Criminal Law and Morality at War

25
Criminal Law and Morality at War Page 1 of 25 PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2015. All Rights Reserved. Under the terms of the licence agreement, an individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use (for details see http://www.oxfordscholarship.com/page/privacy-policy ). Subscriber: Pontificia Universidad Catolica del Peru (PUCP); date: 30 April 2015 University Press Scholarship Online Oxford Scholarship Online Philosophical Foundations of Criminal Law R.A. Duff and Stuart Green Print publication date: 2011 Print ISBN-13: 9780199559152 Published to Oxford Scholarship Online: May 2011 DOI: 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199559152.001.0001 Criminal Law and Morality at War Adil Ahmad Haque DOI:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199559152.003.0021 Abstract and Keywords This chapter identifies the moral norms applicable to killing in armed conflict and determine whether and to what extent the law of armed conflict (LOAC) and international criminal law (ICL) track these moral norms, and justifiably or unjustifiably depart from them. Section 1 explores the moral and legal norms governing the killing of civilians not directly participating in hostilities, both as an intended means and as a foreseen side effect. It defends one account of these norms against important philosophical challenges by Thomas Scanlon, Victor Tadros, Frances Kamm, and Jeff McMahan. It argues that these moral norms are best understood and defended using the distinctions drawn in criminal law theory between wrongdoing, justifiability, and justification. The remainder of the chapter examines the moral and legal norms governing the killing of civilians directly participating in hostilities as well as of members of armed forces and organized armed groups. Section 2 identifies the conditions under which individuals lose their moral immunity from direct attack, partly by critically examining an analogy drawn by Jeff

description

Derecho Penal y Moral en conflicto

Transcript of Criminal Law and Morality at War

  • Criminal Law and Morality at War

    Page 1 of 25

    PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2015.All Rights Reserved. Under the terms of the l icence agreement, an individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of amonograph in OSO for personal use (for details see http://www.oxfordscholarship.com/page/privacy-policy). Subscriber: PontificiaUniversidad Catolica del Peru (PUCP); date: 30 April 2015

    UniversityPressScholarshipOnlineOxfordScholarshipOnline

    PhilosophicalFoundationsofCriminalLawR.A.DuffandStuartGreen

    Printpublicationdate:2011PrintISBN-13:9780199559152PublishedtoOxfordScholarshipOnline:May2011DOI:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199559152.001.0001

    CriminalLawandMoralityatWarAdilAhmadHaque

    DOI:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199559152.003.0021

    AbstractandKeywords

    Thischapteridentifiesthemoralnormsapplicabletokillinginarmedconflictanddeterminewhetherandtowhatextentthelawofarmedconflict(LOAC)andinternationalcriminallaw(ICL)trackthesemoralnorms,andjustifiablyorunjustifiablydepartfromthem.Section1exploresthemoralandlegalnormsgoverningthekillingofciviliansnotdirectlyparticipatinginhostilities,bothasanintendedmeansandasaforeseensideeffect.ItdefendsoneaccountofthesenormsagainstimportantphilosophicalchallengesbyThomasScanlon,VictorTadros,FrancesKamm,andJeffMcMahan.Itarguesthatthesemoralnormsarebestunderstoodanddefendedusingthedistinctionsdrawnincriminallawtheorybetweenwrongdoing,justifiability,andjustification.Theremainderofthechapterexaminesthemoralandlegalnormsgoverningthekillingofciviliansdirectlyparticipatinginhostilitiesaswellasofmembersofarmedforcesandorganizedarmedgroups.Section2identifiestheconditionsunderwhichindividualslosetheirmoralimmunityfromdirectattack,partlybycriticallyexaminingananalogydrawnbyJeff

  • Criminal Law and Morality at War

    Page 2 of 25

    PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2015.All Rights Reserved. Under the terms of the l icence agreement, an individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of amonograph in OSO for personal use (for details see http://www.oxfordscholarship.com/page/privacy-policy). Subscriber: PontificiaUniversidad Catolica del Peru (PUCP); date: 30 April 2015

    McMahanbetweentheseconditionsandthelegaldoctrineofcriminalcomplicity.

    Keywords:armedconflicts,killing,lawofarmedconflict,internationalcriminallaw,moralnorms

    Criminallawtheoryisconcerned,inpart,withunderstandingthepropernormativerelationshipbetweenmoralwrongs,legalwrongs,andcrimes.Liberalretributivists,forexample,tendtobelievethatmostmoralwrongsshouldnotconstitutelegalwrongs,andthatmostlegalwrongsshouldnotconstitutecrimes.Asliberals,theytendtobelievethatconductshouldbemadeunlawfulonlyifdoingsowillpreventsubstantiallymoreharmtoothersthanitwillbringabout,andthatunlawfulconductshouldbemadecriminalonlyifdoingsowillpreventsubstantiallymoreoverallharmtoothersthanwouldlessintrusiveorcoerciveformsoflegalregulation.Inaddition,asretributivists,theytendtobelievethatlegalwrongsshouldbemadeintocrimesonlyiftheyarealsoseriousmoralwrongs.Ofcourse,liberalretributivistsarenotexclusivelyconcernedwithcreatingorpreservinggapsbetweenmoralwrongs,legalwrongs,andcrimes;theyarealsoconcernedwithclosingsuchgapswherenosuchgapsshouldexist.Ingeneral,allseriousmoralwrongsthecriminalizationofwhichwouldpreventsubstantialoverallharmtoothersshouldbemadeintocrimes.

    Forcriminallawtheoristsinterestedininternationalcrimes,similarissuesariseregardingtherelationshipbetweenmoralwrongscommittedinthecontextofarmed(p.482)conflict,violationsofthelawofarmedconflict,andwarcrimes.Indeed,warcrimesjustareseriousviolationsofthelawofarmedconflictwhicharepunishableunderinternationalcriminallaw.Althoughwarcrimesareoftenperpetratedandseldompunished,itisalmostcertainlythecasethattheirillegalitypreventsmoreharmtoothersthanitbringsaboutandthattheircriminalitypreventsstillmoreoverallharm.Moreover,whileallegationsthataparticularpartytoanarmedconflicthascommittedwarcrimesarealmostalwaysdisputedbytheaccusedpartyanditsallies,itisalmostcertainlythecasethateverywarcrimecurrentlyrecognizedunderinternationallawconstitutesaseriousmoralwrong.Indeed,itistheseriousmoralwrongfulnessofwarcrimes,nottheirtechnicalillegality,whichislikelytoexplainthevigourwithwhichtheircommissionisdenied.Whatislessclear,andthereforemoreinteresting,iswhetherotherseriousmoralwrongscommittedinarmedconflict,someofwhicharealreadylegalwrongsunderthelawofarmedconflict,shouldberecognizedaswarcrimesaswell.

    Ofcourse,wecannotknowwhichmoralwrongscommittedinarmedconflictshouldberecognizedaswarcrimesuntilweknowwhatactsofwarconstitutemoralwrongsandunderstandwhereintheirwrongfulnessconsists.Thepurposeofthischapteristoidentifythemoralnormsapplicabletokillinginarmedconflictanddeterminewhetherandtowhatextentthelawofarmedconflict(LOAC)andinternationalcriminallaw(ICL)trackthesemoralnorms,justifiablydepartfromthem,orunjustifiablydepartfromthem.Section1exploresthemoralandlegalnormsgoverningthekillingofciviliansnotdirectlyparticipatinginhostilities,bothasanintendedmeansandasaforeseensideeffect,anddefendsoneaccountofthesenormsagainstimportantphilosophicalchallengesbyThomasScanlon,VictorTadros,FrancesKamm,andJeffMcMahan.Iarguethatthesemoralnormsarebestunderstoodanddefendedusingthedistinctionsdrawnincriminallaw

  • Criminal Law and Morality at War

    Page 3 of 25

    PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2015.All Rights Reserved. Under the terms of the l icence agreement, an individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of amonograph in OSO for personal use (for details see http://www.oxfordscholarship.com/page/privacy-policy). Subscriber: PontificiaUniversidad Catolica del Peru (PUCP); date: 30 April 2015

    theorybetweenwrongdoing,justifiability,andjustification.TheLOACtracksthesemoralnormsquiteclosely.Bycontrast,ICLdepartsfromthesemoralnormsinwaysthataredifficulttodefend,inpartbecauseICLseemstomistakenlyassignintentionawrong-makingratherthanawrong-justifyingfunction.

    Thebalanceofthechapterexaminesthemoralandlegalnormsgoverningthekillingofciviliansdirectlyparticipatinginhostilitiesaswellasofmembersofarmedforcesandorganizedarmedgroups.Section2attemptstoidentifytheconditionsunderwhichindividualslosetheirmoralimmunityfromdirectattack,partlybycriticallyexaminingananalogydrawnbyJeffMcMahanbetweentheseconditionsandthelegaldoctrineofcriminalcomplicity.BoththeLOACandICLgenerallytracktheseconditionsfairlyclosely,butbothshouldberevisedtoprohibitdirectattacksonmembersofarmedforceswhomtheattackerknowsarenotdirectlyparticipatinginhostilitiesandhavenotassumedacontinuouscombatfunction.Finally,section3arguesthatmoralconstraintsofnecessityandproportionalitylimittheuseofforceevenagainstindividualswhoaremorallyliabletodirectattack.Severalarguments(p.483) totheeffectthattheLOACandICLmayjustifiablyfailtoenforcethesemoralconstraintsareexaminedandfoundunpersuasive.1

    1IMMUNITYFROMDIRECTATTACKUnderinternationallaw,civiliansareallindividualswhoarenotcombatants.Combatants,inturn,includemembersofthearmedforcesofapartytoanarmedconflict(exceptforreligiousandmedicalpersonnel)aswellasparticipantsinaspontaneousarmeduprisingknownasaleveenmasse.ItisbothaviolationoftheLOACandawarcrimetoattackciviliansdirectlyduringarmedconflict,unlessandforsuchtimeastheydirectlyparticipateinhostilities.Thecircumstancesunderwhichciviliansmaylosetheirimmunityfromdirectattackwillbediscussedinsection2.Thetaskofthissectionistoexaminetheconceptualstructureandmoraljustificationofthelegalimmunityfromdirectattackwhichciviliansordinarilyenjoy.ThissectionwilldefendaversionoftheDoctrineofDoubleEffect(DDE),whichistypicallycharacterizedastheviewthatissometimesmorallypermissibletokillciviliansasaforeseeablesideeffectofachievinganintendedmilitaryadvantagebutimpermissibletokillthesamenumberofciviliansasanintendedmeansofachievingasimilarmilitaryadvantage.ThenewinterpretationoftheDDEofferedbelowbeginsbysupplementingtheconceptofpermissibilitywhichdominatesmoralphilosophywiththemorepreciseconceptsofwrongdoing,justifiability,andjustificationderivedfromcriminallawtheory.IarguethatbothdefendersandcriticsoftheDDEmistakenlyassumethatintentionisawrong-makingratherthanawrong-justifyingfeatureofharmingcivilians.

