. D. 2005. The Conceptual Basis For Interprofessional Collaboration: Core Concepts And Theoretical Frameworks. Journal Of Interprofessional Care, Supplement 1, 116-131.

    Ferratt, T. W., Agarwal, R., Brown, C. V. & Moore, J. E. 2005. It Human Resource Management Configurations And It

    Turnover: Theoretical Synthesis And Empirical Analysis. Information Systems Research, 16, 237-255.

    Florida, R. & Cohen, W. H. 1999. Engine Or Infrastructure? The University Role In Economic Development. In: Branscomb,

    L. M., Kodoma, F. & Florida, R. (Eds.) Industrializing Knowledge: University-Industry Linkages In Japan And The United

    States. Cambridge, Ma: Mit Press.

    Fuller, R. B. 2010/1962. Education Automation: Comprehensive Learning For Emergent Humanity, Kosel, Germany, Lars

    Muller Publishers.

    Garnett, A. 2011. Information Science As Knowledge Translation. Bulletin Of The American Society For Information Science

    And Technology, 37, 50-53.

    Goffman, E. 1974. Frame Analysis: An Essay On The Organization Of Experience, Cambridge, Ma, Harvard University Press.

    Gouldner, A. W. 1957. Cosmopolitans And Locals: Toward An Analysis Of Latent Social Roles I. Administrative Science Quarterly, 2, 281-306.

    Granovetter, M. S. 1985. Economic Action And Social Structure: The Problem Of Embeddedness. American Journal Of

    Sociology, 91, 481-510.

    Gray, B. 1996. Review Of: Frame Reflection. Academy Of Management Review, 21, 576-579.

    Gresov, C. & Drazin, R. 1997. Equifinality: Functional Equivalence In Organization Design. Academy Of Management

    Review, 22, 403-428.

    Grol, R. & Grimshaw, J. 2003. From Best Evidence To Best Practice: Effective Implementation Change In Patients' Care. The

    Lancet, 362, 1225 --1230.

    Gupta, A. K. & Govindarajan, V. 1991. Knowledge Flows And The Structure Of Control Within Multinational Organizations.

    Academy Of Management Review, 16, 768-792.

    Hersh, W. R. 1998. How Well Do Physicians Use Electronic Information Retrieval Systems. Journal Of American Medical

    Association, 280, 1347-1352.

    Hersh, W. R., Crabtree, M. K., Hickman, D. H., Sacherek, L., Friedman, C. P., Tidmarsh, P., Mosbaek, C. & Kraemer, D. 2002.

    Factors Associated With Success In Searching Medline And Applying Evidence To Answer Clinical Questions. Journal

    Of The American Medical Informatics Association, 9, 283-293.

    Hew, K. F. & Hara, N. 2007. Knowledge Sharing In O