Ciceronian Conciliare and Aristotelian Ethos

download Ciceronian Conciliare and Aristotelian Ethos

of 15

description

-

Transcript of Ciceronian Conciliare and Aristotelian Ethos

  • 7/17/2019 Ciceronian Conciliare and Aristotelian Ethos

    1/15

    Ciceronian Conciliare and Aristotelian EthosAuthor(s): Elaine FanthamSource: Phoenix, Vol. 27, No. 3 (Autumn, 1973), pp. 262-275Published by: Classical Association of CanadaStable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/1088043.

    Accessed: 03/11/2014 23:33

    Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at.

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

    .JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of

    content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms

    of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].

    .

    Classical Association of Canadais collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to

    Phoenix.

    http://www.jstor.org

    This content downloaded from 200.45.170.30 on Mon, 3 Nov 2014 23:33:24 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=cachttp://www.jstor.org/stable/1088043?origin=JSTOR-pdfhttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/stable/1088043?origin=JSTOR-pdfhttp://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=cac
  • 7/17/2019 Ciceronian Conciliare and Aristotelian Ethos

    2/15

    CICERONIAN

    CONCILIARE

    AND

    ARISTOTELIAN

    ETHOS

    ELAINE FANTHAM

    IN

    THE SECOND BOOK

    of

    De OratoreCicero

    analyses

    the ratiodicendi

    n

    terms

    of

    three functions:

    1)

    ut

    probemus

    vera

    esse,

    quae

    defendimus;

    (2)

    ut conciliemus os

    nobis,

    qui

    audiunt;

    (3)

    ut

    animos

    eorum,

    d

    quem-

    cumque

    ausa

    postulabit

    motum,

    ocemus

    2.115).

    This

    paper

    is

    concerned

    with the

    second

    of

    these

    functions s

    presentedby

    Cicero,

    and

    with

    the

    Aristotelian

    heory

    of

    ranrs

    ..

    &&..

    .

    70r

    -00ovs

    (Rhet.

    1.2.1356 a

    5-13)

    from

    which he

    derived this

    second

    function.'

    shall

    try

    to

    explain

    the

    modifications

    icero

    made,

    his motives

    n

    makingthem,

    and the

    diffi-

    culties

    arising

    fromhis choice of

    adaptation.

    The

    theme

    of

    conciliare

    returns

    briefly

    n 2.121

    among

    the

    VTrexvOL

    riLares,

    lla

    quae

    totaab

    oratore

    ariuntur.

    There are tres es

    quae

    adfidem

    faciendam

    olae

    valent

    ..

    ut et

    concilienturnimi

    t

    doceantur tmoveantur.

    These

    receive further

    omment

    n

    128:

    tres

    sunt

    res,

    ut

    ante

    dixi:

    una

    conciliandorum

    hominum,

    altera

    docendorum,

    ertia

    concitandorum. arum trium

    partium prima

    lenitatem

    orationis,

    secunda

    acumen,

    tertia

    vim

    desiderat,

    am

    hoc necesse

    st,

    ut

    s,

    qui

    nobiscausam

    adiudicaturus

    it,

    aut

    inclinatione

    voluntatis propendeat in nos aut defensionis rgumentis dducaturaut animi permotione

    cogatur.

    From

    these

    ntroductory

    emarks

    we derive

    the dea that

    115)

    the

    urors

    must be

    won

    over

    to

    us,

    the

    advocates2

    114

    has

    parenthetically

    ncluded

    xThe

    association

    of

    conciliare

    with

    the

    Aristotelian

    iaortsb,&

    70oi

    ovs

    is

    not

    made

    explicit

    in the

    literary

    and exoteric

    De

    Oratore,

    which

    generally

    avoids

    Greek

    terms.

    Antonius

    acknowledges

    his

    debt

    to

    Aristotlefor

    he

    analysis

    of

    ogical proof

    n

    2.160,

    but

    does

    not

    repeat

    the

    acknowledgment

    for

    the

    "ethical" or

    emotive

    proofs.

    Cicero

    explicitly

    mentions

    '0LKbV,

    and

    gives

    ts

    motive as ad

    benevolentiam

    onciliandam

    inOrator128: duo sunt enimquae bene ractata b oratore dmirabilem loquentiamfaciant;

    quorum

    alterum

    est

    quod

    Graeci

    1O0LK6V

    ocant,

    ad

    naturas et

    mores

    et

    ad

    omnem

    vitae

    consuetudinem

    accommodatum;

    alterum

    quod

    eidem

    iraerTLK6b

    nominant, uo

    pertur-

    bantur

    animi et

    concitantur,

    n

    quo

    uno

    regnat

    oratio.

    llud

    superius

    come, iucundum,

    ad

    benevolentiam conciliandam

    paratum.

    It should

    be

    noted that if

    OLK6V

    nd

    7ra7erTLK6P

    re

    here

    used

    as

    nouns,

    rather

    than

    adjectives,

    this

    is

    a

    Hellenistic

    extension

    of

    Aristotle's

    practice

    (see

    below,

    note

    9).

    Cicero here

    defines

    r07LK6P

    s

    speech

    adapted

    to

    mores,

    the

    natural

    translation

    of

    i607.

    As

    J.

    E.

    Sandys

    comments

    on

    Orator,

    oc.

    cit.

    [Cambridge

    1885]

    p.

    131),

    the

    mores are

    not

    clearly

    identified

    s

    those of

    the

    speaker,

    or

    the

    audience,

    whereas

    there can

    be

    no

    doubt

    that the

    animi

    affected

    byira07?1LKb6

    re

    those of

    the

    audience. We

    must

    there-

    fore

    go

    back to the earlier

    and fuller

    ccount

    in

    De

    Oratore

    o

    see

    whereCicero

    places

    the

    emphasis

    of

    the

    genus quod

    ad

    vitam

    t

    mores

    ccommodatur

    De

    Orat. 2.213

    =

    Orator128

    above).

    This is one of

    the

    problems

    which I

    attempt

    to

    solve in the

    following

    pages.

    2See

    now

    George

    Kennedy,

    "The

    Rhetoric of

    Advocacy

    in

    Greece

    and

    Rome,"

    A7P

    89

    (1968)

    419-436. In this

    broad historical

    study

    he

    traces

    the

    principal

    effects

    of

    the

    262

    PHoENIx,

    Vol. 27

    (1973)

    3.

    This content downloaded from 200.45.170.30 on Mon, 3 Nov 2014 23:33:24 PMAll use subject toJSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 7/17/2019 Ciceronian Conciliare and Aristotelian Ethos

    3/15

    CICERONIAN CONCILIARE AND ARISTOTELIAN

    ETHOS 263

    both

    advocate and

    client),

    nd

    (128)

    this

    requires

    enitas

    o

    make

    the

    ury

    inclined o favour

    us.

    There

    may

    also

    be

    a contrast

    ntended

    between

    the

    conscious inclinatiovoluntatis nd the unwitting r unwillingpermotio

    animi.

    The

    concept

    of

    lenitas is

    important

    for Cicero's rhetorical

    theory

    because

    it enables

    him to

    bridge

    he

    gap

    between he

    ethical

    and aesthetic

    aspects

    of

    speech;

    in

    Cicero's

    theoretical

    writings

    t

    is

    most

    often

    ssoc-

    iated with

    style;

    compare, .g.,

    Leg.

    1.11,

    n

    which

    Atticus,

    emarking

    n

    Cicero's

    adaptation

    of

    his

    style

    to

    increasing

    ge

    and his

    reduction

    of

    contentio,

    dds

    ut

    iam

    oratio

    tua

    non

    multum

    b

    philosophorum

    enitate

    absit. Historical

    writing

    s said

    in

    De

    Orat.

    2.64

    to

    require

    genus

    orationis

    fusum tquetractumt cum lenitatequadam aequabiliterprofluens ine

    hac

    iudiciali

    asperitate;

    nd

    for

    he

    combinationwith

    equabilis,

    compare

    Orator

    3,

    elaborant

    lii

    in

    lenitate

    et

    aequabilitate

    et

    puro

    .

    .

    et candido

    genere

    dicendi.

    t

    is

    also

    applied

    to

    delivery

    nd

    intonation,

    s

    in

    2.184

    below

    and

    Orator

    6

    (with

    Sandys'

    note ad

    loc.,

    p.

    65 of

    his

    edition).

    But

    at the

    moral

    evel enitas

    s the

    quality

    of

    wise

    and merciful

    ecision

    n

    the

    judge

    or

    jury,

    defined

    by

    Cicero in

    Part.

    Or.

    78,

    in

    relation

    to

    justice:

    ea

    (sc.iustitia)

    n

    moderatione

    nimi

    advertendienitas

    nominatur.

    ot

    only

    does this

    correspondclosely

    to the

    Aristotelian

    ccount

    of

    irLELKEta

    n

    Rhet.

    1.13,

    1374

    a

    30

    following;

    but

    brLELKEL

    nd

    the

    trVLLKr7S

    n

    a more

    general

    ense

    are

    important

    lements

    n

    the deal ethoswhich

    Aristotle ets

    up

    forhis orator

    t Rhet.

    1.2.

    1356

    a

    7

    and

    a

    13,

    and

    2.1.1378

    a

    15.