    1.1IntentionandjustificationThomasScanlonhasrecentlyarguedthatacombatant'sintentioninkillingciviliansisirrelevanttowhetherthekillingofthoseciviliansismorallypermissible.2(p.484)Permissibility,Scanlonargues,isafunctionofthereasonsforandagainstperforminganaction,andtheintentionwithwhichanactionwouldbeperformeddoesnotcountamongthereasonsfororagainstperformingthataction.Scanlonconcludesthatthepermissibilityofagivenmilitaryoperationdependsonitsanticipatedoutcomes,

  • Criminal Law and Morality at War

    Page 4 of 25

    PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2015.All Rights Reserved. Under the terms of the l icence agreement, an individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of amonograph in OSO for personal use (for details see http://www.oxfordscholarship.com/page/privacy-policy). Subscriber: PontificiaUniversidad Catolica del Peru (PUCP); date: 30 April 2015

    specificallyontheharmitwillcausetociviliansaswellasonthemilitaryadvantageitwillachieve.Ifthemilitaryadvantageoutweighsthecivilianharmthenitispermissibleforthecombatantstoachievetheformerattheexpenseofthelatter,irrespectiveofwhethertheirintentionindoingsoistoachievethemilitaryadvantageortoharmcivilians.

    ThefirstproblemwithScanlon'sviewisthathisuseofpermissibilityisinsensitivetothedifferencesbetweennon-wrongfulconduct,wrongfulconductthatisjustifiable,andwrongfulconductthatisbothjustifiableandjustified.Now,thekillingofciviliansisapresumptivemoralwrong(thatis,aninfringementofamoralrightorduty)whethercommittedintentionally,knowingly,recklessly,ornegligently.Tothatextent,Scanloniscorrect:acombatant'sintentiondoesnotdeterminewhetherthekillingofciviliansiswrongfulornon-wrongful.Moreover,thewrongofkillingciviliansisjustifiable(thatis,supportedbyundefeatedreasons)onlyifitiscausedbyoralongsidetheachievementofasufficientlyimportantmilitaryobjective.Tothisextentaswell,Scanloniscorrect:thejustifiabilityofkillingciviliansturnsontheobjectivemoralreasonsforandagainstkillingthem,notontheintentionsofthecombatant.However,thewrongofkillingciviliansisonlyjustified(thatis,performedforundefeatedreasons)whentheachievementofthemilitaryadvantageisamongthecombatant'sreasonsforaction.3Itisinthissensethatintentionisnotawrong-makingfeatureofkillingcivilians(withaculpablementalstate)butratherawrong-justifyingfeature.Thekillingofciviliansmaybejustifiable(forexample,asanecessarysideeffectofaproportionatemilitaryadvantage)andyetthecombatantwhokillsthemmaybeunjustifiedindoingso(forexample,ifhersolereasonforactionistospreadterrorbykillingthecivilians).Itfollowsthatanactmaybepermissible(thatis,ajustifiablewrong)yetanindividualmayactimpermissibly(thatis,withoutjustification)inperformingitforthewrongreasons.

    Certainly,actingjustifiablyenjoysakindoflogicalpriorityoveractingwithajustification:thelatterisimpossiblewithouttheformer,whiletheformerispossiblewithoutthelatter.ButactingwithajustificationiscentraltoourmorallivesinawaythatScanlonofallpeopleshouldrecognize.ForatthecoreofScanlon'scontractualismisthedesiretojustifyourselvestoothers,orratherthedesirabilityofbeingabletodoso,andwecannotjustifyourselvestoothersbyalludingtoreasonsforwhichwecouldhaveactedbutdidnot.Instead,wemustsharewiththemourreasonsforactingaswedid.Whenwearecalledtoaccountforouractions,andinparticularto(p.485) accountforthewrongswecommit,wearecallednotmerelytogiveananswerbuttogiveouranswer.

    Scanloncomesclosertothetruthwhenheobservesthatmoralprinciplescanserveeitherasguidestodeliberation(theirdeliberativefunction)orasstandardsofevaluation(theircriticalfunction).4Hesaysthatthedeliberativefunctionofmoralprinciplesistodeterminewhichactionapersonhasdecisivereasonstoperform,whilethecriticalfunctionistodeterminewhetherornotthepersonperformedthatactionforthosereasons.However,Scanlon'sterminologyisquitemisleading,foritisstrangetosaythatamoralprinciplehasfulfilleditsdeliberativefunctionevenifitplaysnoroleinanindividual'sdeliberations.Inotherwords,ifanindividualisunawareofthereasonsidentifiedbyamoralprinciple,oradvertstothemonlytodisregardthemandacton

  • Criminal Law and Morality at War

    Page 5 of 25

    PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2015.All Rights Reserved. Under the terms of the l icence agreement, an individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of amonograph in OSO for personal use (for details see http://www.oxfordscholarship.com/page/privacy-policy). Subscriber: PontificiaUniversidad Catolica del Peru (PUCP); date: 30 April 2015

    entirelydifferentreasons,thenitisquiteoddtosaythattheprinciplehasdischargedadeliberativefunction.Perhapsitisbettertospeakofagovernancefunctionconcernedwiththejustifiabilityofaction,aguidancefunctionconcernedwithactingwithjustification,andacriticalperspectivefromwhichbothcanbeevaluated.

    1.2MeansandendsThekillingofciviliansisapresumptivemoralwrongthatisonlyjustifiedwhenperformedforundefeatedreasons,thatis,forreasonsthatareneitheroutweighednorexcluded.Thislastpointiscrucialbecauseoneclassofpotentialreasonsforkillingciviliansisnotmerelyoutweighedbythevalueoftheirlivesbutexcludedfrombeingweighedagainsttheirlivesinthefirstplace.Inparticular,thekillingofcivilianscannotbejustifiedbythecausalconsequencesornon-causalresultsoftheirdeaths.Forexample,thekillingofcivilianscannotbejustifiedasameansofspreadingterror(acausalconsequence)orofexpressinggenocidalhatred(anon-causalresult).Civiliandeathsdonotmerelyoutweightheirconsequencesandresultsbutinsteadexcludethemfromjustificatoryconsideration.

    Bycontrast,thekillingofcivilianscanbejustifiedbythecausalantecedentsoraccompanimentsoftheirdeaths.Forexample,thekillingofcivilianscanbejustifiedwhenthedeathsarecausedbytheachievementofamilitaryadvantage(forexample,whenthedeathsresultdirectlyfromthedestructionofamilitaryobjective),orbyanattackwhichbothachievesamilitaryadvantageandkillscivilians(forexample,whenthedeathsresultdirectlyfromanattackwhichalsodirectlyresultsinthedestructionofamilitaryobjective,butneitherthedeathsnorthedestructionofthemilitaryobjectiveresultsfromtheother).Inaddition,thekillingofcivilianscannotbejustifiedwhenasimilarmilitaryadvantagecouldhavebeenachievedbyusing(p.486) morediscriminatingweaponsorselectingmoreremotetargetsandtherebyavoidingorreducingharmtocivilians.

    Thisaccountofthewrongfulnessofkillingcanbeconceptualizedintermsofamandatorynormconsistingofaprimaryreasonnottokillciviliansaswellasanexclusionaryreasonwhichprecludesthecausalconsequencesandnon-causalresultsofkillingciviliansfromcountinginitsfavour.5Mostpeoplewouldagreethatsomeincentivestoharmotherscannotcountinfavourofdoingso(forexample,thefactthatharmingsomeonewouldgiveonesadisticorvindictivepleasure).WhatIamproposinghereisthatincentivestoharmotherscanberenderednormativelyinertbytheircausalhistory.Bycontrast,actswhichcauseciviliandeathsmayalsohavecausalconsequenceswhicharenotthemselvescausedbythoseciviliandeaths(namelythecausalantecedentsandaccompanimentsofthosedeaths).Theselatterconsequencesfalloutsidethescopeoftheexclusionaryreasonandmaybebalanceddirectlyagainsttheprimaryreasonnottokillcivilians.Thisaccountpreservestheinsightattheheartofthemeans/sideeffectdistinction.6

    Inaseparatechapterinthisvolume,VictorTadrosarguesthatcausalrelationshipsbetweenharmsandbenefitsdonotpossesintrinsicmoralsignificance.Instead,Tadrosarguesthatwhatmattersmorallyiswhetheronepersontreatsanotherasameans,

  • Criminal Law and Morality at War

    Page 6 of 25

    PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2015.All Rights Reserved. Under the terms of the l icence agreement, an individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of amonograph in OSO for personal use (for details see http://www.oxfordscholarship.com/page/privacy-policy). Subscriber: PontificiaUniversidad Catolica del Peru (PUCP); date: 30 April 2015

    whichTadrosarguesisafunctionofthefirstperson'smotivations.7Infactthisistheoppositeofthetruth.Treatingsomeoneasameans,causallyspeaking,iswrongfulifandonlyiftheyarenotameans,morallyspeaking.PtreatsVasameanswhenPharmsVinordertoachievethecausalconsequencesornon-causalresultsofharmingV.Visameansinsofarasmoralitypermitsthecausalconsequencesornon-causalresultsofharmingVtobeweigheddirectlyagainsttheprimaryreasonsnottoharmVinthefirstplace.Ifmoralitypermitssuchdirectweighing,thenVisameansandthereisnothingwrongwithtreatingVassuch.Bycontrast,ifmoralityforbidssuchdirectweighing,thenVisnotameansanditisindeedwrongfultotreatVassuch.

    Thefundamentalissue,then,isnotoneoftreatmentbutoneofstatus.Ifthekillingofcivilianscouldbejustifiedbyreferencetothecausalconsequencesornon-causalresultsoftheirdeathsthenmoralityitselfwouldtherebyregardciviliansasmeanstobeusedopportunisticallyoreliminatedentirelytoservetheendsofothers.Bycontrast,ifthekillingofcivilianscanbejustifiedbyreferencetothecausalantecedentsoraccompanimentsoftheirdeathsthenmoralityonlyconcedesthat(p.487) legitimateendsmaysometimesbepursuedeventhoughtheirpursuitincidentallycausesciviliandeaths.

    Tadrosiscorrectthatmotivationsarerelevanttomoralpermissibility,thoughnotinthewayhethinks.Tadrosthinksthatintentionplaysawrong-makingrolebecauseintentionisanecessaryelementofthewrongofkillingorharmingsomeoneasameans.Infact,killingorharmingsomeonealmostalwaysconstitutesafree-standingmoralwrong;killingorharmingsomeoneasameansismerelyonewayofcommittingsuchabasicwrongwithoutjustification.Moreover,thekillingofciviliansisamoralwrongthatcanbecommittedintentionally,knowingly,recklessly,ornegligently.Thatwrongisjustifiableiftheciviliandeathsweretheunavoidableandproportionatecausalconsequencesoftheachievementofamilitaryadvantageoroftheactthatachievesthatmilitaryadvantage.Thatwrongisjustifiediftheachievementofthatmilitaryadvantagewasthereasonforitscommission.8

    WealsoarenowinabetterpositiontoidentifyasecondproblemwithScanlon'sapproach.Scanlonstipulatesthattheconceptofmilitaryadvantageincludesdestroyingenemycombatantsorwar-makingmaterialsbutexcludeshasten[ing]theendofthewarbyunderminingpublicmorale.9Sincekillingorinjuringcivilianshardlyevercausallycontributestothedestructionofopposingcombatantsorwar-makingmaterials,Scanlon'sviewentailsthatciviliansmayalmostneverbekilledorharmedasameansofachievingmilitaryadvantagebutmayoftenbekilledasasideeffectofachievingmilitaryadvantage.However,Scanlondoesnothavetoendorsethemeans/sideeffectdistinctiontoreachthisresult,sinceitfollowsfromhisstipulation.

