Critical Empathy Vernon Lee s Aesthetics

26
AUTUMN 2012 Critical Empathy: Vernon Lee’s Aesthetics and the Origins of Close Reading Benjamin Morgan V ictorians read books with their bodies. They frequently read aloud, of course, but bodily reading also took subtler forms. Arthur Symons remembered caressing the ribbed paper of Walter Pater’s Studies in the History of the Renaissance (1873). William Morris’s poetry, Stephen Arata suggests, was best appreciated by crafts- people who read as they worked. The sensation novel famously preached to the nerves, operating, according to one line of reasoning, as a modern technology that conveyed as many physical shocks as the bustle and speed of railway travel. These are not just our own theories, either; the Victorians knew quite well that their reading practices depended upon a corporeal substructure. Nicholas Dames has found that Victorian novel critics were finely attuned to the “affective mechanics” of prose (56). And the scandal of some of the century’s most scandalous poetry, from the spasmodics to the aesthetes, lay precisely in its inappropriate stimulation of readers’ bodies. 1 By the early twentieth century, however, literary criticism no longer paid much attention to the kinaesthetics of literature, which seemed an ignoble counterpart to its aesthetics. Most famously, the American literary critics William K. Wimsatt and Monroe Beardsley cordoned off meaning from feeling in “The Affective Fallacy,” which ABSTRACT: Vernon Lee has recently received renewed attention for her theory of physi- ological empathy, which held that artworks were pleasing insofar as they provoked feel- ings of bodily movement. While most studies of Lee take this to be a primarily visual theory, I argue that Lee’s aim was to understand how language mediates corporeal experience. Lee’s unusual views about the physiological origin of metaphor and the promise of quantitative literary analysis formed the basis for a method of empathic close reading that was simultaneously somatic and systematic. I show that this type of reading was a significant target for the anti-affective rhetoric of the New Criticism. As such, Lee’s “critical empathy” suggests a provocative alternative to inherited practices of close reading.

description

Critical Empathy Vernon Lee s Aesthetics

Transcript of Critical Empathy Vernon Lee s Aesthetics

Page 1: Critical Empathy Vernon Lee s Aesthetics

Autumn 2012

Critical Empathy: Vernon Lee’s Aesthetics and the Origins of Close Reading

Benjamin Morgan

Victorians read books with their bodies. they frequently read aloud, of course, but bodily reading also took subtler forms. Arthur Symons remembered caressing the ribbed paper of

Walter Pater’s Studies in the History of the Renaissance (1873). William morris’s poetry, Stephen Arata suggests, was best appreciated by crafts-people who read as they worked. the sensation novel famously preached to the nerves, operating, according to one line of reasoning, as a modern technology that conveyed as many physical shocks as the bustle and speed of railway travel. these are not just our own theories, either; the Victorians knew quite well that their reading practices depended upon a corporeal substructure. nicholas Dames has found that Victorian novel critics were finely attuned to the “affective mechanics” of prose (56). And the scandal of some of the century’s most scandalous poetry, from the spasmodics to the aesthetes, lay precisely in its inappropriate stimulation of readers’ bodies.1

By the early twentieth century, however, literary criticism no longer paid much attention to the kinaesthetics of literature, which seemed an ignoble counterpart to its aesthetics. most famously, the American literary critics William K. Wimsatt and monroe Beardsley cordoned off meaning from feeling in “the Affective Fallacy,” which

AbstrAct: Vernon Lee has recently received renewed attention for her theory of physi-ological empathy, which held that artworks were pleasing insofar as they provoked feel-ings of bodily movement. While most studies of Lee take this to be a primarily visual theory, I argue that Lee’s aim was to understand how language mediates corporeal experience. Lee’s unusual views about the physiological origin of metaphor and the promise of quantitative literary analysis formed the basis for a method of empathic close reading that was simultaneously somatic and systematic. I show that this type of reading was a significant target for the anti-affective rhetoric of the new Criticism. As such, Lee’s “critical empathy” suggests a provocative alternative to inherited practices of close reading.

Page 2: Critical Empathy Vernon Lee s Aesthetics

32 BenjAmIn morgAn

VICtorIAn StuDIeS / VoLume 55, no. 1

pathologized readerly affects such as “goose-flesh experience,” “the ‘shiver down the spine’” (43), and “tears, prickles, or other physiolog-ical symptoms” (47). the epigraph to their essay, a german music theorist’s observation that “we might as well study the properties of wine by getting drunk” (31), perhaps best expresses their efforts to radically isolate meaning from the reader’s body. getting too excited about literature is like getting drunk at a wine tasting: the responsible reader will put her feelings aside and soberly reflect on irony and imagery. Wimsatt and Beardsley’s essay is a polemical expression of a depersonalized critical practice that originated with I. A. richards’s aesthetic theory in the 1920s and was disseminated by the successful pedagogy of the new Criticism.

Why did embodied reading become so distasteful? In order to answer this question, I argue, we need to think about empathy. the aesthetics of empathy underwent a similar and related transition to that which occurred within Anglo-American literary criticism. empathy was originally a term denoting an unconscious physiological reaction to an object, a reaction that involved either the projection of one’s ego into an object or one’s physical mimicry of it. But in the first half of the twentieth century, as a number of historians have observed, empathy lost its bodily connotations and came to signify a psycholog-ical process similar to what would have been called sympathy in the eighteenth and nineteenth centuries.2 In the past two decades, which have seen a resurgence of interest in empathy in the humanities and social sciences, the concept has been understood as closely related to sympathy: sympathy and empathy describe how one individual can share and understand the feelings of another.3 the relation between literature and empathy, as a result, has generally been viewed as impor-tant in relation to ethics (in philosophy) or altruism (in psychology). Writing from the perspective of virtue ethics, martha nussbaum and michael Slote have advocated a liberal humanist version of empathy. especially in nussbaum’s work, the novel is an important site for culti-vating empathy because it positions readers as “people who care intensely about the sufferings and bad luck of others” (66). Suzanne Keen’s work on empathy and literature questions this view, discovering that actual readers empathize in unexpected ways.4 the realistic portrayal of a morally deserving character does not always incite the strongest empathic response; indeed, characters are not empathy’s only objects.5

Page 3: Critical Empathy Vernon Lee s Aesthetics

CrItICAL emPAthy 33

Autumn 2012

this focus on literary empathy as an ethical mode related to sympathy has left unexplored some interesting questions about how the earlier physiological version of empathy helped reimagine the relation-ship between bodies and texts. In this essay, I provide some historical groundwork for a theory of empathic reading that focuses on somatic rather than ethical experience. to do so, I examine a sort of empathy that can perhaps best be explained through an example offered by its foremost theorist, the essayist and critic Vernon Lee. In The Beautiful: An Introduction to Psychological Aesthetics (1913), Lee argues that when we look at a mountain, we experience it as a triangle in motion: “It rises. . . . It rises and keeps on rising, never stopping unless we stop looking at it” (72). Lee describes this sense of rising as an “empathic movement” (73), by which she means a compound of actual upward eye movement and a bodily memory of past feelings of rising. this movement explains “the mysterious importance, the attraction or repulsion, possessed by shapes, audible as well as visible, according to their empathic character” (74). As she works with this example, Lee emphasizes the correspondence between the internal movements of a breathing, balancing body and the perceived movement of a triangle whose lines are “striving” to “arrive” at a point (72). Lee didn’t deny that this type of response could have some-thing to do with feeling for other persons, whom we encounter as we do mountains, as materially substantial beings. For the purposes of this essay, however, I use the term “motional empathy” to distinguish those aspects of Lee’s theory that emphasize the formal, shape-oriented response on which she was most centrally focused.

