Comparative Method and British Politics

18
The Comparative Method and the Study of British Politics Samuel H. Beer I My title suggests paradox. How can you make comparisons when you are dealing with only one system? The question has poini and I am going to hinge these brief introductory remarks on methodology on a distinction be- tween what I shall call the method of comparison and the method of hypothesis. When we first began discussing these questions of comparative politics quite some years ago, we talked a good deal about what we called "the logic of comparison." In trying to imagine what procedure this logic involved, we would think of an interesting phenomenon such as two-party systems and then try to work out an orderly procedure for determining the necessary and sufficient conditions for its existence. Frankly, in our projections of what we thought this method might achieve, the prospects were somehow not nearly so bright as we felt they ought to be. Was not comparison the social scientist's equivalent of the natural scientist's laboratory? It was only when we added to our operations the method of hypothesis that the prospects began to brighten. We moved our stress from induction to deduction. We approached comparison through theory rather than ap- proaching theory through comparison. From theory-from Aristotle or Hobbes, from Marx or Weber-we drew out hypotheses about important and interesting events and then sought to test them in particular contexts. In this way interesting questions about political development and about such things as the role of elites, classes, and intellectual innovation were injected into comparative and historical studies. Of course, I am aware that the two methods are complementary. When you have tested a hypothesis in one particular context you will probably go on to test it in another. If you have found the hypothesized correlation you will want a control to assure you that the connection is real, not accidental. Moreover, as you move on from case to case it is likely and desirable that your initial hypotheses or hunches will be developed and revised. Nevertheless, the difference in emphasis can mean a difference in research strategy. It is perhaps mainly a difference in what you focus on at the start: theory or fact. The former-the method of hypothesis-is, I think, partic- ularly appropriate for the study of individual systems. Sensitized in count- less ways by your knowledge of theory, you examine some system or aspect of a system, draw out hypotheses that seem relevant, and test them against the facts. Looking back, it seems to me that this method reflects the way I proceeded when I made a study of British parties and pressure groups several years ago.1At present I am engaged in bringing this study up to date. In this article 1 British Politics in the Collectivist Age (New York, 1965). 19 The Comparative Method and the Study of British Politics Samuel H. Beer I My title suggests paradox. How can you make comparisons when you are dealing with only one system? The question has poini and I am going to hinge these brief introductory remarks on methodology on a distinction be- tween what I shall call the method of comparison and the method of hypothesis. When we first began discussing these questions of comparative politics quite some years ago, we talked a good deal about what we called "the logic of comparison." In trying to imagine what procedure this logic involved, we would think of an interesting phenomenon such as two-party systems and then try to work out an orderly procedure for determining the necessary and sufficient conditions for its existence. Frankly, in our projections of what we thought this method might achieve, the prospects were somehow not nearly so bright as we felt they ought to be. Was not comparison the social scientist's equivalent of the natural scientist's laboratory? It was only when we added to our operations the method of hypothesis that the prospects began to brighten. We moved our stress from induction to deduction. We approached comparison through theory rather than ap- proaching theory through comparison. From theory-from Aristotle or Hobbes, from Marx or Weber-we drew out hypotheses about important and interesting events and then sought to test them in particular contexts. In this way interesting questions about political development and about such things as the role of elites, classes, and intellectual innovation were injected into comparative and historical studies. Of course, I am aware that the two methods are complementary. When you have tested a hypothesis in one particular context you will probably go on to test it in another. If you have found the hypothesized correlation you will want a control to assure you that the connection is real, not accidental. Moreover, as you move on from case to case it is likely and desirable that your initial hypotheses or hunches will be developed and revised. Nevertheless, the difference in emphasis can mean a difference in research strategy. It is perhaps mainly a difference in what you focus on at the start: theory or fact. The former-the method of hypothesis-is, I think, partic- ularly appropriate for the study of individual systems. Sensitized in count- less ways by your knowledge of theory, you examine some system or aspect of a system, draw out hypotheses that seem relevant, and test them against the facts. Looking back, it seems to me that this method reflects the way I proceeded when I made a study of British parties and pressure groups several years ago.1At present I am engaged in bringing this study up to date. In this article 1 British Politics in the Collectivist Age (New York, 1965). 19

Transcript of Comparative Method and British Politics

Page 1: Comparative Method and British Politics

The Comparative Method

and the Study of British Politics

Samuel H. Beer

I My title suggests paradox. How can you make comparisons when you are dealing with only one system? The question has poini and I am going to hinge these brief introductory remarks on methodology on a distinction be- tween what I shall call the method of comparison and the method of hypothesis.

When we first began discussing these questions of comparative politics quite some years ago, we talked a good deal about what we called "the logic of comparison." In trying to imagine what procedure this logic involved, we would think of an interesting phenomenon such as two-party systems and then try to work out an orderly procedure for determining the necessary and sufficient conditions for its existence. Frankly, in our projections of what we thought this method might achieve, the prospects were somehow not nearly so bright as we felt they ought to be. Was not comparison the social scientist's equivalent of the natural scientist's laboratory?

It was only when we added to our operations the method of hypothesis that the prospects began to brighten. We moved our stress from induction to deduction. We approached comparison through theory rather than ap- proaching theory through comparison. From theory-from Aristotle or Hobbes, from Marx or Weber-we drew out hypotheses about important and interesting events and then sought to test them in particular contexts. In this way interesting questions about political development and about such things as the role of elites, classes, and intellectual innovation were injected into comparative and historical studies.

Of course, I am aware that the two methods are complementary. When you have tested a hypothesis in one particular context you will probably go on to test it in another. If you have found the hypothesized correlation you will want a control to assure you that the connection is real, not accidental. Moreover, as you move on from case to case it is likely and desirable that your initial hypotheses or hunches will be developed and revised.

Nevertheless, the difference in emphasis can mean a difference in research strategy. It is perhaps mainly a difference in what you focus on at the start: theory or fact. The former-the method of hypothesis-is, I think, partic- ularly appropriate for the study of individual systems. Sensitized in count- less ways by your knowledge of theory, you examine some system or aspect of a system, draw out hypotheses that seem relevant, and test them against the facts.

Looking back, it seems to me that this method reflects the way I proceeded when I made a study of British parties and pressure groups several years ago.1 At present I am engaged in bringing this study up to date. In this article

1 British Politics in the Collectivist Age (New York, 1965).

19

The Comparative Method

and the Study of British Politics

Samuel H. Beer

I My title suggests paradox. How can you make comparisons when you are dealing with only one system? The question has poini and I am going to hinge these brief introductory remarks on methodology on a distinction be- tween what I shall call the method of comparison and the method of hypothesis.

When we first began discussing these questions of comparative politics quite some years ago, we talked a good deal about what we called "the logic of comparison." In trying to imagine what procedure this logic involved, we would think of an interesting phenomenon such as two-party systems and then try to work out an orderly procedure for determining the necessary and sufficient conditions for its existence. Frankly, in our projections of what we thought this method might achieve, the prospects were somehow not nearly so bright as we felt they ought to be. Was not comparison the social scientist's equivalent of the natural scientist's laboratory?

It was only when we added to our operations the method of hypothesis that the prospects began to brighten. We moved our stress from induction to deduction. We approached comparison through theory rather than ap- proaching theory through comparison. From theory-from Aristotle or Hobbes, from Marx or Weber-we drew out hypotheses about important and interesting events and then sought to test them in particular contexts. In this way interesting questions about political development and about such things as the role of elites, classes, and intellectual innovation were injected into comparative and historical studies.

Of course, I am aware that the two methods are complementary. When you have tested a hypothesis in one particular context you will probably go on to test it in another. If you have found the hypothesized correlation you will want a control to assure you that the connection is real, not accidental. Moreover, as you move on from case to case it is likely and desirable that your initial hypotheses or hunches will be developed and revised.

Nevertheless, the difference in emphasis can mean a difference in research strategy. It is perhaps mainly a difference in what you focus on at the start: theory or fact. The former-the method of hypothesis-is, I think, partic- ularly appropriate for the study of individual systems. Sensitized in count- less ways by your knowledge of theory, you examine some system or aspect of a system, draw out hypotheses that seem relevant, and test them against the facts.

Looking back, it seems to me that this method reflects the way I proceeded when I made a study of British parties and pressure groups several years ago.1 At present I am engaged in bringing this study up to date. In this article

1 British Politics in the Collectivist Age (New York, 1965).

19

Page 2: Comparative Method and British Politics

Comparative Politics October 1968 Comparative Politics October 1968

I shall give an account of my progress in the hope that it will illustrate this method. First I wish to bring out the theoretical background, with stress on certain aspects of modernization theory. Next I shall turn to recent changes, focusing on questions raised by theory. A concluding section will be con- cerned with possible future developments.

II My immediate concern has been to place British politics in the context of the "organizational revolution."2 By this I mean the rise of the large-scale, formal organization to a position of dominance in most spheres of Western society during recent generations. The leading example is the great business corporation. But as Weber pointed out in his discussion of "universal bureaucratization," we see similar forms in government, education, and politics.

In this task of description and explanation, I have been helped by or- ganization theory, especially those ideas developed in the study of economic concentration. At the same time, I have been concerned with the further elaboration of these ideas, using the British materials to get some light on why such organizations arise in the field of parties and pressure groups, what effect their size has upon their internal structure and external relations, and, finally, what their tendencies of future development may be. To put the matter briefly and ambitiously, my concern has been to work out the "laws" of political concentration. Thus, not only is theory brought to the study of fact, but also, I hope, such study is so conducted as to enhance theory.

While my emphasis is on recent decades, these are examined against a background of British political development going back to the sixteenth century. The most recent phase, which I call Collectivist, is considered as following earlier phases, Radical, Liberal, Old Whig, and Old Tory. These terms, I have said, "characterize the main stages in what one may call the modernization of British politics."3 My larger concern therefore is also with the forces that have impelled development over a broad sweep of British history. This is not the place to elaborate a theory of modernization. A few broad outlines, however, may be sketched in order to show how, with re- gard to certain major forces and trends, contemporary British politics is continuous with preceding phases.

This term "modernization" is a question rather than an answer. The question is whether one can find in Western society of recent centuries and in the process by which it arose a type or model that is useful for general comparative study and analysis. Following Weber, I should say that the key concept is rationalization.4 By a process of rationalization I mean the growth of scientific knowledge in the broadest sense and the impact of this

2 Kenneth Boulding, The Organizational Revolution (New York, 1953). 3 British Politics in the Collectivist Age, p. x. 4 See also Talcott Parsons, The Social System (Glencoe, 1951), on "institutionalized

rationalization and 'cultural lag,'" pp. 505-520; and Parsons, "Certain Primary Sources and Patterns of Aggression in the Social Structure of the Western World," Essays in Sociological Theory, Pure and Applied (Glencoe, 1949).

I shall give an account of my progress in the hope that it will illustrate this method. First I wish to bring out the theoretical background, with stress on certain aspects of modernization theory. Next I shall turn to recent changes, focusing on questions raised by theory. A concluding section will be con- cerned with possible future developments.

II My immediate concern has been to place British politics in the context of the "organizational revolution."2 By this I mean the rise of the large-scale, formal organization to a position of dominance in most spheres of Western society during recent generations. The leading example is the great business corporation. But as Weber pointed out in his discussion of "universal bureaucratization," we see similar forms in government, education, and politics.