    While

    this

    wider

    sense of

    irLEKls-"reasonable,

    moderate,

    gentlemanly"-

    extends

    beyond

    the

    range

    of

    lenis,

    Cicero's

    choice of

    lenis and

    lenitas

    enabled

    him

    to

    include,

    s

    I

    will

    show,

    esthetic nd

    stylistic

    onnotations

    which

    -LeLKeLa

    acked.

    Of the three

    functions icero

    discusses

    first he

    varietiesof

    ntellectual

    proof docere)whichare closest to theorthodox nventio heoryof post-

    Aristotelian

    hetoric,

    nd

    leads

    up

    to

    a

    catalogue

    of

    the

    Aristotelian

    opoi

    in

    163-173.

    After

    conversational

    digression

    Antonius

    proceeds

    to con-

    sider the

    psychological functions,

    onciliare

    and movere:

    182-184 deal

    separate

    dentities f

    advocate

    and client

    found

    ccasionally

    n

    Athens

    nd

    almost

    universally

    n Rome.

    He

    discusses

    e

    Orat.

    .182-184,

    n

    pages

    34-435, oncluding

    hat

    "most

    especially

    he

    possibility

    f effective

    ontrast

    etween

    atron

    nd client

    s

    not

    recognised,"

    nd

    comments n

    the

    slowness f

    Roman

    rhetoricalheory o assimilatethe

    mplications

    fthe

    eparate

    ersonalities

    f

    advocate nd client. he

    whole rticle

    is

    full

    f

    valuable

    comments n

    many

    spects

    of

    Ethos,

    nd

    I offer

    my

    own

    discussion

    (written

    efore

    consulted

    ennedy's

    work)

    n

    the

    hope

    that

    this

    nalysis

    f

    the

    con-

    flicts

    enerated

    n

    Cicero's

    daptation

    f

    Greek

    heory

    ill

    provide

    useful

    ppendix

    o

    his

    paper.

    For

    further

    iscussion

    ee

    Kennedy's

    he

    Art

    f

    Rhetoric

    t

    Rome

    Princeton

    1972)

    139

    (on

    the

    treatmentf

    Ethos

    n

    rhetorical

    heory),

    nd

    220-221

    (on

    De

    Orat.

    2.182-184).

    This content downloaded from 200.45.170.30 on Mon, 3 Nov 2014 23:33:24 PMAll use subject toJSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 7/17/2019 Ciceronian Conciliare and Aristotelian Ethos

    4/15

    264 PHOENIX

    specifically

    with the former. ince 182 is a difficult

    ection,

    t seems

    wise

    to set it out in fullbefore

    ttempting

    n

    analysis.

    Valet igiturmultum d vincendum robarimoreset instituta tfacta et vitameorum, qui

    agent ausas,

    et

    eorum, ro quibus,

    et tem

    mprobari

    dversariorum,nimosque

    eorum,

    pud

    quos

    agetur,

    onciliari

    quam

    maximead benevolentiam

    cum

    erga

    oratorem um

    erga

    llum,

    pro

    quo

    dicet

    orator.Conciliantur

    utem nimi

    dignitate

    ominis,

    ebus

    gestis,

    xistimatione

    vitae;

    quaefacilius

    ornari

    possunt,

    i

    modo

    unt,

    quamfingi,

    i

    nulla

    sunt.

    Sed

    haec

    adiuvant

    in

    oratore;

    enitas vocis

    voltus

    pudor[is

    significatio],

    erborum

    omitas;

    si

    quid persequare

    acrius,

    ut

    invitus

    t

    coactus

    acere

    videare.

    Facilitatis,

    liberalitatis,

    mansuetudinis, ietatis,

    grati animi,

    non

    appetentis,

    non

    avidi

    signa

    proferre erutile

    est;

    eaque omnia, quae

    proborum,

    emissorum,

    on

    acrium,

    non

    pertinacium,

    on

    itigiosorum,

    on

    acerborum

    unt,

    valde

    benevolentiam

    onciliant

    balienantque

    ab

    eis,

    in

    quibus

    haec non

    sunt;

    itaque

    eadem

    suntin adversarios x contrario onferenda.

    In

    the first entence

    he

    aim

    is

    given

    as

    winning

    pproval

    for he

    mores

    et

    instituta

    ..

    etc. both

    of

    patrons

    (eorum

    qui

    agent

    causas)

    and clients

    (eorum

    pro quibus),

    with

    a

    corresponding

    iscrediting

    f

    the

    adversaries.

    While the

    second sentence

    ppears

    to be

    merely

    rephrasing

    f

    the

    first,

    it

    brings

    nto

    prominence

    he

    third

    party

    concerned,

    he

    iudices

    (apud

    quos

    agetur)

    and the theme verb

    conciliare,

    which

    is

    then

    expanded by

    what

    follows;

    uch

    goodwill

    s

    won

    by

    a

    man's

    prestige, chievements,

    nd

    reputation,but these may be lacking.What is the next connectionof

    thought?

    Sed

    relates to the

    problem

    of

    the

    defendant without

    these

    merits.

    Certain

    qualities

    in

    the

    patron

    such

    as

    lenitas

    of

    delivery'

    and

    demeanour

    can

    compensate

    for

    hese deficiencies.We are now

    discussing

    the

    character

    isplayed

    by

    the

    peaker,

    nd

    thenext

    entence,facilitatis...

    signa proferre

    erutile

    est,

    appears

    to continue

    this theme.

    "It

    is

    very

    advantageous

    to

    display

    the

    marks

    of

    good

    and

    amiable

    qualities."

    Only

    with

    the commenton

    bestowing

    he

    corresponding

    ad

    qualities

    on

    the

    adversaries,

    do

    we

    realise

    that

    signa

    proferre

    may

    refer

    o

    adducing

    evi-

    denceof theamiablequalitiesof theclientrather han thespeakerhimself,

    as

    a

    means

    of

    benevolentiam

    onciliare.4

    8The

    text here

    is

    damaged.

    The

    mss

    read lenitas

    vocis

    voltus

    pudoris

    significatio

    verborum omitas.

    Wilkins

    follows

    Kayser

    in

    bracketing

    -is

    significatio;

    Harnecker

    extends

    the

    brackets

    to

    pudoris

    significatio

    erborum

    omitas, reading

    lenitas

    vocis et

    voltus.

    The

    problem

    does not affect ur

    interpretation

    s a

    whole,

    but I believe

    that

    the

    three elements

    of

    vox,

    voltus,

    and verba

    are all

    necessary,

    and would

    not

    extend the

    brackets

    beyond

    pudoris

    significatio.

    4Antonius' reference

    ere

    corresponds

    o the

    recommendationshe will himself

    give

    for

    the

    principium

    n

    2.320

    ff.

    imilarlypopuli benevolentiam

    ihi conciliaram n

    200

    relates

    to the

    captatio

    benevolentiae,

    ttributed

    by

    traditional rhetoric

    to the

    beginning

    of

    the

    speech.

    A

    comparison

    of

    Aristotle's

    comments

    on

    the exordium n the

    Rhetoricawith

    the

    Roman

    texts

    reveals the

    tradition

    and

    its

    modifications. he

    starting

    point

    is

    Rhet.

    3.14

    1415

    a

    35 f.:

    MXyerzat

    U

    raDra

    EK

    /re

    ro

    X-yov70OS

    (1)

    KaL

    rov

    &KpoarofD

    2)

    Kal

    ro

    D

    rp&hyparos

    3)

    Kal

    ro

    V

    avwrtov

    4).

    Compare

    Rhet.

    Her.

    1.5.8:

    Benivolos

    auditores

    facere

    quattuor

    modis

    possumus;

    ab

    nostra

    (1),

    ab

    adversariorum

    nostrorum

    4),

    ab

    auditorum

    persona

    (2),

    et

    ab

    rebus

    ipsis

    (3).

    Cic.

    Inv.

    1.16.22:

    Benivolentia

    quattuor

    x

    This content downloaded from 200.45.170.30 on Mon, 3 Nov 2014 23:33:24 PMAll use subject toJSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 7/17/2019 Ciceronian Conciliare and Aristotelian Ethos

    5/15

    CICERONIAN

    CONCILIARE

    AND ARISTOTELIAN

    ETHOS

    265

    Section

    183

    adds

    in

    parenthesis

    that

    this

    style

    of

    speaking

    is

    most

    successful

    n cases where t is not

    possible

    to

    play

    on the audience's

    emo-

    tions;heregentle nd mild' speech s mostappropriate, nd mostrecom-

    mends

    client,

    nd

    a

    definition

    s

    offered

    or

    heword

    reus,

    which s the

    ink

    returning

    s

    to

    the

    main

    argument

    n 184. Horum

    igitur

    xprimere

    mores

    oratione

    ustos,

    ntegros,

    eligiosos,

    imidos,

    erferentis

    niuriarum

    mirum

    quiddam

    valet eems to

    recapitulate

    the last

    sentence

    of

    182

    above,

    but

    relates

    to the

    client.

    Antonius

    dds that

    f

    peakers

    do

    this,

    whether

    n the

    preamble,

    narrative,

    r

    conclusion,

    t

    will

    often

    e

    even

    more

    ffectivehan

    the

    case

    proper.

