Dostoevsky's Critique of the Aesthetics of Dobroliubov

18
Dostoevsky's Critique of the Aesthetics of Dobroliubov Author(s): Robert L. Jackson Source: Slavic Review, Vol. 23, No. 2 (Jun., 1964), pp. 258-274 Published by: Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/2492935 . Accessed: 14/06/2014 12:16 Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at . http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp . JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. . Association for Slavic, East European, and Eurasian Studies is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Slavic Review. http://www.jstor.org This content downloaded from 188.72.126.181 on Sat, 14 Jun 2014 12:16:23 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Transcript of Dostoevsky's Critique of the Aesthetics of Dobroliubov

Dostoevsky's Critique of the Aesthetics of DobroliubovAuthor(s): Robert L. JacksonSource: Slavic Review, Vol. 23, No. 2 (Jun., 1964), pp. 258-274Published by:Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/2492935 .

Accessed: 14/06/2014 12:16

Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at .http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

.JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range ofcontent in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new formsof scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].

.

Association for Slavic, East European, and Eurasian Studies is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserveand extend access to Slavic Review.

http://www.jstor.org

This content downloaded from 188.72.126.181 on Sat, 14 Jun 2014 12:16:23 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

DOSTOEVSKY'S CRITIQUE OF THE AESTHETICS OF DOBROLIUBOV

BY ROBERT L. JACKSON

I In 1861, in the second issue of his new journal Vremia, Dostoevsky published an article entitled "Mr. --bov and the Question of Art."I In it he attacks the utilitarian aesthetics of the radical literary critic N. A. Dobroliubov (1836-61); at the same time he sets forth the funda- mentals of his own idealist aesthetic. Dostoevsky's article is his first major critique of the utilitarian and materialist outlook of the radical democrats led by N. G. Chernyshevsky (1828-89) and Dobroliubov.2 It anticipates his later polemic with the radicals in Notes from the Underground (1864). The problem of freedom, significantly, is in the foreground of both works. The insistence on freedom in artistic creation is the central motif of "Mr. Dobroliubov and the Question of Art." It is to this problem that we wish to direct principal attention.

II Dostoevsky was arrested with other members of the Petrashevsky Circle in 1849 and brought to trial. In his "Affidavit," filed before the trial commission, Dostoevsky asserted that he had quarreled with the literary critic V. G. Belinsky (1811-48) in 1848 over the question of the "ideas of literature and [the problem] of tendency in literature." Dostoevsky insisted that his view had been "radically opposed" to Belinsky's and that he had reproached Belinsky for trying to give literature a "local meaning" by reducing it to description of newspaper facts or scandalous events. Dostoevsky told Belinsky (according to the "Affidavit") that

MR. JACKSON is associate professor of Russian literature at Yale University.

1 q). M. JOCTOeBCUKR, <<. 60B la BOOlpOC o6 n.C1yCCTBe,>> pp. 62-95 in Cmambu 3a

1845-1878 to&t, Vol. XIII of Hosznoe co6panue xy0omceem6ennux npoU36eOenuUi (Moscow and Leningrad, 1926-30). All citations from Dostoevsky's belles-lettres and critical writings refer to this edition of Dostoevsky's works.

2 Chernyshevsky and Dobroliubov, as is well known, were strongly influenced in their philosophy by Ludwig Feuerbach and in their social criticism by the French utopian socialists. While the two Russian thinkers could be considered rationalists in the eighteenth-century sense of a complete faith in reason, they bear a strong affinity in their manner of thinking to the nineteenth-century popularizers of science such as Vogt, Moleschott, and Buchner, as well as to the English utilitarians. In his aesthetics and literary criticism Dobroliubov based himself on Chernyshevsky's "Aesthetic Relations of Art to Reality" (1855); this work is essentially an application of Feuerbach's materialism to aesthetics.

This content downloaded from 188.72.126.181 on Sat, 14 Jun 2014 12:16:23 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Dostoevsky and the Aesthetics of Dobroliubov 259

nothing would be gained by "spleen," by buttonholing the passer-by and "forcibly preaching to him and teaching him with mind and reason."3

Dostoevsky likewise affirmed that he once spoke at Petrashevsky's in connection with a literary quarrel with Petrashevsky; at that time Dostoevsky had insisted that "art needs no tendency, that art was a goal in itself, that the author should busy himself with artistry, and the idea will come of itself, because it is a necessary condition of artistry. In a word, it is known that this tendency is diametrically opposed to the journalistic [approach] and ... [to the view that literature must serve as a] fire brigade. Many also knew that this had been my tendency for several years. Finally, everybody heard our quarrel at Petrashevsky's; everybody can attest to what I have said."4 In additional testimony at the trial Dostoevsky observed that Durov, a member of the Petrashevsky Circle, had supported him in the view that literature needs no tendency except the "purely artistic" and in the view that "tendency binds the writer, cramping his freedom, and to the bargain, a splenetic, abusive tendency which ruins artistry."5

Undoubtedly Dostoevsky, in an effort to cover up his conspiratorial activities, exaggerates the importance of his literary differences with Belinsky.6 But his testimony is convincing on the question of his point of view.7 It is a striking fact, moreover, that here in nucleus form-in Dostoevsky's "Affidavit" in 1849-are to be found the central points of his later critique of Dobroliubov in 1861, namely: the concept of art as a goal in itself, the notion that in free creation the "idea will come of itself," and the belief that tendency cramps the freedom of the writer.

III Dostoevsky returned to St. Petersburg in 1859 after ten years in prison and exile in Siberia. He later spoke of this decade as a period of the "rebirth of my convictions."8 The concept of rebirth (as opposed to

3 Cf. HI. 4). Be.UrLoB ,Z(omoecxmuii 6 npogecce nempawuesgeg (Moscow, 1936), p. 85. 4 Ibid., p. 86. 5 Ibid., pp. 124-25. In a note to his testimony at this point Dostoevsky adds: "With

which Petrashevsky completely agreed. It turned out that the quarrel resulted from a misunderstanding. All the guests of Petrashevsky were witnesses."