In this task of description and explanation, I have been helped by or- ganization theory, especially those ideas developed in the study of economic concentration. At the same time, I have been concerned with the further elaboration of these ideas, using the British materials to get some light on why such organizations arise in the field of parties and pressure groups, what effect their size has upon their internal structure and external relations, and, finally, what their tendencies of future development may be. To put the matter briefly and ambitiously, my concern has been to work out the "laws" of political concentration. Thus, not only is theory brought to the study of fact, but also, I hope, such study is so conducted as to enhance theory.

While my emphasis is on recent decades, these are examined against a background of British political development going back to the sixteenth century. The most recent phase, which I call Collectivist, is considered as following earlier phases, Radical, Liberal, Old Whig, and Old Tory. These terms, I have said, "characterize the main stages in what one may call the modernization of British politics."3 My larger concern therefore is also with the forces that have impelled development over a broad sweep of British history. This is not the place to elaborate a theory of modernization. A few broad outlines, however, may be sketched in order to show how, with re- gard to certain major forces and trends, contemporary British politics is continuous with preceding phases.

This term "modernization" is a question rather than an answer. The question is whether one can find in Western society of recent centuries and in the process by which it arose a type or model that is useful for general comparative study and analysis. Following Weber, I should say that the key concept is rationalization.4 By a process of rationalization I mean the growth of scientific knowledge in the broadest sense and the impact of this

2 Kenneth Boulding, The Organizational Revolution (New York, 1953). 3 British Politics in the Collectivist Age, p. x. 4 See also Talcott Parsons, The Social System (Glencoe, 1951), on "institutionalized

rationalization and 'cultural lag,'" pp. 505-520; and Parsons, "Certain Primary Sources and Patterns of Aggression in the Social Structure of the Western World," Essays in Sociological Theory, Pure and Applied (Glencoe, 1949).

20 20

Page 3: Comparative Method and British Politics

Samuel H. Beer Samuel H. Beer

knowledge upon culture and social structure. Knowledge has extended human control and enhanced the sense of human competence ever since prehistoric man made his first tools and established his first laws. Modernity, however, was produced and characterized by a particular kind of knowl- edge, viz., knowledge that was at once empirically founded and systemati- cally ordered. We may call it scientific only if the term is understood broadly enough to include the protoscience and developing folk technology that led to some of the earlier products of modernity, such as the first inventions of the Industrial Revolution. For the purposes of this present study we espe- cially need to distinguish the highly developed science, both natural and social, of recent decades which is producing the "scientific revolution" and which has vastly enhanced the impact of rationalization upon both society in general and the polity in particular. It is in this new phase of the mod- ernizing process that we find some of the principal forces tending to trans- form British politics of the Collectivist age.

Rationalization has been a principal force producing directly and indi- rectly some of the main features of modern society, such as industrialization and bureaucratization. Yet we must not try to make it explain too much. There are important traits of the modern polity which derive from other sources. With regard to attitudes and values, one of the most important is what may be called "voluntarism." By this I mean the view that human wishes are the basis of legitimacy in constitutional structure and in public policy. The principal contrast is with the premodern views of classical and medieval political culture that the basis of legitimacy is to be found in some source outside the human will, such as divine command or a teleo- logical order.

Rationalism, as the notion that men have the ability scientifically to con- trol nature and society, does not logically entail voluntarism, the notion that men ought to design their environment, natural and social, to suit their own purposes and wishes. Yet in the rise of political modernity the two are closely associated. For instance, the modern conception of law-making in- volves both. It includes the notion that men can use their empirically de- rived knowledge to control events in order, say, to promote the increase in the wealth of the nation by the appropriate economic policy. It also ex- presses the attitude that what men want-whether, for instance, it is the greater national power of mercantilist theory or the consumers' satisfaction of Smithian economics-should be the basis of public policy.

The importance of this association is that the rise of voluntarism has given a wide scope to the process and products of rationalization. The ap- plication of science and technology to economic, social, and political prob- lems greatly alters the mode of life in these spheres, often requiring far- reaching adaptation of norms and values. If premodern attitudes prevailed, the resulting conflict between a rigid ethical discipline and the requirements of a developing society would lead to severe strain and conflict. Indeed, because such attitudes have in many respects survived, Western moderni- zation has frequently been marked by a special kind of conflict to which Parsons has given the name "fundamentalist reaction."5 In Britain these

knowledge upon culture and social structure. Knowledge has extended human control and enhanced the sense of human competence ever since prehistoric man made his first tools and established his first laws. Modernity, however, was produced and characterized by a particular kind of knowl- edge, viz., knowledge that was at once empirically founded and systemati- cally ordered. We may call it scientific only if the term is understood broadly enough to include the protoscience and developing folk technology that led to some of the earlier products of modernity, such as the first inventions of the Industrial Revolution. For the purposes of this present study we espe- cially need to distinguish the highly developed science, both natural and social, of recent decades which is producing the "scientific revolution" and which has vastly enhanced the impact of rationalization upon both society in general and the polity in particular. It is in this new phase of the mod- ernizing process that we find some of the principal forces tending to trans- form British politics of the Collectivist age.

Rationalization has been a principal force producing directly and indi- rectly some of the main features of modern society, such as industrialization and bureaucratization. Yet we must not try to make it explain too much. There are important traits of the modern polity which derive from other sources. With regard to attitudes and values, one of the most important is what may be called "voluntarism." By this I mean the view that human wishes are the basis of legitimacy in constitutional structure and in public policy. The principal contrast is with the premodern views of classical and medieval political culture that the basis of legitimacy is to be found in some source outside the human will, such as divine command or a teleo- logical order.

Rationalism, as the notion that men have the ability scientifically to con- trol nature and society, does not logically entail voluntarism, the notion that men ought to design their environment, natural and social, to suit their own purposes and wishes. Yet in the rise of political modernity the two are closely associated. For instance, the modern conception of law-making in- volves both. It includes the notion that men can use their empirically de- rived knowledge to control events in order, say, to promote the increase in the wealth of the nation by the appropriate economic policy. It also ex- presses the attitude that what men want-whether, for instance, it is the greater national power of mercantilist theory or the consumers' satisfaction of Smithian economics-should be the basis of public policy.

The importance of this association is that the rise of voluntarism has given a wide scope to the process and products of rationalization. The ap- plication of science and technology to economic, social, and political prob- lems greatly alters the mode of life in these spheres, often requiring far- reaching adaptation of norms and values. If premodern attitudes prevailed, the resulting conflict between a rigid ethical discipline and the requirements of a developing society would lead to severe strain and conflict. Indeed, because such attitudes have in many respects survived, Western moderni- zation has frequently been marked by a special kind of conflict to which Parsons has given the name "fundamentalist reaction."5 In Britain these

5 Parsons, "C rtain Primary Sources." 5 Parsons, "C rtain Primary Sources."

21 21

Page 4: Comparative Method and British Politics

Comparative Politics October 1968 Comparative Politics October 1968

conflicts have usually been milder than in most other countries of the West. Yet they have occurred, and even today in some spheres of British political development one can discern this typical strain of modernization. A princi- pal instance would be the tenacious assertion of class identities by members of both upper and lower strata.

III Voluntarism leaves open many questions, not the least of which is, Whose wishes are to govern? An elitist version could be conceived which put so high a value on the wishes of a few that the many would be wholly excluded from power. Fascism would fit this pattern. Yet in contrast with classical and medieval notions, there does seem to be in voluntarism an openness, if not a tendency, toward democracy. While it is fairly obvious that knowledge of the good, on which premodern conceptions based authority, is unequally distributed throughout society, it is hard to deny that every man at least knows what he wants.

Another tendency toward democracy, or at any rate toward that partici- pation of which democracy is one variety, is more interesting and probably more important. It arises from situational rather than ideal forces. Very broadly, the proposition is that the pattern of public policy itself sometimes requires that certain groups be given power. When we study the rise of democracy we commonly concentrate on the struggle of excluded groups for access to influence and authority. One of the interesting problems of modernization studies is how excluded groups acquire and use the non- political power necessary to wage successfully this struggle for entry. Yet we should also recognize that a group's chances for success may be greatly enhanced by the polity's need for their participation. It has, for instance, been cogently argued that the Reform Act of 1867 was necessary in order to win the consent and cooperation of the skilled working class for the new pattern of government intervention that was being inaugurated.6 Nor is the possibility confined to modern times: the origins of medieval representation have been interpreted as "self-government at the King's command."7

A major instance, however, is provided by the new system of functional representation that has arisen in Britain in the Collectivist period. The wel- fare state and especially the managed economy of recent decades simply could not operate without the advice and cooperation of the great organized producers' groups of business, labor, and agriculture, and the history of these groups provides many instances showing the powerful influence of government in calling them into existence, shaping their goals, and endow- ing them with effective power.8 At the present time the burdens and com- plexities of the welfare state and managed economy similarly require a still greater mobilization of consent.

I do not by any means intend to say that every such need of public policy will be met by a corresponding and appropriate incorporation of the rele- vant group into the effective polity. An authoritarian system may meet the

6 By Prof. H. L. Beales of the University of London in private conversation. 7 Albert B. White, Self-Government at the King's Command: A Study in the Begin-

nings of English Democracy (London, 1933). 8 British Politics in the Collectivist Age, esp. Ch. 12.

conflicts have usually been milder than in most other countries of the West. Yet they have occurred, and even today in some spheres of British political development one can discern this typical strain of modernization. A princi- pal instance would be the tenacious assertion of class identities by members of both upper and lower strata.

III Voluntarism leaves open many questions, not the least of which is, Whose wishes are to govern? An elitist version could be conceived which put so high a value on the wishes of a few that the many would be wholly excluded from power. Fascism would fit this pattern. Yet in contrast with classical and medieval notions, there does seem to be in voluntarism an openness, if not a tendency, toward democracy. While it is fairly obvious that knowledge of the good, on which premodern conceptions based authority, is unequally distributed throughout society, it is hard to deny that every man at least knows what he wants.

Another tendency toward democracy, or at any rate toward that partici- pation of which democracy is one variety, is more interesting and probably more important. It arises from situational rather than ideal forces. Very broadly, the proposition is that the pattern of public policy itself sometimes requires that certain groups be given power. When we study the rise of democracy we commonly concentrate on the struggle of excluded groups for access to influence and authority. One of the interesting problems of modernization studies is how excluded groups acquire and use the non- political power necessary to wage successfully this struggle for entry. Yet we should also recognize that a group's chances for success may be greatly enhanced by the polity's need for their participation. It has, for instance, been cogently argued that the Reform Act of 1867 was necessary in order to win the consent and cooperation of the skilled working class for the new pattern of government intervention that was being inaugurated.6 Nor is the possibility confined to modern times: the origins of medieval representation have been interpreted as "self-government at the King's command."7

A major instance, however, is provided by the new system of functional representation that has arisen in Britain in the Collectivist period. The wel- fare state and especially the managed economy of recent decades simply could not operate without the advice and cooperation of the great organized producers' groups of business, labor, and agriculture, and the history of these groups provides many instances showing the powerful influence of government in calling them into existence, shaping their goals, and endow- ing them with effective power.8 At the present time the burdens and com- plexities of the welfare state and managed economy similarly require a still greater mobilization of consent.