    Further

    autem),

    from he

    feeling

    nd nature

    f

    the

    peech

    it

    can resultthat

    quasi

    mores

    ratoris

    ffingat

    ratio;

    genere

    nim

    quodam

    sententiarumtgenereverborum,dhibitaetiam actione enifacilitatemque

    significante,

    fficitur

    t

    probi,

    ut

    bene

    morati,

    t

    boni

    viri

    esse

    videamur.

    n

    the

    ast

    sentencefacilitatemque

    ignificante

    ppears

    to

    resumefacilitatis

    ..

    locis

    comparatur;

    b nostra

    (1),

    ab adversariorum

    4),

    ab

    iudicum

    persona

    (2),

    ab

    ipsa

    causa

    (3).

    Cic.

    De

    Orat. 2.321: aut

    ex

    reo

    (1)

    aut

    ex

    adversario

    4)

    aut

    ex

    re

    (3)

    aut

    ex

    eis

    apud quos agetur

    2)

    sententias uci

    licebit.

    Rhet.

    Her. and

    De

    Inv.

    are

    clearly

    transcriptions

    f

    the

    same

    source,

    which

    altered the

    Aristotelianorder

    to

    give

    greater

    prominence

    o

    the adversarius.

    De

    Oratore iffersn two

    ways: by

    postponing

    the

    referenceto the audience

    to

    fourth

    position

    it restores

    the

    emphasis on their role; also, just as Antonius in 2.80-82 had refused to accept the

    limitation

    of

    captatio

    benevolentiae

    o the

    principium,

    o

    in 322

    he

    concludes

    his

    summary

    of

    the

    sententiae:

    ex

    eis

    autem

    apud

    quos agetur

    ut

    benevolos

    beneque

    existimantes

    efficiamus,

    uod

    agendo

    efficitur

    elius

    quam rogando.

    est

    id

    quidem

    in totam

    orationem

    confundendam

    nec minime n

    extremam,

    ed

    tamen

    multa

    principia

    ex

    eo genere

    ignuntur.

    Because

    of this belief

    n

    the

    diffusion

    f

    the

    captatio

    throughout

    he

    speech,

    Cicero

    has

    included

    his comments

    on

    this

    technique

    in the context of

    his discussion

    of

    conciliare

    (182-183)

    and

    movere

    200;

    cf.

    206-209)

    rather than under the

    heading

    of

    dispositio.

    Aristotle

    also,

    in

    his

    section

    on

    arrangement,

    mentions

    r76

    evovv

    rodafcat

    s

    a

    goal

    of

    the

    exordium,

    isted,

    as

    in

    De

    Oratore,

    under

    'rp6s

    rTv aKpoarCyv.

    He

    too

    refers

    back

    (3.14.1415 b 29) to his previous discussion, that is to 2.1.1378 a 22-23, on EC-oLa as an

    ingredient

    n

    irtins

    v

    7r4

    Oete

    nd

    to

    2.4,

    on

    the

    7rd06os

    f

    tXLta.

    6In

    Dionysius

    of

    Halicarnassus

    (see

    Lockwood, CQ

    23

    [1929]

    183-184)

    and

    in

    Quin-

    tilian,

    6.2,

    Ethos and

    )0GKL

    are

    identified

    with

    a

    quieter,

    milder evel

    of

    speech

    than

    Pathos

    and

    7rar7rLK'.

    Grube,

    both

    in

    The

    Greek nd

    Roman

    Critics

    291-292)

    and

    in his

    notes to

    Aristotle

    n

    Poetry

    nd

    Style 51,

    n.

    2), suggests

    that

    Quintilian's

    words reflect

    the

    practice

    of

    Cicero

    and

    perhaps

    earlier

    critics;

    even in Aristotlethe

    application

    of

    the

    adjective

    'OLK6S

    o the

    Odyssey

    n

    Poetics

    24

    may

    depend

    on

    associating

    W0os

    with

    a

    quieter

    emotional level. This

    distinction between Ethos

    and

    Pathos does not

    seem

    to

    occur in the

    Rhetorica;

    t

    is

    however

    present,

    without

    being

    used

    to

    definethe

    terms,

    n

    Cicero as

    in

    Dionysius. Compare Dionysius De Dem. 8,

    in which

    IG0KK

    s the

    last of

    a

    parallel sequence 1Xap

    ...

    vetLvy...

    .EZ6a

    contrasted

    with

    7raOI7tK';

    or ib.

    43:

    r7d

    V

    da'roTpayvvEL

    tE

    E

    L

    TLKpaLvEL

    rv

    aKO7V,

    r

    a

    rpavbEL

    KaL

    XEaLvEL,

    al

    7-t

    V

    i&

    7rOos

    KTpo7reL

    robs

    &KObOVT7s, &

    5'

    els

    'Oos brad'7yera.

    From

    Cicero,

    compare

    the

    contrast made in

    De Oratore

    .200:...

    generi

    orationis

    vehementi

    tque

    atroci

    genus

    illud

    alterum

    ..

    lenitatis t

    mansuetudinis,

    r

    212: in

    his

    duobus

    generibus uorum

    lterum

    ene,

    alterum

    vehemens sse volumus ..

    ,

    and

    the antithesis of

    asperitas

    contentioniswith

    remissio

    enitatis,

    r the comments n

    Orator

    128

    (above,

    note

    1).

    This content downloaded from 200.45.170.30 on Mon, 3 Nov 2014 23:33:24 PMAll use subject toJSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 7/17/2019 Ciceronian Conciliare and Aristotelian Ethos

    6/15

    266

    PHOENIX

    signa

    proferre

    f the end of

    182,

    and,

    at the same

    time,

    learly

    efers o

    the

    amiable

    qualities

    of

    the

    speaker

    himself.

    There are several confusionsatenthere: is Antoniusdiscussing he art

    of

    recommending

    he

    speaker,

    or the

    client? s he

    commenting

    n

    style,

    r

    content?

    he

    end

    of

    184 s

    clear n

    tself.

    Conciliare

    will nvolve

    portraying6

    by

    one's

    sentiments,

    tyle,

    and

    delivery,

    he

    excellenceof the

    speaker's

    character, straightforward

    iece

    of

    self-dramatisation

    y

    the orator

    as

    his

    own

    playwright

    nd

    performer.

    ore

    difficults

    the

    entence

    beginning

    horum

    gitur xprimere

    mores,

    oth n its relation

    o the end of

    182,

    and

    to

    the

    placida,

    summissa,

    enis

    oratio ecommended

    n 183.

    If we take

    signa

    proferre

    n 182 in the

    sense first

    roposed,

    displaying

    marksof the

    orator's

    own good qualities,this is consistentwiththe end of 184, and withthe

    emphasis

    on

    style

    and

    manner

    mpliedby

    placida,

    summissa,

    enis oratio.

    This

    then

    eems

    to be the

    sense

    required.

    But how can the

    orator

    express

    the excellent

    characterof

    his

    client

    n

    his

    speech

    by placida,

    summissa,

    lenis... oratio?

    That

    is,

    by

    his

    style

    and

    delivery?

    This

    presupposes

    an

    amazing

    degree

    f dentification etween

    patron

    and

    client;

    without

    t the

    orator

    can

    express

    his

    client's merits

    only

    by explicit

    statements

    bout

    them.

    In

    this

    difficulty

    oth

    the double

    meaning

    of

    lenis,

    passing

    from

    morality

    o

    style,

    and Cicero's

    own

    intense

    faith

    n

    the

    effect f

    style,

    influencehis

    statements;

    but it

    would seem

    that the initial

    distinction

    betweencommendation

    f the

    speaker

    himself,

    nd

    of the

    client,

    has not

    been

    maintained,

    nor

    ts

    implications

    onsistently

    xplored.

    n

    the atter

    part

    of

    this

    paper

    I

    shall

    argue

    that the

    distinction

    ailsto

    be

    maintained

    because

    it was irrelevant o

    Cicero's Aristotelian

    ource,

    and

    has

    been

    grafted

    y

    Cicero onto a

    presentation

    n

    quite

    different

    erms.

    More

    problems

    arise from

    the later references o this function

    n

    Antonius'account

    of

    his

    great

    defence f

    Norbanus

    (200

    ff.).

    quod

    ubi sensi me in

    possessionem

    udicii

    ac

    defensionis

    meae

    constitisse,

    uod

    et

    populi

    benevolentiam mihi

    conciliaram,...

    et

    iudicum

    animos

    totos...

    ad

    causam nostram

    converteram,

    um

    dmiscere

    huic

    generi

    rationisvehementi

    tque

    atroci

    genus

    illud

    alterum,

    de

    quo

    ante

    disputavi,

    lenitatis et

    mansuetudinis

    coepi.

    Paradoxically

    n

    this

    passage

    the

    conciliaram lause is associated

    with

    the

    violent and emotive

    function,

    while

    the

    characteristic

    enitas

    f technical

    conciliare

    omes

    second,

    associated with

    Antonius'

    vindication

    f his own

    role

    as

    defending

    ounsel,

    and consists

    only

    of

    winning

    he

    goodwill

    f

    the

    audience forthepatronus.This is confirmed y the later sentence (201)

    where

    the

    antithesis

    commendatio: oncitatio

    orresponds

    o

    ut

    mansue-

    6Exprimere

    nd

    ejingere

    both

    belong

    to

    the

    vocabulary

    of

    the

    plastic

    arts;

    ef. Austin

    on

    Pro

    Caelio

    12,

    non

    expressa

    sed adumbrata

    igna

    virtutum

    notes,

    p.