    Despitereachingtherightresultregardingliabilitytodirectattack,Scanlon'srestrictiveunderstandingofmilitaryadvantageisnotultimatelyplausible.Forexample,itisundeniablymilitarilyadvantageoustopreventnon-uniformedcombatantsfrominterminglingwithacivilianpopulationandusingciviliansashumanshields.However,itis

  • Criminal Law and Morality at War

    Page 7 of 25

    PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2015.All Rights Reserved. Under the terms of the l icence agreement, an individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of amonograph in OSO for personal use (for details see http://www.oxfordscholarship.com/page/privacy-policy). Subscriber: PontificiaUniversidad Catolica del Peru (PUCP); date: 30 April 2015

    notjustifiabletopursuethismilitaryadvantagebyforciblyandpermanentlydisplacingthecivilianpopulationinwhichtheopposingcombatantsseektohide.Similarly,itisperfectlylegitimateforapartytoarmedconflicttocreatepoliticalpressureontheopposingpartytostopfightingandacceptthetermsofajustpeace,forexample,throughpropaganda.Whatisillegitimateistokillorinjureciviliansasameansofcreatingsuchpoliticalpressure.Thus,civilianimmunityfromdirectattackcannotbedefendedsolelybyrestrictivelydefiningmilitaryadvantagebutonlybyexplainingwhyitisimpermissibletokillciviliansasameansofachievinganymilitaryadvantage.(p.488)

    1.3SideeffectsandindirectmeansThereisonelastissuethathasbeenraisedinthephilosophicalliteraturethatneedstobeaddressed.Iarguedabovethatdeathorinjurytocivilianscannotbejustifiedbyitscausalconsequencesornon-causalresults.Thisclearlyrulesoutdirectattacksoncivilians.Theremainingquestioniswhetheranattackthatisdirectedatcombatantsormilitaryobjectivesbutthatcausesdeathorinjurytociviliansasasideeffectcannonethelesstakethefurthercausalconsequencesornon-causalresultsofthedeathorinjurytociviliansintoaccountwhendeterminingtheoverallproportionalityoftheattack.Forexample,JeffMcMahanhaswrittenthat,althoughingeneral,civiliansmaynotbeharmedorkilledasanintendedmeansofdeterringfuturewarsthedeterrenteffectthatcasualtiesamongcivilianscanhavedoescountasagoodeffectincalculationsofwideproportionality.10Morenarrowly,FrancesKammhasarguedthatciviliandeathscausedbythedestructionofamilitaryobjectivemaybejustifiableifthesurvivingcivilianswillbetoogrief-strickentorebuildtheobjective,thussustainingthemilitaryadvantageproducedbytheinitialattack.11Inthesecases,civiliansareharmedbothasacausalconsequenceofachievingonemilitaryadvantageandasacausalantecedentofachievinganothermilitaryadvantage(orsustainingthefirstmilitaryadvantage).Doesthismorecomplexcausalstructuremakeamoraldifferencetothepossibilityofjustifyingdeathandinjurytocivilians?

    Infact,thereisnodifferenceinmoralpermissibilitybetweencaseslikethoseconstructedbyMcMahanandKammandcasesinwhichadirectattackonamilitaryobjectivekillstoofewcivilianstosufficientlydeterordemoralizethesurvivorsandisthereforefollowedupwithadirectattackonsurvivingcivilians.Aswehaveseen,thecausalconsequencesandnon-causalresultsofciviliandeathsareexcludedfromcountinginfavourofkillingthem.Itismorallyirrelevantwhethercombatantsintendtobringaboutsuchexcludedoutcomesormerelyforeseesuchexcludedoutcomesandactontheconditionthattheywilloccur.Suchoutcomesshouldnotbesubjectivelyintendedbecausetheyareobjectivelyexcluded;combatantsarenotjustifiedinpursuingsuchoutcomesbecausesuchoutcomescannotrenderciviliandeathsjustifiable.Similarly,thereisnodifferenceinmoralpermissibilitybetweenthescenariosenvisionedbyMcMahanandKammandascenarioinwhichacombatantrealizesthatdirectingoneweaponssystematamilitaryobjectivewillcausetoofewciviliansdeathsassideeffectstosufficientlydeterordemoralizethesurvivorsandthereforeselectsamoredestructiveweaponssysteminstead.Thisisbecausecombatantscanonlyapplytherequirementofminimalforceaftertheyfirstidentify(p.489) thenon-excludedoutcomesofanattack;onlythencanthey

  • Criminal Law and Morality at War

    Page 8 of 25

    PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2015.All Rights Reserved. Under the terms of the l icence agreement, an individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of amonograph in OSO for personal use (for details see http://www.oxfordscholarship.com/page/privacy-policy). Subscriber: PontificiaUniversidad Catolica del Peru (PUCP); date: 30 April 2015

    determinehowtobringthoseoutcomesaboutwhilecausingtheleastpossibleharmtocivilians.

    Neitherdirectattacksonciviliansnordirectattacksonmilitaryobjectivesthatkillciviliansasasideeffectcanbejustifiedbythecausalconsequencesornon-casualresultsoftheciviliandeathstheycause.Ifthecausalantecedentsofciviliandeathsareinsufficienttojustifythosedeathsthenthemerepresenceofthoseantecedentscannottransformthecausalconsequencesornon-causalresultsofthosedeathsfromexcludedtonon-excludedbasesforjustifyingthosedeaths.Suchcausalantecedentsareredherrings,sourcesofmisdirectionratherthanjustification,andtheoperationscontemplatedbyMcMahanandKammaresimplyindirectformsoftheunjustifiablewrongthatinitsdirectformisknownasterrorism.

    1.4LawandmoralityHowwelldotheLOACandICLreflectthemoralnormsdiscussedabove?TheLOACsucceedsadmirably.Theintentionalandknowingkillingofciviliansisprohibitedbytheprincipleofcivilianimmunity,whichforbidscombatantsfrommakingcivilianstheobjectofattack.12Therecklessornegligentkillingofciviliansisprohibitedbytheprincipleofdistinction,whichrequirescombatantstodoeverythingfeasibletodistinguishbetweenciviliansandopposingcombatantsbeforelaunchinganattack;13andbytheprincipleofdiscrimination,whichforbidsattackswhicharenotaimedtostrikeopposingcombatantsandmilitaryobjectiveswhileavoidingciviliansandcivilianobjects.14Theprincipleofdistinctionforbidsrecklessnessornegligencewithrespecttocircumstances(namelywhethertheindividualsattackedareciviliansorcombatants),whiletheprincipleofdiscriminationforbidsrecklessnessornegligencewithrespecttoresults(namelywhichindividualsareattackedinthefirstplace).Finally,theprinciplesofnecessityandproportionalitystatethatincidental(sideeffect)harmtociviliansisjustifiableifandonlyifthereisnolessharmfulwayofachievingasimilarmilitaryadvantageandtheharmtociviliansisnotexcessiveinrelationtothemilitaryadvantageanticipated.15

    Bycontrast,ICLcapturesneithertheLOACnortheunderlyingmoralnormsgoverningthekillingofcivilians.Forexample,itisawarcrimeintentionallytodirectanattackatindividualswhomoneknowstobecivilians.16However,itisnotawarcrimetodirectanattackatcivilianswhomoneshouldknowareciviliansbut(p.490) whomoneunreasonablybelievestobeopposingcombatants.Norisitawarcrimetolaunchanindiscriminateattackthatisnotdirectedataspecificmilitarytargetbutratheratanentireareaorthatusesweaponsthatbytheirnaturecannotbedirectedatmilitarytargetsandawayfromcivilians.Similarly,itisawarcrimetolaunchanattackintheknowledgethatitwouldcauseincidentalharmtociviliansthatisclearlyexcessiveinrelationtotheconcreteanddirectoverallmilitaryadvantageanticipated.17However,itisnotawarcrimetocausegreaterharmtociviliansthannecessarytoachieveagivenmilitaryadvantage,ortocauseincidentalharmtociviliansthatisdemonstrablydisproportionatebutnotclearlyexcessiveinrelationtothatmilitaryadvantage.18

    ThesegapsbetweentheLOACandICLaremorallyindefensible.Inparticular,thesegaps

  • Criminal Law and Morality at War

    Page 9 of 25

    PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2015.All Rights Reserved. Under the terms of the l icence agreement, an individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of amonograph in OSO for personal use (for details see http://www.oxfordscholarship.com/page/privacy-policy). Subscriber: PontificiaUniversidad Catolica del Peru (PUCP); date: 30 April 2015

    arenotwarrantedbythesupposeddifficultyofprovingthatacombatantactedrecklesslyornegligentlyduringarmedconflict,orthatlessharmfulmeansofachievingasimilarmilitaryadvantagewereavailable,orthatincidentalharmtocivilianswasexcessivebutnotclearlyexcessive.Concernsthatcombatantswillbefalselyconvictedarebestaddressedbydemandingstrictadherencetothestandardofproofbeyondareasonabledoubt,notbyadoptingweaksubstantivenorms.Itisnotcredibletomaintainthatforensicevidence,eyewitnesstestimony,and(increasingly)videorecordingsofmilitaryoperations,combinedwhenappropriatewiththeexpertanalysisofcurrentandformermilitaryofficers,cannevermeetthisstandard.Thefactisthatcombatantsdosometimesfireblindlyintocars,crowds,androomsinsteadofpositivelyidentifyingandpreciselytargetingopposingforces;theydosometimesuseprimitiverocketsandimprovisedexplosivedevicesthatarebytheirverynatureindiscriminate;andtheydosometimescausegreaterincidentalharmtociviliansthannecessarytoachieveagivenmilitaryadvantage.Unfortunately,evenclearcasesofunjustifiedwrongdoinginarmedconflictwillrarelybepresentedtointernationalcriminaltribunalsorcourtsmartial.Butwhentheyarepresentedtosuchcourtstheyshouldbeprosecutedandpunished,andwhenevertheyoccurtheyshouldbecondemnedaswarcrimes.

    2LIABILITYTODIRECTATTACKIarguedabovethatthekillingorharmingofanindividualispresumptivelyamoralwrongwhichcannotbejustifiedbythecausalconsequencesornon-causalresultsof(p.491)herdeathorinjury.Thisiswhatitmeansforanindividualtoenjoyimmunityfromdirectattack.Itseemstofollowthatforcertainindividualstolosetheirimmunityfromdirectattackisforthekillingofsuchindividualstobejustifiableeitherbyreferencetothecausalantecedentsoraccompanimentsoftheirdeathsorbyreferenceto(atleastsomeof)thecausalconsequencesornon-causalresultsoftheirdeaths.Thepurposeofthissectionistoidentifyandcomparethecircumstancesunderwhichindividualslosetheirmoralandlegalimmunityfromdirectattack.