I do not by any means intend to say that every such need of public policy will be met by a corresponding and appropriate incorporation of the rele- vant group into the effective polity. An authoritarian system may meet the

6 By Prof. H. L. Beales of the University of London in private conversation. 7 Albert B. White, Self-Government at the King's Command: A Study in the Begin-

nings of English Democracy (London, 1933). 8 British Politics in the Collectivist Age, esp. Ch. 12.

22 22

Page 5: Comparative Method and British Politics

Samuel H. Beer Samuel H. Beer

need by a mobilization of consent that involves little or no real accommoda- tion of the structure of power. Moreover, and more generally, the "needs" of systems, as of individuals, simply may go unfulfilled. Yet the fact that such situational pressures do arise throws light on an important connection between rationalization and participation, two of the major features com- monly ascribed to the modern polity.

As a matter of historical fact, we do find that the development of public policy under the influence of growing knowledge has been associated with the extension of democracy, or its authoritarian substitute. No doubt the forces promoting each of these developments are in many respects inde- pendent of one another. Yet there are strong ties that tend to make them develop together. Rationalization and participation can in the short run come into conflict, as is shown by the familiar problem of reconciling democracy and planning. Yet as the analysis of this problem also shows, in the long run the two go together. The kind of flexible and constantly chang- ing control typically exercised by modern polities cannot rest on rigid norms and unthinking custom, but must enlist the active response and understanding of affected groups. Certainly, in considering the possible future developments of a political system, as we shall do at a later point of this article, we should look for those changes in public policy that may re- quire an adjustment of the structure of power in favor of relevant groups.

IV Rationalism and voluntarism characterize the modern spirit and generally pervade attitude and behavior so far as a society is modern. In politics, they suggest a broad but distinctive class of systems, defining the basic orienta- tions that legitimize and institutionalize processes of rationalization and democratization.

What do these criteria tell us about the five types of politics that I have used to periodize British political development? The premises of Old Tory political behavior were still essentially medieval, reflecting the ancient faith of "the Great Chain of Being." Actually, under the influence of a powerful monarch and newly centralized government, law-making was practiced on a far wider scale than before, yet was still restricted in theory by the notion of a fixed and unchanging order of man and nature and in fact by conscious imitation of a hierarchic and corporatist past. The modernism of nineteenth- century politics stands out in sharp contrast. Laisser-faire itself expressed a growing systematic knowledge of society and was consciously adopted as a public policy that would promote economic development. In political thought, the source of legitimacy was now conceived as human will-for the Liberals, the will of rational, independent men; for the Radicals, the will of all the people.

Our focus on modernization makes the Old Whig model a fascinating example of transitional politics. Its basic orientation is modern, for although much of the Old Tory ideal of hierarchy and corporatism is retained, the premises have shifted radically, permitting far greater scope for human contrivance and changing circumstance. Incidentally, the significance of this period in British development is suggested by a comparative look at

need by a mobilization of consent that involves little or no real accommoda- tion of the structure of power. Moreover, and more generally, the "needs" of systems, as of individuals, simply may go unfulfilled. Yet the fact that such situational pressures do arise throws light on an important connection between rationalization and participation, two of the major features com- monly ascribed to the modern polity.

As a matter of historical fact, we do find that the development of public policy under the influence of growing knowledge has been associated with the extension of democracy, or its authoritarian substitute. No doubt the forces promoting each of these developments are in many respects inde- pendent of one another. Yet there are strong ties that tend to make them develop together. Rationalization and participation can in the short run come into conflict, as is shown by the familiar problem of reconciling democracy and planning. Yet as the analysis of this problem also shows, in the long run the two go together. The kind of flexible and constantly chang- ing control typically exercised by modern polities cannot rest on rigid norms and unthinking custom, but must enlist the active response and understanding of affected groups. Certainly, in considering the possible future developments of a political system, as we shall do at a later point of this article, we should look for those changes in public policy that may re- quire an adjustment of the structure of power in favor of relevant groups.

IV Rationalism and voluntarism characterize the modern spirit and generally pervade attitude and behavior so far as a society is modern. In politics, they suggest a broad but distinctive class of systems, defining the basic orienta- tions that legitimize and institutionalize processes of rationalization and democratization.

What do these criteria tell us about the five types of politics that I have used to periodize British political development? The premises of Old Tory political behavior were still essentially medieval, reflecting the ancient faith of "the Great Chain of Being." Actually, under the influence of a powerful monarch and newly centralized government, law-making was practiced on a far wider scale than before, yet was still restricted in theory by the notion of a fixed and unchanging order of man and nature and in fact by conscious imitation of a hierarchic and corporatist past. The modernism of nineteenth- century politics stands out in sharp contrast. Laisser-faire itself expressed a growing systematic knowledge of society and was consciously adopted as a public policy that would promote economic development. In political thought, the source of legitimacy was now conceived as human will-for the Liberals, the will of rational, independent men; for the Radicals, the will of all the people.

Our focus on modernization makes the Old Whig model a fascinating example of transitional politics. Its basic orientation is modern, for although much of the Old Tory ideal of hierarchy and corporatism is retained, the premises have shifted radically, permitting far greater scope for human contrivance and changing circumstance. Incidentally, the significance of this period in British development is suggested by a comparative look at

23 23

Page 6: Comparative Method and British Politics

Comparative Politics October 1968 Comparative Politics October 1968

France, which moved from its Old Tory period directly to Liberal and Radical regimes, with a resulting shock from which it has not yet fully recovered.

On the whole, the five types of politics show a trend toward greater modernization. May we say then that the Collectivist model is the most modern? In the British case this could be argued. The public policy of the welfare state and managed economy certainly reflects the broadest and deepest power of social control. In conception the Collectivist model is more democratic than the others since it provides not only for parliamentary but also for functional representation. Moreover, one could also reasonably contend that in the British context Radical democracy could never achieve its object until it was transformed by the class politics of the Collectivist phase.

Yet it must not be assumed that further political development in Britain must continue this trend. The developing needs of the pattern of policy may reduce as well as enhance the importance of groups, even conceivably eliminating some from effective participation. In relation to the economy, it has been possible to conceive of the withering away of the rentier; similarly, important political classes can lose their relevance to policy and decline. Such changes make us consider among the possibilities not only further democratization, but also a "rehierarchization."9

Above all, even though these conceptions are useful for comparative analysis, we must not infer from them that the British succession will be followed in other countries. That the British polity went through an indi- vidualist phase, for instance, is no reason to believe that other countries will or must go through a similar phase. Indeed, countries that modernize later can be expected to use their knowledge of what happened elsewhere in order to guide or, if they choose, to short-circuit some phase. Our growing knowledge of modernization is itself an example of the rationalization process and shows how it may give us greater control over political develop- ment.

Modernization theory helps us pick out and identify important trends. It is, however, an aid not only to description, but also to explanation, sug- gesting ways to get at the dynamics of the process and the causes of change. In the present study, rationalism, as an orientation that institutionalizes the pursuit of knowledge and its application to problems of control, is a princi- pal source of this dynamism. We can get a closer look at some of the com- plexities of this process if we turn now to the tendencies of Collectivist politics.

V In constructing a model of Collectivist politics, I made a two-fold use of theory. One task was to identify the basic orientations of political actors. In doing this I exploited the resources of the history of political thought, vulgarized so as to throw light on operative ideals. British socialist thought helps one get a grasp of the premises of action of the Labour party, espe-

France, which moved from its Old Tory period directly to Liberal and Radical regimes, with a resulting shock from which it has not yet fully recovered.

On the whole, the five types of politics show a trend toward greater modernization. May we say then that the Collectivist model is the most modern? In the British case this could be argued. The public policy of the welfare state and managed economy certainly reflects the broadest and deepest power of social control. In conception the Collectivist model is more democratic than the others since it provides not only for parliamentary but also for functional representation. Moreover, one could also reasonably contend that in the British context Radical democracy could never achieve its object until it was transformed by the class politics of the Collectivist phase.

Yet it must not be assumed that further political development in Britain must continue this trend. The developing needs of the pattern of policy may reduce as well as enhance the importance of groups, even conceivably eliminating some from effective participation. In relation to the economy, it has been possible to conceive of the withering away of the rentier; similarly, important political classes can lose their relevance to policy and decline. Such changes make us consider among the possibilities not only further democratization, but also a "rehierarchization."9

Above all, even though these conceptions are useful for comparative analysis, we must not infer from them that the British succession will be followed in other countries. That the British polity went through an indi- vidualist phase, for instance, is no reason to believe that other countries will or must go through a similar phase. Indeed, countries that modernize later can be expected to use their knowledge of what happened elsewhere in order to guide or, if they choose, to short-circuit some phase. Our growing knowledge of modernization is itself an example of the rationalization process and shows how it may give us greater control over political develop- ment.

Modernization theory helps us pick out and identify important trends. It is, however, an aid not only to description, but also to explanation, sug- gesting ways to get at the dynamics of the process and the causes of change. In the present study, rationalism, as an orientation that institutionalizes the pursuit of knowledge and its application to problems of control, is a princi- pal source of this dynamism. We can get a closer look at some of the com- plexities of this process if we turn now to the tendencies of Collectivist politics.

V In constructing a model of Collectivist politics, I made a two-fold use of theory. One task was to identify the basic orientations of political actors. In doing this I exploited the resources of the history of political thought, vulgarized so as to throw light on operative ideals. British socialist thought helps one get a grasp of the premises of action of the Labour party, espe-

9 The expression of a Tory acquaintance of mine. 9 The expression of a Tory acquaintance of mine.

24 24

Page 7: Comparative Method and British Politics

Samuel H. Beer Samuel H. Beer

cially during the party's "Socialist Generation," which ran roughly from 1918 through 1945. Tory thought, although, as one would expect, more dif- fuse and less formalized in utterance, brings out the orientations of the central current of sentiment and behavior among Conservatives.

In both cases, these orientations, while suffused with the rationalist and voluntarist ethos of modernity, also embody other values, especially con- ceptions of class, which exhibit powerful strands of premodern thought and feeling. These values center on class, yet they conceive its functions quite differently, the Socialist regarding class as creating a horizontal division in society, while the Tory looks on it as a form of vertical integration. In spite of such vitally important differences, however, both sets of class values legitimize a complex set of more particular attitudes supporting party government and functional representation. In the British political community, this general acceptance of party government and functional representation leads to massive political concentration-on the one hand the mass party and on the other hand what we might call the mass pressure groups, meaning by this especially the great producers' organizations of the industrial economy, such as trade unions and trade associations.

The use of theory in the analysis above may be thought of as a kind of political anthropology. Like the cultural anthropologist, we can look for the orientations or premises of action that support, perhaps through intervening levels of thought and feeling, a set of particular attitudes displayed in com- plex, concrete behavior. Although we are dealing with the intentional and purposive life of a community, the findings have explanatory value, insofar as they locate motivational bases on which behavior depends.

The conceptions of party government and functional representation greatly help in identifying and describing the broad outlines of British politics in the twentieth century and in setting off certain of its distinctive features from those of the liberal and individualist nineteenth century. As we examine the political behavior of this more recent time, however, we find patterns of behavior that are not included in this description. We find uniformities derived from the structures and patterns legitimized by the operative ideals of Collectivist politics, but not intended by them. The model of party government and functional representation, in other words, has not only manifest functions, but also latent functions.