6Dostoevsky wrote in 1873 that he had parted ways with Belinsky "for a variety of reasons, quite unimportant ones in any case" (Jte6nuxn nucame.A, in Homaoe co6panue .... XI, 8). He maintains that although he had ceased to visit Belinsky in the last year of his life, he "passionately had accepted at that time all his teachings" (p. 10). Yet in the same reminiscences Dostoevsky observed that he and Belinsky were at opposite poles on the question of religion; in this sphere Belinsky regarded Dostoevsky as a "naive man" (p. 9). It seems quite probable that at this time Dostoevsky succeeded in harmonizing quite con- tradictory philosophical, literary, and political views.

7 The secret agent P. D. Antonelli, who spied on the Petrashevsky gatherings, corrobo- rates in part Dostoevsky's testimony. He notes that Petrashevsky used to quarrel with the Dostoevsky brothers, "reproaching them for their manner of writing which allegedly did not lead to any development of ideas in society" (Be.L'qt1HoB, op. cit., p. 197).

8, ue6mun nucamem, XI, 139.

This content downloaded from 188.72.126.181 on Sat, 14 Jun 2014 12:16:23 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

260 Slavic Review

radical transformation) is particularly relevant to any consideration of the evolution of Dostoevsky's aesthetic and religious thought. Dosto- evsky had come under the strong influence of Belinsky and the poetics of the "natural school" in the 1840's. His first work, Poor Folk (Bednye liudi, 1846) was welcomed by Belinsky as a major success for the new social realism. Dostoevsky's primary aesthetic education, how- ever, was effected in the heightened Romantic and philosophic atmos- phere of the 1830's and early 1840's; the influence of German idealism (Schelling, Schiller, Fichte, Hegel) was dominant. It was in this period that Dostoevsky added a love of classical and neoclassical literature to a youthful literary affiliation with romanticism (Corneille to the young Dostoevsky was the very "spirit of romanticism"); it was at this time, also, that Dostoevsky became infatuated with the work of Schiller. Dostoevsky soon came under the influence of Belinsky and the new realist school; it is extremely doubtful, however, that he ever aban- doned the fundamental idealist assumptions of the romantic aesthetic. In any case, the period of prison and exile (marked by a resurgent interest in religion) was one in which Dostoevsky began to review the question of the relation between art and religion. Dostoevsky wrote his brother Mikhail in 1856 that he was preparing an article, "Letters About Art," which was the "fruit of decades of careful thought. I conceived it all to the last word as far back as in Omsk [Dostoevsky's prison]." Dostoevsky wrote that his article was "essentially on the significance of Christianity in art."9 Dostoevsky did not publish this article and it has not been preserved, but he probably incorporated many of its ideas in his critique of Dobroliubov in 1861. Still in Siberia in 1858, however, Dostoevsky wrote his brother that he believed he could "say something remarkable about art,"10 that he was preparing several articles on "modern poets, on the statistical tendency of litera- ture, on the uselessness of tendencies in art."11l

In the subscription prospectus of Vremia for 1861 Dostoevsky an- nounced that the second issue of the journal would deal with the "question of the significance of art and of its actual relation to real life." The question of the relation of art and Christianity is not men- tioned here; nor is it raised, directly, in "Mr. Dobroliubov and the Question of Art"; but the deeply idealist content of Dostoevsky's aesthetic suggests a rebirth of convictions long overdue.12

9 Hucbya, ed. A. C. AOIHaH]aH (Moscow and Leningrad, 1928-34), I, 183-84. 10 Ibid., II, 570. II Ibid., P. 593. 12 The deep Platonism of Doestoevsky's higher aesthetic is obvious in "Mr. Dobroliubov

and the Question of Art." The notion-essentially Platonic-of the medieval Christian aesthetic that all beauty is a theophany is central to Dostoevsky's aesthetic outlook. It should be noted in this connection that many features of Dostoevsky's aesthetic resemble Chateaubriand's Christian aesthetic in Genie du Christianisme (1802). Dostoevsky men- tions this work in a letter to his brother in 1838. The conception of Christianity not only as truth but as beauty-the chief idea of Genie du Christianisme-is at the core of Dostoev-

This content downloaded from 188.72.126.181 on Sat, 14 Jun 2014 12:16:23 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Dostoevsky and the Aesthetics of Dobroliubov 261

IV Dostoevsky attacks the utilitarian aesthetic in his critique of Dobro- liubov; it is not, however, with the purpose of withdrawing art to lofty and inaccessible positions, but rather in order to affirm the organic unity of art and man's needs. Art poverfully aids human development, Dostoevsky believed, and only the "most extreme theoreticism and, from another side, the most vulgar lack of talent, can negate this force.... We don't stand for art for art's sake.'"13 Dostoevsky only insists upon the "independent significance of art, the naturalness of this independence, and, therefore, its complete necessity in the cause of social development and consciousness."''14

Art can help a cause a great deal because of its tremendous resources and strength, Dostoevsky wrote in "Mr. Dobroliubov and the Question of Art": "We repeat: of course, one can only desire this, but not demand, if alone for the reason that people demand chiefly when they want to compel by force, while the first law in art is freedom of in- spiration and creation. Everything that has been brought forth by demand, everything drawn out, from time immemorial has not suc- ceeded, and instead of benefit has brought only harm.'"15

Two interrelated thoughts are contained here: first, that the artistic process, by nature free, cannot be coerced without violating the in- tegrity of art; second, that "demand" itself conceals the threat of real violent compulsion from without. The raising of the problem of demand in the double aspect of violence to both art and man points to Dostoevsky's deep fear of the coefficient of compulsion in radical utilitarian and utopian socialist theory. Dostoevsky significantly com- pared his life in prison to a "compulsory communism."16 Later in Notes from the Underground (1864) he cast his hero in the role of a despairing prisoner rebelling against a socialist utopia and the walls of his own rationalistic consciousness. Apollon Grigoriev, Dostoevsky's associate on the journals Vremia and Epokha, wrote in a literary essay in 1864 of his hostility to everything that emerges from the "naked logical process, that is, to theory with its narrow grasp of life and with its despotism ready to pass to terror. "17 Dostoevsky's almost obsessive

sky's higher aesthetic. In his aesthetic thought Dostoevsky is clearly indebted to various German idealist thinkers. Possibly the single most important German influence was Schiller with his central conception of moral education through the refinement of aesthetic sensibility (a basic conception with Chateaubriand though in a strictly Christian context). Dostoevsky, like Schiller, certainly was marked by the Winckelmann cult of Hellenism. Very important in any consideration of direct influences would be Apollon Grigoriev's "organic" theory of art; Grigoriev, a collaborator of Dostoevsky on Vremia, was deeply influenced by Schelling.