    2.1LiabilitytodefensiveforceThemostfamiliarwaytoloseone'smoralimmunityfromdirectattackistobecomeliabletodefensiveforceor,puttheotherwayaround,tobecometheappropriateobjectofsomeoneelse'srightofself-defence.Forexample,ifsomeoneisliabletodefensiveforcethentheymaybeharmedasameansofeliminatingthethreattheythemselvespose(anon-causalresult)ortopreventordeterathreatposedbyothers(acausalconsequence).Inaseriesofimportantbooksandarticles,JeffMcMahanhasarguedthatindividualsbecomeliabletodefensiveforcewhentheyaremorallyresponsibleforanunjustifiablethreattoanotherperson.19AccordingtoMcMahan,moralresponsibilityforathreatrequires(i)thatonecausallycontributetothethreat,and(ii)thattheriskthatone'sconductwouldcausallycontributetothethreatwasforeseeableeveniftheriskwastoosmalltorenderonerecklessornegligentintakingtherisk.20McMahanarguesthatmuch(though,asweshallsee,notall)ofthemoralityofkillinginwarcanbeexplainedintermsofthemoralityofdefensiveforce.Ifsuchacontinuityofmoralprinciplesdidexist,itwouldsupportasimilarcontinuityoflegalprinciplesbetweenICLandordinarycriminallaw.

  • Criminal Law and Morality at War

    Page 10 of 25

    PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2015.All Rights Reserved. Under the terms of the l icence agreement, an individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of amonograph in OSO for personal use (for details see http://www.oxfordscholarship.com/page/privacy-policy). Subscriber: PontificiaUniversidad Catolica del Peru (PUCP); date: 30 April 2015

    ThereareatleasttwoproblemswithMcMahan'sviewofliabilitytodefensiveforce.First,responsibilityforanunjustifiablethreatisnotnecessarytobecomeliabletodefensiveforce.AsIhavearguedelsewhere,onecanbecomeliabletodefensiveforcebyposingajustifiedthreattosomeonewhohasnotforfeitedorwaivedherownrightofself-defence.21Forexample,supposethataTacticalBomberisabouttostrikealegitimatemilitaryobjectivethedestructionofwhichwillkillanecessaryandproportionatenumberofnearbycivilians.Ifthosecivilianshavedonenothingtolosetheirrighttoself-defencethentheyarejustifiedinkillingtheTacticalBomber.TheciviliansarenotmorallyrequiredtoallowthemselvestobekilledeveniftheTacticalBomberfightsforajustcause.Atthesametime,theTactical(p.492) Bomberhasdonenothingtoloseherrighttoself-defenceandisthereforejustifiedinusingdefensiveforceagainstthoseciviliansiftheyusedefensiveforceagainsther.22Indeed,McMahannowagreesthattheposingofajustifiedthreatcangiverisetoasymmetricalself-defensesituation.23

    IsubmitthatMcMahan'sproposedcriterionforliabilitytodefensiveforceismoreplausibleasacriterionforforfeitureoftherightofself-defence.24Inotherwords,responsibilityforanunjustifiablethreatmightbewhatcausesonetoloseone'srighttodefendoneselfagainstthoseonethreatens.Itisforthisreasonthatunjustifiedaggressorshavenorighttodefendthemselvesagainstthenecessaryandproportionatedefensiveforceoftheirvictims.Bycontrast,ifthethreatoneposesisjustifiedthenoneretainsone'srighttodefendoneselfagainstthosewhoseektodefendthemselvesagainstthatthreat.Itisforthisreasonthatthosewhoposethreatstoinnocentothersthatarejustifiedasthelesserevilmaydefendthemselvesagainstthedefensiveforceofthoseinnocentothers.Finally,ifoneposesnothreatatallthenoneretainsone'srighttousedefensiveforceevenagainstthreatsthatarejustifiedasthelesserevil.25

    Second,whilecausalcontributionandforeseeableriskseemsufficienttomakeoneresponsibleforthethreatsoneposesandliabletodefensiveforceonthatbasis(whatwemayrefertoasprimaryresponsibilityandprimaryliability)theydonotseemsufficienttomakeoneresponsibleforthethreatsposedbyothersorliabletodefensiveforceonthatbasis(whatwemayrefertoasderivativeresponsibilityandderivativeliability).Atseveralpoints,McMahandrawsparallelsbetweenderivativeliabilitytodefensiveforceandderivativeliabilitytopunishment,invokingthedoctrineofcriminalcomplicitytosupporthispositiononkillinginwar.Forexample,McMahanwritesthatcivilianscanbeinstigatorsofunjustwars,oraidersandabettorswhoshareresponsibilityforunjustactsofwarperpetratedbyunjustcombatants.26McMahanconcludesthatcivilianscanbecomemorallyliabletodirect(p.493) attackthroughparticipationinthegeneralwareffortandwar-sustainingactivities,forexample,byadvocatingwar,lobbyingpoliticianstosupportwar,votingforcandidatesthatsupportwar,payingtaxesthatfundthewareffort,workinginthedefenceindustry,andwrongfullyfailingtoopposethewar.27

    However,acloseexaminationofcriminalcomplicityunderminesratherthansupportsMcMahan'sposition.First,observethatcomplicityinthecrimeofanotherpersongenerallyrequiresthespecificintention(notmereforeseeability)tocontributecausallytotheperpetrator'sconduct,inadditiontothementalstateregardingtheresultsofthat

  • Criminal Law and Morality at War

    Page 11 of 25

    PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2015.All Rights Reserved. Under the terms of the l icence agreement, an individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of amonograph in OSO for personal use (for details see http://www.oxfordscholarship.com/page/privacy-policy). Subscriber: PontificiaUniversidad Catolica del Peru (PUCP); date: 30 April 2015

    conductthatisrequiredfortheperpetrator'scommissionofthecrime.Furthermore,anaccomplicemustcausallycontributetotheperpetrator'scommissionofthecrime,andnotmerelytotheperpetrator'sgeneralcapacitytocommitsuchcrimes.Generally,thismeansthatanaccomplicemustaid,assist,enable,facilitate,orwrongfully(thatis,inbreachofaduty)failtopreventthecommissionofacrimetheperpetratoralreadyintendstocommitormustabet,procure,instigate,solicit,encourage,ororderthecommissionofacrimetheaccompliceintendsfortheperpetratortocommit.Bycontrast,onedoesnotbecomeanaccomplicetoacrimebyassistingtheperpetratorinordinaryaspectsoflife(forexample,bycookingfood,washingclothes,orprovidingreligiousormedicalservices)evenifthisassistanceindirectlycontributestotheperpetrator'sabilitytocommitcrimes.Ifcomplicityisnecessaryforliabilitytodirectattackthenitwouldseemthatmedicalandreligiouspersonnelinthearmedforces,aswellasmilitarycontractorsandcivilianemployeesofarmedforceswhoperformnon-combat-relatedfunctions,generallyretaintheirimmunityfromdirectattack.

    Thesecondproblemwithviewingderivativeliabilitytodirectattackthroughthelensofcriminalcomplicityisthatthelensisitselfdistorted.Criminallawtheoristshavecogentlyarguedthatderivativeliabilitytopunishmentshouldrequirethatanaccomplicemakeanecessarycausalcontributiontotheconductoftheperpetrator.28Encouragingthecommissionofacrimetheperpetratoralreadyintendstocommit,orfacilitatingthecommissionofacrimeforwhichtheperpetratoralreadyhasthenecessarymeansandopportunity,shouldnotbeenough.29Moreover,itwouldbestrangeindeedifderivativeliabilitytodirectattackcouldrestonsuchabasis.Cheeringdepartingtroopsorsendingsupportiveletterstothefrontlines,evenifspecificallyintendedtoencouragesoldierstofight,doesnotseemsufficienttoexposeonetodirectattackevenifnecessarytoavoidthethreatposedbythosesoldiers.Indeed,itishardtobelievethatlocalswhoencouragearmedgroupsoperatingontheirterritorytherebymakethemselvesliabletodirectattackbyopposingforces.McMahancorrectlynotesthatitisseldomnecessaryoreffectivetoattackcivilian(p.494) supportersasameansofavertingathreat,butthepointhereisthatciviliansupportersareseldomnecessarytogeneratethethreatinthefirstplace.30Crucially,ifderivativeliabilitytodirectattackrequiresintentionallymakinganecessarycausalcontributiontoathreatposedbyanotherperson,thenmostciviliansparticipatinginthegeneralwar-effortorwar-sustainingactivitiesretaintheirimmunityfromdirectattack.

    ItshouldbenotedthatMcMahanconceivesofdefensiveforceasameansofredistributingtheriskofwrongfulharmsawayfromthoseatriskandtowardthosemostresponsibleforcreatingtherisk.31ItisforthisreasonthatMcMahanthinksthatifonepersonisevenslightlyresponsibleforariskofharmandanotherpersonisnotresponsibleatall,andiftheharmcannotbedividedamongthemoravoidedbybothofthem,thenthenon-responsiblepersonmayshifttheriskentirelytotheslightlyresponsibleperson.However,toasignificantextent,McMahan'sreferencestoriskanddistributionaremisleading.WhatisreallyatissueiswhetherIcanharmyouasameansofavoidingharmtomyselfifIamnotresponsibleforthepossibilitythatImaybeharmedandyouareatleastslightlyresponsibleforthepossibilitythatImaybeharmed.Putthat

  • Criminal Law and Morality at War

    Page 12 of 25

    PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2015.All Rights Reserved. Under the terms of the l icence agreement, an individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of amonograph in OSO for personal use (for details see http://www.oxfordscholarship.com/page/privacy-policy). Subscriber: PontificiaUniversidad Catolica del Peru (PUCP); date: 30 April 2015

    way,McMahan'spositionseemslessplausible.AsMcMahanconcedes,sinceitissubstantiallyworsetodoharmtoothersthantoallowharmtoothersortooneself,itseemshardtoacceptthataslightdifferenceinprimaryresponsibilitywouldjustifydoingharmtoanotherpersonasameansofavoidingharmtooneself.32Indeed,itisevenhardertoacceptthataslightdegreeofderivativeresponsibilitycanjustifydoingharmtoanotherpersonwhoposesnothreatasameansofavoidingharmtooneself.Sincemostcivilianswhoparticipateinthegeneralwareffortorwar-sustainingactivitiesbearonlyslightandderivativeresponsibilityforspecificmilitaryoperations,theydonotseemliabletodirectattacktopreventthoseoperations.

    2.2JustcauseandliabilitytodirectattackInhismorerecentwork,McMahanhasstatedthatliabilitytodirectattackisnotentirelycoextensivewithliabilitytodefensiveforce.Instead,McMahanbelievesthatthereareatleasttwobasesofliabilitytodirectattackinarmedconflict.Thefirstisresponsibilityforanunjustifiedthreat.Thesecondisresponsibilityforaninjustice(p.495) thepreventionorrectificationofwhichprovidestheopposingpartytoarmedconflictwithajustcauseforwar.33Forexample,civiliansparticipatinginthegeneralwareffortorwar-sustainingactivitiesmayshareresponsibilityforanunjustinvasionormilitaryoccupationasawholeeveniftheyarenotcomplicitinthespecificmilitaryoperationswhichconstituteitsparts.Similarly,prisonersofwarwhofoughtforanunjustcauseshareresponsibilityforthecreationorperpetuationofanunjustthreatorotherseriousinjustice.34AccordingtoMcMahan'ssecondcriterion,suchciviliansandprisonersofwararepotentiallyliabletobeharmedasameansofachievingajustcause.