In identifying these latent functions and in tracing their origin and inter- connection, organization theory proves useful. Economists in their study of economic concentration have shown how the size of the large corporation affects both its internal structure and its external relations. These conse- quences of economic concentration can be summarized under four headings, two relating to internal effects and two relating to external effects: man- agerialism, bureaucracy, bargaining, and what Galbraith has called "de- pendence effect."10

Abstracting from the economic context, I found this analysis of the tendencies of large-scale organization highly suggestive when applied to political formations. While not exactly analogous, this pattern of relations in the economic field helped me find similar consequences resulting from

cially during the party's "Socialist Generation," which ran roughly from 1918 through 1945. Tory thought, although, as one would expect, more dif- fuse and less formalized in utterance, brings out the orientations of the central current of sentiment and behavior among Conservatives.

In both cases, these orientations, while suffused with the rationalist and voluntarist ethos of modernity, also embody other values, especially con- ceptions of class, which exhibit powerful strands of premodern thought and feeling. These values center on class, yet they conceive its functions quite differently, the Socialist regarding class as creating a horizontal division in society, while the Tory looks on it as a form of vertical integration. In spite of such vitally important differences, however, both sets of class values legitimize a complex set of more particular attitudes supporting party government and functional representation. In the British political community, this general acceptance of party government and functional representation leads to massive political concentration-on the one hand the mass party and on the other hand what we might call the mass pressure groups, meaning by this especially the great producers' organizations of the industrial economy, such as trade unions and trade associations.

The use of theory in the analysis above may be thought of as a kind of political anthropology. Like the cultural anthropologist, we can look for the orientations or premises of action that support, perhaps through intervening levels of thought and feeling, a set of particular attitudes displayed in com- plex, concrete behavior. Although we are dealing with the intentional and purposive life of a community, the findings have explanatory value, insofar as they locate motivational bases on which behavior depends.

The conceptions of party government and functional representation greatly help in identifying and describing the broad outlines of British politics in the twentieth century and in setting off certain of its distinctive features from those of the liberal and individualist nineteenth century. As we examine the political behavior of this more recent time, however, we find patterns of behavior that are not included in this description. We find uniformities derived from the structures and patterns legitimized by the operative ideals of Collectivist politics, but not intended by them. The model of party government and functional representation, in other words, has not only manifest functions, but also latent functions.

In identifying these latent functions and in tracing their origin and inter- connection, organization theory proves useful. Economists in their study of economic concentration have shown how the size of the large corporation affects both its internal structure and its external relations. These conse- quences of economic concentration can be summarized under four headings, two relating to internal effects and two relating to external effects: man- agerialism, bureaucracy, bargaining, and what Galbraith has called "de- pendence effect."10

Abstracting from the economic context, I found this analysis of the tendencies of large-scale organization highly suggestive when applied to political formations. While not exactly analogous, this pattern of relations in the economic field helped me find similar consequences resulting from

10 J, K. Galbraith, The Affluent Society (Boston, 1958), p. 158. 10 J, K. Galbraith, The Affluent Society (Boston, 1958), p. 158.

25 25

Page 8: Comparative Method and British Politics

Comparative Politics October 1968 Comparative Politics October 1968

concentration in parties and pressure groups and so to see the meaning and interconnection of forms of behavior that had previously seemed unrelated.

The distinctive intellectual contribution of sociology, Robert Merton has said, is to be found in the study of unintended consequences.1' In this sense this analysis of the "laws" of political concentration, i.e., of the latent functions of certain purposive structures, can be thought of as a kind of political sociology.

VI With the hunches and hypotheses suggested by these elements of organiza- tion theory, we can detect and order the unanticipated consequences set in train by the pattern of party government and functional representation. As has often been observed, the mass party, even if its inspiration is highly democratic, tends to separate the leadership from the rank and file and to accumulate influence in their hands. The conventions of British cabinet government also work in this direction. But it is well to see that such tendencies toward managerialism also inhere in other large formations such as workers' and employers' organizations as well as political parties.

A major source of managerialism is the specialized and indeed profes- sional skills that leaders must develop and exercise if they are to hold their organizations together and carry out their purposes. Organizational neces- sities of this kind help us explain the decline of the Labour party conference and of the party's extraparliamentary organization from the role given it in the party's image of itself and actually carried out in the earlier phases of its history. Such elitist tendencies cause little strain among Tories, whose ancient sociology accepts hierarchy as a law of orderly life. Insofar, how- ever, as political managers win their status by achievement and by demon- strated capacities of expertise or professional knowledge, there is as sharp a clash of managerialism with Tory as with Socialist values.

Size and complexity in political formations as in other organizations also tend to promote bureaucracy or, to use the more general term, formalization. Sidney Webb's neat constitution of 1918, as elaborated and amended over the years, illustrates the point. On the Conservative side, the party and its leaders have shown themselves remarkably forward in the use of formal organization from the days of Disraeli through the era of Woolton. No doubt, however, there is greater reluctance than among Socialists to formalize the framework of vital decisions and authoritative positions, as shown by the long delay in establishing an explicit set of rules for choice of a party leader.

"Managerial bureaucracy" refers to the effects of concentration on in- ternal structures. Its effects on external relations are twofold. The operative ideals of functional representation legitimize and even require consultation between government and producers' groups. The degree of concentration achieved by many of these groups in their respective fields means, however, that consultation almost inevitably becomes negotiation and, indeed, a kind

concentration in parties and pressure groups and so to see the meaning and interconnection of forms of behavior that had previously seemed unrelated.

The distinctive intellectual contribution of sociology, Robert Merton has said, is to be found in the study of unintended consequences.1' In this sense this analysis of the "laws" of political concentration, i.e., of the latent functions of certain purposive structures, can be thought of as a kind of political sociology.

VI With the hunches and hypotheses suggested by these elements of organiza- tion theory, we can detect and order the unanticipated consequences set in train by the pattern of party government and functional representation. As has often been observed, the mass party, even if its inspiration is highly democratic, tends to separate the leadership from the rank and file and to accumulate influence in their hands. The conventions of British cabinet government also work in this direction. But it is well to see that such tendencies toward managerialism also inhere in other large formations such as workers' and employers' organizations as well as political parties.

A major source of managerialism is the specialized and indeed profes- sional skills that leaders must develop and exercise if they are to hold their organizations together and carry out their purposes. Organizational neces- sities of this kind help us explain the decline of the Labour party conference and of the party's extraparliamentary organization from the role given it in the party's image of itself and actually carried out in the earlier phases of its history. Such elitist tendencies cause little strain among Tories, whose ancient sociology accepts hierarchy as a law of orderly life. Insofar, how- ever, as political managers win their status by achievement and by demon- strated capacities of expertise or professional knowledge, there is as sharp a clash of managerialism with Tory as with Socialist values.

Size and complexity in political formations as in other organizations also tend to promote bureaucracy or, to use the more general term, formalization. Sidney Webb's neat constitution of 1918, as elaborated and amended over the years, illustrates the point. On the Conservative side, the party and its leaders have shown themselves remarkably forward in the use of formal organization from the days of Disraeli through the era of Woolton. No doubt, however, there is greater reluctance than among Socialists to formalize the framework of vital decisions and authoritative positions, as shown by the long delay in establishing an explicit set of rules for choice of a party leader.

"Managerial bureaucracy" refers to the effects of concentration on in- ternal structures. Its effects on external relations are twofold. The operative ideals of functional representation legitimize and even require consultation between government and producers' groups. The degree of concentration achieved by many of these groups in their respective fields means, however, that consultation almost inevitably becomes negotiation and, indeed, a kind

11 Robert K. Merton, Social Theory and Social Structure, (Glencoe, 1949), Ch. 1, "Manifest and Latent Functions," p. 66.

11 Robert K. Merton, Social Theory and Social Structure, (Glencoe, 1949), Ch. 1, "Manifest and Latent Functions," p. 66.

26 26

Page 9: Comparative Method and British Politics

Samuel H. Beer Samuel H. Beer

of collective bargaining. The annual price review between the government and the National Farmers Union is a good example. Of even more im- portance are the repeated efforts of governments to achieve agreement with trade unions and trade associations on an incomes policy from which, in- deed, when the efforts are successful, a kind of "extraparliamentary legisla- tion" results.

When we look at the relations of the parties and the electorate, however, the appropriate term is "bidding" rather than "bargaining." These two fairly evenly matched parties make an intense effort to identify and attract every vote that might float. This leads to a great stress on group appeals. One can think of these voters as consumer groups, the beneficiaries or prospective beneficiaries of the welfare state. "The voter," as Lord Woolton once said, "is also the consumer." One result of this process of bidding is to enhance the role of the usually poorly organized consumer groups in the electoral and governmental process. At the same time there is a certain "dependence effect" as political parties shape the often inchoate wishes of these electors.

One further tendency of political concentration should also be mentioned because of its bearing on a major development of recent years. In Britain as in most other Western countries during the postwar period, the intensity of political conflict significantly, and rather unexpectedly, diminished, lead- ing to much discussion of "the decline of ideology" and "consensus politics." Various reasons will be considered at a later point. Here it may be pointed out how this tendency is promoted by the objective political conditions under which the two mass parties must operate. Each party when seeking power must bid for the votes of many of the same consumers' groups and when in power must bargain with much the same set of producers' groups. These are the hard realities of getting elected and of governing. Together they have worked to promote a convergence of party program, greatly les- sening the ideological distance between Socialist and Conservative. As ideological contours have faded a new group politics has appeared as a more and more prominent feature of the political scene.

VII Such in brief are the latent functions of the model of party government and functional representation. The two major situational factors from which they flow are a high level of political concentration and a wide scope of government intervention. It is also important that there are two major parties and that they have been fairly evenly matched in electoral strength. The propositions embodied in this analysis are not merely descriptive, but also explanatory. If we do not project too much onto the term, we can think of them as "laws" of political concentration. They are continuous with much well-established organization theory and go on to develop certain hypothe- ses in a form that makes them testable in the context of other political systems.

In the previous analysis, latent function is in each instance in conflict with operative ideal. The tension and strain that result have a psychological aspect that can be readily illustrated. One example is the long agony of the Labour party in the fifties when it was torn by the conflict between its

of collective bargaining. The annual price review between the government and the National Farmers Union is a good example. Of even more im- portance are the repeated efforts of governments to achieve agreement with trade unions and trade associations on an incomes policy from which, in- deed, when the efforts are successful, a kind of "extraparliamentary legisla- tion" results.

When we look at the relations of the parties and the electorate, however, the appropriate term is "bidding" rather than "bargaining." These two fairly evenly matched parties make an intense effort to identify and attract every vote that might float. This leads to a great stress on group appeals. One can think of these voters as consumer groups, the beneficiaries or prospective beneficiaries of the welfare state. "The voter," as Lord Woolton once said, "is also the consumer." One result of this process of bidding is to enhance the role of the usually poorly organized consumer groups in the electoral and governmental process. At the same time there is a certain "dependence effect" as political parties shape the often inchoate wishes of these electors.