motional empathy involves affect in ways that are more self-referential than the affects involved in ethical or altruistic engagement. In his influential essay “the Autonomy of Affect,” the cultural theorist Brian massumi distinguishes between affect and emotion, writing that emotion implies a “sociolinguistic fixing” of the meaning of an experi-ence, while affect implies an “immediately embodied,” “purely auto-nomic” reaction (25). While I agree with those of massumi’s critics who are troubled by his positing of a pre-semantic domain of bodily experi-ence, this distinction is useful for sorting out the different levels on which Lee theorizes empathy.6 It is true that perceiving the formal move-ment of a “rising” triangle can lead to feelings like excitement, vitality, or constriction, all of which might seem to be emotions. But in Lee’s under-standing, to be uplifted by a mountain does not require that the moun-tain be personified or even imagined as sentient; as a result, her work

Page 4: Critical Empathy Vernon Lee s Aesthetics

34 BenjAmIn morgAn

VICtorIAn StuDIeS / VoLume 55, no. 1

articulates an odd kind of empathy—the kind I am calling motional empathy—whose primary orientation is not toward the social domain. to borrow massumi’s terms, motional empathy is not yet sociolinguisti-cally fixed. It consists of affects that are autoreferential (for example, “I feel energized”) rather than emotions that are intersubjective (“I share your sadness”).

In the first part of this essay, I argue that Lee’s careful atten-tion to the relationship between motional empathy and language distinguishes her work from previous psychological aesthetics. In the second part, I argue that Lee’s theory of empathy plays a significant but overlooked role in the history of literary criticism. Lee’s theory of empathy was part of a broader project that sought to take seriously a wide range of embodied aesthetic responses. As part of this project, Lee wrote a series of essays on the corporeal feeling of reading that parallel her essays on painting, sculpture, and music. Lee’s empathic reading contests our received history of a break between Victorian physiological aesthetics and later literary formalisms, especially the new Criticism. Put simply, Lee endorses kinaesthetic responses to the rhythms of prose while still gesturing toward the systematic formalist methods that characterized the new Criticism. In making this series of claims, my goal is partly to contextualize Lee’s literary criticism. But the larger significance of my argument has to do with how Lee’s physi-ological theory of empathy can challenge us to reconsider histories and contemporary methods of close reading.

Einfühlung and The Science of Aesthetics

At its origins, empathy is not an experience related to literature or language. the german term Einfühlung, later translated as “empathy,” first appears in a dissertation by the philosopher robert Vischer, On the Optical Sense of Form (1873), which proposes that humans instinctively project themselves into the objects they see. In an important passage, Vischer writes that a dreamer’s body “unconsciously projects its own bodily form—and with this also the soul—into the form of the object.” “From this,” he adds, “I derived the notion that I call ‘empathy’ [Einfühl ung]” (97). not merely a dream state, Einfühlung was provoked in everyday life by basic visual sensations such as the stimulating pleasures of curves, light, and complementary colors. more complex versions of Einfühlung took two forms: “physiognomic,” which involved static physical

Page 5: Critical Empathy Vernon Lee s Aesthetics

CrItICAL emPAthy 35

Autumn 2012

forms, like a small flower that produces a feeling of compression; and “mimicking,” which involved movement, like tree branches that cause a viewer to feel as though she is spreading her arms (104–05).

the psychologist theodor Lipps developed Vischer’s idea, aban-doning its metaphysical tenor, challenging the notion of literal physical mimicry, and suggesting the possibility of Einfühlung for persons in addi-tion to objects. Like Vischer’s, Lipps’s version of Einfühlung is oriented toward visual perception. Lipps came to his study of empathy by way of an interest in optical illusions; his early work had addressed a debate over whether it was a cognitive or perceptual defect that allowed an optical illusion to trick the mind. this question about how the mind interacts with visual faculties then became central to his descriptions of Einfühlung. In his Ästhetik: Psychologie des Schönen und der Kunst (Aesthetics: The Psychology of Beauty and Art) (1903), Lipps observes that when we look at a line, we “create” the line with our bodies by following it from point to point with our eyes. our body thus contributes to the existence of the line by more or less performing it. Lipps emphasizes that he is not just describing a process of contemplation internal to the mind (“was mir die reflexion sagt” ‘what reflection tells me’) but a feeling of being identical with the line (“ich fühle mich fortstrebend und tätig in der Linie” ‘I feel myself striving and acting in the line’). “As we know,” Lipps says, “this is the meaning of Einfühlung” (1: 236–37, my translation). According to Lipps, the same sort of thing occurs when one looks at a Doric column and considers the mechanical forces that allow it to support the building; the column pleasantly “sets up an image [Bild] of similar effort within ourselves” (Raumästhetik 7, my translation).

Lipps’s emphasis on the “image” of effort differentiated his theory from that of a rival, Karl groos, who believed that physical imitation of visual form (“innere nachahmung” ‘inner mimicry’), and not just the image of movement, took place in the moment of aesthetic experience. According to groos, a beautiful object incites “movement and postural sensations (especially those of equilibrium), light muscular innervations, together with visual and respiratory move-ment” (328). By contrast, others argued that Einfühlung didn’t exist at all. In 1903, the psychologist oswald Külpe placed subjects in a dark room, projected twenty-eight images of greek architecture and sculp-ture on the wall for three seconds each, and discovered that no columns, Doric or otherwise, caused viewers to feel as though they were moving (Külpe 231).

Page 6: Critical Empathy Vernon Lee s Aesthetics

36 BenjAmIn morgAn

VICtorIAn StuDIeS / VoLume 55, no. 1

the other major context for what Lee would eventually theo-rize as empathy was a British tradition originating with edmund Burke’s Philosophical Enquiry (1757) that treated aesthetics as a science of perception. just as german psychological theory was focused on problems of sensory perception, this brand of aesthetics examined the pleasurable sensory qualities of objects rather than their complex, human-created meanings. Writing in the wake of a new physiological model of the self developed in the 1820s and 1830s, theorists including george Field, Alexander Bain, and David ramsay hay argued that aesthetic pleasure was best understood as the body’s response to form, color, and sound. hay, for example, studied the relative beauty of basic geometrical shapes, arguing in numerous books that a universal math-ematics of harmony explained the beauty of architecture, music, color, and women. Similarly viewing aesthetics as the science of pleasurable sense perception, Bain argued in his mid-century psychology text-books that curves were more pleasing than angles because they allowed the eye to move in a more natural fashion, and that musical harmony pleasurably impressed the nerves.7

herbert Spencer and Charles Darwin’s theories of development and evolution in the late 1850s shifted the temporal and quantitative scale of what was sometimes called “aesthetical science” from the discrete moment of perception to deep evolutionary time, and from the indi-vidual to the species. A central question after Darwin and Spencer was whether aesthetic pleasure contained any sort of species utility, and, if not, why it existed. Darwin, as jonathan Smith has argued, made the idea of an animal sense of beauty a crucial part of The Descent of Man (1871) (27–28). Like Darwin, Spencer inquired into aesthetic pleasure from the perspective of evolutionary time, arguing in Principles of Psychology (1855) that the arts release pent-up energies that, in a less leisurely society, would have been expended in mere survival. though they viewed aesthetics through a much wider temporal lens, works in this vein retained a focus on a bodily economy of pleasure made up of ener-gies, instincts, and release valves. these physiological and evolutionary aesthetics were synthesized by the science writer grant Allen in Physiolog-ical Aesthetics (1877), which was well received by Victorian intellectuals, including Vernon Lee, who already in 1880 took the stance that art is an “organic physico-mental entity” (“Comparative Aesthetics” 306). Appearing just as psychology was becoming a consolidated, autonomous discipline, Allen’s work presaged the study of aesthetic experience by

Page 7: Critical Empathy Vernon Lee s Aesthetics

CrItICAL emPAthy 37

Autumn 2012

professional psychologists. In the early issues of Britain’s first psychology journal, Mind, the science of beauty was debated by prominent thinkers including james Sully, henry rutgers marshall, and james h. tufts. By the end of the century, aesthetics was widely considered a science, with Einfühlung as one of its major subfields.