    60);

    Ac.

    1.27,

    e

    qua

    omnia

    expressa

    atque

    eficta sint;

    N.D.

    1.47,

    cum

    artificium

    ffingitisabricamque

    divinam;

    Off.

    .69,

    solidam

    atque

    expressam

    figiem,

    nd

    De

    Orat.

    3.15,

    in

    quibus

    omnibus

    fere ocrates

    exprimitur,

    f

    personal

    portrayal

    through anguage.

    This content downloaded from 200.45.170.30 on Mon, 3 Nov 2014 23:33:24 PMAll use subject toJSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 7/17/2019 Ciceronian Conciliare and Aristotelian Ethos

    7/15

    CICERONIAN CONCILIARE AND ARISTOTELIAN

    ETHOS

    267

    tissimus

    viderer nd

    ut et

    acerrimus

    in

    Caepionis

    invidia

    renovanda

    (viderer).

    hus

    in

    practice

    Antonius'

    technique

    does not

    conform

    o

    the

    theoretical oleofconciliare s presenting he mores fthe defendantn a

    favourable

    ight,

    while the

    emotivedefence

    f

    seditio

    s

    actually

    described

    by

    a

    contradictory,

    on-technical se

    of

    conciliare.

    Similarly

    nalysis

    of

    the

    emotions o

    be

    roused eads to

    a

    conflicting

    se

    of

    conciliare

    n

    the idiom amorem onciliare

    206):

    in

    the discussion

    on

    arousing

    the

    affection

    f

    the

    udges

    in

    206-208,

    the

    first ection of

    the

    catalogue

    of

    emotions,

    Cicero

    s

    basically

    repeating

    he

    aims

    and

    methods

    included

    n

    the function f

    conciliare

    n 182-184.

    Confronted

    by

    this

    overlap

    Cicero

    reveals his embarrassment

    n

    212.

    He has ended theaccount of the emotivefunctionn 206-211with nvidia

    (210)

    and misericordia

    211),

    and his demands made

    upon

    the

    speaker

    enable him

    to reiterate n

    211

    the

    distinctionmade

    in 201

    between

    the

    commendatio

    robitatis,

    hich

    hould be

    lenis

    .

    .

    atque

    ummissa,

    nd

    the

    (pars)

    quae

    suscipitur

    ab

    oratore d

    commutandos nimos

    atque

    omni

    rationeflectendos,

    hich

    should

    be

    intenta c

    vehemens. ut he

    has

    finally

    to

    admit the

    overlap

    of

    categories.

    est

    quaedam

    in

    his duobus

    generibus,

    uorum

    alterum

    ene,

    alterum

    vehemens

    sse

    volumus,

    difficilis d distinguendum imilitudo;nam et ex illa lenitate, qua conciliamur eis, qui

    audiunt,

    ad

    hanc vim

    acerrimam,

    ua

    eosdem

    excitamus,

    nfluat portet liquid

    ...

    neque

    est

    ulla

    temperatior

    ratio

    uam

    lla,

    n

    qua

    asperitas

    ontentionisratoris

    psius

    humanitate

    conditur,

    emissio

    autem lenitatis

    quadam

    gravitate

    t

    contentione

    irmatur

    212).

    The

    discussion s

    already taking

    another

    direction,

    s the

    reference

    o

    humanitas

    shows;

    and Cicero

    is

    leading

    off

    gradually

    towards

    Caesar

    Strabo's

    digression

    n

    wit,

    but

    before

    he

    leaves the

    psychological

    func-

    tions

    he

    makes

    one final

    comment

    216).

    illa autem, quae aut conciliationis causa leniter aut permotionisvehementerguntur,

    contrariis

    commotionibus

    uferenda

    sunt,

    ut

    odio

    benevolentia,

    ut

    misericordij

    invidia

    tollatur.

    Conciliatio

    has

    here

    become

    merely

    a

    label

    for

    one

    section of

    movere;

    that

    part

    whose business t is

    to stir

    up friendly

    r

    favourable

    motions,

    and

    can be

    cancelled

    by

    arousing

    contrary

    motions.What

    started

    as

    an

    apparently

    ndependent

    spect

    of the

    orator's

    skill,

    with a

    differentunc-

    tion from he

    emotiverole of

    movere,

    as

    been

    transformednto

    the

    gentler

    sub-group

    ncluded

    n

    the wider

    range

    of

    movere.

    he

    descriptive

    ole of

    conciliare,

    ts connectionwith

    characterisation

    y

    style

    and

    content of

    (a)

    the

    patron

    and

    (b)

    the

    client,

    has been

    blurred

    y

    the

    application

    f

    the

    same

    term

    o

    a

    category

    f

    the more

    mportant

    motion-rousing

    unction

    in

    the

    longer

    following

    ection.

    Why

    does Cicero

    choose the

    term

    onciliare o

    distinguish

    his

    eparate

    characterising

    function?

    After

    all,

    the

    verb

    clearly

    implies

    a

    form of

    This content downloaded from 200.45.170.30 on Mon, 3 Nov 2014 23:33:24 PMAll use subject toJSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 7/17/2019 Ciceronian Conciliare and Aristotelian Ethos

    8/15

    268

    PHOENIX

    acting

    upon

    the

    emotions,

    ifferingnly

    n

    intensity

    f

    passion

    from

    ther

    forms

    f

    movere.

    e

    does

    not seem to

    rely

    on

    any

    philosophical

    istinction,

    such

    as that conciliare

    cts

    upon

    the

    reason,

    movere

    pon

    the

    emotions;

    the

    only

    hint

    of such a distinction ies in the

    phrases

    nclinatio

    voluntatis

    as

    opposed

    to

    permotio

    nimi

    in

    129

    above.

    If both functions re

    emotive,

    why keep

    them

    distinct?

    The

    only special

    quality

    of the

    conciliare-

    function s

    its

    descriptive

    ontent.

    The choice of

    terminology

    ecomes more

    meaningful

    f

    we turn

    to

    consider

    (a)

    the classification

    of Cicero's ultimate

    or direct

    source,

    Aristotle,

    in

    his

    analysis

    of

    rhetorical

    proofs,

    and

    (b)

    the

    different

    circumstances nd values

    of

    oratory

    ssumed

    by

    the Greek

    and Roman

    critics.

    In

    his introduction

    o

    the

    Rhetorica,

    ristotle

    istinguishes

    hree

    kinds

    of

    bEXvoL

    t1orELS

    (1.2.1356

    1-4):

    a')

    al

    t

    y&p

    low

    v

    $7v

    1W0^et

    0

    XM'ovos,

    a(')

    it

    7T

    T6

    Tpoa)vKLaOLVtatl

    rws,

    Y')

    C4

    Av

    brW

    o

    6yCy,

    bd

    ro

    5ELKVubVaz

    aiLveaOa E5KVbva.

    e

    then

    comments

    n

    the

    rLoTeLs

    &&& o

    0ovys,

    describing

    hem

    s

    b0av

    oT'r

    Xex05

    6

    X6'yos OTeE

    Al6rtTrov

    roL7aL

    rTv

    Xeyovra.

    Tots

    ydp

    erieMLEKEaL

    rLaoebOAev

    XXOV

    Kal

    OTTov

    ... et Kal

    roVro

    avpalvl

    tv

    ik&V

    X6yov,

    &,XX,&

    b&d

    6

    rpobebo?&o0aL

    ovbyWta

    tva

    TbV

    XMyovra.

    ....

    &XX& xeb6V

    cr

    E

    reV KvpLWTrr)YV

    XEL

    rTv

    T740os

    (1356

    a

    5-15).7

    The

    speech

    mustbeuttered o as to makethe orator

    &dAerutros

    compare

    Cicero's

    adfidemfaciendam,

    .121).

    This element

    n

    the

    definition

    ecurs

    in Rhet. 1.9.1366 a

    34;

    2.1.1378 a 19 f.

    There

    is

    emphasis

    on

    the

    need

    for

    brLeLtKeLa8

    compare

    Cicero's use

    of

    lenis,

    lenitas, 2.128, 182,

    etc.);

    the

    problem

    is

    to make

    himself

    appear

    7rotov

    rva;

    this recurs

    in

    Rhet.

    1.9.1366

    a

    30;

    2.1.1378

    a

    22

    (roCovrov).

    side

    referencen 1.8.1366

    a

    12

    f.

    ties

    up

    this

    type

    of

    proof

    with the

    1j0l

    of

    states and

    constitutions,

    making

    it clear

    that

    the orator

    should know

    the nature and

    aims

    of a

    state,

    so

    7On

    the use of

    '0os

    in

    Aristotle's

    Rhetorica,

    ee

    E.

    M.

    Cope,

    Introduction o

    Aristotle's

    Rhetoric

    London

    1867)

    110-113. He

    distinguishes

    hree

    applications

    of the

    word.