One further tendency of political concentration should also be mentioned because of its bearing on a major development of recent years. In Britain as in most other Western countries during the postwar period, the intensity of political conflict significantly, and rather unexpectedly, diminished, lead- ing to much discussion of "the decline of ideology" and "consensus politics." Various reasons will be considered at a later point. Here it may be pointed out how this tendency is promoted by the objective political conditions under which the two mass parties must operate. Each party when seeking power must bid for the votes of many of the same consumers' groups and when in power must bargain with much the same set of producers' groups. These are the hard realities of getting elected and of governing. Together they have worked to promote a convergence of party program, greatly les- sening the ideological distance between Socialist and Conservative. As ideological contours have faded a new group politics has appeared as a more and more prominent feature of the political scene.

VII Such in brief are the latent functions of the model of party government and functional representation. The two major situational factors from which they flow are a high level of political concentration and a wide scope of government intervention. It is also important that there are two major parties and that they have been fairly evenly matched in electoral strength. The propositions embodied in this analysis are not merely descriptive, but also explanatory. If we do not project too much onto the term, we can think of them as "laws" of political concentration. They are continuous with much well-established organization theory and go on to develop certain hypothe- ses in a form that makes them testable in the context of other political systems.

In the previous analysis, latent function is in each instance in conflict with operative ideal. The tension and strain that result have a psychological aspect that can be readily illustrated. One example is the long agony of the Labour party in the fifties when it was torn by the conflict between its

27 27

Page 10: Comparative Method and British Politics

Comparative Politics October 1968 Comparative Politics October 1968

deeply felt democratic and socialist myth and the hard realities of political survival. Nor is the strain of conflict of this sort embodied simply in fac- tional conflict. Perhaps even more significant is its impact on individuals, dividing them against themselves, as, for instance, in the case of a Tory leader who wins his position by achievement, yet attempts to adapt to the surviving conceptions of hierarchic class feeling among his fellows. Voters in the mass may also be affected, responding with unease and confusion to the fact that the great political organizations do not merely respond to the public will, but in some degree manufacture it.

These psychological aspects have a bearing on political development and would be worth exploring further. Here our concern is with the more direct tendencies to change proceeding from the Collectivist model. The unantici- pated consequences that we have considered are themselves departures in behavior from an intended pattern, which for a longer or shorter period was established. Yet, as this brief sketch suggests, latent functions may in an important sense work to maintain the structure or other unit from which they proceed, even though they are in conflict with its purpose. The Labour party, for instance, could hardly have survived if it had not modified its original practice to allow for far stronger leadership. Latent functions may support even while they transform a structure.

VIII Having looked at the tendencies of the Collectivist model as exhibited gen- erally in the postwar period, we may now consider what has been happening in the sixties and then go on to examine the possibilities of the future. In this discussion I want even more explicitly to make the concept of rationali- zation the focus of inquiry. This concept is especially relevant to recent developments because of the explosion of scientific knowledge with its ramifying impact throughout society. One of the most obvious effects is on the economy where, as we are continually told, the scientific revolution has become the principal dynamic force, bringing about a professionalization of the mode of production, distribution, and exchange. Among other things, it continually reduces the number of manual workers and increases the white-collar class equipped with technical and professional training, a change in occupational structure that cannot help but have important effects upon parties and politics.

Moreover, the scientific revolution affects the polity not only indirectly through economic development, but also directly as our knowledge of so- ciety itself responds to the scientific impulse. Thus, for instance, not only in government departments, but also in the leading echelons of parties and pressure groups there is occurring a professionalization of reform as the social sciences are applied to problems of public policy. Surely the most weighty instance of the way greater knowledge can affect politics is the impact of Keynesian economics on the conflict of parties. Throughout the West and well before the era of affluence, this revolution in ideas dissolved the rigid doctrines of prewar "capitalism" and "socialism," bringing old combatants into a wide area of agreement, as the emergence of "Butskell- ism" revealed to slightly astonished Britons in the early 1950's. In this way,

deeply felt democratic and socialist myth and the hard realities of political survival. Nor is the strain of conflict of this sort embodied simply in fac- tional conflict. Perhaps even more significant is its impact on individuals, dividing them against themselves, as, for instance, in the case of a Tory leader who wins his position by achievement, yet attempts to adapt to the surviving conceptions of hierarchic class feeling among his fellows. Voters in the mass may also be affected, responding with unease and confusion to the fact that the great political organizations do not merely respond to the public will, but in some degree manufacture it.

These psychological aspects have a bearing on political development and would be worth exploring further. Here our concern is with the more direct tendencies to change proceeding from the Collectivist model. The unantici- pated consequences that we have considered are themselves departures in behavior from an intended pattern, which for a longer or shorter period was established. Yet, as this brief sketch suggests, latent functions may in an important sense work to maintain the structure or other unit from which they proceed, even though they are in conflict with its purpose. The Labour party, for instance, could hardly have survived if it had not modified its original practice to allow for far stronger leadership. Latent functions may support even while they transform a structure.

VIII Having looked at the tendencies of the Collectivist model as exhibited gen- erally in the postwar period, we may now consider what has been happening in the sixties and then go on to examine the possibilities of the future. In this discussion I want even more explicitly to make the concept of rationali- zation the focus of inquiry. This concept is especially relevant to recent developments because of the explosion of scientific knowledge with its ramifying impact throughout society. One of the most obvious effects is on the economy where, as we are continually told, the scientific revolution has become the principal dynamic force, bringing about a professionalization of the mode of production, distribution, and exchange. Among other things, it continually reduces the number of manual workers and increases the white-collar class equipped with technical and professional training, a change in occupational structure that cannot help but have important effects upon parties and politics.

Moreover, the scientific revolution affects the polity not only indirectly through economic development, but also directly as our knowledge of so- ciety itself responds to the scientific impulse. Thus, for instance, not only in government departments, but also in the leading echelons of parties and pressure groups there is occurring a professionalization of reform as the social sciences are applied to problems of public policy. Surely the most weighty instance of the way greater knowledge can affect politics is the impact of Keynesian economics on the conflict of parties. Throughout the West and well before the era of affluence, this revolution in ideas dissolved the rigid doctrines of prewar "capitalism" and "socialism," bringing old combatants into a wide area of agreement, as the emergence of "Butskell- ism" revealed to slightly astonished Britons in the early 1950's. In this way,

28 28

Page 11: Comparative Method and British Politics

Samuel H. Beer Samuel H. Beer

reason has had as much to do with reducing the class struggle as any ma- terial force.

In the economic sphere the dominance of science and applied technology is a major characteristic of the "postindustrial" society. It should not be surprising if its impact were also wide and deep enough to produce a "post- collectivist" politics.

IX It will be convenient to consider the changes of the sixties under the two headings of party government and functional representation.

If we ask whether there has been a further lessening of the ideological distance between the two parties, the answer is clearly Yes. The last major Labour program of the fifties, The Future Labour Offers You, which was put out in 1958, showed how far group politics had qualified party politics. The harsh defeats suffered by Hugh Gaitskell when he tried in 1959-1960 to alter Clause IV, the ancient pledge of universal public ownership, revealed great strength on the part of the old myth. Yet by the first years of-iron- ically-Harold Wilson's leadership, revisionism had clearly carried the day, and the old rhetoric of nationalization had just about vanished from party and trade-union oratory.

On the Conservative side there had been at least an equivalent movement toward their opponents. Although the Conservatives showed after returning to power in 1951 that they had accepted not only the welfare state, but also the managed economy, they still rejected planning. Under Macmillan, how- ever, they gave up their brief flirtation with "neoliberalism" and created the National Economic Development Council, establishing what they hoped would be a British version of French planification. After Labour took office in 1964, the two parties came to look even more alike. Like the Conserva- tives in the late 1950's who had been obliged to resort to deflation in order to protect the pound, Labour not only accepted that obligation, but finally resorted to the deliberate creation of unemployment in attempting to honor it. A left wing among backbenchers and in the party organization continued to protest and resist. Yet a comparison with the "Keep Left" group in the days of Attlee's government shows how vastly the Left had declined in weight, influence, and ideas.

If class ideologies have declined, class politics, on the other hand, con- tinues to flourish mightily. By class politics I mean primarily class voting, although I also include other partisan behavior such as party membership. If we take manual and nonmanual occupations as identifying respectively the working class and the middle class and then ask how each of these two groups has divided its support between the two main parties since the war, we find that in spite of party convergence, affluence, and like developments, the index of class voting has remained remarkably high and stable over the years.12 In the elections of both 1964 and 1966 there were slight shifts in

12 See Robert R. Alford, Party and Society (Chicago, 1963), p. 348; and Alford, "Class Voting in the Anglo-American Political Systems," in Seymour Martin Lipset and Stein Rokkan, eds. Party Systems and Voter Alignments (New York, 1967), esp. p. 85 and p. 93, n. 51.

reason has had as much to do with reducing the class struggle as any ma- terial force.

In the economic sphere the dominance of science and applied technology is a major characteristic of the "postindustrial" society. It should not be surprising if its impact were also wide and deep enough to produce a "post- collectivist" politics.

IX It will be convenient to consider the changes of the sixties under the two headings of party government and functional representation.

If we ask whether there has been a further lessening of the ideological distance between the two parties, the answer is clearly Yes. The last major Labour program of the fifties, The Future Labour Offers You, which was put out in 1958, showed how far group politics had qualified party politics. The harsh defeats suffered by Hugh Gaitskell when he tried in 1959-1960 to alter Clause IV, the ancient pledge of universal public ownership, revealed great strength on the part of the old myth. Yet by the first years of-iron- ically-Harold Wilson's leadership, revisionism had clearly carried the day, and the old rhetoric of nationalization had just about vanished from party and trade-union oratory.

On the Conservative side there had been at least an equivalent movement toward their opponents. Although the Conservatives showed after returning to power in 1951 that they had accepted not only the welfare state, but also the managed economy, they still rejected planning. Under Macmillan, how- ever, they gave up their brief flirtation with "neoliberalism" and created the National Economic Development Council, establishing what they hoped would be a British version of French planification. After Labour took office in 1964, the two parties came to look even more alike. Like the Conserva- tives in the late 1950's who had been obliged to resort to deflation in order to protect the pound, Labour not only accepted that obligation, but finally resorted to the deliberate creation of unemployment in attempting to honor it. A left wing among backbenchers and in the party organization continued to protest and resist. Yet a comparison with the "Keep Left" group in the days of Attlee's government shows how vastly the Left had declined in weight, influence, and ideas.

If class ideologies have declined, class politics, on the other hand, con- tinues to flourish mightily. By class politics I mean primarily class voting, although I also include other partisan behavior such as party membership. If we take manual and nonmanual occupations as identifying respectively the working class and the middle class and then ask how each of these two groups has divided its support between the two main parties since the war, we find that in spite of party convergence, affluence, and like developments, the index of class voting has remained remarkably high and stable over the years.12 In the elections of both 1964 and 1966 there were slight shifts in

12 See Robert R. Alford, Party and Society (Chicago, 1963), p. 348; and Alford, "Class Voting in the Anglo-American Political Systems," in Seymour Martin Lipset and Stein Rokkan, eds. Party Systems and Voter Alignments (New York, 1967), esp. p. 85 and p. 93, n. 51.

29 29

Page 12: Comparative Method and British Politics

Comparative Politics October 1968 Comparative Politics October 1968

middle-class strata to Labour, with the result that "the class polarisation of the British electorate was perhaps fractionally reduced."'13 A rather similar but more substantial shift also was revealed among Labour MP's, candi- dates elected in 1965-1966 showing a striking increase in professional oc- cupations and university background.