The Language of Empathy

In the 1890s, Lee and her lover, Clementina Anstruther-thomson, spent much of their time in museums looking at greek art in order to conduct what Lee calls an “objective” study of the feelings it provoked (Beauty and Ugliness 276). Lee was unaware of the theories of groos, Lipps, and Vischer when she began developing this version of embodied aesthetics. But she was not scientifically naive: as a number of Lee scholars have shown, she developed her theory of art in relation to British physiological aesthetics.8 Lee’s views were also indebted to Walter Pater, with whom she was close. Pater had rejected metaphysics in the Conclusion to The Renaissance (1873), and had asked in the Preface, “What is this song or picture . . . to me? What effect does it really produce on me? . . . how is my nature modified by its presence, and under its influence?” (xix-xx). In 1897, Lee and Anstruther-thomson took these questions a step further in a major essay on psychological aesthetics, “Beauty and ugliness.” the essay uses the language of physiological aesthetics to answer Pater’s questions with brilliant, almost parodic literalness. In one representative passage, Anstruther-thomson looks at the facade of Santa maria novella and notes that “the perception of the middle part [of the building] . . . involves an adjustment which prevents the thorax from collapsing as much as usual during the act of expiration,” therefore producing a feeling of expansion (560). here, the presence of art certainly produces Paterian “effects” and “modifications.”

But as Lee’s insistence on objectivity implies, her work departs from the introspective standpoint of Pater’s “me.” Santa maria novella does not cause a flight of fancy or offer imaginative access to the past, as La Gioconda famously does for Pater, but merely causes the viewer to shift her balance and breathe more deeply. Art’s effects resonate in a specific body with muscles and lungs rather than in an abstract subject. When Lee discovered german psychology, she recognized that Einfühlung, not aestheticism, explained her and Anstruther-thomson’s response to

Page 8: Critical Empathy Vernon Lee s Aesthetics

38 BenjAmIn morgAn

VICtorIAn StuDIeS / VoLume 55, no. 1

beauty. over the next fifteen years, she published a number of essays on the topic, some of which were collected in Beauty and Ugliness (1912), an unfortunately ponderous and disorganized book. Despite its stylistic infelicities, the book was at the forefront of widespread interest in empathy in Anglo-American aesthetics.

Lee and Anstruther-thomson develop physiological aesthetics in two directions, which I would characterize as procedural and theo-retical. Both developments are oriented toward language. Procedurally, they transform empathy from an abstract theory into a critical practice that involves writing about what one feels. Studying empathy implicitly requires a transcription of semiconscious bodily responses into narra-tive. In Lee’s work, as distinct from previous physiological aesthetics, empathy is linked with writing and expression rather than with mute response. theoretically, Lee bases many of her arguments about empathy on language—either metaphors used in everyday speech or the figures used by other empathy theorists to describe the moment of “feeling-into” (Einfühlung). more than mere skirmishes over philosoph-ical terms, Lee’s arguments proceed from a deep conviction that the phenomenon of empathy is not divorced from language; rather, empathy explains how we use and understand metaphor.

this turn to language was probably as much out of necessity as out of intellectual commitment. Lee did not have the requisite training to be a mainstream physiological aesthetician, nor, as a woman, could she easily have obtained it. What she and Anstruther-thomson did have was extensive experience actually looking at art. It is possible that Lee spent more time viewing artworks than did any other writer on physiological aesthetics—perhaps more, even, than Pater and john ruskin, whose travels in europe were not as extensive. Lee lived in Italy, where she spent much of her time visiting churches and museums; she often spent winters in London, where she passed her days at the British museum, the Victoria and Albert museum, and the national gallery; and when commuting between england and Italy, she would visit the Louvre and the churches of northern France (gunn 148). In the 1890s, Anstruther-thomson accompanied Lee on these travels. As she visited museums, Lee kept diaries detailing the state of her body as she looked at art: its “palpitations,” the strains of music that were stuck in her mind, and whether she was tired or bored. Based upon the lived experience of the gallery and museum, Lee and Anstruther-thomson’s work aspired systematically to collect data about aesthetic response in

Page 9: Critical Empathy Vernon Lee s Aesthetics

CrItICAL emPAthy 39

Autumn 2012

order to arrive inductively at a general aesthetic theory. Lee later describes this method as a process of continually asking herself, “‘how have I perceived and felt to-day in my relations with given works of art?’ until little by little I have found myself with so many introspective data to verify and compare that there has ensued a deliberate system” (Beauty and Ugliness 242). this characterization of words as “data” is clearly meant to elevate the humble diary into a proper scientific object. But it simultaneously, if perhaps unintentionally, transforms motional empathy into a linguistic phenomenon.

to analyze this narrative mediation of empathy more closely, I turn to Anstruther-thomson’s first-person accounts. this writing formed a large part of the essay “Beauty and ugliness,” and Lee published many of Anstruther-thomson’s notes posthumously in Art and Man (1924). Lee scholars have noted that Anstruther-thomson’s body can be read as one origin of Lee’s theory of empathy, but Anstruther-thomson’s writing has generally been read as context for Lee’s theory rather than on its own terms.9 yet in her seemingly naive essays, lectures, and frag-ments, whose topics range from art restoration to the mythology of centaurs, Anstruther-thomson describes her response to art in ways that reflexively theorize how an immediate, uninformed response to art might achieve relevance beyond the individual viewer.

In one particularly evocative lecture, “What Patterns Can Do to us,” Anstruther-thomson explains the precise formal mechanisms by which the two-dimensional patterns on a vase compensate for imperfections in the vase’s three-dimensional form (see fig. 1). Anstruther-thomson does not see the patterns as optical illusions, but as provocations for complex interactions between the viewer’s body and the physical vase. the patterns on the vase, in other words, do not trick a mind conceived as separate from the body, but immediately affect the body and mind together in such a way that aesthetic pleasure is the residue manifested in consciousness. Describing what Lee would have designated “empathy,” Anstruther-thomson recounts the forces and movements that join the vase and her body:

other parts of our body will insist on telling us about the vase, too. In fact, they insist on helping our eye by doing the shapes in some rudimentary fashion inside us to an extent we may feel almost as an actual alteration of the shape of our own body. So the addition of a lifting pattern to the base of the vase comes to us as a very real modification in the shape of the vase, because it suddenly thrusts into our own body a feeling of lifting which we cannot help realizing. And every

Page 10: Critical Empathy Vernon Lee s Aesthetics

40 BenjAmIn morgAn

VICtorIAn StuDIeS / VoLume 55, no. 1

additional shape is hammered into us so energetically by our body that we have to believe its testimony rather than that of our eye. (140)

this passage is more complex than it may at first seem. Anstruther-thomson ruptures the distinction between subjectivity and objectivity by making aesthetic experience the result of actions and forces that are equally the formal properties of a visual form and the physical proper-ties of a human body (the “lifting” pattern on the vase lifts Anstruther-thomson’s body). In contrast to idealist aesthetics, this type of aesthetic response has little to do with contemplation or cognition. relin-quishing interior consciousness, Anstruther-thomson understands agency to exceed the human viewer. She takes the work of art to be more active than the viewer who encounters it: a given pattern makes the viewer a passive recipient as it “thrusts” its lifting feeling.