    (1)

    the

    present

    reference,

    g0os

    Cv

    7TY

    X&yoV'T

    (2)

    "The

    character

    of

    constitutions

    or

    formsof

    government

    and

    of

    the

    different

    eriods

    of

    life,

    youth,

    manhood..,

    .and so

    forth;

    (these)

    are to

    be

    studied

    for

    he

    purpose

    of

    accommodating

    our

    language

    to the

    tone

    and

    sentiments

    prevailing

    under certain

    forms of

    government,

    and

    characteristic

    of,

    or

    peculiar

    to,

    certain

    ages

    and

    conditions

    of

    life,

    and

    thereby

    conciliating

    the

    audience,

    when

    it

    happens

    to

    be

    composed

    of

    members

    of

    one or

    other

    of

    these

    classes."

    (3)

    i0os

    belonging

    to

    style;

    this

    appears

    only

    in

    Book 3

    (see

    pp.

    271-272

    below).

    8Aristotle's discussion of

    ?brclKeta

    in

    1.13.1374

    a

    30

    f.

    starts from

    this

    definition:

    Tar

    8~

    rteKrs

    T6

    rap&

    T6V

    vyeYpappvZO

    V

    V61o

    V&

    LKCatoV

    see

    Cope,

    op.

    cit.

    [above,

    note

    7]

    190-193).

    This

    is

    very

    close

    to

    his

    definition f the

    brnKEKIs

    n

    Eth.Nic.

    1137

    b

    34

    f.:

    6

    ICt)

    &KpqfoiKatos~

    ~a

    76

    XELpov.

    But

    the

    adjective

    (and

    noun)

    had a

    wider

    sense

    in

    general

    Greek

    usage,

    as a

    basic word of

    social

    recommendation,

    ike

    gentlemanly,

    respectable;

    so

    Socrates in

    Apol.

    22

    a

    5,

    36

    c

    1

    opposes

    it to

    caDXos

    (see

    Burnet

    ad

    loc.).

    In

    Aristotle

    too,

    where

    hrLEteK7'

    explains

    &L6brtLtros

    n

    Rhet.

    1.2.1356 a

    7,

    it is

    genera-

    lised.

    On

    its

    range,

    and

    relationship

    with

    enis

    see

    p.

    263

    above.

    This content downloaded from 200.45.170.30 on Mon, 3 Nov 2014 23:33:24 PMAll use subject toJSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 7/17/2019 Ciceronian Conciliare and Aristotelian Ethos

    9/15

    CICERONIAN

    CONCILIARE AND

    ARISTOTELIAN ETHOS

    269

    as

    to

    be ableto

    ssume

    imilar

    0G

    imself:

    T6

    hv

    'p

    K&rrTs

    30os

    ravW7arov

    &ddVY4l

    r1

    s

    e&Kar4v7

    tvac.

    is

    analysis

    f

    virtue

    n

    1.9. eads

    to a

    comment

    on thevalue of thisanalysis or he

    5evrTpa

    7rLrTas:

    vUCf7ieraL

    p

    &Jaa

    irept

    robrvTWXeyovTra K&KEWila 7IXOv 4v

    irotoi

    r

    wes

    broXn-Orlb06~E0a aTA

    7T

    10os,

    i

    7rep

    v bevrTepa

    irtrtLs.

    TK

    r7y

    Tbr&v

    ydp

    Lav rTE&Kal

    XXov

    d&AtrwTroV

    5vvba6;eOa

    7rotety

    rpbs

    ApETr'

    1366

    a

    29-33).

    Facts

    about

    virtue,

    asically

    seful

    or

    raising

    thers

    (Tr

    'trawoiVTr,

    1366

    29),

    will nable he rator o

    represent

    imselfs virtuous. ristotle

    subsequently

    oncentrates

    n

    the

    ogical roofs,eaving

    he

    bevrEpa

    iLrTLS

    until

    Book

    2.

    This

    begins

    2.1)

    by distinguishing

    ntellectualrommoral

    proofs.

    hen

    he

    repeats

    he

    mportant

    lements

    f

    his

    riginal

    efinitionf

    the

    7rLaTLrs

    v

    7

    Oet:

    av&dyKrl

    .

    .Kal

    abrVT6robv

    rTa alIv

    ,V

    rpLTV

    aratKEV6AEW

    roXZ

    yap &badpet

    7rpbs

    7rLTW,

    &XATcraAvV ra

    ts

    at

    ovXaZs,

    dra

    Kal

    v

    raTs

    tKas r6rOSby

    tva

    6atv'elaua M'XOTra

    Kal

    r

    6rpbs

    aCbrobs

    V7roXaI3cz'vEU

    XEtU

    7rws

    abrT6

    (2.1.1377

    24-29).

    This

    type

    f

    proof,

    hen,

    epends

    n

    two

    hings:

    he

    haracter

    hich he

    orator

    resents

    n

    his

    peech,

    nd

    the

    ttitude owards

    he

    udiencewith

    which

    he

    represents

    imself.

    hese

    are

    elaborated n

    2.1.1378a7f.:

    r70o

    I

    .LV abrobStvaL

    rtrobs obsMyovras

    rpLarL

    rdTLrTa..rT.

    .

    Tapra 6pbV7it

    Kat

    l ET

    Kaltivota.

    ollowing

    his,

    n 1378

    19,

    Aristotle

    refers

    he

    reader ack to

    1.9

    for he

    means

    by

    which

    rators an make

    themselves

    ppear

    6pbpveo al

    rovbatot.

    The

    question

    f

    presenting

    ne's

    eDvota

    s

    to be

    studied

    n

    the

    section

    n

    7raif0.

    his is

    generallygreed

    o

    refer he

    readerforward

    o the

    sectionon

    OXla,

    n 2.4

    (1380

    b

    43-

    1381

    b,

    end).

    The whole

    nature f

    this

    proof

    onsists

    n

    portrayal

    r

    description;

    resenting

    he

    speaker

    n

    a

    certain

    ight;

    he

    evoLa

    t

    issue

    is

    the

    speaker's

    wn

    (real

    or

    supposed)

    goodwill

    o the

    audience,

    not

    theirs owards im. pecificoncernwithwinningheir

    eivota,

    heequi-

    valent

    fCiceronian

    onciliare,

    lthough

    his

    s

    the

    underlying

    otive

    f

    the

    rLrTa

    s

    Tod0

    ovs,

    s not

    discussed ere.

    When

    Aristotle

    omes

    o

    discuss

    OtXMa

    n

    2.4.,

    he

    does

    so

    analytically,

    without

    tating

    motive

    r

    application;

    t

    s

    merely

    ne

    of

    he

    r6.

    which

    the

    oratormust

    knowhow

    to

    rouse.

    n

    one

    sense sizable

    proportion

    f

    this

    hapter

    eflectshe

    ssue

    f

    ivoca

    nderlying

    he econd

    roof,

    or

    is

    emphasis

    s

    repeatedly

    n

    the

    tXla

    men

    feel

    for

    hose

    whose ttitude o

    themselves

    nd their

    oyalties

    s

    favourable.

    e

    has

    ncluded

    his

    hapterto satisfywoneedsoftheorator: a) accordingo itsclassification,o

    show

    by

    what

    persons

    nd causes

    he

    r&0o

    f

    tXta

    s roused:hence

    how

    can

    the

    speaker

    rouse

    t

    in

    the

    audience,

    owards

    thers r

    towards

    himself?

    b)

    to

    satisfy

    he

    reference

    rom

    .1.1378

    22-3:

    what

    s

    tXtta

    like?

    Hence howcan

    the

    peaker

    ortray

    imselfo show hat

    he

    feels t

    towards

    the

    audience? Yet it

    should

    be

    noted that the

    words

    Evovs,

    ivoLa

    This content downloaded from 200.45.170.30 on Mon, 3 Nov 2014 23:33:24 PMAll use subject toJSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 7/17/2019 Ciceronian Conciliare and Aristotelian Ethos

    10/15

    270

    PHOENIX

    do not occur even

    once.

    That

    is, although

    Aristotle

    has referred

    he

    readers

    to

    this

    section

    for

    he

    technique

    of

    making

    oneself

    ppear

    edvous,

    he has formulated hechapterto illustrate

    rdos,

    and has notadapted it

    to

    the

    needs

    of

    the

    taTsLu

    be

    ro

    i^0ovs.

    The

    later sections

    2.12-17,

    on

    the characteristics ssociated with

    age,

    class,

    and

    fortune,

    re

    designed

    to

    continue he

    analysis

    of motions

    n

    the

    audience so that the

    speaker

    may

    know how

    to

    appeal

    to

    the

    type

    of

    audience he

    is

    dealing

    with.

    It

    is

    a

    discussion

    of

    4,

    in

    one

    sense,

    but

    is

    aimed

    at

    the

    third,

    emotive

    category

    of

    proof.

    Yet

    M6d6ric

    Dufour

    (Aristote:

    Rhitorique

    ivre

    2

    [Paris

    1960]

    ntroduction

    9)

    is too

    absolute

    in

    denying

    ts

    relevanceto

    the

    rlrn

    tLT

    roDT

    0ovs.Cope

    (Introduction

    o

    Aristotle'sRhetoric, 10) points to the directions n 2.13.1390 a 29-33,

    oTe

    fre t

    t?ldroexovral

    rdlres

    obs

    7T^o

    bTerTpqy

    Oe

    XeyopJEovsO

    6

    OV

    Kal

    robs

    6Solovs

    bK

    87Xov

    ws

    XpCopeV0oOTs

    67yos

    roLDroT

    avodWvra

    Oal

    TO

    Kal

    o

    X6roL.