Perhaps the most important and certainly not the least puzzling develop- ments relate to party membership.14 We recognize, of course, that only a small fraction of the millions reported by each party are in fact active party workers. Still these millions represent a source of great financial support and a recruiting ground for the scores of thousands of activists. Although the Conservatives do not keep a very exact account, their membership fell from about 2.8 million to 2.3 million between the early fifties and early sixties. On the Labour side, individual membership reached a peak in 1953 of about one million after some years of steady growth. From 1953 to 1966, however, the figure dropped by almost 25 percent. Trade-union member- ship in the party reached its peak in 1956, also after a long and steady climb. In the following ten years, although the trade-union total fell off by only 2 percent, it failed to keep pace with the work force, which grew by some 7 percent. The Labour party, far from embracing ever larger circles of the working class, suffered not merely a stop but an absolute decline.

As for causes of this decline, the most plausible is the change in occupa- tional structure. In manufacturing alone, for instance, between 1954 and 1964, the percent of administrative, technical, and clerical workers rose from 18.4 to 23.1. The effect on membership in the unions themselves has been marked. Although white-collar workers are being unionized, they do not make up for losses in the declining occupations, such as mining, ship- building, and textiles, and between 1953 and 1963, although the total num- ber of employees went up 9 percent, trade-union membership rose only 4 percent.

Such changes in occupational structure surely must affect political be- havior. Yet the relationship is not simple. For one thing, this occupational shift has been going on for a long time. From 1931 to 1951, for instance, manual wage-earners declined as a percent of the population from 70.3 to 64.2, while white-collar employees rose from 23.0 percent to 30.9 percent. Yet it was in the mid-fifties that the Labour party reached the peak of its individual and trade-union membership. Moreover, the fact that the Con- servative party has also lost membership suggests that the relevant condi- tion must affect both parties.

The decline of ideological distance between the parties could well be an influence. The relationship is familiar: a party reaches out to attract new voters, but in the process waters down the doctrine that had previously attracted new recruits. Yet this formulation implies a diminution of intensity of support among partisans which does not square easily with the fact that per capita financial contribution from the local parties to the national La- bour party has almost doubled during the period of declining membership.

13 D. E. Butler and Anthony King, The British General Election of 1966 (New York, 1966), p. 265.

14 For a searching discussion, see Leon Epstein, Political Parties in Western De- mocracies (New York, 1967), esp. Ch. 4, "The Socialist Working-Class Party."

middle-class strata to Labour, with the result that "the class polarisation of the British electorate was perhaps fractionally reduced."'13 A rather similar but more substantial shift also was revealed among Labour MP's, candi- dates elected in 1965-1966 showing a striking increase in professional oc- cupations and university background.

Perhaps the most important and certainly not the least puzzling develop- ments relate to party membership.14 We recognize, of course, that only a small fraction of the millions reported by each party are in fact active party workers. Still these millions represent a source of great financial support and a recruiting ground for the scores of thousands of activists. Although the Conservatives do not keep a very exact account, their membership fell from about 2.8 million to 2.3 million between the early fifties and early sixties. On the Labour side, individual membership reached a peak in 1953 of about one million after some years of steady growth. From 1953 to 1966, however, the figure dropped by almost 25 percent. Trade-union member- ship in the party reached its peak in 1956, also after a long and steady climb. In the following ten years, although the trade-union total fell off by only 2 percent, it failed to keep pace with the work force, which grew by some 7 percent. The Labour party, far from embracing ever larger circles of the working class, suffered not merely a stop but an absolute decline.

As for causes of this decline, the most plausible is the change in occupa- tional structure. In manufacturing alone, for instance, between 1954 and 1964, the percent of administrative, technical, and clerical workers rose from 18.4 to 23.1. The effect on membership in the unions themselves has been marked. Although white-collar workers are being unionized, they do not make up for losses in the declining occupations, such as mining, ship- building, and textiles, and between 1953 and 1963, although the total num- ber of employees went up 9 percent, trade-union membership rose only 4 percent.

Such changes in occupational structure surely must affect political be- havior. Yet the relationship is not simple. For one thing, this occupational shift has been going on for a long time. From 1931 to 1951, for instance, manual wage-earners declined as a percent of the population from 70.3 to 64.2, while white-collar employees rose from 23.0 percent to 30.9 percent. Yet it was in the mid-fifties that the Labour party reached the peak of its individual and trade-union membership. Moreover, the fact that the Con- servative party has also lost membership suggests that the relevant condi- tion must affect both parties.

The decline of ideological distance between the parties could well be an influence. The relationship is familiar: a party reaches out to attract new voters, but in the process waters down the doctrine that had previously attracted new recruits. Yet this formulation implies a diminution of intensity of support among partisans which does not square easily with the fact that per capita financial contribution from the local parties to the national La- bour party has almost doubled during the period of declining membership.

13 D. E. Butler and Anthony King, The British General Election of 1966 (New York, 1966), p. 265.

14 For a searching discussion, see Leon Epstein, Political Parties in Western De- mocracies (New York, 1967), esp. Ch. 4, "The Socialist Working-Class Party."

30 30

Page 13: Comparative Method and British Politics

Samuel H. Beer Samuel H. Beer

Another portentous innovation of the sixties surely needs to be consid- ered. This is the parties' increasing use of new communications techniques, especially survey research and advertising and television. In both parties there was strong initial resistance. On the Conservative side the ideal of Tory statesmanship suggests that the role of the governing class is to govern and then to ask the approval of the people, on whose favorable judgment it can, in the long run, count. On the Labour side the notion of conference as the authentic voice of the working class is no more favorable to the use of survey research to identify the wishes of voters. The effectiveness of the new techniques in winning elections, however, finally broke through these ob- stacles. Fears of their slipping popularity led the Conservatives to take the first step in 1959, even though they were at that time in office. Labour followed suit in 1964, being greatly influenced by the scientific findings of Dr. Mark Abrams and the leadership of Hugh Gaitskell. Indeed this whole change in tactics was part of the "revisionist" triumph over the ideologues. In 1966 both parties continued their efforts, the Conservatives in their at- tempt to locate "target voters" making a far more ambitious use of survey research than had ever been made before.

For all the remaining resistances of traditionalism, there can be no doubt that this revolution in electoral methods and the resulting professionaliza- tion of vote-getting will go forward. The conventional wisdom of the party leader and agent about the voter appeal of pensions, housing, education, and other elements in the bidding process is now refined and made far more exact by survey research, while the attempt to win the support of the rele- vant groups is heightened by an increasingly sophisticated use of advertis- ing and television.

The effects of this major step in rationalization are not likely to be con- fined to elections, and can hardly help affecting the power structures of the two parties. There is still a role for the local activists, yet as a means of as- certaining and influencing the public will they are overshadowed by the new techniques. In the Labour party, the effect will surely be to reduce still further the role of conference in policy-making. With regard to the positions of the two parties, the new and more effective processes of bidding may very well draw them even closer together. Tory statesmanship itself cannot wholly resist the effect of hard evidence of the voters' desires. In 1966, for example, when survey research showed that the voters preferred Labour's policy of comprehensive education to the Conservative stand, statesmanship at least compromised by omitting the mention of education from the mani- festo. No doubt the immensely increased demands for money which the new techniques entail also could affect power structure. In 1964, for exam- ple, Labour trebled its expenditures on its preelection campaign as com- pared with 1959. It is worth mentioning that a special committee has recently proposed that the Labour party adopt a system of graduated dues for its individual members, varying with their incomes.

x In revising his standard work on British pressure groups in 1965, Professor Finer wrote: "... . The most striking impression I have received is the stabil- ity and durability of the system it describes.... Broadly speaking, the same

Another portentous innovation of the sixties surely needs to be consid- ered. This is the parties' increasing use of new communications techniques, especially survey research and advertising and television. In both parties there was strong initial resistance. On the Conservative side the ideal of Tory statesmanship suggests that the role of the governing class is to govern and then to ask the approval of the people, on whose favorable judgment it can, in the long run, count. On the Labour side the notion of conference as the authentic voice of the working class is no more favorable to the use of survey research to identify the wishes of voters. The effectiveness of the new techniques in winning elections, however, finally broke through these ob- stacles. Fears of their slipping popularity led the Conservatives to take the first step in 1959, even though they were at that time in office. Labour followed suit in 1964, being greatly influenced by the scientific findings of Dr. Mark Abrams and the leadership of Hugh Gaitskell. Indeed this whole change in tactics was part of the "revisionist" triumph over the ideologues. In 1966 both parties continued their efforts, the Conservatives in their at- tempt to locate "target voters" making a far more ambitious use of survey research than had ever been made before.

For all the remaining resistances of traditionalism, there can be no doubt that this revolution in electoral methods and the resulting professionaliza- tion of vote-getting will go forward. The conventional wisdom of the party leader and agent about the voter appeal of pensions, housing, education, and other elements in the bidding process is now refined and made far more exact by survey research, while the attempt to win the support of the rele- vant groups is heightened by an increasingly sophisticated use of advertis- ing and television.

The effects of this major step in rationalization are not likely to be con- fined to elections, and can hardly help affecting the power structures of the two parties. There is still a role for the local activists, yet as a means of as- certaining and influencing the public will they are overshadowed by the new techniques. In the Labour party, the effect will surely be to reduce still further the role of conference in policy-making. With regard to the positions of the two parties, the new and more effective processes of bidding may very well draw them even closer together. Tory statesmanship itself cannot wholly resist the effect of hard evidence of the voters' desires. In 1966, for example, when survey research showed that the voters preferred Labour's policy of comprehensive education to the Conservative stand, statesmanship at least compromised by omitting the mention of education from the mani- festo. No doubt the immensely increased demands for money which the new techniques entail also could affect power structure. In 1964, for exam- ple, Labour trebled its expenditures on its preelection campaign as com- pared with 1959. It is worth mentioning that a special committee has recently proposed that the Labour party adopt a system of graduated dues for its individual members, varying with their incomes.

x In revising his standard work on British pressure groups in 1965, Professor Finer wrote: "... . The most striking impression I have received is the stabil- ity and durability of the system it describes.... Broadly speaking, the same

31 31

Page 14: Comparative Method and British Politics

Comparative Politics October 1968 Comparative Politics October 1968

great organisations still hold the centre of the stage, continue to make the same sort of demands, and press them by the same sort of tactics."15 With regard to functional representation, two developments, both continuous with past trends, are notable. The system of quasi-corporatism bringing government and producers' groups into intimate and continuous relation- ships has been still further elaborated and institutionalized. At the same time, the expert, the scientifically and professionally trained person, has continued to gain a position of greater influence. In neither case, however, has the course of events been smooth; on the contrary, like British planning itself, it has been punctuated by "Stop and Go."