Anstruther-thomson’s language alienates the body from the speaker at a level that is rhetorical as well as physiological. the body “hammers” and “[does] shapes . . . inside us,” but it also operates in the linguistic registers of “telling” and offering “testimony.” the body thus possesses a subjectivity that is autonomous from the subject who inhabits the body: her body’s doing and speaking is not identical with Anstruther-thomson’s doing and thinking. the body is further displaced as a collective possession—“our body,” “our own body”—shared by the lecturer and her listeners. Via the rhetorical inclusive-ness of the first-person-plural pronoun, Anstruther-thomson presents

Fig. 1. Clementina Anstruther-thomson, “three outlines of a greek amphora, redrawn for experiment by C. A.-t.” Clementina Anstruther-thomson, Art and Man:

Essays & Fragments, edited by Vernon Lee (London: john Lane, 1924): 138.

Page 11: Critical Empathy Vernon Lee s Aesthetics

CrItICAL emPAthy 41

Autumn 2012

the figure of an imaginatively shared physical self. the body, insepa-rable from the mind, becomes an important source of knowledge, awareness, and information: this is a critical practice not premised upon a mind/body divide. her lecture does not lead to an intersubjec-tive emotional economy of feelings and sentiments that we might see between a person and a personified thing. rather, if we read closely, it is clear that this is an interobjective motional economy of force and energy, hammering and thrusting, weighing and lifting. In this and other writing, what Anstruther-thomson has to say about empathy is matched in importance by how she says it. hers is an exhortative mode of writing that theorizes implicitly through its use of language rather than explicitly by logical reasoning. this instance illustrates one way in which Lee and Anstruther-thomson transform the notion of empathy: they make forms of paraliterary writing—the lecture, the gallery diary—central to empathic experience.

Linked to this shift in method is a second important transfor-mation, having to do with metaphor. Lee identified a “special pecu-liarity” of empathy, its close ties to figurative language, in a 1904 Quarterly Review article:

Einfühlung . . . is at the bottom of numberless words and expressions whose daily use has made us overlook this special peculiarity. We say, for instance, that hills roll and mountains rise. . . . We attribute movement to motionless lines and surfaces; they move, spread out, flow, bend, twist, etc. they do, to quote m. Souriau’s ingenious formula, what we should feel ourselves doing if we were inside them. For we are inside them; we have felt ourselves, projected our own experience into them. (“recent Aesthetics” 433, emphasis original)

here, Lee embraces a theory that, following ruskin, we might call the “empathetic fallacy.” ruskin found that bad poets do exactly what Lee describes: a person overwhelmed by emotion might inaccurately feel that foam “crawls” and, if he or she is a bad poet, will simply transcribe that feeling into verse. But for Lee, there is a tremendous degree of accuracy in this kind of description. to write that foam crawls may be a poor description of what the foam does, but it is a precise description of what we feel when we look at it. Common “words and expressions” therefore provide insight into the way that empathy operates, since, according to this account, figurative language is natural and physio-logical, not arbitrary and cultural. We may understand Lee’s theory of figurative speech, then, as partially anticipating what george Lakoff

Page 12: Critical Empathy Vernon Lee s Aesthetics

42 BenjAmIn morgAn

VICtorIAn StuDIeS / VoLume 55, no. 1

and mark johnson have theorized as “metaphorical concepts” (6). Like Lee, they argue that the meaning of an unconsciously used metaphor such as “finishing up” is inseparable from physical and cultural experi-ences of “verticality” (19). Lee’s version of this line of reasoning locates the physiological body as the origin of metaphor. As Lakoff and johnson decipher culture through its metaphors, so Lee relies on metaphor to decipher human psychophysiology.

Lee’s attention to the figures used to describe empathy extends beyond this particular instance. A year after collecting her essays on empathy in Beauty and Ugliness, Lee published The Beautiful as part of a Cambridge university Press series that invited experts to introduce their area of knowledge to educated laypeople. Far more accessible than Beauty and Ugliness, this book successfully disseminated the concept of empathy in Anglo-American aesthetics. throughout The Beautiful, Lee uses everyday language to illustrate technical claims about the psychology of aesthetic experience (the first chapter, for example, addresses “the Adjective ‘Beautiful’”). In a passage that prepares the reader for the strangeness of the theory of empathy—she is about to explain that we empathize with the triangular form of a mountain by rising along with it—Lee observes that it is actually difficult to avoid language that betrays an original empathic relation to one’s visual environment:

of course we all know that, objects the reader, and of course nobody imagines that the rock and the earth of the mountain is rising, or that the mountain is getting up or growing taller! All we mean is that the mountain looks as if it were rising. the mountain looks! Surely here is a case of putting the cart before the horse. no; we cannot explain the mountain rising by the mountain looking, for the only looking in the business is our looking at the mountain. And if the reader objects again that these are all figures of speech, I shall answer that Empathy is what explains why we employ figures of speech at all, and occasionally employ them, as in the case of this rising mountain, when we know perfectly well that the figure we have chosen expresses the exact reverse of the objective truth. (61–62)

here, Lee clarifies what it means for empathy to be “at the bottom” of familiar expressions (“recent Aesthetics” 433). It is not just that certain metaphors happen to be based on embodied experience, but that the very possibility of figuration is the result of our visual rela-tionship with a material environment. In noting the double attribution of the verb “looks” to the mountain and to the viewer, Lee creates a palimpsest of linguistic and visual figures that mirrors the way in which

Page 13: Critical Empathy Vernon Lee s Aesthetics

CrItICAL emPAthy 43

Autumn 2012

her theory writes language onto the domain of visual perception. the triangular form of the mountain expresses itself physiologically as the viewer’s unconscious tendency to rise, and it expresses itself linguistically as the viewer’s spoken attribution of agency to the mountain. (A similar duplication of words and force is at play in Anstruther-thomson’s vase, which testifies and hammers.) For Lee, this double relationship is the origin of figurative language. Where Lipps invites his reader to discover empathy by looking at a line, Lee asks her reader to learn about empathy by reflecting on what it means to say that something “looks.”

It may seem that the emphasis on language is merely a peda-gogical heuristic. After all, in The Beautiful Lee is writing for readers who are not versed in the technical language of psychology; her concern with language may proceed from a wish to explain difficult concepts in everyday terms. But Lee turns her attention to words and phrases even when addressing the most difficult and arcane aspects of empathy theory. In a more technical essay originally written for the French journal Revue Philosophique, Lee objects to Lipps’s claim about what happens to the ego of a person who experiences empathy by challenging the metaphor he uses. In his Ästhetik, Lipps says almost in passing that the empathic ego “lives in the thing contemplated” (“es lebt in der betrachteten Sache”), meaning that the self “transcends”—literally, is lifted above (“hinausgehoben”)—the individual by becoming absorbed in an external aesthetic object (2: 87). Latching onto this phrase, Lee asks whether the image of an ego “living” elsewhere implies

leaving the realm of reality (imagined in some way as dimensional space) to take up its abode in “the work of art,” to participate in its life and to detach itself from its own, after the fashion of the Lenten retreat of a Catholic escaping from the world and purifying himself in the life of a convent? this metaphor might be applied, but it would not make us forget that the ego is not an entity apart. (Beauty

and Ugliness 59)

just as Lee finds clues about how Einfühlung operates by examining metaphors in everyday speech, she exposes Lipps’s reliance on the idea of an autonomous ego by interrogating his figurative language.

Perhaps figuration proves to be fertile ground for Lee because the theory of empathy had been caught up in tensions between language and embodied perception from its inception. In On the Optical Sense of Form, Vischer generates multiple neologisms besides Einfühlung in his attempt to describe unusual modes of perception. he coins the terms

Page 14: Critical Empathy Vernon Lee s Aesthetics

44 BenjAmIn morgAn

VICtorIAn StuDIeS / VoLume 55, no. 1

Anfühlung (attentive feeling), Ausfühlung (out-feeling), Nachfühlung (responsive feeling), Zufühlung (immediate feeling), and Zusammenfüh-lung (feeling-together); he also formulates all of these terms with the suffix -empfindung, or sensation (thus Einempfindung, sensing-into). one senses that this proliferation of terms seeks to compensate through sheer abundance for the resistance to language of one’s embodied response to objects. For Lee, this resistance means that the experience of empathy is usually captured unconsciously, through metaphor. empathy is an expe-rience that must be unearthed with the tools of linguistic analysis; it resists the scientific formula and opts instead for the obliquity of meta-phor and the partiality of first-person narrative.