13 <<IHoA]a]cEa Ha 1863 roA,>> HoAoe co6panue ..., XIII, 512. 14 <<PaccRambI HI. B. YcileHCEoro,>> ibid., p. 551. 15 <<r. 6o0B .... >> p. 69. 16 Hucuta, I, 143. 17 A. rpHropbeBl, Coltuneni,r (St. Petersburg, 1876), p. 615.

This content downloaded from 188.72.126.181 on Sat, 14 Jun 2014 12:16:23 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

262 Slavic Review

concern with compulsion becomes more comprehensible in the light of a literary theory which projected a brand of social realism as the literary concomitant of ineluctable historical forces driving to a new, socialist society. Dobroliubov was the leading exponent of this new social realism.

In theory Dobroliubov made no demands upon literature. The function of the "realistic critic" in his view was to study literary works in order to determine their characteristic or typical features. We do not feel called upon to "cultivate the aesthetic taste of the public," he wrote in an essay on the dramatist A. Ostrovsky. "We only set forth here those results which we have obtained from a study of Ostrovsky's works from the standpoint of the reality he depicted."18 The writer cannot deal with problems or issues before they have matured in reality. "Literature answers the questions of life with what is in life."19

But who shall determine what is in life and whether literature is responding properly to the questions raised by reality? Dobroliubov assumes this function; in practice, the prescriptive character of his criticism takes its point of departure here. "This environment has now reached the point when it itself can facilitate the appearance of such a man," wrote Dobroliubov in reference to the Bulgarian hero of Turgenev's novel On the Eve (Nakanune, 1860).20 Proceeding from this premise Dobroliubov could criticize the writer A. Pleshcheev for offering up to the reader, instead of men of action, dreamers and feeble armchair philosophers who make no contribution to the public cause. "Why, now, should one write touching stories about their dreams and inner sufferings, which lead to nothing useful?" "Yes, we attach no practical importance to the beautiful strivings of the soul as long as they remain only strivings; yes, we value only facts, we recognize the worth of people only through actions."21 ". . . we do not demand hero- ism, but want only more consciousness and definiteness of strivings in the good youths."22 The demand, of course, falls upon the writer. The prescriptive character of some of Dobroliubov's criticism is par- ticularly evident in his review of the poetry of I. Nikitin. "Life," Dobroliubov declared, "now is affirming its rights on all sides, realism is invading everywhere."23 Dobroliubov criticized Nikitin for writing about his personal discord with the world about him and calls upon him to turn to the "reproduction of those living images out of which are formed his best views."24

18 H. A. 0o6poa1o60B, <<TemrHoe gapCTBo,>> in H36pauuoe co'tuuenuw (Moscow, 1948), pp. 103-4.

19 <<0 CTeIIeHH yYaCTHJ HipEAHOCTH B pa3BHTHH pYCC10o0 iI,TepaTypI,>> ibid., p. 26. 20 <<4orAa me lpIIleT HaCT0JUIHA AeCHEb?,>> ibid., p. 242. 21 <<BAaroHaMepeHHEiCT H AeJITeaLHocTL,>> in ColtuueuLrz H. A. ko6posuo6o6a (St. Peters-

burg, 1908), III, 272. 22 Ibid., p. 276. 23 <<CTHXOTBopeigHs HBaHa HKHnTHHa,>> H36p. col., p. 422. 24 Ibid., p. 240.

This content downloaded from 188.72.126.181 on Sat, 14 Jun 2014 12:16:23 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Dostoevsky and the Aesthetics of Dobroliubov 263

In his review of Dobroliubov, Dostoevsky remarked that such pre- scriptive criticism is impermissible-"to be a despot is impermissible, and really, for example, you, Mr. Dobroliubov, dealt almost despotic- ally with Mr. Nikitin. 'Write about your needs, describe the needs and requirements of your class!' . ..'But after all I myself am one in need,' continues Mr. Nikitin, 'physical bread I have, but I have need of spiritual bread.' "25

The juxtaposition of physical and spiritual bread points to funda- mental philosophical and social issues which underlie the entire debate in aesthetics between Dostoevsky and Dobroliubov: the problem of materialism and of its social solution to the problems of man and society. Here in this debate, as later though somewhat ambiguously in "The Legend of the Grand Inquisitor," Dostoevsky insists on the choice of spiritual bread with its coefficient of freedom. Those "un- solved historical contradictions of human nature" which serve the Grand Inquisitor as cause for lifting from man his burden of freedom, serve Dostoevsky in his debate with Dobroliubov as the bulwark for his central postulate on the nature and significance of beauty and art, on art as an organic need of man.

Dostoevsky's organic theory of art is pivotal in his debate with Dobroliubov. The imposition of any demands upon art, Dostoevsky maintained, is based on a misunderstanding of the basic laws of art and of its chief essence-freedom of inspiration. Art is an organic whole with its own organic life and, hence, fundamental and unchangeable laws for this life. Art is as much of a need for man as eating and drinking. The need for beauty and creation which embodies it is inseparable from man, and without it man, perhaps, would not want to live in the world. Man thirsts for it, finds and accepts beauty unconditionally, and this is just because it is beauty.... The need for beauty develops most at the moment in which man is in discord with reality, in disharmony, in struggle, that is, when he is living most of all, because man lives most of all precisely at the time when he is seeking and striving for something; at that time also there manifests itself within him the most natural desire for everything harmonious, for tranquillity, and in beauty there is both harmony and tranquillity.26

This is the heart of Dostoevsky's higher aesthetic, the core of his aesthetic humanism.