    McMahan'sconclusionrestsonthepremisethatajustcauseisacausethatmaypermissiblybepursuedbymeansofwar.35Thispremiseisnotobviouslytrue.Onemightinsteadsupposethatajustcauseisacausethatmaypermissiblybepursuedinthefaceofarmedopposition.Onthisview,combatantsdonothaveaspecialrighttokillthoseresponsibleforaninjusticeasameansofpreventingorcorrectingthatinjustice.Instead,combatantsretaintheirgeneralrighttousedefensiveforcetoprotectthemselvesorothersfromwrongfulharm.Themoralsignificanceofjustcauseisthatcombatantspursuingajustcausearerelievedofthegeneraldutytoretreat,surrender,oravoidconflictratherthanusedefensiveforce.36Thisconceptualpointisobscuredwhenastateactsinnationalself-defenceagainstanimminentorongoingarmedattack.Insuchcases,thelinebetweenpursuingajustcause(compellingtheopposingpartytoceaseitsattack)anddefendingagainstarmedresistance(fromopposingforcesthatrefusetoretreatorsurrender)iseasytooverlook.Asaresult,itiscommonlybutmistakenlyassumedthatthekillingofopposingcombatantsisaninherentmilitaryadvantagetowhichtheconstraintsofnecessityandproportionalitydonotapply.

    Bycontrast,ifweallow,forthesakeofargument,thatarrestingterroristsordestroyingweaponsofmassdestructionmayprovideajustcauseforresortingtoarmedforcethenitbecomesclearthatcombatantsareonlyjustifiedinengagingopposingforcestotheextentnecessarytoachievetheirjustcause.Suchcombatantsmayengageindefensiveoperationsagainstthosewhoattackthem,oroffensiveoperationsagainstthosewho

  • Criminal Law and Morality at War

    Page 13 of 25

    PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2015.All Rights Reserved. Under the terms of the l icence agreement, an individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of amonograph in OSO for personal use (for details see http://www.oxfordscholarship.com/page/privacy-policy). Subscriber: PontificiaUniversidad Catolica del Peru (PUCP); date: 30 April 2015

    wouldotherwiseattackthem.37However,individualswhodonotandwouldnototherwiseengageinarmedresistancetothepursuitofthejustcauseormakenecessarycausalcontributionstothearmedresistanceofothers(p.496) arenotliabletobekilledmerelyasameansofachievingthejustcause.Inshort,liabilitytodirectattackderivesfromprimaryorderivativeresponsibilityforattacksoncombatantspursuingajustcause,notresponsibilityfortheinjusticethatgivesrisetothatjustcause.

    Oneimportantimplicationoftheviewdescribedaboveisthatindividualsbecomeliabletodirectattackbyengaginginorcommittingthemselvestoarmedresistance,andceasetobeliabletodirectattackwhentheydisengagefromarmedresistanceeithervoluntarily(forexample,throughsurrenderordesertionorbytakingreservestatus)orinvoluntarily(forexample,throughillness,injury,orcapture).Bycontrast,pastengagementinarmedresistanceisnotabasisforliabilitytodirectattack.Theissueisnotmerelythat,asMcMahanobserves,itisseldomnecessaryoreffectivetousedefensiveforceagainstindividualswhosecausalcontributionstopresentorfuturethreats(or,forMcMahan,injustices)lieinthepast.38Theissueisthatoncetheircausalcontributionstopresentorfuturethreatshavecometoanendso,too,doestheirliabilitytodirectattack.So,contrarytoMcMahan'sposition,ontheviewproposedaboveprisonersofwarmaynotbeharmedevenasanecessarymeansofachievingthejustcausetheypreviouslyopposed.

    2.3Directparticipationinhostilities,continuouscombatfunctions,andmeremembershipIngeneral,itisneitheraviolationoftheLOACnorawarcrimetodirectlyattackciviliansifandforsuchtimeasthosecivilianstakeadirectpartinhostilities.AccordingtoanimportantreportrecentlyissuedbytheInternationalCommitteeoftheRedCross(ICRC),civilianstakeadirectpartinhostilitieswhentheycommitaspecificactwhichmeetsthefollowingcumulativecriteria:

    1.Theactmustbelikelytoadverselyaffectthemilitaryoperationsormilitarycapacityofapartytoanarmedconflictor,alternatively,toinflictdeath,injury,ordestructiononpersonsorobjectsprotectedagainstdirectattack(thresholdofharm),and2.theremustbeadirectcausallinkbetweentheactandtheharmlikelytoresulteitherfromthatact,orfromacoordinatedmilitaryoperationofwhichthatactconstitutesanintegralpart(directcausation),and3.theactmustbespecificallydesignedtodirectlycausetherequiredthresholdofharminsupportofapartytotheconflictandtothedetrimentofanother(belligerentnexus).39(p.497)

    Inaddition,theICRCwritesthat[c]iviliansloseprotectionagainstdirectattackforthedurationofeachspecificactamountingtodirectparticipationinhostilities40butafterwardsregainthatprotection[u]ntilthecivilianinquestionagainengagesinaspecificactofdirectparticipationinhostilities.41

    Thefirstcriterioncertainlyencompassesavarietyofactswhichwouldtriggermoral

  • Criminal Law and Morality at War

    Page 14 of 25

    PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2015.All Rights Reserved. Under the terms of the l icence agreement, an individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of amonograph in OSO for personal use (for details see http://www.oxfordscholarship.com/page/privacy-policy). Subscriber: PontificiaUniversidad Catolica del Peru (PUCP); date: 30 April 2015

    liabilitytodirectattack,suchasactslikelytoinflictdeathorinjuryonindividualswhoretaintheirrighttoself-defence.However,thefirstcriterionalsoencompassesactslikelytoadverselyaffectmilitaryoperationsormilitarycapacitywithoutnecessarilykillingorinjuringcombatantsorcivilians.TheICRCgivesanumberofexamples,includingsabotagingmilitaryequipmentandinterferingwithmilitarycomputernetworks.42Ordinarily,itwouldbedisproportionatetousedeadlyforceindefenceofproperty,eveniflessforcewouldbeinadequatetothetask.However,ifcertainpropertyisessentialtoone'ssurvivalthenonemaydefendone'slifebydefendingone'sproperty.Similarly,actswhichadverselyaffectmilitaryoperationsormilitarycapacitywillgenerallyeitherleavecombatantsvulnerabletoattackbyopposingforcesorcompelcombatantstochoosebetweenabandoningtheirpursuitoftheirjustcauseandpursuingtheirjustcauseatgreaterrisktothemselves.Givensufficientlyhighstakes,theuseoflethalforceagainstcivilianswhoseactionsadverselyaffectmilitaryoperationsorcapacitymaybeproportionate.

    Thesecondcriterionrequiresadirectcausallinkeitherbetweentheactandtheharmlikelytoresultfromthatactorbetweenacoordinatedmilitaryoperationofwhichthatactconstitutesanintegralpartandtheharmlikelytoresultfromthatoperation.43AccordingtotheICRC,directcausationshouldbeunderstoodasmeaningthattheharminquestionmustbebroughtaboutinonecausalstep.44Itfollowsthataspecificactmakesoneliabletodirectattackifitiseitherlikelytocausecognizableharmwithouttheinterveningactsofothersorifitisanintegralpartofacoordinatedmilitaryoperationthatislikelytocausecognizableharmwithouttheinterveningactsofothers.Forexample:

    [t]hedeliverybyaciviliantruckdriverofammunitiontoanactivefiringpositionatthefrontlinewouldalmostcertainlyhavetoberegardedasanintegralpartofongoingcombatoperationsand,therefore,asdirectparticipationinhostilities.Transportingammunitionfromafactorytoaportforfurthershippingtoastorehouseinaconflictzone,ontheotherhand,istooremotefromtheuseofthatammunitioninspecificmilitaryoperationstocausetheensuingharmdirectly.45

    Thiscriterionseemslargelyinkeepingwiththeviewdefendedintheprevioussection,namelythatliabilitytodirectattackrequiresthatthethreatenedharm(p.498) wouldbeproximatelycausedbyone'sownvoluntaryconductorbytheconductofanotherpersontowhichoneintentionallymakesanecessarycausalcontribution.Intriguingly,theICRC'suseofthephraseintegralpartmightsuggestthatacivilianmustbeaco-principalandnotmerelyanaccessorybeforethefactinordertobecomederivativelyliabletodirectattack.However,theICRCelsewhereindicatesthatacivilianmaybecomederivativelyliabletodirectattackbytransportingweaponstothesiteofaspecificmilitaryoperationtobeperformedlater.46

    Thethirdcriterion,requiringaspecificdesigntoopposeonepartyorsupporttheother,createsthemostinterestingcontrastbetweentheLOACandordinarycriminallawprinciplesofself-defence.Forexample,starvingorimpoverishedciviliansmayattemptforciblytotakefoodorsuppliesfrommembersofanarmedforcewithouttherebyintendingtoopposetheachievementofthatforce'smilitaryorpoliticalobjectivesorto

  • Criminal Law and Morality at War

    Page 15 of 25

    PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2015.All Rights Reserved. Under the terms of the l icence agreement, an individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of amonograph in OSO for personal use (for details see http://www.oxfordscholarship.com/page/privacy-policy). Subscriber: PontificiaUniversidad Catolica del Peru (PUCP); date: 30 April 2015

    supportanyopposingparty.SuchciviliansretaintheirimmunityfromdirectattackundertheLOAC,whilecombatantswhodirectlyattackthemcommitawarcrimewhichtheymayjustifyintermsofself-defenceordefenceofothers.Whilemoralliabilitytodefensiveforceturnsonresponsibilityforathreat,moralliabilitytodirectattackinarmedconflictadditionallyrequiresarmedresistancetotheachievementofajustcause.TheLOACadoptsthelattercriterionofliability,withtheimportantmodificationthatcivilianslosetheirlegalimmunityfromdirectattackbyresistingtheachievementofanymilitaryadvantage,evenbyanarmedforcefightingforanunjustcause.Onlyifthelattercriterionisnotsatisfiedwillrecoursebemadetocriminallawprinciplesofliabilitytodefensiveforce.

    Aswehaveseen,civilianslosetheirlegalimmunityfromdirectattackbydirectlyparticipatinginhostilitiesandregaintheirimmunityassoonastheirdirectparticipationcomestoanend.Bycontrast,membersofanorganizedarmedgroupactingasthearmedforcesofanon-statepartytoanarmedconflictlosetheirlegalimmunityfromdirectattackforaslongastheyassumeacontinuouscombatfunction.AccordingtotheICRC,individualswhosecontinuousfunctioninvolvesthepreparation,execution,orcommandofactsoroperationsamountingtodirectparticipationinhostilitiesareassumingacontinuouscombatfunction.47Suchindividualsareliabletodirectattackbefore,during,orafterdirectparticipationinspecificmilitaryoperationsandtheyregaintheirimmunityfromdirectattackonlyupondisengagingfromtheircontinuouscombatfunction.

