Disordered Minds/Minding Disorder

35
Bryan Miller JHU Philosophy Dept.

description

Prometheus Seminar SeriesDisordered Minds/Minding DisorderThe Philosophy of PsychiatryBryan Miller — JHU Philosophy Dept.

Transcript of Disordered Minds/Minding Disorder

Page 1: Disordered Minds/Minding Disorder

Bryan MillerJHU Philosophy Dept.

Page 2: Disordered Minds/Minding Disorder

Minding Disorder: Philosophy’s role

Address issues deemed to be “meta-scientific”▪ Is psychiatry a science? Are there laws of psychiatry? ▪ Are mental disorders natural kinds? Or social kinds?

Help tidy-up potential conceptual confusions ▪ What is a mental disorder?▪ Categorization of disorders?

Page 3: Disordered Minds/Minding Disorder

Disordered Minds: Psychiatry’s role The self Belief states Perception & Cognition Human nature Cognitive architecture

Page 4: Disordered Minds/Minding Disorder

What is philosophy of psychiatry? Applied philosophy of science

▪ Philosophy of physics▪ Philosophy of biology▪ Philosophy of social sciences▪ Philosophy of psychology

philosophy of mind

Page 5: Disordered Minds/Minding Disorder
Page 6: Disordered Minds/Minding Disorder

A branch of psychology?

A branch of medicine?

Is it a science?

What demarcates science from non-science?

Page 7: Disordered Minds/Minding Disorder

It is, at the least, reasonable to think that psychiatry is a science.

Of course, whether it is will depend on the nature of the phenomenon—mental disorders—that psychiatry is concerned with.

“What is a mental disorder?”

Page 8: Disordered Minds/Minding Disorder

Schizophrenia Bipolar Disorder Depression OCD Autism Alzheimer’s Capgras Syndrome

Cotard syndrome Alcohol/drug

addiction Depression Sociopathy ADHD Cortical Blindness Drapetomania

What do all these things have in common?

Page 9: Disordered Minds/Minding Disorder

Mental disorder is the behavior resulting from an underlying cause (the unconscious) “Unconscious mechanisms drive conscious

experiences and behavior and can be revealed and rendered intelligible by the psychoanalytic technique of interpretation.”

Page 10: Disordered Minds/Minding Disorder

Thomas Szasz Mental disorders are not true “disorders”

because there are no accompanying lesions Mental disorder as “problems in living” Diagnosis as a means of power and control *Note: As far as I know, Szasz is not a scientologist!

Page 11: Disordered Minds/Minding Disorder

Mental disorder has a normative as well as an objective component Harm Conditions Dysfunctioning mental mechanism

Page 12: Disordered Minds/Minding Disorder

Mental Disorders are neuropathologies

Page 13: Disordered Minds/Minding Disorder

If psychiatry is a science, then the categories it investigates should support inductive generalizations.

We want to be able to investigate a few instances of a category and project what we learn to all members of the category.

Only certain categories/classes support scientifically interesting inductive generalizations—natural kinds.

Page 14: Disordered Minds/Minding Disorder

What is a natural kind?1.A Natural kind is a class that has a property

cluster that result from some causal mechanism(s).

2.The mechanism(s) which causally sustain the relevant property cluster can be considered the defining feature of a natural kind.

Page 15: Disordered Minds/Minding Disorder

Psychiatry ought to only investigate mental disorders that are natural kinds.

DSM-IV categories of mental disorder are symptom based—categories are based on symptom-clusters.

These categories are often treated as though they are natural kinds, kinds that should be scientifically investigated and that possess underlying causal unity.

Page 16: Disordered Minds/Minding Disorder

The problem: Many DSM IV categories are probably

not natural kinds!!!

What’s the big deal? Investigating non-natural kinds may stall

progress.

Page 17: Disordered Minds/Minding Disorder

DSM-IV: Delusion A false belief The belief is based on incorrect inference about external

reality Entrenched and rigid. The belief is not one ordinarily accepted by other

members of the person's culture or subculture (e.g., it is not an article of religious faith).

Page 18: Disordered Minds/Minding Disorder

1. Some delusions are probably caused by motivational factors employed for coping.

e.g., erotomania

2. Some delusions are likely caused by cognitive/perceptual impairments.

e.g., Capgras

* Suggests various causal mechanisms.