“Vital Tempo”

If a close reading of Lee’s aesthetics reveals that she is deeply invested in the language of empathy, her other writing of the period reveals that she is equally interested in what it would mean to empathize with language. Lee’s literary criticism and her aesthetics have generally been treated separately, in part because her book of literary criticism, The Handling of Words (1923), was published well after her writing on empathy. In fact, however, most of the essays collected in the volume were written and published at the same time as her essays on aesthetic empathy. reading Lee’s literary criticism alongside her empathy theory allows us both to recognize coherence across Lee’s critical projects and to see how her work anticipated and challenged twentieth-century literary formalisms.

even before she began writing about visual empathy, Lee had explored how a reader might somatically respond to linguistic patterns. Beginning in the 1890s, Lee focused on literature as a psychological medium: a book, Lee writes in “of Writers and readers” (1891), is “a certain number of items conveyed from one mind to another, and a certain mode of conveying” (529). Framed as means of conveyance, literature raises a constellation of questions that center on the cogni-tive mechanics of language: What uses of language convey meaning most precisely? how do readers with different sorts of minds extract similar meanings from the same poem? What are the specific qualities that make this “conveying” pleasing?

In 1903 and 1904, Lee published a three-part series of articles in the Contemporary Review, “Studies in Literary Psychology,” that answered

Page 15: Critical Empathy Vernon Lee s Aesthetics

CrItICAL emPAthy 45

Autumn 2012

these questions. the titles alert the reader that Lee’s focus will be textual, even linguistic: “the Syntax of De Quincy [sic],” “the rhetoric of Landor,” and “Carlyle and the Present tense.” the first essay adopts a method for evaluating prose that Lee had first encountered in the work of the hungarian historian emil reich and that she would develop over the next twenty years (Seed xiii). the logic of this method is as follows. First, Lee observes that style can be thought of as a physical tic—“a kind of gesture or gait”—that symptomatically reveals the writer’s tempera-ment. If this is the case, the critic can act as a psychologist who deciphers language in order to uncover the writer’s “unconscious habit” (“Syntax” 713). to do so requires a mathematical critical practice that quantifies parts of speech. Lee therefore adds together the writer’s verbs, adverbs, and active participles, and compares this result to the total number of nouns and adjectives.

thomas De Quincey, it turns out, uses more parts of speech in the latter category (static) than in the former (active). on its own, this is perhaps not very informative, but when brought into relation with other writers the results become more interesting: similarly quanti-fying the prose of Daniel Defoe and robert Louis Stevenson produces “the exactly opposite result.” Inspired by this discovery, Lee writes, “It seemed to me now that I had got two categories of style—the one in which the chief part was given to action, as in Defoe and Stevenson; and the other in which, so to speak, mere being . . . was to the fore” (“Syntax” 713). Lee’s quantitative analysis of parts of speech in one passage of De Quincey’s Levana (1845) leads her to the conclusion that “a certain heavy jerkiness” and “lack of movement” results from the preponderance of inactive nouns and adjectives; “the fine movement of this passage seems to begin when this crowd of pronouns . . . at last comes to an end” (717).

nicholas Dames has persuasively traced the origins of this reading-by-numbers to nineteenth-century psychophysics and the physiological language of Victorian literary criticism: Lee’s computa-tional mode disintegrates prose into its “minimal units,” just as experi-mental physiologists treated perception as a sum of “ just noticeable differences” (189). But unless we read Lee’s computational literary criticism in relation to her theory of visual empathy, her determina-tions may seem arbitrary. What justifies the leap from a quantitative observation (a preponderance of nouns) to a particular somatic expe-rience, such as “heavy jerkiness”? We can answer this question by

Page 16: Critical Empathy Vernon Lee s Aesthetics

46 BenjAmIn morgAn

VICtorIAn StuDIeS / VoLume 55, no. 1

attending to the mutually constitutive relationship between Lee’s literary and aesthetic theories: both are partial articulations of a larger model of corporeal aesthetic response that Lee understands to operate across the arts, including prose, painting, sculpture, architecture, and music. too many pronouns produce jerkiness by the same mechanism that a triangle produces a sensation of rising or that a musical phrase gives a sense of forward movement.

Lee articulates this connection between her literary and aesthetic theory, though implicitly, in an 1894 article in the New Review, “the Craft of Words.” though Lee does not use the term, she describes a phenomenon resembling empathy, but here it results from literary rather than visual form:

there are words which make the reader think and feel, in a way live, slowly; and there are other words which make the reader think, feel, and live quickly, and quickly and smoothly, or quickly and jerkily, as the case may be. Above all, there are arrangements of words—combinations of action and reaction of word upon word, which, by opening up vistas or closing them, make the reader’s mind dawdle, hurry, or labour busily along. now, by a law of our mental constitution, whatever kind of movement a picture, a piece of music, or a page of writing sets up in us, that particular kind of movement do we attribute to the objects represented or suggested by the picture, the music, or the writing; it is no idle affectation, no mere conventional desire to make things match, which makes us hate the lengthy telling of a brief moment, the jerky description of a solemn fact. (577)

the “law of our mental constitution” that Lee describes is remarkably similar to what would eventually go under the name “empathy” in Beauty and Ugliness. just as Anstruther-thomson finds in the movement of forms on a greek vase a sense of vitality and lively activity, Lee finds in the patterns of language the rhythms of lived experience.

this attribution of felt movement to language is the obverse of Lee’s theory that we unconsciously derive metaphor from original experiences of empathy. Like other aesthetic forms, literary prose has forceful temporal effects that, if ineffectively deployed, disrupt a read-er’s cognitive ambulation. In a 1923 letter to the Times, Lee describes this feeling as a trans-artistic “vital tempo”: “What for me corresponds to the patterns of melody and harmony of the musician, to the patterns of lines and colours of the painter, is not the events and feelings of which [the novelist] tells us . . . but the pattern of words, the co-ordinations of verbal tenses . . . with which he solicits our responsive sensibility and imagination” (“Vital tempo” 8). When Lee empathizes with literature,

Page 17: Critical Empathy Vernon Lee s Aesthetics

CrItICAL emPAthy 47

Autumn 2012

she feels the movement of syntax. motional empathy specifically excludes the “events and feelings” that make up narrative.

given the aesthetic qualities of Lee’s literary criticism (its attention to reading as sensory experience) and the literary qualities of her aesthetics (its drive toward making visual forms into language), we should think of Lee’s writing on literature not merely as literary criticism but as part of a cross-media project promoting empathy itself as a critical mode. motional empathy is not limited to the visual domain; it accounts for a wide range of responses to art, literature, and music. the body is a node where the formal properties of any art—color, sound, depth, syntax—intersect. As opposed to earlier physio-logical aesthetics that disaggregated complex artworks into lines, curves, and angles, Lee focuses on how the body synthesizes formal qualities as feeling. this practice is critical because the body is not a mute receptor for formal stimuli; rather, the somatic reception of form provokes articulation—unconsciously as metaphor, or consciously as a gallery diary or lecture. empathic critical response works across and between the arts without erasing the differences among them.