    TheICRCofferstwoargumentsinfavourofbasingliabilitytodirectattackontheassumptionofacontinuouscombatfunction.First,theICRCstatesthatitwouldgiveorganizedarmedgroupsanunfairadvantageoverStatearmedforcestoallow(p.499)theformerbutnotthelattertoenjoyimmunityfromdirectattackinbetweenspecificmilitaryoperations.48Thisargumentdoesnotseemparticularlystrong,sincetheunfairadvantageitidentifiescouldjustaseasilybecuredbygrantingStatearmedforcesimmunityfromdirectattackonthesameterms.Second,theICRCsuggeststhat,unlikecivilianswhosefuturedirectparticipationinhostilitiesisverydifficulttoanticipate,thosewhoassumeacontinuouscombatfunctioncanbereliabl[y]predict[ed]todirectlyparticipateinfuturehostilities.49Thisargumentseemssound,assumingofcoursethatitisjustifiabletodirectdefensiveforceatthosewhowouldotherwisecarryoutorparticipateinimminentorfutureattacks,eveniftheyarenotcurrentlycarryingoutorparticipatinginincipientorongoingattacks.Boththecommonlaw,bypermittingdefensiveforceagainstimminentattacks,andmoderncriminallaw,bypermittingdefensiveforcethatisimmediatelynecessarytopreventafutureattack,seemcommittedtothisassumption.

    Onthisassumption,directattacksonthosewhoassumeacontinuouscombatfunctionwillalmostalwaysbeeitherjustified(bythefactthattheywouldotherwisedirectlyparticipateinfuturehostilities)orexcused(byareasonablebeliefthattheywouldotherwisedirectlyparticipateinfuturehostilities).Bycontrast,directattacksoncivilianswhohavedirectlyparticipatedinpasthostilitiesonaspontaneous,unorganizedor

  • Criminal Law and Morality at War

    Page 16 of 25

    PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2015.All Rights Reserved. Under the terms of the l icence agreement, an individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of amonograph in OSO for personal use (for details see http://www.oxfordscholarship.com/page/privacy-policy). Subscriber: PontificiaUniversidad Catolica del Peru (PUCP); date: 30 April 2015

    sporadicbasiswilloftenbeneitherjustifiednorexcusedsince[e]venthefactthatacivilianhasrepeatedlytakenadirectpartinhostilities,eithervoluntarilyorunderpressure,doesnotallowareliablepredictionastofutureconduct.50Indeed,itseemsplausiblethatcombatantswillbettercomplywiththemoralnormsgoverningtheirconductiftheydirectlyattackonlythoseindividualswhoareeitherdirectlyparticipatingincurrenthostilitiesorassumingacontinuouscombatfunctionthanifcombatantstrytoidentifyonacase-by-casebasisandthendirectlyattackthoseindividualswhowouldotherwisedirectlyparticipateinfuturehostilities.

    Thisfinallybringsustomembersofthearmedforcesofastatepartytoanarmedconflict,wholosetheirlegalimmunitytodirectattacksimplybyenteringtheirstate'sarmedforces.Membersofstatearmedforcesmaybedirectlyattackedeveniftheyarenotdirectlyparticipatinginhostilitiesandeveniftheydonotassumeacontinuouscombatfunctionwithintheirarmedforces.Thisisespeciallystrikingbecauseprivatemilitarycontractorsandcivilianemployeesofthearmedforcesperformingnon-combatfunctionsarenotlegallyliabletodirectattack,unlessandforsuchtimeastheydirectlyparticipateinhostilitiesorassumeacontinuouscombatfunction.51Butmembersofarmedforcesperformingnon-combatfunctionsenjoynosuchlegalprotection.(p.500)

    Nodoubtitisoftenextremelydifficulttodistinguishbetweenmembersofarmedforceswhoassumeacontinuouscombatfunctionandmemberswhodonot,perhapsevenmoredifficultthandistinguishingbetweencivilianswhoaredirectlyparticipatinginhostilitiesandcivilianswhoarenot.Itthereforemaybeunfairtodemandthatcombatantsrefrainfromdirectattacksonopposingarmedforcesunlessoruntiltheyhavemadesuchdifficultdistinctions.Moreover,itwouldbeunjusttopunishcombatantswhoreasonablybelievethatthemembersofthestatearmedforceswhomtheyattackhaveassumedacontinuouscombatfunction.Nevertheless,theseconsiderationsdonotsupportasubstantivelegalliabilitytodirectattack,onlyaninversionoftheusualprecautionscombatantsarerequiredtotakeundertheLOAC.Forexample,theLOACrequiresthat,incasesofdoubt,combatantsmustpresumethatindividualsare(i)civilians,(ii)notdirectlyparticipatinginhostilities,and(iii)notassumingacontinuouscombatfunction.Bycontrast,itseemsreasonabletoholdthat,incasesofdoubt,individualsidentifiedasmembersofstatearmedforcesmaybepresumedtoassumeacontinuouscombatfunction.Thisseemsafairriskforthelawtoimposeonindividualswhovolunteertojointhearmedforcesoftheirstateorwhoareconscriptedbutneverthelesshaveanopportunitytochoosebetweentherisksofmembershipandthepunishmentforrefusal.

    However,ifacombatantcomestoknowthatamemberofthearmedforcesofanopposingstateisneitherdirectlyparticipatinginhostilitiesnorassumingacontinuouscombatfunctionthenthecombatantisneitherjustifiednorexcusedindirectlyattackingthatindividual.Inotherwords,whilecombatantsmaynotdirectlyattackanindividualwhoisnotamemberofopposingstatearmedforcesunlesstheyreasonablybelievetheindividualisdirectlyparticipatinginhostilitiesorassumingacontinuouscombatfunction,combatantsmayattackamemberofopposingstatearmedforcesunlesstheyreasonablybelievethememberisnotdirectlyparticipatinginhostilitiesorassumingacontinuous

  • Criminal Law and Morality at War

    Page 17 of 25

    PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2015.All Rights Reserved. Under the terms of the l icence agreement, an individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of amonograph in OSO for personal use (for details see http://www.oxfordscholarship.com/page/privacy-policy). Subscriber: PontificiaUniversidad Catolica del Peru (PUCP); date: 30 April 2015

    combatfunction.Accordingly,itshouldbeaviolationoftheLOACaswellasawarcrimetodirectlyattackamemberofanopposingarmedforcewhomoneknowsisneitherdirectlyparticipatinginhostilitiesnorassumingacontinuouscombatfunction.52

    Itmightbearguedthatmembersofstatearmedforces(exceptmedicalandreligiouspersonnel)havecommittedthemselvestofightiforderedtodosoandmaythereforebedirectlyattackedtopre-emptorpreventthemfromparticipatinginfuturemilitaryoperations.Thisisnotanimplausibleargument.However,theonly(p.501) membersofanarmedforcethataremorallyliabletodirectattacktopre-emptorpreventfuturemilitaryoperationsarethosememberswhowouldotherwisedirectlyparticipateinthosefuturemilitaryoperations.Ifamemberofastatearmedforcehasnotassumedacontinuouscombatfunctionthenitisunwarrantedtoactonthepresumption(thatis,unlessconfrontedbyevidencetothecontrary)thatshewilldirectlyparticipateinfuturemilitaryoperations.Theriskthatadirectattackonsuchanindividualwouldbeunjustifiableistoohighfortakingsucharisktobeexcusable.

    3CONSTRAINTSONDIRECTATTACKInordinarylife,thekillingofanotherhumanbeingisbothapresumptivemoralwrongaswellasacrimewhichcallsforanexculpatoryexplanationintheformofajustification,anexcuse,oradenialofresponsibility.Inarmedconflict,bycontrast,theintentionalkillingofcombatantswhoarenothorsdecombatisneitheraviolationoftheLOACnorawarcrimeunlesscommittedtreacherouslyorperfidiously,suchasbypretendingtobesickorinjured,tosurrenderorcallatruce,ortobeamemberoftheUnitedNationsortheRedCross.Inotherwords,whilekillinganotherhumanbeingiscriminalexceptundercarefullyspecifiedcircumstances,killinganopposingcombatantiscriminalonlyundercarefullyspecifiedcircumstances.Putanotherway,ICLdoesnotconsiderthekillingofcombatantstobeajustifiableorexcusableoffence;rather,ICLdoesnotgenerallyconsiderthekillingofcombatantsanoffenceatall.Thus,questionsofjustificationorexcuseneverarise.Thekillingofcombatantsisgenerallyanon-eventunderICL.

    OnemightconcludethatthisstructuraldifferencebetweenordinarycriminallawandICLreflectsopposingviewsofthevalueofhumanlife.Infact,thisstructuraldifferencemayreflectinsteadanattempttoincorporatejustificatoryelementsintotheoffencedefinitionsofvariouswarcrimes.Inotherwords,sinceonedoesnotwrongindividualswhohavemadethemselvesliabletodirectattack,combatantspursuingajustcausecommitnowrongbyattackingopposingforceswhoundertakeacontinuouscombatfunctionorcivilianswhotakedirectpartinhostilities.53However,evenindividualswhoareliabletodirectattackcanbewrongedifattacksagainstthemviolateothermoralconstraints,includingthoseagainstperfidyand(p.502) treachery.Accordingly,IwillarguebelowthattheunnecessaryordisproportionatekillingofopposingcombatantsshouldbeprohibitedbytheLOACandpunishedasawarcrime.

    3.1NecessityandproportionalityIarguedabovethatthefirst-order,primaryreasonsnottokillorinjureotherhumanbeingsareordinarilyprotectedbysecond-order,exclusionaryreasonsthatprecludethe

  • Criminal Law and Morality at War

    Page 18 of 25

    PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2015.All Rights Reserved. Under the terms of the l icence agreement, an individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of amonograph in OSO for personal use (for details see http://www.oxfordscholarship.com/page/privacy-policy). Subscriber: PontificiaUniversidad Catolica del Peru (PUCP); date: 30 April 2015

    justificationofkillingorinjuringhumanbeingsbyreferencetothecausalconsequencesornon-causalresultsofdoingso.Ialsoarguedthatatleastsomeoftheseexclusionaryreasonsceasetoapplytoindividualswhoposeorarecomplicitinthreatstootherswhoretaintheirrighttoself-defence,andthatsuchindividualsmaythereforebekilledorinjuredasameansofovercomingthethreattheyposeorinwhichtheyarecomplicit.Bycontrast,theprimaryreasonsagainstkillingorinjuringsuchindividualsareleftstanding.Itfollowsthattheuseofdefensiveforceisjustifiableonlyifthethreatcouldnotbeavoidedwithoutusingforceatallorbyusinglessforceandifthemostseriousharmthreatenedtoanyvictimiscomparabletothemostseriousharminflictedonanyattacker.Otherwise,theprimaryreasonsagainstkillingorinjuringindividualswhoareliabletodefensiveforcewoulddefeatthereasonsinfavourofdoingso.