A new and greater commitment to planning was institutionalized in new machinery that the Conservatives inaugurated and Labour developed: the National Economic Development Council with its score or so of little Ned- dies for specific fields, the Department of Economic Affairs, the National Board for Prices and Incomes. Through these channels, consultation be- tween government and producers' groups was widened and regularized. A major change facilitating this new level of contact was the crucial shift in the attitudes of organized business toward the acceptance of economic planning. Even after the war, industry continued to be torn between its old principle of independence of government and the new possibilities of ex- ercising influence on it at the cost of closer association. Finally, in the early sixties a decision was made in favor of the latter alternative, reflected in the vigorous advocacy by the Federation of British Industries of economic planning for growth on the French model. Indeed, it was industry's accept- ance of its new responsibilities in the NEDC that led to the amalgamation of the three main peak organizations into one comprehensive organization, the Confederation of British Industry. Nor was this new commitment purely organizational: individual firms cooperated heartily in providing the massive information needed for Labour's National Plan.

In the sixties, as in the forties, however, the success of planning depended upon the restraint of inflation, a particularly acute problem for an economy in the exposed international position of the British. Again as in the past, the new group politics caused difficulties.16 Governments showed great re- luctance to restrict consumption, private and public. Against this back- ground of excessive demand, it was even harder to achieve success in the effort to hold down the forces making for inflation on the side of costs, es- pecially wages. The attempt to set up an effective incomes policy was the core of the problem, and the prolonged and intricate bargaining of the La- bour Government with producers' groups, especially trade unions, makes a fascinating chapter in the development of functional representation. Par- liament played a residual role, and while the threat to use legal powers did gradually materialize, events again made it clear that the real foundation of a successful policy would have to be voluntary cooperation.

As of this writing, it can only be said that the incomes-policy attempt was a failure. The reason was in part a matter of choice and will: the massive transport-workers' union as of old, supported by such unions as the engi-

15 S. E. Finer, Anonymous Empire (London, 1966), p. ix. 16 I have discussed the relationship in "The British Legislature and the Problem of

Mobilizing Consent," in Elke Frank, ed. Lawmakers in a Changing World (Englewood Cliffs, 1966), esp. pp. 37-39.

great organisations still hold the centre of the stage, continue to make the same sort of demands, and press them by the same sort of tactics."15 With regard to functional representation, two developments, both continuous with past trends, are notable. The system of quasi-corporatism bringing government and producers' groups into intimate and continuous relation- ships has been still further elaborated and institutionalized. At the same time, the expert, the scientifically and professionally trained person, has continued to gain a position of greater influence. In neither case, however, has the course of events been smooth; on the contrary, like British planning itself, it has been punctuated by "Stop and Go."

A new and greater commitment to planning was institutionalized in new machinery that the Conservatives inaugurated and Labour developed: the National Economic Development Council with its score or so of little Ned- dies for specific fields, the Department of Economic Affairs, the National Board for Prices and Incomes. Through these channels, consultation be- tween government and producers' groups was widened and regularized. A major change facilitating this new level of contact was the crucial shift in the attitudes of organized business toward the acceptance of economic planning. Even after the war, industry continued to be torn between its old principle of independence of government and the new possibilities of ex- ercising influence on it at the cost of closer association. Finally, in the early sixties a decision was made in favor of the latter alternative, reflected in the vigorous advocacy by the Federation of British Industries of economic planning for growth on the French model. Indeed, it was industry's accept- ance of its new responsibilities in the NEDC that led to the amalgamation of the three main peak organizations into one comprehensive organization, the Confederation of British Industry. Nor was this new commitment purely organizational: individual firms cooperated heartily in providing the massive information needed for Labour's National Plan.

In the sixties, as in the forties, however, the success of planning depended upon the restraint of inflation, a particularly acute problem for an economy in the exposed international position of the British. Again as in the past, the new group politics caused difficulties.16 Governments showed great re- luctance to restrict consumption, private and public. Against this back- ground of excessive demand, it was even harder to achieve success in the effort to hold down the forces making for inflation on the side of costs, es- pecially wages. The attempt to set up an effective incomes policy was the core of the problem, and the prolonged and intricate bargaining of the La- bour Government with producers' groups, especially trade unions, makes a fascinating chapter in the development of functional representation. Par- liament played a residual role, and while the threat to use legal powers did gradually materialize, events again made it clear that the real foundation of a successful policy would have to be voluntary cooperation.

As of this writing, it can only be said that the incomes-policy attempt was a failure. The reason was in part a matter of choice and will: the massive transport-workers' union as of old, supported by such unions as the engi-

15 S. E. Finer, Anonymous Empire (London, 1966), p. ix. 16 I have discussed the relationship in "The British Legislature and the Problem of

Mobilizing Consent," in Elke Frank, ed. Lawmakers in a Changing World (Englewood Cliffs, 1966), esp. pp. 37-39.

32 32

Page 15: Comparative Method and British Politics

Samuel H. Beer Samuel H. Beer

neers' under newly radical leadership, simply refused to cooperate. Yet there were also important structural weaknesses, on the side of both employers' and employees' organizations, which throw interesting light on the stage of political concentration reached by the British polity. As compared with similar groups in such countries as Sweden, British producers' groups have long been criticized for their lack of cohesion. Yet modern economic man- agement, which entails the making of bargains that will be kept, requires coherent and authoritative leadership on both sides of the private sector. Concentration among unions has gone forward, and today 70 percent of trade-union membership is included in some eighteen huge organizations. The dynamics of union growth seem inexorably to be eliminating the many small organizations, while the separatism of different crafts is in part over- come by the further growth of general unions.

At the same time, however, full employment has led to a shift of much significant collective bargaining from the national to the plant level. Even when national organizations did accommodate their agreements on wage rates to the criteria of the incomes policy, "earnings drift" at the workplace level continued to swell the forces of cost inflation. As compared with the time when nationally agreed wage rates were virtually identical with earn- ings, this new development has meant a real and major loss of authority on the part of the national unions. Whether their central power should be strengthened or these decentralized practices should be recognized and regularized is being ardently debated. Whatever structure is adopted, it can be said that if this new stage of rationalized control of the economy is to succeed, some corresponding means must be found to mobilize consent among the affected groups.

This failure of planning has also meant a certain setback for that profes- sionalization of policy-making which is a growing characteristic of British as of other Western governments. If we look generally at the role of the scientist in British government, we can see that it has grown slowly and steadily in Britain during the past two or three decades, although by no means as greatly as in the United States. As has often happened to other groups and classes in the past, the new needs of public policy have elevated the effective power and influence of the scientifically and professionally trained strata. Britain gave scientists new and important functions during the war and since then, relative to GNP, has invested about as much in civilian research and development as has the United States. The network of advisory committees that cluster around government departments includes a high proportion of scientifically trained people. The creation of the Min- istry of Technology has improved their position within the administration and given science policy a new importance.

Indeed, when Harold Wilson took office in 1964 it was with great prom- ises of bringing the scientific revolution to fruition in Britain. One immedi- ate instance was a flocking of dons, particularly economists, to Whitehall, a migration reminiscent of American practice and indeed consciously imitat- ing it. If the original hopes for economic planning had been fulfilled, the role of the professional would have been even greater than it is today. The pressure of economic crisis, however, with its usual features of inflation and an international deficit, forced authority away from the new organs and back toward the Treasury, which although by no means as innocent of

neers' under newly radical leadership, simply refused to cooperate. Yet there were also important structural weaknesses, on the side of both employers' and employees' organizations, which throw interesting light on the stage of political concentration reached by the British polity. As compared with similar groups in such countries as Sweden, British producers' groups have long been criticized for their lack of cohesion. Yet modern economic man- agement, which entails the making of bargains that will be kept, requires coherent and authoritative leadership on both sides of the private sector. Concentration among unions has gone forward, and today 70 percent of trade-union membership is included in some eighteen huge organizations. The dynamics of union growth seem inexorably to be eliminating the many small organizations, while the separatism of different crafts is in part over- come by the further growth of general unions.

At the same time, however, full employment has led to a shift of much significant collective bargaining from the national to the plant level. Even when national organizations did accommodate their agreements on wage rates to the criteria of the incomes policy, "earnings drift" at the workplace level continued to swell the forces of cost inflation. As compared with the time when nationally agreed wage rates were virtually identical with earn- ings, this new development has meant a real and major loss of authority on the part of the national unions. Whether their central power should be strengthened or these decentralized practices should be recognized and regularized is being ardently debated. Whatever structure is adopted, it can be said that if this new stage of rationalized control of the economy is to succeed, some corresponding means must be found to mobilize consent among the affected groups.

This failure of planning has also meant a certain setback for that profes- sionalization of policy-making which is a growing characteristic of British as of other Western governments. If we look generally at the role of the scientist in British government, we can see that it has grown slowly and steadily in Britain during the past two or three decades, although by no means as greatly as in the United States. As has often happened to other groups and classes in the past, the new needs of public policy have elevated the effective power and influence of the scientifically and professionally trained strata. Britain gave scientists new and important functions during the war and since then, relative to GNP, has invested about as much in civilian research and development as has the United States. The network of advisory committees that cluster around government departments includes a high proportion of scientifically trained people. The creation of the Min- istry of Technology has improved their position within the administration and given science policy a new importance.

Indeed, when Harold Wilson took office in 1964 it was with great prom- ises of bringing the scientific revolution to fruition in Britain. One immedi- ate instance was a flocking of dons, particularly economists, to Whitehall, a migration reminiscent of American practice and indeed consciously imitat- ing it. If the original hopes for economic planning had been fulfilled, the role of the professional would have been even greater than it is today. The pressure of economic crisis, however, with its usual features of inflation and an international deficit, forced authority away from the new organs and back toward the Treasury, which although by no means as innocent of

33 33

Page 16: Comparative Method and British Politics

Comparative Politics October 1968 Comparative Politics October 1968

expertise as it once was, remains especially the home of the generalist and nonprofessional administrator.

XI In this brief sketch of recent developments, there appear no great departures from the model of Collectivist politics. Britain's politics, like Britain's prob- lems, bears a remarkable resemblance to what it was ten and even twenty years ago. Yet there are incremental changes in economy and polity which could bring about a qualitative change. What are some of the shapes that this political future may take?

The further development of corporatism is surely to be expected. Planning is inevitable in an economy that seeks both stability and expansion. In the absence of a totalitarian bureaucracy, such planning means that the enter- prises and people that carry out the plans must be brought in on their formu- lation. To this extent, as planning develops, functional representation will likewise grow, becoming an even more important part of the representative system of the polity. The structure may become more centralized, as has been the tendency in the past. Or it may functionally and territorially de- centralize tasks that are not excessively burdening the center. The exten- sion of control through some form of bureaucratic structure, however, seems hardly to be avoided.

But corporatism cannot constitute a complete polity and must be supple- mented by some other source of will and direction such as has come in the past from the party system. One of the more apocalyptic possibilities has recently been characterized by a friend of mine speaking generally of the dangers facing Western countries. This possibility he described as "Caesarism based on technocracy because of the difficulties experienced by democracy in dealing with complexity." The demand for planning is in- exorable, but the regime of parties is incapable of generating among the populace the understanding and acceptance that will produce the decisions necessary for planning. A Caesarism, perhaps less authoritarian and more manipulative thanks to the new techniques of communication, performs this essential function of forming the public will, no doubt in conjunction with a controlled system of corporatism.