Page 19: Disordered Minds/Minding Disorder

1. Bottom-up: abnormal experience that then modifies belief system.

2. Top-down: start with modified beliefs that “give rise” to strange experiences.

* Suggests various causal mechanisms.

Page 20: Disordered Minds/Minding Disorder
Page 21: Disordered Minds/Minding Disorder

Origins: “Division of emotional labor”

Gives rise to multiple personalities?

Fictive selves vs. Real Selves

Are multiple personalities the same as multiple selves?

Do neurotypicals only have one self? Is it a Fictive self

Page 22: Disordered Minds/Minding Disorder

What is the relation between delusions and beliefs?

Delusions do not integrate well and are not sensitive to updating in the face of new evidence.

Does this suggest that delusions are not beliefs?

Or does it suggest our previous notions of belief are too strong—i.e., no account of beliefs consistent with empirical data suggests the strict conditions that are often imposed on beliefs.

Page 23: Disordered Minds/Minding Disorder

If most disorders are just deviations from the norm along a continuum then we learn something about human nature. Most people have multiple personalities. Most people have obsessive-compulsive tendencies

in certain domains. Most people have delusions. Most people experience depression.

We need to keep these facts in mind if philosophical claims hinge on alleged features of human nature (i.e., descriptive ethics, theories of rationality).

Page 24: Disordered Minds/Minding Disorder

How tightly linked are cognition and perception? Top-down accounts of delusions suggest that

cognition can influence perception. How much influence can the physiological

component of depression have on agency and cognition? Do depressives perceive, or conceive, the world differently

What can we learn about the content of mental states from mental disorders such as delusions?

Page 25: Disordered Minds/Minding Disorder

Do mental disorders tell us anything about the cognitive architecture of the human mind-brain? Can we infer dedicated modules from

observed mental disorders? Can we infer that certain cognitive

processes are not modular; rather, that they are domain general?

Page 26: Disordered Minds/Minding Disorder
Page 27: Disordered Minds/Minding Disorder

Coming in April!!! Questions? Email:

[email protected]

Keynote SpeakerProf. Pascal Boyer Why obsessive people and religious people perform

rituals

Page 28: Disordered Minds/Minding Disorder

Delusions are (probably) not a natural kind: What Samuels missed about realization, Bryan Miller In “Delusions as a natural kind” Richard Samuels argues contrary to theorists such as Peter Zachar (2000) and Nassir Ghaemi (2004) that delusions probably do constitute a natural kind. Samuels supports his claim, the natural kind thesis (hereafter, NK thesis), by showing that several objections to it are mistaken. One of the strongest objections that Samuels must face is the heterogeneity objection, the claim that the NK thesis is false because delusions are realized by a number of heterogeneous neural and/or cognitive states. Samuels’ response to this objection notes that this only shows that delusions are multiply realizable and that this fact is consistent with and supportive of the NK thesis. In this paper, I argue that Samuels’ response to the heterogeneity objections fails to support the NK thesis insofar as it employs a form of realization that does not give rise to natural kinds. I conclude by remarking on how the failure to secure the natural kind status of delusions might be problematic for a special case of delusions—namely, religious delusions.

Dworkin on the Moral Psychology of Abortion, Jonathon Hricko In his book Life’s Dominion, Ronald Dworkin argues that, though defenders of the pro-life position may say that they object to abortion because they believe that it violates the rights and interests of the fetus, they actually object to it because they believe that it violates the intrinsic value of the fetus. Dworkin attempts to reach this conclusion by arguing that the former belief is incoherent. I will draw an analogy between the abortion debate and the conjunction fallacy in order to argue that Dworkin cannot reach his conclusion by means of the arguments he gives. The fact that a belief is incoherent is no reason to conclude that people do not hold that belief. Just as the probability rankings that people assign to a set of statements is an empirical issue, so is what people think about abortion, and so an empirical investigation is necessary to determine whether Dworkin’s conclusion is correct.