    This makes

    the

    same

    connection

    with ethical"

    proof

    s

    in

    1.8.1366

    a

    12

    (above,

    page

    268).

    Thus when

    n

    2.18.1391

    b

    34

    Aristotle

    tates

    rnt

    '

    W

    V

    GOLKobs

    obs

    X6yovs

    WxeraL

    roteY,

    Kai

    rept

    Trovrwcv

    &6opwrat,

    t is

    reasonable

    to take

    ?70LKobs9

    s

    covering

    oth

    he

    rtLarets

    t

    ro4Oovs

    and

    those

    tIv

    os

    rar0eat;

    orhe

    has

    used the

    analytical

    material f 2.4.

    and

    2.12-17 to

    equip

    the

    peaker

    withboth

    ategories

    f

    proof.

    O90n

    he

    range

    of

    meaning

    of

    710LK6s

    n

    Aristotle's

    Rhetorica,

    ee

    Lockwood in

    CQ

    23

    (1929)

    180-181.He

    analyses

    hree

    passages

    ncluded

    n this

    discussion,

    nd

    suggests

    three

    eparate

    usages

    for

    the

    word,

    which

    do

    not,

    however

    orrespond

    o

    the

    three

    distinct ses

    of

    i0os

    listed

    n

    note

    7.

    (1)

    In

    3.7.1408 22

    f.,

    the

    adjective

    s

    applied

    to

    speech

    n

    character

    morata

    ratio

    the

    third

    se

    of

    80os).

    2)

    In

    2.18.1391

    29,

    t s

    rather

    "adapted

    to

    the

    character f

    the

    audience

    o

    whom

    t is

    addressed"

    the

    second

    use

    of

    ~Oos).

    He

    does

    not

    discuss

    heuse of

    OmLKbs

    n

    2.18.1391

    b 34.

    (3)

    In

    2.21.1395

    b

    17,

    t

    is

    connected

    ith

    2rpoalpeors,

    nd

    related

    o a

    man's

    rtXos.

    Here

    t s

    "moral,"

    of

    moral

    value,"or"tomark particular oral haracter."This sequally he ase n3.16.1417

    20,

    on

    7'0LKJL

    7,cyfls,

    not

    considered

    by Lockwood,

    whereas in

    1417

    a

    27

    10LK.d

    re

    utterancesn

    character,

    s

    at

    3.7.1408

    22

    above.)

    Some

    additional

    omments

    re

    needed.

    Lockwood

    ignores

    .8.1366

    a

    12:

    brel

    6'

    ob

    pb6o'

    at

    trLerEtsylouraW

    .'

    ro6EfrtKKo

    6yo

    V

    XXa

    Kal

    W&'

    076LK0o

    r~

    y^p

    roL

    va

    a

    alveo-Oa&

    pXb

    Myovra

    Lretebopev,

    roro

    6'

    EOr

    Wv

    &

    dyaObs

    qathlnra&

    depovs

    &JAow),

    bo&

    &

    a

    d

    T

    7i1j

    ,

    roXLrecwu

    pKaars

    xew

    ~

    IES.

    Here

    the

    adjective

    s

    specifically

    pplied

    o

    the

    9Oos

    f

    the

    peaker,

    hefirst

    sage

    of

    70os

    listed

    by

    Cope.

    This

    appears

    o

    be the

    nly

    nstancen

    the

    Rhetorica,

    nd

    theuse

    s

    adjectival,

    nd

    has

    not

    yet

    taken

    n

    an

    independent

    ife

    s a

    noun,

    which

    may

    be the

    ase n

    Orator

    28

    (above,

    note

    1).

    Lockwood

    oints

    ut that

    0mLK6bis notrecordednAst, ndapparentlynotused

    by

    Plato. Aristotleeemsto use

    it as

    an

    innovation, espite

    previous

    ccur-

    rences

    n, e.g.,

    the

    Poetics

    ch.

    24),

    and

    s careful o

    associate

    t

    with

    ts root

    noun

    0os.

    In

    2.21.1359 17

    and

    3.7.1408 22

    f.,

    nd

    16,

    1417

    20

    and

    27, although

    ifferent

    ses

    of

    0bLK6s

    re

    involved,

    t

    is

    supported

    by

    references o

    70os

    EXetw,

    r

    roL~elI.

    It

    seems

    that

    whatever

    0os

    rOLte

    makes

    speech

    770LK6v;

    whatever

    i0os

    9XEL

    s itself

    7706KbP.

    hus in

    1.8.1366

    12

    and

    2.18.1391

    b 34

    O&Kd6s

    67os

    reflects

    he

    30os

    of

    either

    peaker

    r

    audience.

    This content downloaded from 200.45.170.30 on Mon, 3 Nov 2014 23:33:24 PMAll use subject toJSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 7/17/2019 Ciceronian Conciliare and Aristotelian Ethos

    11/15

    CICERONIAN

    CONCILIARE AND ARISTOTELIAN

    ETHOS

    271

    Unlike

    the recommendations

    f

    Cicero,

    Aristotle's ccount

    s

    entirely

    n

    terms

    f

    representation: escription

    f the orator'scharacter

    nd

    attitude.

    The Ciceronian mphasison theact ofconciliare, fwinning enevolence,

    has converted

    the

    unstressed

    motive

    of

    Aristotle's

    proof

    nto

    its

    actual

    method.At the

    same

    time,

    he Aristotelian

    iscussion f contenthas

    been

    largely

    displaced by

    Cicero's

    emphasis

    on

    style

    and

    manner

    of

    delivery.

    There is

    another

    major

    difference.

    ristotle

    enerally peaks

    as

    though

    the orator

    s

    acting

    on

    his

    own

    behalf,

    nd excludes

    the client

    element.

    n

    deliberative

    oratory,

    in which as Aristotle

    says

    (2.1.1356

    a

    15)

    the

    speaker's t0os

    s

    most

    mportant,

    here

    s

    no

    client,

    nd

    normally

    no

    other

    party

    to

    defend

    r

    support.

    n

    forensic

    ratory

    n

    Greece,

    the

    speech

    was

    normally eliveredbythedefendant, o that fthe oratorwas nothimself

    the

    defendant

    Aristotle's

    remarks

    would

    have to be

    applied

    to

    the

    defendant s

    speaker

    of

    the

    orator's words.

    K.

    J.

    Dover,

    in

    Lysias

    and

    the

    CorpusLysiacum

    Berkeley

    1968),

    Chapter

    8,

    pp.

    149-150,

    discusses the

    circumstances

    overning

    consultant's

    decision whether

    o

    speak

    in his

    own

    person

    for

    he

    defendant,

    r

    to write

    speech

    wholly

    r

    n

    part

    for he

    client to

    perform.

    ristotle akes

    no

    notice

    of

    this ssue

    in

    Books

    1

    and

    2

    of

    the

    Rhetorica,

    n

    connectionwith

    90os.

    The

    sole

    references

    o a

    client-

    figure

    are

    fK

    c7v

    ar&Pvydp

    a^ts

    rTE

    alc

    AXXoprv

    lOttrLtT0o

    8vvf67Oa0a troseT rpbs

    cpEripv

    1.9.1366

    32),

    and

    (in

    a referenceackto

    1.9)

    EK

    7'Wv 'brTWvp

    KAP

    Tep6v 7LS

    &Y

    avrbv

    aaaKEvae

    Le

    r7Lorop

    2.1.1378 21-22).

    He

    does not

    regard

    he

    client,

    ither

    s

    subject

    or

    performer

    f the

    speech,

    s a

    significant

    lement

    n

    his

    discussion."'

    In

    his earlier ook

    The

    Art

    of

    Persuasion

    n

    Greece

    Princeton

    963),

    pp.

    91-92,

    Kennedy

    aw a reference

    o

    this

    ype

    f

    composition

    or

    client-speaker

    n

    Rhet.

    .7.

    'HOoroda,

    he

    stylistic

    haracterisation

    f a

    client-speaker,

    as

    practised yLysias

    ong

    before

    he

    omposition

    f he

    Rhetorica,nd is described y Dionysius fHalicarnassusnLys. 8 ff.

    What

    Aristotle

    says

    in

    3.7.1408 a

    24

    is:

    r&Oavo

    T

    7b

    rpa-Aa

    Kal

    7 oIKELa

    ts~

    ...

    (6)

    Kcl

    1OLKU1

    LiT

    7

    EK

    rL'v

    cfr/ELCEov

    EL,

    05

    &KOXOVOEJL

    &pJ6r77ovaa

    dtaryq've&L

    al

    ies,

    uchas the

    anguage

    ppropriate

    o a

    Spartan,

    r

    Thessalian,

    r

    a

    woman.He

    adds

    (1408

    30)

    MAv

    i

    Kal

    d

    ra

    v6Para

    iLca1a

    Xy

    7~

    e,

    roL~

    r

    b

    Oos.

    ob

    ydp

    7rabr7

    obby'

    raabros

    ypoPos

    Av

    Kai

    reraLbev8J.Lvo

    Zlretev.