this physiological formalism complicates the opposition between embodied feeling and disembodied formalism with which I began this essay, allowing us to rethink a crucial transition in the history of literary criticism. Lee’s The Handling of Words appeared a year before the book to which we usually trace modern literary analysis, I. A. richards’s Principles of Literary Criticism (1924). Due to its careful atten-tion to language and form, Lee’s book has occasionally been recog-nized for its prescience. As Vineta Colby notes in her biography, one editor of Lee’s work finds in The Handling of Words evidence that Lee anticipated such luminaries as “I. A. richards, the russian formalists, mikhail Bakhtin, Wolfgang Iser, and roland Barthes” (200). my claim is less ambitious but more precise: Lee’s empathic literary theory was unattractive to critics such as richards precisely because it promised to reconcile Victorian physiological aesthetics with theories and practices that became central to the new Criticism.

richards framed Principles of Literary Criticism as overcoming, rather than developing, the kind of aesthetics that Lee pursues. the titles of richards’s opening chapters vividly convey this polemical rejec-tion: “the Chaos of Critical theories” and “the Phantom Aesthetic State” catalogue affective aesthetic theories in order to challenge their fallacies. Lee’s theory of empathy has the misfortune to appear in both:

Page 18: Critical Empathy Vernon Lee s Aesthetics

48 BenjAmIn morgAn

VICtorIAn StuDIeS / VoLume 55, no. 1

first as one of the failed attempts to explain the value of the arts, and then as an example of the misguided supposition that we can point at something called “aesthetic experience” that is as different from everyday life as “mathematical calculation is from eating cherries” (14). What would later be taken as a founding gesture of new Criticism begins in part by dismissing Lee’s project as chaotic and misdirected.

tracing the fate of empathy through richards’s intellectual progeny, one finds various grounds for disregarding Lee’s innovations. Wimsatt and Beardsley reject empathy in “the Affective Fallacy” (1949): “the Einfühlung or empathy of Lipps and related pleasure theo-ries” (28) are outmoded forms of criticism that confuse the emotional effect of art with art itself, and therefore fail to be criticism at all: “general affective theory at the literary level has . . . produced little actual criticism. . . . In applied criticism there would seem to be not much room for synaesthesis or for the touchy little attitudes of which it is composed” (45). A few years later, in Wimsatt and Cleanth Brooks’s widely influential Literary Criticism: A Short History (1957), Lee at first seems simply to have disappeared between chapters twenty-two on Pater’s aestheticism and twenty-three on Benedetto Croce’s expres-sionism. But she makes a belated appearance in a chapter on richards, as a foil representing the error of taking beauty as a positive quality of an object. Lee’s theory of empathy, according to Wimsatt and Brooks, is “too vague to represent any real advance over the usual hedonistic account of art” (615). rené Wellek, in a 1966 essay, makes rare refer-ence to her literary criticism and studies of style—“they seem often elementary but are full of shrewd observations unusual for the time (the 1890s) in which they were written”—but only in order to note that her scientific work on empathy is “superseded” and that the position taken by Bernard Berenson (a rival of Lee’s) has better withstood the test of time (185). Although one encounters occasional attempts to resuscitate Lee’s theories, such as richard Fogle’s chapter on “empathic Imagery” in The Imagery of Keats and Shelley (1949), her crit-ical project did not on the whole withstand this critique.

If one views Lee’s empathy as an unverifiable affective response to art, then it is not surprising that it would be anathema to a generation of critics disturbed by the unruly personal interpretations of poetry that richards took to task in Practical Criticism (1929). In the decades following Lee’s publications, the goal of Anglo-American criticism was not to culti-vate individual sensibilities but to establish a set of principles that would

Page 19: Critical Empathy Vernon Lee s Aesthetics

CrItICAL emPAthy 49

Autumn 2012

prevent as far as possible the confusion of personal feeling and poetic meaning. these critics certainly would have read Anstruther-thomson’s lecture on how a greek vase makes her body lift upward as the visual corollary of richards’s students’ inability to summarize a poem. In Prac-tical Criticism, the subjectivity of response is precisely the problem that needs to be diagnosed—as, for example, “stock response” or “irrelevant association” (223)—and then pedagogically solved.

But if we read Lee’s theory of empathy as a data-based account of aesthetic and literary response, we can recognize the new Critical rejection of Lee’s aesthetics as a strategic move in the service of a literary history that wishes for a clear break between Victorian moral-aesthetic evaluative criticism and modern analytical, descriptive criti-cism. In her literary criticism, Lee, like richards, works toward a systematic, autonomous method. Indeed, it is so implicitly teachable that one especially clever reviewer of The Handling of Words applied it to Lee’s own writing, discovering that she is, by her own metric, a “none too accurate writer” (“Words”). In its most developed form, Lee’s method involves the quantification of language according to parts of speech in order to explain systematically the effects of prose—not Wimsatt and Beardsley’s “touchy little attitudes” or hedonism (43). From this perspective, we can see that richards is not trying to solve a problem that Lee created by indulging the extreme subjectivism of empathy. rather, Lee and richards are both seeking objective literary-critical practices. But where richards’s version of objectivity rejects the body as a site of linguistic meaning, turning instead to the brain, Lee retains corporeal experience as central to her theory of reading.

I would like to elaborate this claim by analyzing one instance in which Lee’s literary empathy provides some tools for resisting richards’s history of criticism. A long section at the core of richards’s Principles reveals that richards and Lee share sympathies that are obscured by richards’s introductory chapters. Beginning with “A Sketch for a Psychology,” moving through his notorious squiggly diagram of a read-er’s response to a line of robert Browning’s “Pan and Luna” (1880), and concluding with an application of this psychological theory to sculpture and music, richards lays the technical groundwork for the book’s influ-ential claims about how the arts provide “finer adjustment” (234) and “increased competence and sanity” (235), and extend the “range and complexity of the impulse-systems” (237). richards’s middle chapters on the mechanics of psychological response closely track Lee’s observations

Page 20: Critical Empathy Vernon Lee s Aesthetics

50 BenjAmIn morgAn

VICtorIAn StuDIeS / VoLume 55, no. 1

on the dynamics of prose. to analyze the physiological dimension of linguistic rhythm, richards selects the same writer that Lee chose for one of her first objects of “random analysis” in 1903: Walter Savage Landor, the romantic poet and essayist (“rhetoric” 856). Quoting Landor, richards asks some questions about cadence: “After ‘obscurely green’ would it be possible (quite apart from sense) to have ‘deeply dark’ or ‘impenetrably gloomy’? Why, apart from sense, can so few of the sylla-bles be changed in vowel sound, in emphasis, in duration or otherwise, without disaster to the total effect?” richards is more conservative than Lee in drawing conclusions from his substitutive method of close reading, but his answers likewise attend to the felt rhythms of prose narrative: “As with all such questions about sensory form and its effects, only an incomplete answer can be given. the expectancy caused by what has gone before, a thing which must be thought of as a very complex tide of neural settings, lowering the threshold for some kinds of stimuli and raising it for others, and the character of the stimulus which does actu-ally come, both play their part” (Principles 135).

the ebb and flow of “neural settings” relocates to the brain what Lee’s 1903 analysis of Landor had identified as an effect on the body. For Lee, Landor’s greatness lies in the fact that his syntax and diction do not put the reader to sleep or give her a headache. this may sound like the faintest of all possible praise, but Lee is sincere:

his structure of sentences, for instance, is both musically and grammatically a wonder. See . . . how he alternates nouns, verbs, adjectives, and even adjectives and participles. . . . your mind is stimulated to such gentle yet vigorous exercise by the beautiful and constantly varied cadence, never putting you to sleep by one sort of repetition, nor giving you a headache by another. (“rhetoric” 859)

richards and Lee both understand prose to stimulate the body so as to produce “exercise” (Lee) or “sanity” (richards). But for Lee, this stim-ulation accords with the discourse of nineteenth-century physiological aesthetics, from hay to Allen, that richards frames Principles as having overcome. “Vigorous exercise” is much more akin to the corporeal response of Anstruther-thomson’s lifting and Spencer’s evolutionary energy than to richards’s mental processing of the “articulatory verbal image,” “auditory verbal image,” and “tied imagery” (116). Lee’s literary criticism extends the nineteenth-century notion that art exercises the body, but she develops a modern method of computational analysis to demonstrate how this exercise takes place.