Dostoevsky's theory of art comes as a clear response to Dobroliubov's materialist and utopian theory of poetry-the aesthetic concomitant, one might say, to that social utopia which Dostoevsky attacks in Notes from the Underground in 1864. In his review of Nikitin's poetry, Dobroliubov had characterized the function or sphere of poetry as

25 <<r. 60B . . .,>> p. 95. 26 Ibid., p. 94.

This content downloaded from 188.72.126.181 on Sat, 14 Jun 2014 12:16:23 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

264 Slavic Review

"life, living activity, its eternal struggle and the eternal striving of man to achieve harmony with himself and with nature." Poetry has long depicted man's discord with his surroundings. But the reasons for this discord, according to Dobroliubov, have been sought erroneously "either in the mysterious forces of nature or in the dualistic structure of the human organism, and in accordance with this poetry treated the external nature and psychological antagonism of man." Dobroliubov, however, envisages a social solution to the phenomenon of discord in man and art. Attention, he continues, is being directed nowadays to the "distribution of goods of nature between people, to the organiza- tion of social relations." Poetry has taken up this subject, but only in a general way; it is the novel, however, the "creation of the new time," which has "stemmed directly from this new view of the structure of social relations as the cause of the universal discord."27

The theoretical roots of Dobroliubov's scorn for poetry are disclosed here. In its practical aspects, poetry-particularly the poetry of senti- ment, mood, and nature with its myth, fantasy, allegory, and historical themes-was remote and of no use to Dobroliubov in the immediate struggle. In its theoretical aspects, poetry was the main camping ground of Dobroliubov's chief enemy: philosophical idealism. Here were gathered all those "ideologists" beginning with Plato who rise up against realism, insist upon dualism, and believe that only pure ideas have reality;28 here also were to be found his opponents in the "aesthetical" camp who imagine that beautiful works are the beginning of all good and who think that literature, "especially poetry," "makes history ... remakes even moral and national character."29

These same opponents support the contemporary poet in the con- viction that social activity is not his affair and that he will stand apart when the "change and reconstruction of the social building" occurs. But sooner or later, Dobroliubov insisted, poetry will undertake a study of "social inequities"-following its discovery that "man agonizes and anguishes, is carried away and falls, rises and rejoices not from the power of dark forces, and from inevitable fate, and not because two opposing elements sit within him, but simply from one or another measure of inequity in social relations."30

Dobroliubov's theory of poetry was objectionable to Dostoevsky on two grounds: first, its frankly materialist character; and second, its concept of a definitive social solution to the problems of man, its rejection of the principle of permanent conflict, or dialectic, in man and history. In this connection the most crucial feature in Dostoevsky's concept of beauty is the notion that the "need for beauty develops most

27 <<CTHIXOTBopeHHJ HBiEaHa HHRHTHTEa,>> H36p. cot., p. 426. 28 <<O CTeIIHHi yYaCTHI iiapOOAHOCTH.. .,>> ibid., p. 25. 29 Ibid., p. 24. 30 <<CTHXOTBopeHHI HBaHa HHJXHTHHa,>> ibid., p. 426.

This content downloaded from 188.72.126.181 on Sat, 14 Jun 2014 12:16:23 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Dostoevsky and the Aesthetics of Dobroliubov 265

when man is in discord with reality, in disharmony, in struggle.''31 Dostoevsky-in complete contrast to Dobroliubov's purely historical and materialist understanding of the element of discord in human existence-views man's discord with reality as an innate and eternal aspect of the human condition. This concept of conflict, of ambi- valence within man and permanent discord between man's ideal and reality, has the character almost of a formal creative principle in Dostoevsky's art.32

The view of ambivalence as suffering, yet as constituting the essence of consciousness; the view of man's eternal struggle for the ideal as the very essence of creative being, form the most decisive argument in Notes from the Underground against the idea of a rational and har- monious social utopia. This view of man's condition, taken from its aesthetic side, plays a similar role in demolishing Dobroliubov's aes- thetic utopia. Indeed, at the point at which Dobroliubov visualizes a socially motivated end to all discord in man and poetry, at the point at which he projects a new role for the poet "in the reconstruction of the social building," Dostoevsky postulates disintegration and chaos in the aesthetic-and for Dostoevsky therefore moral-sphere. There can be no vital life or healthy creation outside conflict. Man lives most when he is striving. When the struggle ceases, when man achieves the ideal of his desires, Dostoevsky observed, when he finds what he has been seeking, life begins to slow up. There have been examples when man, attaining the ideal of his desires, satiated, began to anguish, sought out "another ideal" and no longer valued that which he had enjoyed, but "even consciously deviated from the straight path, sharply stimulating in himself alien tastes, unhealthy, sharp, inharmonic, sometimes monstrous ones, losing measure and an aesthetic sensitivity for healthy beauty and demanding instead of it exceptions. And therefore beauty is an attribute of everything healthy...."33

The aesthetic ideal, then, is characterized by health, harmony, and measure. But when man achieves the ideal of his desires, the aesthetic ideal becomes unhealthy, inharmonious, and disfigured, a condition reflected in the simultaneous breakdown of morality and taste. The concept that inertia, stagnation, and moral disintegration inevitably entail a qualitative change in aesthetic taste or vision was first expressed by Dostoevsky in a feutilleton in 1847. Discussing the moral and spiri-

31 <<r. 6B ... ,>> p. 86. 32 "And thus man strives on earth for an ideal which is contrary to his nature,"

Dostoevsky wrote in some notes in 1864. "When man has not fulfilled the law of striving for the ideal, i.e., has not brought love to people or to another being through a sacrifice of his I ... he experiences suffering and has called this condition sin. And so man cease- lessly must experience suffering, which is balanced by a heavenly pleasure in fulfilling the law, i.e., by sacrificing himself. Precisely here is earthly equilibrium. Otherwise, the earth would be senseless." Quoted by C. BopI;eBcRHil in likeapuu u /kocmoe6cxuMi (Moscow, 1956), p. 213.