Page 29: Disordered Minds/Minding Disorder

Religion, Rationality, and Altruism, John WatermanReligion is puzzling from an evolutionary perspective. Religious ritual and belief have clear adaptive costs in time and effort, but they don't have clear compensating benefits. By any right, natural selection should have eliminated them long ago. Instead we find religion is a human universal. How should we explain this? An age old, if now unpopular, view explains that religion’s worth derives from promoting morality. Costly Signaling Theory, an adaptationist approach gaining currency among cognitive scientists of religion, updates this view. It argues religious beliefs and rituals are adaptations integral to the evolution of human altruism. The theory claims the adaptive benefits of religion accrue by mitigating the threat narrow self-interest poses to cooperative behavior. In this essay I argue that Costly Signaling Theory fails as an explanation of the evolution of cooperation in populations with unrelated individuals. Using the framework of evolutionary game theory, I show that religious belief and religious ritual are neither necessary nor sufficient for eliminating the underlying adaptive instability of cooperative behavior. I conclude with a discussion of the evolutionary relationship between religion and morality, and by considering a pending question for both adaptationist and spandrelist theories of religious cognition.

Between Adaptations and Spandrels: Cognitive science and evolutionary psychology of religion, Derek Leben Many psychologists, anthropologists, and biologists currently attempt to explain religion as not only a biological-cognitive product, but as an evolutionary adaptation. This paper will discuss the adaptationist argument as well as the supposed alternative, that religion is a useless ‘by-product’ of other cognitive systems (‘spandrelism’). It will be argued that the adaptationist argument is not effective, due to a failure to distinguish beneficial uses from ‘proper’ evolutionary functions, as well as a much wider variety of evolutionary causes than simply an adaptation or spandrel (kluge, exaptation, co-opted mechanism). Other cases such as language and moral appraisal will also be considered for comparison.

Page 30: Disordered Minds/Minding Disorder
Page 31: Disordered Minds/Minding Disorder

Bayne, T. and Pacherie, E. (2005). “In defence of the doxastic conception of delusion,” Mind & Language, 20 (2): 163–188.

Bermúdez, J. (2001). “Normativity and rationality in delusional psychiatric disorders,” Mind & Language, 16 (5): 493–457.

Bermudez, J. and Cahen, A. (2008). Non-conceptual Mental Content. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Bortolotti, L. (2009) Delusions. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Boyd, R. (1999). Homeostasis, Species and Higher Taxa. in Species: New Interdisciplinary Essays. Wilson, R. (ed.)

Cambridge: MIT Press 141-186 Boyer, P., & Lienard, P. (2006). Why ritualized behavior in humans? Precaution systems and action-parsing in

developmental, pathological and cultural rituals. Behavioral&Brain Sciences, 29, 1–56. Cartwright, N. et al .(200?) Philosophy of Science: Laws. Craver, C. F. (2007). Explaining the brain: Mechanisms and the mosaic unity of neuroscience. Oxford: Oxford

University Press. Devitt, M. (1994). The Methodology of Naturalistic Semantics. The Journal of Philosophy. Vol. 91: 10, pp. 545-572. Dretske, F. I., 1981, Knowledge and the Flow of Information (Oxford: Blackwell). Fine, C., Craigie, J. and Gold, I. (2005). “Damned if you do, damned if you don't: The impasse in cognitive accounts

of the Capgras delusion,” Philosophy, Psychiatry & Psychology, 12: 143–151. Fodor, J., (1974), ‘Special sciences, or the disunity of science as a working hypothesis’, Synthese 28: 77-115. Fodor, J., (1978), "Propositional Attitudes," The Monist 61: 501-523. Friedlander, L., Desrocher, M., 2006. Neuroimaging studies of obsessive–compulsive disorder in adults and children.

Clin. Psychol. Rev. 26 (1), 32–49. Gilleen, J and David, A.S. (2005). The cognitive neuropsychiatry of delusions: from psychopathology to

neuropsychology and back again. Psychological Medicine, 35: 5-12. Ghaemi, S.N. (2004). The perils of belief: Delusions reexamined. Philosophy, Psychiatry, and Psychology. 11:1, 49-

54. Griffiths, P. E. (1997). What Emotions Really Are: The Problem of Psychological Categories. Chicago: Univ. Chicago

Press. Griffiths, P. E. (1999). Squaring the circle: natural kinds with historical essences. In R. A. Wilson (Ed.), Species: New

Interdisciplinary Essays (pp. 208-228). Cambridge, M.A: MIT Press.