Page 21: Critical Empathy Vernon Lee s Aesthetics

CrItICAL emPAthy 51

Autumn 2012

The Feeling of Reading

thinking more carefully about methods that were regarded as failures by the new Critics is especially valuable now, as the field of literary studies again reevaluates its central practices. It once seemed unquestionable that studying literature required close textual analysis. But recent scholarship has challenged the long ascendancy of close reading that was initiated by richards’s early books and that arguably persisted through deconstruction and new historicism. Special issues of New Literary History and Representations have recently asked whether the common methods and goals of close reading—uncovering a text’s polit-ical commitments, historicizing its meaning, plotting its contextual networks—have become ossified.10 In their place, an array of innovative kinds of reading are on offer, which might be tracked by the adjectives that have been proposed as alternatives to the claustrophobic “close”: “surface,” “literal,” “distant,” “cognitive,” “uncritical,” and, fancifully, “obbligato.”11 Within this variegated field of alternatives to close reading, some literary critics have turned to the body of the reader in order to move beyond the disembodied text of new Criticism and poststructur-alism. Charles Altieri has called for more attention to “the sensuous dimension of literary experience” (71); rachel Ablow, discussing “the feeling of reading” (2), observes that we have a “rather limited range of terms” for describing our felt interactions with texts (9).

We can only understand why we have an impoverished sense of literary somatics if we are familiar with how early twentieth-century critics opted out of physiological aesthetics. In this regard, Lee’s account of crit-ical empathy has something important to offer as we imagine alternatives to close reading. As is evident in her interpretation of Landor, Lee’s crit-ical empathy problematizes a new Critical opposition between the reli-able universality of cognition and the unreliable individuality of sensation, while simultaneously presenting a model that includes the feeling of reading within the practice of interpretation. this is a binary that may seem to divide some new experiments with reading. moretti’s “distant” reading, for example, can seem coldly analytical in comparison with the phenomenological approach employed by Schwenger, who narrates his experience of reading particular passages—irrelevant associations and all. Lee resists this binary by comfortably inhabiting both camps at once. on one page of The Handling of Words, she fantasizes that she might

Page 22: Critical Empathy Vernon Lee s Aesthetics

52 BenjAmIn morgAn

VICtorIAn StuDIeS / VoLume 55, no. 1

analyse pages enough—say all the pages he ever wrote . . . and thus arriv[e] at an average classification of all the words which every one of the Writers under comparison ever employed. The Statistical Test applied to Literature. . . . Let me recommend the prosecution of this study to young gentlemen and ladies anxious to fit themselves out as general reviewers. (188–89)

Lee is a distant reader avant la lettre, lacking only the proper software. But, a few pages later, Lee wants critics to use the statistical analysis of words in order to explore “how” readers think: “how, meaning: is the thinking to be done easily or with effort; quickly or slowly, smoothly or jerkily? . . . how also, in the sense of a horse’s paces (is it an amble or a gallop?), or a man’s gesture and action, leaning or supporting, leaping or stumbling” (191). Lee offers the provocative image of what the new Criti-cism might have looked like had it embraced corporeality rather than cognition, while still developing a systematic form of literary analysis.

At the same time that it provides a point of origin for a modern kinaesthetics of reading, Lee’s critical empathy also foregrounds rela-tions between the feeling of reading, the feeling of looking, and the feeling of hearing. Lee’s work therefore challenges us to think not only about the compatibility of quantitative and somatic criticism, but also about how the feeling of reading is one of many corporeal responses to the arts. reading often seems like a special kind of aesthetic experi-ence because it depends so entirely upon the cognitive realization of concepts. one cannot see a poetic image in the same unmediated way that one sees a color or hears a sound; novels are less immediately avail-able to perception than ballets or paintings. Lee’s empathic theory of form resists this distinction, insisting that art and literature are related by their shared project of affecting bodies—and not only in the case of famously exciting novels like The Woman in White (1860). even Marius the Epicurean (1885), Lee wrote in the last essay she published before her death, is a text that a reader feels—and no one who has read Pater’s novel will be surprised to learn that it conveys a sense of “insufficient locomotion” (“handling” 303). Lee reminds us that these feelings matter just as much as it matters that wine makes you drunk, despite Wimsatt and Beardsley’s influential exclusion of this kind of somatic experience as a side effect. the object of that exclusionary gesture was not a simplistic confusion of meaning and effect, but a highly devel-oped theory of how bodies mediate shapes—of triangles, sentences, and musical phrases—to create meaning.

University of Chicago

Page 23: Critical Empathy Vernon Lee s Aesthetics

CrItICAL emPAthy 53

Autumn 2012

NOTES

1on these embodied forms of reading, see Symons; Arata; Daly 34–55; and Dames 25–70.

2on the history of empathy and its relation to sympathy, see Burdett, greiner, jahoda, moyn, and Pigman.

3Psychologist nancy eisenberg notes that empathy is “comprehension of anoth-er’s emotional state . . . and is similar to what the other person is feeling” (671); sympathy “is not the same as what the other person is feeling . . . but consists of feelings of sorrow or concern” (672).

4See Keen, Empathy and the Novel 65–99.5See Keen, “empathetic hardy.”6See Leys for an example of this critique of massumi.7See Bain, Emotions and Senses.8See Burdett; Lanzoni.9See maltz; Psomiades.10See Best and marcus, eds., The Way We Read Now and Felski and tucker, eds.,

Context?11See Best and marcus for “surface” reading; Apter and Freedgood for “literal”

reading; moretti for “distant” reading; Zunshine for “cognitive” reading; Warner for “uncritical” reading; and Schwenger for “obbligato” reading.

WORKS CITED

Ablow, rachel. “Introduction: the Feeling of reading.” The Feeling of Reading. ed. Ablow. Ann Arbor: u of michigan P, 2010. 1–10.

Allen, grant. Physiological Aesthetics. London: h. S. King, 1877.Altieri, Charles. “the Sensuous Dimension of Literary experience: An Alternative to

materialist theory.” New Literary History 38.1 (2007): 71–98.Anstruther-thomson, Clementina. “What Patterns Can Do to us.” Art and Man: Essays

& Fragments. ed. Vernon Lee. London: john Lane, 1924. 137–53.Anstruther-thomson, Clementina, and Vernon Lee. “Beauty and ugliness.” Contempo-

rary Review 72 (oct. 1897): 544–69; 72 (nov. 1897): 669–88.Apter, emily, and elaine Freedgood. Afterword. The Way We Read Now. ed. Stephen Best

and Sharon marcus. Spec. issue of Representations 108.1 (2009): 139–46.Arata, Stephen. “on not Paying Attention.” Victorian Studies 46.2 (2004): 193–205.Bain, Alexander. The Emotions and the Will. London: john W. Parker, 1859.‡‡‡. The Senses and the Intellect. London: john W. Parker, 1855.Best, Stephen, and Sharon marcus. “Surface reading: An Introduction.” The Way We

Read Now. ed. Best and marcus. Spec. issue of Representations 108.1 (2009): 1–21.Best, Stephen, and Sharon marcus, eds. The Way We Read Now. Spec. issue of Representa-

tions 108.1 (2009).