With this very familiar specter one may contrast a tendency of more re- cent vintage, which insofar as it is realized would disrupt the imposing monism described in the previous paragraph with a radically new kind of dualism. The pattern of policy we suggested above carries the impersonality and centralization of bureaucracy to a new height, legitimizing them with the authority of science and modern rationality. Yet, as we have recently learned again, precisely this set of factors can produce a powerful reaction. There are precedents in the past. Upon the foundation laid by voluntarism, modernity has from time to time produced a romantic reaction that rejects not only the discipline of an objective ethics, but also the discipline of an industrial environment. In Britain, from the Luddites to D. H. Lawrence, different classes and times have shared this impulse, of which student anarchism is only a recent flowering.

But if rebellious students are the most vivid exhibit, the possibilities of a regional or local politics are more serious and no less romantic. In recent

expertise as it once was, remains especially the home of the generalist and nonprofessional administrator.

XI In this brief sketch of recent developments, there appear no great departures from the model of Collectivist politics. Britain's politics, like Britain's prob- lems, bears a remarkable resemblance to what it was ten and even twenty years ago. Yet there are incremental changes in economy and polity which could bring about a qualitative change. What are some of the shapes that this political future may take?

The further development of corporatism is surely to be expected. Planning is inevitable in an economy that seeks both stability and expansion. In the absence of a totalitarian bureaucracy, such planning means that the enter- prises and people that carry out the plans must be brought in on their formu- lation. To this extent, as planning develops, functional representation will likewise grow, becoming an even more important part of the representative system of the polity. The structure may become more centralized, as has been the tendency in the past. Or it may functionally and territorially de- centralize tasks that are not excessively burdening the center. The exten- sion of control through some form of bureaucratic structure, however, seems hardly to be avoided.

But corporatism cannot constitute a complete polity and must be supple- mented by some other source of will and direction such as has come in the past from the party system. One of the more apocalyptic possibilities has recently been characterized by a friend of mine speaking generally of the dangers facing Western countries. This possibility he described as "Caesarism based on technocracy because of the difficulties experienced by democracy in dealing with complexity." The demand for planning is in- exorable, but the regime of parties is incapable of generating among the populace the understanding and acceptance that will produce the decisions necessary for planning. A Caesarism, perhaps less authoritarian and more manipulative thanks to the new techniques of communication, performs this essential function of forming the public will, no doubt in conjunction with a controlled system of corporatism.

With this very familiar specter one may contrast a tendency of more re- cent vintage, which insofar as it is realized would disrupt the imposing monism described in the previous paragraph with a radically new kind of dualism. The pattern of policy we suggested above carries the impersonality and centralization of bureaucracy to a new height, legitimizing them with the authority of science and modern rationality. Yet, as we have recently learned again, precisely this set of factors can produce a powerful reaction. There are precedents in the past. Upon the foundation laid by voluntarism, modernity has from time to time produced a romantic reaction that rejects not only the discipline of an objective ethics, but also the discipline of an industrial environment. In Britain, from the Luddites to D. H. Lawrence, different classes and times have shared this impulse, of which student anarchism is only a recent flowering.

But if rebellious students are the most vivid exhibit, the possibilities of a regional or local politics are more serious and no less romantic. In recent

34 34

Page 17: Comparative Method and British Politics

Samuel H. Beer Samuel H. Beer

years, localism has become a major principle of opposition, especially in by-elections. More to the point is the powerful upsurge of Celtic national- ism. As English civil servants continually point out, the demands of Scots nationalists make no economic sense. Yet enthusiasm for the Scottish Na- tionalist party grows and confronts not only Liberals but also Labourites and Conservatives with the prospect of being wiped out north of the Tweed. Welsh nationalists like the Scots have one MP at present. But close ob- servers forecast growing success for them in the not too distant future.

If we subtract the extremism from these two possibilities, they suggest a party dualism based not on class but on a central-local axis, such as char- acterized many nations during the early years of their development. Whether such tendencies would be powerful enough to sustain a two-party system, as did the principles of Hamilton and Jefferson in the United States, seems dubious, but they might well loosen and disorganize the present orderly play of parties.

That orderly play itself tends to transform the system. If the parties con- tinue to converge, conceivably they could produce a condition of "party duopoly without product differentiation." Further professionalization of leadership would reduce the power of militants and open the way to a highly flexible policy. Through two "catchall" parties, competing teams of leaders would seek power on the basis of shifting coalitions of voters. Conceivably an "era of good feeling" could supervene in which the old dualism would be dissolved by the overwhelming dominance of one party. In view of Labour's gloomy prospects at the moment, it is not idle to specu- late on this possibility of democratic one-party government. Broadly agreed on the basic outlines of the welfare state and managed economy, a set of lively factions within this great catchall party would contest for party and so governmental control. One is reminded of the CDU, or the Christian Democrats of Italy, or indeed not a little of the Tories during their recent long tenure of power.

The discussion of the catchall party and of factions suggests a more radical alternative that should not be dismissed. This is the withering away of party altogether. Ostrogorski, it will be remembered, regarded party as the dead hand of traditionalism extended in a new form into the era of liberty. Instead of parties he preferred combinations of citizens shift- ing with issues and problems. Without trying to follow his proposals ex- actly, we should at least consider the possibility that parties may become fairly dysfunctional and as a result decline and disappear. Ostrogorski did indeed have a point when he observed their traditionalizing influence. By freezing voters in their adherence to a symbol, they prevent a flexible re- sponse to new problems. The continuance of class lines and class interests gave some justification to the stereotyping of political response. If we can suppose the decline of class, more flexible means of mobilizing opinion and changing the configurations of loyalty and support would be appropriate. In this sense we might think of party as characterizing a transitional stage between traditional society and a fully modern society.

As in any discussion of British politics, we return at the end to the basic question of class. In Britain, class trails with it ancient habits of thought and feeling that hark back to Old Toryism. Even those who rebelled and still rebel against class as the product of industrial capitalism acquired their

years, localism has become a major principle of opposition, especially in by-elections. More to the point is the powerful upsurge of Celtic national- ism. As English civil servants continually point out, the demands of Scots nationalists make no economic sense. Yet enthusiasm for the Scottish Na- tionalist party grows and confronts not only Liberals but also Labourites and Conservatives with the prospect of being wiped out north of the Tweed. Welsh nationalists like the Scots have one MP at present. But close ob- servers forecast growing success for them in the not too distant future.

If we subtract the extremism from these two possibilities, they suggest a party dualism based not on class but on a central-local axis, such as char- acterized many nations during the early years of their development. Whether such tendencies would be powerful enough to sustain a two-party system, as did the principles of Hamilton and Jefferson in the United States, seems dubious, but they might well loosen and disorganize the present orderly play of parties.

That orderly play itself tends to transform the system. If the parties con- tinue to converge, conceivably they could produce a condition of "party duopoly without product differentiation." Further professionalization of leadership would reduce the power of militants and open the way to a highly flexible policy. Through two "catchall" parties, competing teams of leaders would seek power on the basis of shifting coalitions of voters. Conceivably an "era of good feeling" could supervene in which the old dualism would be dissolved by the overwhelming dominance of one party. In view of Labour's gloomy prospects at the moment, it is not idle to specu- late on this possibility of democratic one-party government. Broadly agreed on the basic outlines of the welfare state and managed economy, a set of lively factions within this great catchall party would contest for party and so governmental control. One is reminded of the CDU, or the Christian Democrats of Italy, or indeed not a little of the Tories during their recent long tenure of power.

The discussion of the catchall party and of factions suggests a more radical alternative that should not be dismissed. This is the withering away of party altogether. Ostrogorski, it will be remembered, regarded party as the dead hand of traditionalism extended in a new form into the era of liberty. Instead of parties he preferred combinations of citizens shift- ing with issues and problems. Without trying to follow his proposals ex- actly, we should at least consider the possibility that parties may become fairly dysfunctional and as a result decline and disappear. Ostrogorski did indeed have a point when he observed their traditionalizing influence. By freezing voters in their adherence to a symbol, they prevent a flexible re- sponse to new problems. The continuance of class lines and class interests gave some justification to the stereotyping of political response. If we can suppose the decline of class, more flexible means of mobilizing opinion and changing the configurations of loyalty and support would be appropriate. In this sense we might think of party as characterizing a transitional stage between traditional society and a fully modern society.

As in any discussion of British politics, we return at the end to the basic question of class. In Britain, class trails with it ancient habits of thought and feeling that hark back to Old Toryism. Even those who rebelled and still rebel against class as the product of industrial capitalism acquired their

35 35

Page 18: Comparative Method and British Politics

Comparative Politics October 1968 Comparative Politics October 1968

sense of identity and solidarity not only from those objective conditions, but also from a much older heritage. In this sense class diminishes as mod- ernization proceeds.

Strong as this heritage may be, however, it still requires some current and objective focus for its survival. If such foci cannot be eliminated, neither can the sense of class. One focus consists of differences in material well-being and style of life. Quite conceivably affluence could spread to the point where this basis of class and class politics had virtually vanished. Another focus consists of the relationship of individuals to the ownership of the means of production. The spread of bureaucratization continually erodes this difference by making employees of more and more members of the economy. But class also, and I am inclined to think this is the most im- portant meaning of the term, rests on differences of power. The prospect of eliminating differences of power in society and so of eliminating the differ- ent attitudes that men take toward the distribution of power seems highly unlikely.

Conceivably, the two parties could become irrelevant to British politics if they were contesting nothing but the distribution of material goods and services. Similarly, if that myth of universal nationalization produced by the political imagination of Labour's founders were the party's only reason for being, the party might well see the time when there was no future for it. But Tories and Socialists also confront one another as advocates of distinc- tive attitudes toward the distribution of power. In the Tory acceptance of the social goal of security, Conservatives have much in common with So- cialists. But the Tory belief in inequality, not merely with regard to dis- tributive justice but also with regard to power in the state and in society, puts a fundamental principle at issue between Tories and Labour. However evanescent Labour's commitment to the goal of fellowship may have be- come, British socialism is still "about equality." Even in Britain's postin- dustrial society, there is likely to be a vigorous future for her present party dualism.

sense of identity and solidarity not only from those objective conditions, but also from a much older heritage. In this sense class diminishes as mod- ernization proceeds.

Strong as this heritage may be, however, it still requires some current and objective focus for its survival. If such foci cannot be eliminated, neither can the sense of class. One focus consists of differences in material well-being and style of life. Quite conceivably affluence could spread to the point where this basis of class and class politics had virtually vanished. Another focus consists of the relationship of individuals to the ownership of the means of production. The spread of bureaucratization continually erodes this difference by making employees of more and more members of the economy. But class also, and I am inclined to think this is the most im- portant meaning of the term, rests on differences of power. The prospect of eliminating differences of power in society and so of eliminating the differ- ent attitudes that men take toward the distribution of power seems highly unlikely.

Conceivably, the two parties could become irrelevant to British politics if they were contesting nothing but the distribution of material goods and services. Similarly, if that myth of universal nationalization produced by the political imagination of Labour's founders were the party's only reason for being, the party might well see the time when there was no future for it. But Tories and Socialists also confront one another as advocates of distinc- tive attitudes toward the distribution of power. In the Tory acceptance of the social goal of security, Conservatives have much in common with So- cialists. But the Tory belief in inequality, not merely with regard to dis- tributive justice but also with regard to power in the state and in society, puts a fundamental principle at issue between Tories and Labour. However evanescent Labour's commitment to the goal of fellowship may have be- come, British socialism is still "about equality." Even in Britain's postin- dustrial society, there is likely to be a vigorous future for her present party dualism.

36 36