    There

    need be no

    reference here to

    language

    as

    designed

    to

    characterise

    he

    speaker,

    as there

    was

    in

    the

    account of

    X~cts

    ,raf7O7Ki

    in the

    preceding

    section

    (1408

    a

    20-24).

    Instead Aristotle

    is

    "oCompare

    ennedy,

    The

    Rhetoric

    f

    Advocacy,"

    20-421.He

    shows

    hat

    lthough

    Aristotle

    wice

    n

    the

    Rhetorica

    efers

    o

    anecdotes n

    which

    specific

    dvocate

    poke

    himself or

    his

    client

    1.13.1374

    36;

    2.20.1393

    b

    22-23)

    he

    "never

    discusses he

    varied

    possibilities

    hich

    dvocacymight

    pen"

    . .

    "in

    rhetorical

    heory

    he

    itigant

    s as-

    sumedto

    speak

    for

    himself,

    resumably

    ecause this

    s the basic

    situation n

    a

    Greek

    court."

    This content downloaded from 200.45.170.30 on Mon, 3 Nov 2014 23:33:24 PMAll use subject toJSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 7/17/2019 Ciceronian Conciliare and Aristotelian Ethos

    12/15

    272

    PHOENIX

    discussing

    how to make

    language

    fitting

    o

    a

    Spartan,

    Thessalian,

    or

    a

    woman.

    But women and

    foreigners

    ould

    not

    plead

    their wn

    cases,

    so

    Aristotlecannot be discussinghow to characterise client,but rather

    how to

    include

    narrative

    uotations

    n

    the

    style

    of

    those

    quoted.

    This is

    apparent

    in

    Kennedy's

    second reference

    3.16.1417

    a

    27),

    aXX&

    7'7LK6d

    Tr6peva

    &T1rq

    0 Oe,

    olov

    b~

    Ita

    Xycowv

    aLObt?e:

    this

    technique

    of

    charac-

    terisation

    s foruse in

    narrative,

    when a

    third

    party

    has

    to

    be

    portrayed.

    This was

    seen

    quite

    clearly by Cope

    (Introduction

    o

    Aristotle's

    hetoric,

    112):

    "The third

    variety

    of

    0Oos...

    belongs

    to

    style,

    and

    accordingly

    appears

    only

    n book 3 .... It occurs

    usually,

    and

    is most

    appropriate

    n

    the second

    division

    of the

    speech,

    &t?irttEs

    r

    narrative."

    It would seemthen thatin theRhetoricaAristotle oes notdiscuss the

    implications

    f

    the

    orator-client

    elationship,

    either

    ssuming

    the

    client

    as

    possible

    speaker,

    nor

    giving

    more

    than

    minimal

    ttention o the

    type

    of

    oratory

    which

    nvolvesdefence f

    another.The

    double role of

    depicting

    the

    character

    nd attitudeof both

    speaker

    and client

    would

    be

    more

    rare

    in Greek

    courts,

    nd is

    not

    thereforen

    issue n the

    Rhetorica.

    Whether r

    not his

    interests

    re

    primarily

    n

    deliberative

    ratory,

    Aristotle

    makes

    it

    clear

    that this

    type

    of

    oratory

    s

    the

    main field

    f

    the

    7rlo~s

    Ld

    70rov

    0ovs,

    so

    that

    the

    t0os

    to be

    represented

    s

    that

    of

    one

    man,

    the

    orator.

    Comparing

    the Ciceronian withthe

    Aristotelian

    resentation,

    we can

    see

    that Cicero's

    difficulties

    ave

    arisen

    for

    four

    easons.

    1)

    Since

    Cicero

    sets

    his comments

    n the contextof

    forensic,

    ot

    deliberative

    ratory,

    he

    has

    to accommodate

    them to

    Roman

    forensic

    practice.

    Unless the

    defendantwas himself n

    orator

    such

    as

    Caelius

    Rufus,

    who

    spoke

    in

    his

    own defencede

    vi,

    56

    B.c.),

    this

    always

    entailed

    a

    distinction

    etweenthe

    patronus,

    speaking

    in

    his

    own

    person,

    and the

    client;

    hence

    conciliare

    involved

    a

    double

    function,

    f

    creating

    credit for the

    character

    and

    attitudes of both parties. (2) Cicero's choice of the verb conciliare,

    appropriate

    o the

    purpose

    of

    this,

    as also

    of

    other

    categories

    f

    proof,

    s

    too

    general,

    nd

    prevents

    him

    from

    istinguishing

    etween

    he

    descriptive

    role

    of

    the "ethical"

    proof,

    with

    its

    emphasis

    on

    ror6v

    uva

    salvea0at

    r

    XMyovra

    Rhet.

    2.1.137

    b

    27)

    and

    the

    emotive

    role

    of

    the

    7rior&

    ldl

    rWVP

    eKpoaracv

    Rhet.

    1.2.1356

    a

    15).

    It

    is

    probably

    awareness of

    this

    conver-

    gence

    of

    the two

    proofs

    n

    conciliare

    enevolentiam

    hich

    eads him to

    put

    Amor

    first n

    his list

    of

    emotions,

    whereasAristotle

    had

    begun

    with

    6pyq

    (2.2), passing

    on

    through

    ,rpapvE0ta

    o

    OItla,

    s the

    opposite

    2.3

    and

    4).

    NeverthelessheAristotelianescriptiverinciplesbroughtut nthe

    phrases

    exprimeremores,

    nd

    ut

    quasi

    mores

    ratoris

    Jfingat

    ratio

    2.184),

    and the

    expressed

    im

    ut

    probi,

    ut

    bene

    morati,

    t

    boni

    viri

    esse

    videamur.

    Videri is used

    again

    in

    201,

    ut

    ..

    mansuetissimus

    iderer,

    but the real

    counterpart

    to

    rotLb6

    va

    4alvpeOB

    comes in

    two

    earlier

    passages

    not

    explicitly

    ssociated

    with

    the verb

    conciliare,

    t

    1.89,

    ut

    et

    ipse

    eis

    apud

    This content downloaded from 200.45.170.30 on Mon, 3 Nov 2014 23:33:24 PMAll use subject toJSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 7/17/2019 Ciceronian Conciliare and Aristotelian Ethos

    13/15

    CICERONIAN CONCILIARE AND ARISTOTELIANETHOS

    273

    quos ageret

    alis

    qualem

    se esse

    optaret

    ideretur,

    t ut ei

    qui

    audirent

    ic

    adficerentur

    nimis

    ut

    eos

    adfici

    ellet,

    nd

    (virtually

    epeated)

    at

    2.176,

    in

    the transitionfromdocere o the other functions: i vero dsequetur, t

    talis videatur

    qualem

    se videri

    velit,

    et

    nimos

    orum

    ta

    adficiat,

    pud

    quos

    aget,

    ut

    eos

    quocumque

    velit

    vel trahere

    el

    rapere

    possit,

    nihil

    profecto

    d

    dicendum

    equiret.

    3)

    Aristotlehimselfmakes it

    difficult

    o

    discuss the

    question

    of

    qOLK6V

    learly,

    since

    he

    uses the same

    chapter

    (2.4.)

    as

    raw

    material for he

    two aims of

    (a)

    creating

    MXLa/eivota

    n the audience

    and

    (b)

    representing

    he

    duvoLa

    of

    the orator.

    This has

    a

    psychological

    ustifica-

    tion,

    since

    edora

    in the orator

    begets

    d5voza

    n

    the

    audience,

    but it

    may

    explain

    why

    Cicero's

    presentation

    of

    the two aims

    in

    Antonius' trial

    narrative, singthe same key-word,onciliare, orbothiOLuK6vnd partof

    7raOnpLK6V,

    as become

    inextricably

    onfused,

    and

    it

    contributes o

    the

    overlap

    of

    functions

    which

    causes

    him

    evident

    difficulty

    n

    211-212.

    (4)

    Finally,

    Cicero's

    professional

    ove

    of,

    and faith

    n,

    style,

    means

    that

    he

    sees

    style

    and

    delivery

    s

    a

    primary

    lement

    n

    the

    representation

    f

    the orator's

    enitas

    intended

    to

    translate

    irLLKELa).

    Now

    lenitas of

    style

    can indeed

    effingere

    ores

    oratoris,

    but

    barely

    exprimere

    mores of

    the

    client,

    as

    he

    seems

    to

    maintain

    in

    2.184.

    This

    difficulty

    as

    however

    nothing

    o

    do with

    7o0roda

    to

    suit

    the

    client,

    which

    as we have seen is

    absent

    from

    Aristotleand

    irrelevant o Roman

    practice.

    Roman

    taste

    admitted

    only

    one

    form

    f Ethos n

    this

    ense;

    that

    of

    the

    wise,

    good,

    and

    benevolent statesman

    (Aristotle's

    opo6vLwL,

    arov&saoL,

    nd

    edvoL

    f

    2.1.1378 a

    6

    f.).

    For

    Cicero a

    mild and

    virtuous

    tyle

    portrayed

    he

    Ethos

    of

    the

    orator,

    and would

    reflect ts

    excellence

    upon

    the

    client

    described

    and

    defended.