33 <<r. 6oB.. .,> pp. 86-87.

This content downloaded from 188.72.126.181 on Sat, 14 Jun 2014 12:16:23 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

266 Slavic Review

tual disintegration of the dreamer divorced from life, Dostoevsky observed: "Finally, in his confusion he completely loses that moral sense with which man is capable of evaluating all real beauty."34 This phenomenon is explored by Dostoevsky in such types as the Under- ground Man and, particularly, Fedor Karamazov where moral stag- nation finds aesthetic expression in the morbid delight which they take in the desecration, that is, the disfiguration of the moral ideal; in purely aesthetic terms this moral ideal, as embodied for example in the Madonna, is Ideal Form which takes on the character of a norm for Dostoevsky.

V Dostoevsky's concept of the usefulness of literature and art flows di- rectly from his central postulate on beauty as the incarnation of man's ideal. Dobroliubov had placed, in effect, a time limit on the usefulness of beauty, declaring the vanity of all efforts to evoke the ecstasy of beauty of a person who is but a naked skull. The gods of the Greeks may have been beautiful in ancient Greece, "but they are disgusting in French tragedies."35 The beautiful in Pushkin has no place in the modern era.36 Dostoevsky's position is simple. "Beauty is useful because it is beauty." "Beauty is always useful."37

"I have always believed in the force of the humane, aesthetically expressed impression," Dostoevsky observed in one of his articles in Vremia in 1861.38 In his critique of Dobroliubov, Dostoevsky stressed that the art of the past can influence contemporary life and man. But this influence is always an aesthetic one. The "higher beauty" of the Apollo of Belvedere could perhaps have such a powerful impact upon a young man, Dostoevsky suggests, that it might have an unconscious influence upon him during some great social event in which the young man played a leading role. Historical facts suggest that Corneille and Racine made their influence felt at decisive moments in the historical life of the people.39

34 <<HeTep6yprciGa aeToIIIICL,? llo Afoe co6panue .. ., XIII, 31. 35 <<?0 CTeReHH aCTHlJ HapOAHOCTH .... ,>> H36p. com., p. 24. 36 <<CTHXOTBOPeHHIa HBaHa HHIIIKHTIHa,>> ibid., p. 422. 37 <<r. 60B ... ,>> pp. 94, 88. 38 <<'CBHCTOR' H 'PYCCIRH BeCTHHIE'?,>> JoAnoe co6panue ..., XIII, 191. Dostoevsky here

gives expression to the central idea in Schiller's Briefe iuber die dsthetische Erziehung des Menschen. Schiller speaks out against "Utility ... the great idol of the age," declaring that "in these clumsy scales the spiritual service of art has no weight" (Second Letter). He cautions the "young friend of Truth and Beauty" against plunging into the present with the hope of rapidly "transforming the formless substance of the moral world." "The pure moral impulse is directed at the Absolute; time does not exist for it...." Schiller's advice to the artist is to "give the world on which you are acting the direction toward the good" (Ninth Letter). "Beauty must be exhibited as the necessary condition for humanity" (Tenth Letter). In his critique of utilitarian aesthetics Dostoevsky, like Schiller, affirms the timelessness of the moral impulse in art, that is, the contemporaneity of all beauty (art).

39 <<r.-60B ... ,>> p. 94.

This content downloaded from 188.72.126.181 on Sat, 14 Jun 2014 12:16:23 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Dostoevsky and the Aesthetics of Dobroliubov 267

Corneille and Racine had tremendously impressed Dostoevsky in his youth; "flaming, passionate Racine in love with his ideals," Cor- neille with his "gigantic characters," his "lofty ideals," we read in a letter Dostoevsky wrote in 1840.40 In the same letter Dostoevsky men- tioned Homer as "perhaps only parallel to Christ" in significance.41 Dobroliubov had written that he was interested in Shakespeare and Homer only "for the direct significance they have for us, for our society, and for our times."42 But how is it possible, Dostoevsky asked in his critique of Dobroliubov, to determine the usefulness to man- kind of a work of art like The Iliad. Dostoevsky ventures that The Iliad might even be useful in resolving contemporary questions. In our time, a time of strivings, struggle, hesitations, Dostoevsky believes, The Iliad with its "eternal harmony" might have a decisive influence on the soul. "Our spirit now is highly receptive, the influence of beauty, harmony, and strength might act on it in a grand and beneficial way, usefully act on it, instill energy, support our strength."43

Art in the highest sense is a humanizing force to Dostoevsky, a force whose role in Russian national development he fully recognizes. Russian literature is "now one of the chief manifestations of Russian life,"44 the only organic manifestation, and it was Russian literature that brought the "universal elements" from the West into Russian life.45 In turn Dostoevsky saw these elements as being translated into a universal responsiveness in the Russian people to other peoples and literatures, a responsiveness which he considers its best characteristic.46 .... and if a people preserves the ideal of beauty and its need, that

means that there is a need also for health, the norm, and consequently in this way the highest development of a people is guaranteed."47

The question of the usefulness of art for Dostoevsky, then, is entirely an aesthetic phenomenon. From this standpoint all periods in litera- ture disappear and the contemporary moment is dissolved in the time- lessness of man's striving for the ideal. To the question why art does not always correspond in its ideals with the universal and contemporary ideal, why art is not always faithful to reality, Dostoevsky answered in "Mr. Dobroliubov and the Question of Art" that the question is not correctly posed. "Art is always contemporary and real, it never was otherwise and, chiefly, cannot exist otherwise." And Dostoevsky adds that those who think art deviates from reality do so, first of all, out of an ignorance of the paths of usefulness of art.48

Can a writer ever lose contact with reality? Dostoevsky obviously believed that this was possible. And, by way of an apparent concession

40 Uucc^;ca, I, 58. 46 r. 60B . . .,>> p- 92. 41 Ibid., p. 59. 47I bid., p. 95. 42 <<BTarOHaMepeHHOCTm H AeqTeIbHOCTL,>> H36p. con., p. 267. 48 Ibid., p. 90. 43 <<r. 6oBn...,>> p. 88. 44 <<lIoAHcia Ha 1863 rop,?> J1oAnoe co6panue ..., XIII, 506. 45 <<LBa aareps TeOpeTHIOB,>> ibid., p. 240.