Page 32: Disordered Minds/Minding Disorder

Haslam, Nick. "Kinds of Kinds: A Conceptual Taxonomy of Psychiatric Categories." Philosophy, Psychiatry, & Psychology, 9 (2002), 203-218

Heck, R. G. (2007). Are there different kinds of content? In J. Cohen and B. McLaughlin (Eds.), Contemporary Debates in the Philosophy of Mind. Oxford: Blackwell.

Hempel, C. (1965). Fundamentals of taxonomy. In Aspects of Scientific Explanation. (ed. C. Hempel), pp. 137–154. NY, The Free Press.

Hitchcock, C. and Woodward, J.C (2003) ‘‘Explanatory Generalizations, Part II: Plumbing Explanatory Depths,’’ Nouˆs 37, 2.

Humphreys, N. and Dennett, D. (1989). “Speaking for our selves: An assessment of multiple personality disorder,” Raritan, 9(1): 68–98.

Kunert, H.J., Norra, C. and Hoff, P. (2007). Theories of Delusional Disorders. Psychopathology, 40:191-202. Lewis, D. (1973) ‘‘Causation,’’ Journal of Philosophy 70, 556–567. Machamer, P., Darden, L., & Craver, C. (2000). Thinking about mechanisms. Philosophy of Science, 67, 1-

25. Mataix-Cols, D., do Rosario-Campos, M.C., & Leckman, J.F. (2005). A multidimensional model of obsessive-

compulsive disorder. The American Journal of Psychiatry, 162, 228–238. McDowell, J. (1994a). Mind and World. Cambridge MA: Harvard University Press. Millikan, R. (1989).Biosemantics, The Journal of Philosophy 86.6, pp. 281-297. Millikan, R. (1999). Historical Kinds and the Special Sciences. Philosophical Studies. 95: 45-65 Murphy, D. (2006). Psychiatry in the Scientific Image. Cambridge, MA, MIT Press. Murphy, D. (2009)Psychiatry and the concept of disease as pathology. in M.Broome & L. Bortolotti (eds)

Psychiatry as cognitive neuroscience: philosophical perspectives. Oxford University Press. Murphy, Dominic and Woolfolk, Robert L. "The Harmful Dysfunction Analysis of Mental Disorder."

Philosophy, Psychiatry, & Psychology, 7 (2000), 241-252. Peacocke, C. (2001a). Does perception have a non-conceptual content? Journal of Philosophy 98, 239-

264. Salmon, W. (1990). Four Decades of Scientific Explanation. University of Minnesota Press, Minneapolis.

Page 33: Disordered Minds/Minding Disorder

Samuels, R. (2009). Delusions as a Natural Kind. in M.Broome & L. Bortolotti (eds) Psychiatry as cognitive neuroscience: philosophical perspectives. Oxford University Press.

Simpson, H. et al. (2006) Are there reliable neuropsychological deficits in obsessive–compulsive disorder? Journal of Psychiatric Research, Vol40:3, p 247-257

Szasz, Thomas. The Myth of Mental Illness: Foundations of a Theory of Personal Conduct (New York: Harper and Row, 1974.)

Wakefield, Jerome C. "The Concept of Mental Disorder: On the Boundary Between Biological Facts and Social Values." American Psychologist 47, no. 3. (1992): 373-88.

Wakefield JC: Spandrels, vestigial organs, and such: a reply to Murphy and Woolfolk’s “The harmful dysfunctional analysis of mental disorder.” Philo Psychiatr Psychol 2000; 7:253–269

Woodward, J., and C. Hitchcock (2003) ‘‘Explanatory Generalizations, Part I: A Counterfactual Account,’’ Nouˆs 37: 1–24.

Zachar, P. (2000). Psychiatric disorders are not natural kinds. Philosophy, Psychiatry, and Psychology. 7:167-182.

Page 34: Disordered Minds/Minding Disorder

Which account of mental disorder seems most correct? Why?

If there is essentially a normative component to mental disorder, does this threaten the status of psychiatry as a science?

Can mental disorder ever be valuable?

Page 35: Disordered Minds/Minding Disorder