Page 24: Critical Empathy Vernon Lee s Aesthetics

54 BenjAmIn morgAn

VICtorIAn StuDIeS / VoLume 55, no. 1

Burdett, Carolyn. “‘the subjective inside us can turn into the objective outside’: Vernon Lee’s Psychological Aesthetics.” 19: Interdisciplinary Studies in the Long Nineteenth

Century 12 (2 jun. 2011). <http://www.19.bbk.ac.uk>

Burke, edmund. A Philosophical Enquiry into the Origin of our Ideas of the Sublime and Beau-

tiful. new york: oxford uP, 2009.Colby, Vineta. Vernon Lee: A Literary Biography. Charlottesville: u of Virginia P, 2003. Daly, nicholas. Literature, Technology, and Modernity, 1860–2000. new york: Cambridge

uP, 2004.Dames, nicholas. The Physiology of the Novel: Reading, Neural Science, and the Form of Victo-

rian Fiction. new york: oxford uP, 2007.eisenberg, nancy. “emotion, regulation, and moral Development.” Annual Review of

Psychology 51 (2000): 665–98.Felski, rita, and herbert F. tucker, eds. Context? Spec. issue of New Literary History 42.4

(2011). Fogle, richard. The Imagery of Keats and Shelley: A Comparative Study. Chapel hill: u of

north Carolina P, 1949.greiner, D. rae. “thinking of me thinking of you: Sympathy Versus empathy in the

realist novel.” Victorian Studies 53.3 (2011): 417–26.groos, Karl. The Play of Man. trans. elizabeth L. Baldwin. new york: Appleton, 1901.gunn, Peter. Vernon Lee: Violet Paget, 1856–1935. new york: Arno, 1975.hay, David ramsay. The Natural Principles of Beauty, as Developed in the Human Figure.

edinburgh: Blackwood, 1852.jahoda, gustav. “theodor Lipps and the Shift from ‘Sympathy’ to ‘empathy.’” Journal of

the History of the Behavioral Sciences 41.2 (2005): 151–63.Keen, Suzanne. “empathetic hardy.” Poetics Today 32.2 (2011): 349–89. ‡‡‡. Empathy and the Novel. new york: oxford uP, 2007.Külpe, oswald. “ein Beitrag zur experimentellen Aesthetik.” American Journal of

Psychology 14 (1903): 215–31.Lakoff, george, and mark johnson. Metaphors We Live By. Chicago: u of Chicago P,

2003.Lanzoni, Susan. “Practicing Psychology in the Art gallery: Vernon Lee’s Aesthetics of

empathy.” Journal of the History of the Behavioral Sciences 45.4 (2009): 330–54.Lee, Vernon. The Beautiful: An Introduction to Psychological Aesthetics. Cambridge:

Cambridge uP, 1913.‡‡‡. Beauty and Ugliness. London: john Lane, 1912.‡‡‡. “Carlyle and the Present tense.” Contemporary Review 85 (mar. 1904): 386–92. Pt.

3 of a series, Studies in Literary Psychology.‡‡‡. “Comparative Aesthetics.” Contemporary Review 38 (Aug. 1880): 300–26.‡‡‡. “the Craft of Words.” New Review 11 (Dec. 1894): 571–80.‡‡‡. The Handling of Words, and Other Studies in Literary Psychology. London: john Lane,

1923.‡‡‡. “the handling of Words: A Page of Walter Pater.” Life and Letters 9.50 (1933):

287–310.‡‡‡. “of Writers and readers.” New Review 5 (Dec. 1891): 528–36.‡‡‡. “recent Aesthetics.” Quarterly Review 199.398 (1904): 420–43.

Page 25: Critical Empathy Vernon Lee s Aesthetics

CrItICAL emPAthy 55

Autumn 2012

‡‡‡. “the rhetoric of Landor.” Contemporary Review 84 (Dec. 1903): 856–64. Pt. 2 of a series, Studies in Literary Psychology.

‡‡‡. “the Syntax of De Quincy.” Contemporary Review 84 (nov. 1903): 713–23. Pt. 1 of a series, Studies in Literary Psychology.

‡‡‡. “Vital tempo: Art and human Life.” The Times 14 nov. 1924: 8.Leys, ruth. “the turn to Affect: A Critique.” Critical Inquiry 37.3 (2011): 434–72.Lipps, theodor. Ästhetik: Psychologie des Schönen und der Kunst. 2 vols. hamburg: Leopold

Voss, 1903.‡‡‡. Raumästhetik und Geometrisch-Optische Täuschungen. Leipzig: johann Ambrosius

Barth, 1897.maltz, Diana. “engaging ‘Delicate Brains’: From Working-Class enculturation to

upper-Class Lesbian Liberation in Vernon Lee and Kit Anstruther-thomson’s Psychological Aesthetics.” Women and British Aestheticism. ed. talia Schaffer and Kathy Alexis Psomiades. Charlottesville: u of Virginia P, 1999. 211–229.

massumi, Brian. “the Autonomy of Affect.” Parables of the Virtual: Movement, Affect,

Sensation. Durham: Duke uP, 2002.moretti, Franco. “Conjectures on World Literature.” New Left Review 1 (jan.-Feb. 2000):

54–68.moyn, Samuel. “empathy in history, empathizing with humanity.” History and Theory

45.3 (2006): 397–415.nussbaum, martha. Poetic Justice: The Literary Imagination and Public Life. Boston: Beacon,

1995. Pater, Walter. The Renaissance: Studies in Art and Poetry: The 1893 Text. ed. Donald L. hill.

Berkeley: u of California P, 1980.Pigman, george W. “Freud and the history of empathy.” International Journal of Psycho-

analysis 76 (1995): 237–56.Psomiades, Kathy. “‘Still Burning from this Strangling embrace’: Vernon Lee on

Desire and Aesthetics.” Victorian Sexual Dissidence. ed. richard Dellamora. Chicago: u of Chicago P, 1999. 21–42.

richards, I. A. Practical Criticism. new york: harcourt, 1957.‡‡‡. Principles of Literary Criticism. new york: harcourt, 1961.Schwenger, Peter. “the obbligato effect.” New Literary History 42.1 (2011): 115–28.Seed, David. editor’s Introduction. The Handling of Words. By Vernon Lee. Lewiston:

edwin mellen, 1992. i-xxx.Slote, michael A. The Ethics of Care and Empathy. new york: routledge, 2007.Smith, jonathan. Charles Darwin and Victorian Visual Culture. new york: Cambridge uP,

2006.Spencer, herbert. The Principles of Psychology. Vol. 2. new york: Appleton, 1873.Symons, Arthur. “Walter Pater.” Figures of Several Centuries. London: Constable, 1917. 322.Vischer, robert. On the Optical Sense of Form. Empathy, Form, and Space: Problems in German

Aesthetics. ed. and trans. henry Francis malgrave and eleftherios Ikonomou. Santa monica: getty Center for the history of Art and the humanities, 1994. 89–123.

Warner, michael. “uncritical reading.” Polemic: Critical or Uncritical. ed. jane gallop. new york: routledge, 2004. 13–38.

Page 26: Critical Empathy Vernon Lee s Aesthetics

56 BenjAmIn morgAn

VICtorIAn StuDIeS / VoLume 55, no. 1

Wellek, rené. “Vernon Lee, Bernard Berenson, and Aesthetics.” Discriminations: Further

Concepts of Criticism. new haven: yale uP, 1970. 164–86.Wimsatt, William K., and monroe C. Beardsley. “the Affective Fallacy.” The Sewanee

Review 57.1 (1949): 31–55.Wimsatt, William K., and Cleanth Brooks. Literary Criticism: A Short History. new york:

Knopf, 1964.“Words, Words, Words!” rev. of The Handling of Words by Vernon Lee. Spectator 130.4947

(21 Apr. 1923): 671.Zunshine, Lisa. Why We Read Fiction: Theory of Mind and the Novel. Columbus: the ohio

State uP, 2006.