This content downloaded from 188.72.126.181 on Sat, 14 Jun 2014 12:16:23 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

268 Slavic Review

and in a confusing shift of criteria, Dostoevsky remarked in his article on Dobroliubov that we sometimes think art deviates from reality because "there really are mad poets and prose writers who break all connection with reality, who are transformed into some kind of ancient Greeks or into medieval knights and who ferment in anthologies or in medieval legends." These artists, however, are fully mad, and therefore few in number, Dostoevsky observed. On the other hand, "our poets and artists really can deviate from the real path." And Dostoevsky enumerates various causes of such deviation: absence of a social sense, misunderstanding of civic duty, immaturity, misunderstanding of reality, or an imperfectly formed society. In regard to all this Dostoev- sky finds the "appeals, reproaches, and explanations of Mr. Dobroliubov in the highest degree respectable. But Mr. Dobroliubov really goes much too far." The works that Dobroliubov calls "rattles and album playthings" Dostoevsky finds normal and useful. These "playthings" are useful-Dostoevsky has in mind the works of poets who drew their themes from classical antiquity-because "we are connected both in our historical and inner spiritual life both with the historical past and with the universal."49

Dostoevsky's concession to the Dobroliubov point of view suggests the complexity of his view of the relation of art to society. In a review of the Academy of Arts painting exhibition in 1861 Dostoevsky em- phatically states: "There is not and cannot be in our time any epic, nonparticipating tranquillity; if there has been any, then it is surely only among people lacking in any development...."50 In the final analysis, Dostoevsky's differences with Dobroliubov are not so much on the question of whether art should respond to contemporary reality as on how it should respond; and central to Dostoevsky's position is his insistence that art must remain art in this response regardless of its ideological orientation.

Dostoevsky attacked Dobroliubov for refusing to recognize the primacy of artistry. An inartistic work cannot in any sense achieve its goal, Dostoevsky maintained, and the utilitarians only ruin their cause by refusing to recognize this truth. To demonstrate the self-defeating character of utilitarian aesthetics Dostoevsky analyzed in his critique of Dobroliubov the latter's lengthy review of Marko-Vovchok's "Stories from the Life of the Russian Folk" ("Rasskazy iz narodnogo russkogo byta," 1859). "The task of literature is now to pursue the remnants of serfdom in public life,'"5' Dobroliubov had written in his review, and noted that Marko-Vovchok "in his simple and truthful stories is practically the first warrior in this field."52

49 Ibid., pp. 90-91. 50 <<BbiCTaBra B aiaAe,iHH XyAoXeCTB 3a 1860-1861 roA,>> 1oAzoe co6panue . . ., XIII, 532. 51 <<4epTbs Arif xapaETepHCGTHKH pyCCEOrO npOCToHapOAbs?.>> I36p. coi., p. 244. 52 Ibid., p. 279.

This content downloaded from 188.72.126.181 on Sat, 14 Jun 2014 12:16:23 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Dostoevsky and the Aesthetics of Dobroliubov 269

Dostoevsky underlined the central contradiction in Dobroliubov's analysis of Marko-Vovchok's stories: affirming at the beginning of his review that these stories were not artistically finished works and that therefore there was no need to determine their absolute literary merit, Dobroliubov had concluded his review by the remark that the truth- fulness of the stories form a basis for admitting the high merits of the literary production. The substance of Dostoevsky's criticism of Marko- Vovchok (he dwells on one story in particular) is that her art was so bad as to make a mockery of her ideas. The central failure of Dobro- liubov, on the other hand, was his failure to recognize the unity between the artistic idea of a work (the problem of "truthfulness") and form. "How does one recognize artistry in a work of art? In the fact that we see a harmony, as complete as possible between the artistic idea and that form in which it is embodied."53 Dostoevsky refined this thought even further in another article. "The artistic finish of a piece of art gives to a thought clarity, relief, palpability, truth: and artistic power consists just in truth and in its vivid representation."54

Here truth is not something lifted from nature or reality and placed within the framework of a work of art: here truth is a property of art just as much as art reveals itself in truth.

Dostoevsky did not reject tendency (napravlenie) in literature; on the contrary: ". . . we ourselves yearn, thirst for a good tendency and we highly value it."55 He applauds the nobility of intention and idea of Marko-Vovchok. But intention and idea are not enough. Dostoevsky correctly observed that for utilitarian criticism intention and idea were enough. "In the first instance you want action, you are men of action."56 And indeed this remark goes to the core of much of the literary criticism of Dobroliubov-the critic who chose as epigraph to his essay "When Will the Real Day Come?" ("Kogda zhe pridet nastoiashchii den'," 1860) Heine's "Schlage die Trommel und furchte dich nicht." Dobroliubov calls the writer into battle with all the high responsibility that mortal combat involves.

VI A final problem deserves some consideration. What is Dostoevsky's attitude in his critique of Dobroliubov toward the problem of the social responsibility of the artist? The problem in one sense is elimi- nated by Dostoevsky's theory that all true art is useful and con- temporary. Yet what about the artist's responsibility to society in the face of a grave social or national crisis? Here the problem obviously takes on special moral dimensions. Although Dostoevsky did not share

53 <<r. 60B . . . ,>> p. 72. 54 <<Paccsaa H. B. YdeneHcroro,> HoAzuoe co6pauue ..., XIII, 553. 55 <<r.,60B ... I>> p. 84. 56 Ibid ., p. 85.

This content downloaded from 188.72.126.181 on Sat, 14 Jun 2014 12:16:23 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

270 Slavic Review

the radicals' revolutionary point of view and sense of imminent social crisis, the problem of the writer's moral or social responsibility had to be confronted squarely. Dostoevsky's resolution of this problem is curiously ambiguous and represents an attempt to synthesize, or estab- lish a dialectic of, opposing points of view.