    Itisalsonoteworthythattheharminflictedonindividualswhoareliabletodefensiveforceneednotoutweightheharmthreatened.Theuseofdefensiveforceneednotbethelesserevil,impartiallyconsidered,inordertobejustifiable.Thisistruedespitethefactthatordinarilyitisnotjustifiabletodoharmtoanotherpersoninordertoavoidacomparableharmtooneselforaninnocentthirdparty.Itseemsthatliabilitytodefensiveforcecancelsorannulsthemoralasymmetrybetweendoingandallowingharm.Sinceindividualsmayactjustifiablyonthebasisofanyundefeatedreason,includingeitheroftwoopposingreasonsofcomparableweight,itisjustifiabletoinflictharmonindividualsliabletodefensiveforceeitherasameansorasasideeffectofpreventingcomparableharmtooneselforothers.54Bycontrast,itisonlyjustifiabletoinflictharmonindividualsnotliabletodefensiveforceasasideeffect(butnotasameans)ofpreventingsubstantiallygreaterharmtooneselforothers.(p.503)

    Therequirementofminimumforceentailsthatcombatantsmustofferopposingforcesanopportunitytosurrenderandbetakenprisonerwheneverdoingsowillnotinvolvesignificantlygreaterriskthanusingdeadlyforce.Inaddition,partiestoarmedconflictmayhaveanobligationtodevelopnon-lethalweaponsandusethemwheretheyarelikelytobeeffective.However,giventhenear-universaluseoflethalweaponsinarmedconflict,therequirementofcomparableharmwillalmostalwaysbesatisfiedorreasonablybelievedtobesatisfied.Moreover,theunusualcircumstancesofarmedconflictgenerallypermitcombatantstokillopposingcombatantsinordertopreventinjurytothemselves.First,aninjurymayrenderacombatantmorevulnerabletolaterlethalattackandshemaythereforedefendherlifebydefendingagainstsuchaninjury.Second,aninjurymayrenderacombatantunableorlessabletodefendothers(particularlyhercomradesorcivilians)fromlaterlethalattackandshemaythereforedefendtheirlivesbydefendingagainstsuchaninjury.Finally,aninjurymayforceacombatanttochoosebetweengivingupherpursuitofajustcauseandpursuingthatjustcauseatgreaterrisktoherself.Givensufficientlyhighstakes,deadlyforcemaybeaproportionatemeansofpreventingsuchaninjury.

    Themostdifficultquestionssurroundingnecessityandproportionalityinarmedconflictdonotrelatetothreatsfacedbycombatantsindiscretetacticalsituations,butrathertothemilitaryadvantageswhichcombatantspursueaspartofanoverallstrategytoachieve

  • Criminal Law and Morality at War

    Page 19 of 25

    PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2015.All Rights Reserved. Under the terms of the l icence agreement, an individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of amonograph in OSO for personal use (for details see http://www.oxfordscholarship.com/page/privacy-policy). Subscriber: PontificiaUniversidad Catolica del Peru (PUCP); date: 30 April 2015

    militaryvictory.Asproposedearlier,itisthepursuitofmilitaryvictoryinajustcausethatmakesitjustifiableforcombatantstousedefensiveforce,bothreactivelyandpre-emptively,ratherthanretreating,surrendering,orotherwiseavoidingengagementwithopposingforces.Onthisview,combatantsfightingforajustcausearejustifiedinengagingopposingforces(whentheycouldsafelyavoiddoingso)onlywhennecessarytosecureamilitaryadvantagethatisinturnanecessarypartofajuststrategyforattainingmilitaryvictory.Forpresentpurposes,amilitaryadvantageisanyeventthatcontributestomilitaryvictory;militaryvictoryisachievedwhenopposingforcesarerenderedunwillingorunabletoengageinarmedresistance;andajuststrategyisonethatwouldachieveajustcauseatnecessaryandproportionatecosttoothers.55

    Ontheviewproposed,thekillingofcombatantsisunnecessaryifthecombatantdeathsdonotcausallycontributetotheachievementofamilitaryadvantage(forexample,iftheyarekilledinthefinalhoursbeforeapeacetreatygoesintoeffect)orifasimilarmilitaryadvantagecouldbeachievedwithoutkillingthem(forexample,bytakingthemprisoner).Similarly,ifsecuringamilitaryadvantagewouldnotmakeanecessarycontributiontoajuststrategythencombatantsmaynotengageopposingforcesinordertosecurethatadvantage.Ofcourse,iftheachievementofamilitaryadvantageisanecessarypartofajuststrategythentheexpectedharmtoopposing(p.504) forcescannotbedisproportionateinastrictsense.Thisisbecausethetotalharmtoopposingforcescalledforbyajuststrategyisbydefinitionoutweighedbythevalueofthejustcause.However,sincemilitarystrategiesarecraftedandimplementedunderconditionsofpredictiveuncertainty,onecouldconsideritdisproportionatetoengagewithopposingforcesinpursuitofamilitaryadvantagethatwillonlyslightlyincreasethelikelihoodofmilitaryvictory(forexample,ifalargenumberofopposingforcesaredefendingaremote,fixedpositionthecaptureofwhichwouldjustbarelyincreasethelikelihoodofmilitaryvictory).

    3.2Anewwarcrime?AlthoughthereisnospecificruleoftheLOACexpresslyprohibitingtheunnecessaryordisproportionatekillingofcombatantsorciviliansdirectlyparticipatinginhostilities,theICRChasrecentlyassertedthatsuchkillingsviolategeneralprinciplesoftheLOAC.Specifically,[i]ntheabsenceofexpressregulation,thekindanddegreeofforcepermissibleinattacksagainstlegitimatemilitarytargetsshouldbedetermined,firstofall,basedonthefundamentalprinciplesofmilitarynecessityandhumanity56

    Today,theprincipleofmilitarynecessityisgenerallyrecognizedtopermitonlythatdegreeandkindofforce,nototherwiseprohibitedbythelawofarmedconflict,thatisrequiredinordertoachievethelegitimatepurposeoftheconflict,namelythecompleteorpartialsubmissionoftheenemyattheearliestpossiblemomentwiththeminimumexpenditureoflifeandresources.Complementingandimplicitintheprincipleofmilitarynecessityistheprincipleofhumanity,whichforbidstheinflictionofsuffering,injuryordestructionnotactuallynecessaryfortheaccomplishmentoflegitimatemilitarypurposes.57

  • Criminal Law and Morality at War

    Page 20 of 25

    PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2015.All Rights Reserved. Under the terms of the l icence agreement, an individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of amonograph in OSO for personal use (for details see http://www.oxfordscholarship.com/page/privacy-policy). Subscriber: PontificiaUniversidad Catolica del Peru (PUCP); date: 30 April 2015

    TheICRCconcludesthat:[i]nconjunction,theprinciplesofmilitarynecessityandofhumanityreducethesumtotalofpermissiblemilitaryactionfromthatwhichIHLdoesnotexpresslyprohibittothatwhichisactuallynecessaryfortheaccomplishmentofalegitimatemilitarypurposeintheprevailingcircumstances.58Forexample,theICRCstatesthatitwoulddefybasicnotionsofhumanitytokillanadversaryortorefrainfromgivinghimorheranopportunitytosurrenderwheretheremanifestlyisnonecessityfortheuseoflethalforce.59

    Unfortunately,aswehaveseen,thekillingofcombatantsorciviliansdirectlyparticipatinginhostilities,evenifunnecessaryordisproportionate,isnotawarcrimethatrequiresjustificationorexcuse.Sincethereisordinarilydecisivereasontocriminalizeandpunishseriousmoralwrongdoingwhendoingsowouldpreventsubstantialoverallharmtoothers,thereisatleaststrongreasontomake(p.505) theunnecessaryordisproportionatekillingofcombatantsaninternationalcrime.Nevertheless,thereareatleasttwosignificantargumentsagainstcriminalizingtheunnecessaryordisproportionatekillingofcombatants.

    First,provingthatkillingcertaincombatantswasunnecessarytoachieveagivenmilitaryadvantagerequiresacounterfactualanalysisofthestrategicandtacticaloptionsavailablebutnottakenatthetimethedecisionwasmadetoattack.Itisindeedimportantforcourtsnottoconvictdefendantsbasedonmerespeculationthattheycouldhaveachievedasimilarmilitaryadvantagewithoutkillingsomanyopposingcombatants.Buttherequirementofproofbeyondareasonabledoubtexistspreciselytoensurethatcourtsconvictonlyonthebasisofsufficientevidenceofanactualviolation.Thefactthatunnecessarycombatantkillingsaresometimesdifficulttoprovedoesnotentailthatthosewhichcanbeprovedshouldnotbepunished.Moreover,wheneverintentionallyharmingcombatantswillresultinincidentallyharmingciviliansthenecessityandproportionalityofharmingthelatterwilldependonthenecessityandproportionalityofharmingtheformer.SinceboththeLOACandICLalreadycallforthelatterinquiryitcannotavoidtheformer.

    Inadditiontoproblemsofproof,determiningnecessityandproportionalitycanrequireresolvingdifficultnormativeissues.Forexample,giventhechoicebetweentwoormoremeansofachievingasimilarmilitaryadvantage,isitpermissibletochooseameansthatwillkillmoreopposingcombatantsbutresultinfewerlossestoone'sownforces,orfewerlossestocivilians,orthatissubstantiallymorelikelytoachievethemilitaryadvantagesought?Thesethreeissuesforceprotection,civilianprotection,andlikelihoodofsuccessareindeedcomplex.Theyimplicatethedistinctionbetweenkillingandlettingdie,dutiesofloyaltyandotherassociativeobligations,andmoralchoiceunderconditionsofpredictiveuncertainty.However,theICRChasalreadysuggestedhowtheissuesofforceprotectionandcivilianprotectionshouldberesolvedasamatterofpositivelaw,statingthatoperatingforcescanhardlyberequiredtotakeadditionalrisksforthemselvesorthecivilianpopulationinordertocaptureanarmedadversaryalive.60Moreover,allthreeissuesmustberesolvedinordertomakesimilarjudgmentsregardingthenecessityandproportionalityofincidentalciviliandeaths.Thereisnoobviousreasonnottoconfronttheseissuesinthecontextofcombatantdeathsaswell.

  • Criminal Law and Morality at War

    Page 21 of 25

    PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2015.All Rights Reserved. Under the terms of the l icence agreement, an individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of amonograph in OSO for personal use (for details see http://www.oxfordscholarship.com/page/privacy-policy). Subscriber: PontificiaUniversidad Catolica del Peru (PUCP); date: 30 April 2015

    4CONCLUSIONInordertoevaluatethecurrentcontentandfuturedirectionofinternationalcriminallaw,wemustfirstimproveourunderstandingofthemoralnormsgoverning(p.506) armedconflict.Ihavearguedthatmoralimmunityfromdirectattackisbestunderstoodasexcludingthecausalconsequencesornon-causalresultsofkillingorinjuringindividualsfromcountingtowardthejustificationoftheirdeathorinjury;thatmoralliabilitytodirectattackrequireseitherposingathreattoindividualswhoretaintheirrighttoself-defenceorcomplicityinthethreatsposedbyotherstosuchindividuals;andthatmoralliabilitytodirectattackisconstrainedbymoralnormsofnecessityandproportionality.Onthesegrounds,Ihavearguedthatinternationalcriminallawshouldcondemnandpunishaswarcrimesthereckless,negligent,andunnecessarykillingofciviliansnotdirectlyparticipatinginhostilities;directattacksonmembersofstatearmedforceswhomtheattackerknowsareneitherdirectlyparticipatinginhostilitiesnorassumingacontinuouscombatfunction;aswellastheunnecessaryordisproportionatekillingorinjuringofcombatantsorofciviliansdirectlyparticipatinginhostilities.Implementingtheserecommendationswouldgoalongwaytowardbringinginternationalcriminallawintoalignmentwithitsphilosophicalfoundations.