    The last two

    points require

    further

    omment

    n

    the

    light

    of

    Cicero's

    later

    practice.

    He

    obviously

    valued

    the

    implications

    of

    the

    verb con-

    ciliarewhenhe chose it to represent heAristotelian se ofEthos. Yet he

    uses

    it

    only

    once"

    afterDe

    Oratore

    n

    connection

    with

    this

    theme of the

    three functions.

    n

    Brutus,

    delectare12

    erforms

    his role in

    185,

    187-188,

    197,

    276

    (and

    compare

    322,

    where

    t

    is

    associated

    with the

    conciliatory

    effect

    f

    humour).

    Combined

    with

    delectare

    refidemfacere,

    87, 197,

    and

    animos

    a

    severitate

    raducere,

    97

    (cf.

    322

    again),

    animos

    devincire

    olup-

    "At

    Orator

    128,

    quoted

    in

    note

    1

    above. The

    index

    to Cicero's

    Rhetorica

    ists

    seven

    uses

    of the verb

    subsequent

    to De

    Oratore;

    of

    these three are in

    the idiom

    conciliare

    benevolen-

    tiam:

    Part. Or. 15.2; 28.7; Orator128.7 above. Add Part. Or. 53.2, c.fidem;Brut. 156.11,

    c.

    gratiam

    social,

    not

    rhetorical);

    Orator

    22.7,

    c.

    auditorem

    in

    the

    exordium);

    and

    162.10,

    c.

    voluptatem

    urium

    (on

    compositio).

    The noun

    conciliatio

    ccurs

    only

    n De

    Oratore:

    .216

    and

    2.292

    allude

    to this use of

    Ethos

    and mark

    the end of the

    topic

    of

    psychological

    proofs (216)

    and Antonius'

    recapitulation

    after

    the

    digression

    on

    humour;

    3.205 is

    general,

    in

    a

    long

    list

    of

    emotional

    devices.

    1sA.

    E.

    Douglas,

    Cicero: Brutus

    (Oxford

    1968)

    Intr.

    xxxv,

    no.

    28,

    is

    misleading;

    conciliare occurs in

    none of

    these

    passages.

    This content downloaded from 200.45.170.30 on Mon, 3 Nov 2014 23:33:24 PMAll use subject toJSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 7/17/2019 Ciceronian Conciliare and Aristotelian Ethos

    14/15

    274 PHOENIX

    tate,

    276.

    The different

    mphasis

    in the

    set-piece

    describing

    Crassus'

    famous

    speech

    in the civil causa Curiana

    at 197

    f.,

    the

    counterpart

    f

    Antonius'greatspeech forNorbanus described n De Orat.2.197 f.,may

    account

    for

    the choice of

    delectare,

    ince the issue

    in court

    was

    more

    academic,

    and less

    provocative;

    conciliare was

    not

    an

    urgent

    need.

    However,

    the absence

    of the

    verb

    from he

    other

    references

    o

    the

    three

    functions oes

    suggest

    deliberate

    avoidance

    of

    conciliare s a

    term.

    n

    De

    Optimo

    Genere nd

    in Orator

    lso,

    when Cicero

    distinguishes

    he

    three

    functions,

    e

    uses

    delectare

    or he

    second,

    most

    explicitly

    nd

    repeatedly

    at

    Orator

    69,

    wherehe elaborates

    this in the

    process

    of

    reconciling

    he

    three functions

    with

    the three

    genera:

    subtile

    n

    probando,

    modicum

    n

    delectando,vehemensnflectendo."1onciliareremainsabsent fromthe

    ensuing

    discussion,

    lthough

    t occurs

    casually

    in 122 as

    one

    of

    the

    three

    requirements

    f

    the

    exordium.

    The

    exception

    associated

    with

    Ethos is a

    brief

    llusion in

    128,

    where

    one

    paragraph

    covers

    Aristotle's

    econd and

    third

    proofs

    n a

    summary

    f

    miscellaneous

    heory

    121-128),

    opening

    the

    transition rom

    he first heme fOrator

    othe

    econd

    ection n

    compositio.

    This is

    already

    the

    pattern

    n

    the earlier

    Partitiones

    Oratoriae.When

    Cicero

    discusses the element

    of

    Ethos in

    oratory

    n

    22,

    the

    key

    word

    is

    delectat... oratio .quae significatratoris psius amabilismores.Con-

    ciliare s

    reserved

    for

    he

    specific

    enevolentiam

    onciliare f

    the

    exordium

    (15,

    28)

    and

    for

    the

    amplificatio

    n

    the

    peroration

    which

    (53)

    motu

    animorum

    onciliet n

    dicendo

    idem-surely

    a

    case of

    movere,

    he

    third

    function

    hus this

    special

    use

    of

    conciliare

    apses

    after

    De

    Oratore,

    which

    would

    suggest

    that

    Cicero

    became

    dissatisfied

    with

    the

    term

    ome

    time

    beforehe took

    the further

    tep

    of

    modifying

    he

    three

    functions

    o

    fit he

    three

    tyles

    n

    Orator.We

    may

    then

    be

    ustified

    n

    explaining

    he

    substitu-

    tion

    of

    delectare

    with or

    without

    idem

    acere

    by

    the

    difficulties

    e ex-

    perienced n the application of conciliare n De Oratore, s at 211-212

    above.

    Certainly

    andys

    is

    right

    o

    note on

    Orator 9

    that

    delectare

    as

    no

    connection

    with

    the

    Aristotelian

    riors

    td

    roD

    fliovs

    nd "in

    Aristotle's

    view is

    strictly

    speaking

    superfluous,"

    but

    mistaken in

    denying

    an

    original

    connection

    between

    the

    Ciceronian

    functions

    nd

    Aristotelian

    Pisteis;

    the

    original

    term

    onciliare,

    s

    used

    in

    De

    Oratore,

    was

    chosen to

    laSee

    A.

    E.

    Douglas,

    "A

    Ciceronian

    ontribution

    o

    Rhetorical

    heory,"

    ranos

    55

    (1957) 18-26,

    whose

    account I follow n the chronologyof Cicero's changing approach

    to

    the three

    functions.

    He

    does

    not,

    however,

    comment

    on

    the

    replacement

    of

    conciliare

    by

    delectare;

    s in

    the

    reference

    uoted

    in

    note

    12,

    he

    treats

    the

    two

    verbs

    as

    equivalent.

    This

    article

    seems

    to

    have been

    neglected

    by

    recent

    scholarship

    e.g.,

    Kennedy,

    The Art

    of

    Rhetoric t

    Rome,

    255,

    sees no

    change

    in

    the

    three

    functions

    rom

    De

    Oratore o

    Orator),

    and

    is

    a

    valuable

    corrective

    to the

    scepticism

    which

    explains

    all

    discrepancies

    between

    one work

    of

    Cicero

    and the

    next in

    terms

    of

    his

    acquiescence

    in

    the

    structure

    and

    principles

    of

    his

    different

    ources.

    This content downloaded from 200.45.170.30 on Mon, 3 Nov 2014 23:33:24 PMAll use subject toJSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 7/17/2019 Ciceronian Conciliare and Aristotelian Ethos

    15/15

    CICERONIAN

    CONCILIARE

    AND ARISTOTELIAN

    ETHOS

    275

    reflect

    n

    aspect

    f

    Aristotle's

    resentation

    f

    Ethos;

    t

    was

    n

    discarding

    it,

    nd

    dopting

    electare,

    hat

    Cicero

    evered

    he

    onnection.

    ToreturnoCicero's igh aluationf tyle;nthis edidnot hange.

    In

    Orator

    0

    f.he

    prefaces

    is iscussion

    ith

    categorical

    ssertion

    f

    ts

    primacy

    nddomination

    f he ourt

    ituation:

    um utemt

    uid

    t

    uo

    locodicat

    nvenerit,

    llud

    st

    onge

    maximum,

    idere

    uonam

    modo.

    f

    this

    s

    true

    even

    in

    philosophy,

    how

    much more so

    in

    causis...

    quibus

    totis

    moderatur

    ratio? ts

    importance

    ay

    in

    its

    power

    to

    persuade,

    which

    Cicero saw as

    equal

    to,

    f not

    greater

    han,

    that

    of

    truth r

    logic,

    because

    it

    appealed

    like music

    to

    the uncritical

    enses,

    and

    persuaded,

    as

    it

    were,

    subliminally.

    his

    emerges

    from

    he

    major digression

    t

    Brutus

    187-200,

    ending n the portrayalof the perfect rator n absolute controlof his

    audience

    like

    a

    virtuoso nstrumentalist-it

    has

    become

    his instrument.

    If

    Cicero claimed

    for

    tyle

    more

    than

    Aristotlewould have

    thought

    ither

    possible

    or

    desirable,

    his

    too

    may

    explain

    why

    he

    moved

    from

    he

    partial

    representation

    f

    Aristotle's

    econd

    proof

    by

    conciliare,

    o a

    termwhich

    had

    nothing

    n

    common with

    Aristotle,

    ut

    carried richer

    esthetic and

    stylistic

    ssociations.

    TRINITY

    COLLEGE,

    TORONTO