The problem of responsibility is posed by three examples in his article on Dobroliubov. The first-advanced by the utilitarians in an imaginary debate staged by Dostoevsky-involves a hypothetical battle: you are in the midst of a battle; but instead of helping your comrades you (an artist in soul) suddenly want to paint a picture of the battle. You throw down your weapon, pick up a pencil, and begin to draw. "Of course, you have a full right to give yourself over to your inspira- tion, but would your artistic activity at such a moment be reasonable?" remarks Dostoevsky's spokesman for the utilitarians.57

The example very effectively poses the problem in the utilitarians' context of grave social crisis. Dostoevsky himself adds another example of the same order-partly drawn from the memoirs of I. Panaev: a circle of artists and writers, it appears, maintained that the artist should not busy himself with anything vital or current, politics, domestic or inter- national affairs; artists should concern themselves only with "lofty art." Dostoevsky completely rejects this point of view remarking that it might lead-say in the war of 1812-to some writers and poets preferring to busy themselves with a Greek anthology when all Russian society was busy saving the Fatherland.58

As though the examples of the battlefield and the war of 1812 were not enough to demonstrate to the reader the moral obloquy of with- drawing into lofty art at a time of crisis, Dostoevsky sets before the reader a third, hypothetical situation. On the morning after the ter- rible Lisbon earthquake, the citizens of the city, hoping to find infor- mation on the victims of the disaster, open their newspaper and-in the most prominent position in the paper-read the poem of a famous Lisbon poet. The poem that Dostoevsky quotes in full at this point is, in fact, one of the most beautiful lyrics of the Russian poet Fet (a poet for whom Dobroliubov had no use).

IJIOIIOT, po6Roe AbIxaHbe, PHA BoJIme6HuX H3BMeHenHH TpeJIH COJIOBnq, MHJIoro JIHAa,

Cepe6po H ioiixaHbe B AIIMHLIX TyIIax iypiyp pOauI, COHHOrO py'mbf, OT6JIeCE JHTapa,

CBeT HO'IHO, HO'qHbIe TeHH, H Io63aHHa H CJeBLI TeHH 6eB IonHAa, H Bapi, Bapa !

The Lisbon poet, Dostoevsky observes, attached to his poem the "well-known poetic rule that he is not a poet who cannot leap head- long from the fourth story."

57 Ibid., p. 66. 58 Ibid., p. 67.

This content downloaded from 188.72.126.181 on Sat, 14 Jun 2014 12:16:23 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Dostoevsky and the Aesthetics of Dobroliubov 271

Dostoevsky declares that the inhabitants of Lisbon would probably en masse execute their famous poet in the square, and not at all because he wrote a poem without a verb, but because in view of the disaster of the preceding night the act of the poet would be considered "offensive and unbrotherly." Of course, Dostoevsky relates, after exe- cuting the poet-also a very unbrotherly act-they would without fail rush to Doctor Pangloss for wise advice, and Pangloss would immedi- ately assure them that all was for the best.

At the same time, Dostoevsky asserts, these same Lisbonites thirty or forty years later might erect a monument to their beloved poet precisely for his amazing verse in general and, in particular, for the "purple of the rose." The poem for which they executed the poet might, Dostoevsky adds, even have been of some use to the people of Lisbon, "awakening in them an aesthetic ecstasy and the feeling of beauty, and laid like beneficial dew on the soul of the young generation."59

What is Dostoevsky's own view of the responsibility of the artist in the three examples he sets before the reader? In the first two examples Dostoevsky certainly places the asocial artist in a negative light. It is in his third example that the ambiguity of Dostoevsky's position becomes apparent. Here there is a surprise reversal: the extreme asocial and irrational act of the poet (the publication of the poem with its devil- may-care footnote) is justified by the fact that in the end the poem turned out to have an elevating influence upon men. But it is the poem that is justified, not the poet. "It turns out," Dostoevsky ob- serves, "that art was not guilty on the day of the Lisbon earthquake ... not art, but the poet was guilty of abusing art at the moment when it was not the time for it. He sang and danced at the grave of a dead man ... but once again he, and not art is guilty."60

Nekrasov, expressing that profound sense of civic responsibility that characterizes so much of the nineteenth-century Russian intellectual consciousness, gave the most extreme interpretation to the concept of the poet's responsibility to society. His well-known lines read: "Poetom mozhesh' ty ne byt' /No grazhdaninom byt' obiazan" (from "Poet i grazhdanin," 1856). The poet who wrote this about himself, Dostoev- sky remarked in his Diary of a Writer in 1877, "thereby as it were rec- ognized that he could be judged by the people as a 'citizen.' "61 Dostoevsky, like Nekrasov, recognizes that the artist may be judged as a citizen, and in this sense he recognizes that the artist is both citizen and poet. But-and this seems the essential meaning of the Lisbon example-he prefers to remain with this ambivalence; in the final analy- sis he will censure the artist as citizen but not as poet. Whereas Nekra-

59 Ibid., p. 68. 60 Ibid. 61 le6mux nucameu, XII, 361.

This content downloaded from 188.72.126.181 on Sat, 14 Jun 2014 12:16:23 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

272 Slavic Review

sov in the lines cited gives priority to the citizen over the poet, Dostoev- sky accords special status to the poet: in his conception of a situation in which the poet finds himself at cross purposes with the demands of the citizen, with the exigencies of the moment, Dostoevsky projects the poet essentially as a solitary and tragic figure.