    Notes:(1)Itshouldbenotedattheoutsetthatthechapterexaminesonlythemoralnormsapplicabletotheconductofarmedconflictbycombatantsfightingforajustcause.Inpartthisisbecausemostcombatantsclaimtofightforajustcauseandsuchclaimsareoftendifficulttodecisivelyrefute.Often,themostthelawcanhopetoachievewillbetoholdcombatantstothemoralnormsthatwouldapplytothemiftheirclaimstofightforajustcauseweretrue.

    (2)TMScanlon,MoralDimensions:Permissibility,Meaning,Blame(Cambridge,MA:HarvardUniversityPress,2008),289.

    (3)ThisdiscussiondrawsonJGardner,JustificationandReasons,inASimesterandATHSmith(eds),HarmandCulpability(Oxford:ClarendonPress,1996),103.

    (4)Scanlon,MoralDimensions,238.

    (5)Theconceptsofmandatorynorms,primaryreasons,andexclusionaryreasonswereintroducedinJRaz,PracticalReasonandNorms(revedn;Oxford:OxfordUniversityPress,1999).

    (6)ThisaccountwasoriginallypresentedinAAHaque,Torture,Terror,andtheInversionofMoralPrinciple(2007)10NewCriminalLawReview613.Inotethere(at640)that,forthresholddeontologists,thecausalconsequencesandnon-causalresultsofkillingciviliansareexcludedonlybelowaquantitativeorqualitativethreshold.

    (7)VTadros,WrongdoingandMotivation(thisvolume).

    (8)Moreprecisely,acombatantmustacteitherwiththeintentionofachievingthemilitary

  • Criminal Law and Morality at War

    Page 22 of 25

    PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2015.All Rights Reserved. Under the terms of the l icence agreement, an individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of amonograph in OSO for personal use (for details see http://www.oxfordscholarship.com/page/privacy-policy). Subscriber: PontificiaUniversidad Catolica del Peru (PUCP); date: 30 April 2015

    advantageorontheconditionthatthemilitaryadvantagewillbeachievedandforanotherpermissiblepurpose.Haque,Torture,Terror,andtheInversionofMoralPrinciple,648.

    (9)Scanlon,MoralDimensions,289.

    (10)JMcMahan,KillinginWar(Oxford:OxfordUniversityPress,2009),211.

    (11)FMKamm,FailuresofJustWarTheory:Terror,Harm,andJustice(2004)114Ethics650,6689,nn267;FMKamm,TerrorismandSeveralMoralDistinctions(2006)12LegalTheory19,412,41,n21.

    (12)ProtocolAdditionaltotheGenevaConventionsof12August1949,andRelatingtotheProtectionofVictimsofInternationalArmedConflicts(ProtocolI),art51(2),8June1977,1125UNTS3.

    (13)Ibidart48.

    (14)Ibidart51(4).

    (15)Ibidarts57(3)(necessity)and51(5)(b)(proportionality).

    (16)RomeStatuteoftheInternationalCriminalCourt,art8(2)(b)(i),17July1998,UNDocA/CONF183/9.

    (17)Ibidart8(2)(b)(iv).

    (18)IdiscusssomeoftheseissuesatgreaterlengthinAAHaque,ProtectingandRespectingCivilians:SubstantiveandStructuralDefectsoftheRomeStatute(2011)14NewCriminalLawReview(forthcoming).

    (19)McMahan,KillinginWar,35.

    (20)Ibid177.McMahanreferstoobjectivejustificationratherthanjustifiabilitybutIbelievethatforthepurposesofthissectionthetwoconceptsareequivalent.

    (21)AAHaque,RightsandLiabilitiesatWar,inPHRobinson,SGarveyandKFerzan(eds),CriminalLawConversations(Oxford:OxfordUniversityPress,2009),395.

    (22)Interestingly,becausethecivilianstakeuparmsinself-defenceratherthantotakesidesintheconflict,theyarenottakingdirectpartinhostilitiesandthereforedonotlosetheirlegalimmunityfromdirectattack.TheTacticalBombersdirectattackontheciviliansthereforeviolatestheLOACandconstitutesawarcrime,althoughtheTacticalBombermayclaimself-defenceifchargedwithawarcrime.

    (23)McMahan,KillinginWar,412and238,n3(MyanalysisofthemistakeisslightlydifferentfromHaques).

    (24)Haque,RightsandLiabilitiesatWar.DRMapel,MoralLiabilitytoDefensiveKilling

  • Criminal Law and Morality at War

    Page 23 of 25

    PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2015.All Rights Reserved. Under the terms of the l icence agreement, an individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of amonograph in OSO for personal use (for details see http://www.oxfordscholarship.com/page/privacy-policy). Subscriber: PontificiaUniversidad Catolica del Peru (PUCP); date: 30 April 2015

    andSymmetricalSelf-defense(2009)18JournalofPoliticalPhilosophy198.

    (25)AsimilardynamicisvividlycapturedbyVeraBergelsonscaseofJackandJill:AssumethatcriminalsconditionedthereleaseoftheircaptivesonJacksrapeofJill.Realizingthatthisistheonlywaytosaveseverallives,includingJillsown,Jackreluctantlyagrees.Jill,ontheotherhand,vehementlyproteststhatshewouldratherdiethanbeviolated.WhenJackattemptstooverpowerher,JillfightsbackandseriouslyinjuresJack.VBergelson,Rights,Wrongs,andComparativeJustifications(2007)28CardozoLawReview101,113.If,asBergelsonbelieves,rapecanbejustifiedasameansofpreventingagreaterevilthenBergelsoniscorrectthatbothJackandJillactjustifiably.

    (26)McMahan,KillinginWar,208.

    (27)Ibid21415.

    (28)JDressler,ReassessingtheTheoreticalUnderpinningsofAccompliceLiability:NewSolutionstoanOldProblem(1985)37HastingsLawJournal91.

    (29)ButseeWilcoxvJeffery[1951]1AllER464,KB(findingaccompliceliabilityonthebasisoftrivialandunnecessarycausalcontribution).

    (30)Itmustbeadmittedthatscholarswhoassertthatderivativeliabilitytodirectattackrequiresanecessarycausalcontributiontoathreatposedbyanotherpersonhavenotproducedadetailedargumentinsupportofthatprinciple.LAAlexander,Self-DefenseandtheKillingofNoncombatants:AReplytoFullinwider(1976)5Philosophy&PublicAffairs40815.Nonetheless,somelimitationofthiskindseemsunavoidable.

    (31)JMcMahan,TheBasisofMoralLiabilitytoDefensiveKilling(2005)15PhilosophicalIssues386,3945.

    (32)McMahan,KillinginWar,178.

    (33)JMcMahan,TheMoralityofWarandtheLawofWar,inDRodinandHShue(eds),JustandUnjustWarriors:TheMoralandLegalStatusofSoldiers(Oxford:OxfordUniversityPress,2008),19,22.

    (34)Ibid.

    (35)Ibid5.

    (36)Moreprecisely,combatantsarerelievedofthedutytoretreatorsurrenderonlyifthejustcauseforwhichtheyfightisproportionatetothetotalharmtheyexpecttoinflictinpursuitofthatjustcause.Asimilarviewissuggested,thoughnotpursued,inDRodin,WarandSelf-Defense(NewYork:OxfordUniversityPress,2003),1328.

    (37)Asdiscussedfurtherinthefollowingsection,offensiveoperationsarebestunderstoodintermsofthepre-emptiveuseofdefensiveforcebycombatantspursuinga

  • Criminal Law and Morality at War

    Page 24 of 25

    PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2015.All Rights Reserved. Under the terms of the l icence agreement, an individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of amonograph in OSO for personal use (for details see http://www.oxfordscholarship.com/page/privacy-policy). Subscriber: PontificiaUniversidad Catolica del Peru (PUCP); date: 30 April 2015

    justcause.

    (38)McMahan,KillinginWar,226.

    (39)NMelzer,InterpretiveGuidanceontheNotionofDirectParticipationinHostilitiesUnderInternationalHumanitarianLaw(ICRC,2009),46(availableathttp://www.icrc.org/Web/Eng/siteeng0.nsf/htmlall/p0990/$File/ICRC_002_0990.PDF).

    (40)Ibid70.

    (41)Ibid71.

    (42)Ibid48.

    (43)Ibid46.

    (44)Ibid53.

    (45)Ibid56.

    (46)Ibid66.

    (47)Ibid34(statingthatrecruiters,trainers,financiersandpropagandistsretaintheirimmunityfromdirectattack,asdoindividualswhosefunctionislimitedtothepurchasing,smuggling,manufacturingandmaintainingofweaponsandotherequipmentoutsidespecificmilitaryoperationsortothecollectionofintelligenceotherthanofatacticalnature).

    (48)Ibid72.

    (49)Ibid71.

    (50)Ibid71.

    (51)Ibid37.

    (52)Inaforthcomingarticle,GabriellaBlumarguesthatmembersofarmedforcesmaybepresumedtoposeanimmediatethreatbutindividualmembersmaynotbetargetedifthereisreasontobelievetheyposenoimmediatethreat.GBlum,TheDispensableLivesofSoldiers(2010)2JournalofLegalAnalysis69.Bycontrast,thischapterproposesthatmembersofarmedforcesmaybepresumedtoassumeacontinuouscombatfunctionbutindividualmembersmaynotbetargetedifitisreasonabletobelievetheyareneitherassumingacontinuouscombatfunctionnordirectlyparticipatinginhostilities.Inaddition,directattacksonindividualsassumingacontinuouscombatfunctionarelimitedbytheconstraintsofnecessityandproportionalitydescribedbelow.

    (53)Importantly,sinceliabilityisawrong-obliteratingjustificationratherthanawrong-overridingjustification,theconditionsofliabilitytodirectattackmaybeincorporatedinto

  • Criminal Law and Morality at War

    Page 25 of 25

    PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2015.All Rights Reserved. Under the terms of the l icence agreement, an individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of amonograph in OSO for personal use (for details see http://www.oxfordscholarship.com/page/privacy-policy). Subscriber: PontificiaUniversidad Catolica del Peru (PUCP); date: 30 April 2015

    anoffencedefinitionratherthanadefencedefinitionwithoutglossingoveranymoralremainderleftbehindbytheharmfulact.

    (54)Asindomesticcriminallaw,defensiveforceneednotbestrictlyproportionate.Egdeadlyforcemaybeusedtopreventseriousbodilyinjury.Notealsothattheharmthreatenedtoanyvictimmustbecomparabletotheharminflictedoneachattackerindividually,ratherthanallattackerscumulatively.Itisnotdisproportionatetokillmultipleattackerswhoaretryingtokillyou.Bycontrast,itwouldbedisproportionatetokillmultipleinnocentsasasideeffectofsavingoneself.Whyaggregateharmtotheinnocentaffectsproportionalitywhileaggregateharmtoattackersdoesnotisanimportantquestionthatcannotbeaddressedhere.

    (55)Ajuststrategymustalsojustlydistributeharmsamongthepartiestotheconflictaswellascivilians.Thejustdistributionofharmsisacomplextopicwhichcannotbeadequatelydiscussedhere.

    (56)NMelzer,InterpretiveGuidanceontheNotionofDirectParticipationinHostilitiesUnderInternationalHumanitarianLaw(ICRC,2009),79.

    (57)Ibid79.

    (58)Ibid79.

    (59)Ibid82.

    (60)Ibid82.

    Accessbroughttoyouby: PontificiaUniversidadCatolicadelPeru(PUCP)