Dostoevsky's support of the Lisbon poet may be more complete than it appears at first glance. It cannot be forgotten that Dostoevsky's oppo- nents in 1861 were the same rationalists and utopian socialists against whom the man from the "underground" inveighs in Notes from the Underground in 1864. In the face of critics who, he felt, threatened to compromise the freedom of the artist with utilitarian demands and literary determinism, Dostoevsky brings into the foreground the Lisbon poet, a figure who can best be described as a poet-paradoxicalist or literary "underground" man. In what can only be taken as a deliberate challenge to society, and justification of his poem, the Lisbon poet pro- claims the "well-known poetic rule that he is not a poet who cannot leap headlong from the fourth story." At this point Dostoevsky remarks parenthetically, and with a deceptive simplicity: "For what reason? I don't know to this day; but then let's assume that this is absolutely necessary in order to be a poet; I don't want to argue."62

Dostoevsky advances here-quite cautiously to be sure, and reserving for himself a loophole-a conception of the poet that finds its analogue in some of the reflections of the man from the "underground" on free will as an expression of man's nature. The condition of being a poet *embraces the poet's relation to reality; it involves-according to the poetic rule cited-the readiness to act irrationally. Dostoevsky suggests that the irrational element may be absolutely essential to being a poet. The condition of being a poet, it follows, is not an affair of reason; the act of creation becomes an act of will, and will, as the man from the "underground" observes, "is a manifestation of the whole of life, I mean the whole of human life, including reason...."63

In his defense of artistic freedom Dostoevsky writes not of will but of tvorchestvo-here, "creativeness" or "force of creation." "Creative- ness-the basic element of every art-is an integral, organic attribute of human nature.... [It] develops out of itself, unsubordinated to any- thing, and it demands complete freedom; chiefly-complete freedom in its development." To limit or stifle the creative and artistic needs of man is to "cramp the human spirit in its work and development."64

Dostoevsky recognizes that there may be "great errors and major de- viations" in art;65 he acknowledges that the freedom of the artist may result in an abuse of art in certain circumstances (e.g., the Lisbon earth-

62 <<r. 60B . . . ,>> p. 66. 63 AOCTOeBM(HA, 3anuccu U3 noano.x, in fo'ioe co6pauue . . ., IV, 116. 64 <<r. 60B ... ,>> pp. 65-66. 65 Ibid., p. 93.

This content downloaded from 188.72.126.181 on Sat, 14 Jun 2014 12:16:23 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Dostoevsky and the Aesthetics of Dobroliubov 273

quake or any time of great national crisis), but he posits this freedom as inseparable from the act of creation, the condition of being a poet. Dostoevsky does not support the Lisbon poet in his asocial act, but he suggests-and this would seem to be the leitmotiv of the Lisbon episode -that the justification of the poet consists in the fact that he is a poet, that the poet by his very nature is in tension with society, that without the irrational leap he would not be a poet.

The appearance of Voltaire's Dr. Pangloss at the scene of the Lisbon earthquake with his rationalization of the poet's execution indicates the antirationalist direction of Dostoevsky's thought. Pangloss epito- mizes in his whole philosophy precisely the kind of abstract reasoning that Dostoevsky loathed. The facility with which reason can compro- mise freedom itself is amusingly illustrated by Voltaire at the conclu- sion of the chapter in Candide devoted to the Lisbon earthquake.

"Monsieur ne croit donc pas a la liberte? dit le familier.- Votre Excellence m'excusera, dit Pangloss; la liberte peut subsister avec la necessite absolue, car il etait necessaire que nous fussions libres; car enfin la volonte deter- minee..." Pangloss etait au milieu de sa phrase, quand le familier fit un signe de tete a son estafier, qui lui servait 'a boire du vin de Porto ou d'Oporto.

The episode of the Lisbon poet in Dostoevsky's critique of Dobroliu- bov calls attention, of course, precisely to the impossibility of any com- promise between freedom and absolute necessity.

VII N. N. Strakhov, Dostoevsky's close friend and collaborator on Vremia in the 1860's, wrote in his memoirs that Dostoevsky was devoted to the notion that literature must serve social needs. "But while firmly adher- ing to this notion of service to the moment, and while constantly probing contemporary phenomena and priding himself on grasping them in his work, Fedor Mikhailovich was ready to place above every- thing the strict demands of art."66 There is no reason to believe that Dostoevsky's position as set forth by Strakhov was any different in the 1840's than in the 1860's and 1870's. Dostoevsky believed in the 1840's and in the 1860's that narrow utilitarian and didactic tendencies were alien to art. But in the 1840's Dostoevsky politically was a radical and activist (however ill-defined and rootless the political program); his differences with Belinsky, Petrashevsky, and others over the function of literature in society could only be minor in comparison with the broad areas of agreement in the realm of political and social goals and ideals. In the 1860's, however, Dostoevsky stood in opposition to the radical revolutionary movement. In the context of this basic political shift, his

66 H. H. CTpaxomB, <<BocrioMunanri o OeAop, MHxaMiOBHiwt JOCTOeBCMRoM?,>> Biotpa%q, n.ucibta U 3alxbmTUu U37i 3aflucuou UUudICu 0. M. JoCmoe6cxawo (St. Petersburg, 1883), p. 275.

This content downloaded from 188.72.126.181 on Sat, 14 Jun 2014 12:16:23 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

274 Slavic Review

idealist aesthetic and theory of the function of literature could not but acquire a principled significance in his polemics with the radicals who sought to use literature for revolutionary and socialist ends. Dostoev- sky's critique of Dobroliubov's utilitarian aesthetic, therefore, points to a major reassessment of his political and social attitudes.

Dostoevsky does not abandon the notion that literature should serve society; in practice always harnessing the impulse to serve with the "strict demands of art," he gave himself up in both art and criticism to passionate, and often frankly tendentious, commitment. He believed that the artist had to be absolutely free, but he wanted him free to commit himself organically to serving society and a lofty moral goal. In the deepest human sense he defended the freedom of the beleaguered artist unconditionally, that is, as a man. "Of course, we agree that there could exist a kind of foul, anthological worm who really had lost all sense of reality.. .," Dostoevsky wrote in the ironical manner of the Underground Man in his critique of Dobroliubov. "But, in the first place, even a worm, after all, must live...."67 Yet in the realm of aesthetic theory, Dostoevsky defends the artist because he believed that the artist exercises his freedom as a creator of timeless Beauty, of all that is precious and necessary to man in his moral evolution; though he may abuse this freedom as a citizen, yet as an artist he points out to man-in Schiller's words-the "direction of the good"; to Dostoevsky this was the supreme service of the artist, a service (essentially religious in its ulti- mate significance) which redeemed all human error.

67 <<r. 60B . . . ,>> p. 90.

This content downloaded from 188.72.126.181 on Sat, 14 Jun 2014 12:16:23 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions