Bristow, William F - Self-Consciousness, Normativity and Abysmal Freedom

27
This article was downloaded by:[Alves, Marco Aurelio] On: 10 September 2007 Access Details: Sample Issue Voucher: Inquiry [subscription number 781912732] Publisher: Taylor & Francis Informa Ltd Registered in England and Wales Registered Number: 1072954 Registered office: Mortimer House, 37-41 Mortimer Street, London W1T 3JH, UK Inquiry An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy Publication details, including instructions for authors and subscription information: http://www.informaworld.com/smpp/title~content=t713393858 Self-Consciousness, Normativity and Abysmal Freedom William F. Bristow a a University of California, Irvine, USA Online Publication Date: 01 December 2006 To cite this Article: Bristow, William F. (2006) 'Self-Consciousness, Normativity and Abysmal Freedom', Inquiry, 49:6, 498 - 523 To link to this article: DOI: 10.1080/00201740601016197 URL: http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/00201740601016197 PLEASE SCROLL DOWN FOR ARTICLE Full terms and conditions of use: http://www.informaworld.com/terms-and-conditions-of-access.pdf This article maybe used for research, teaching and private study purposes. Any substantial or systematic reproduction, re-distribution, re-selling, loan or sub-licensing, systematic supply or distribution in any form to anyone is expressly forbidden. The publisher does not give any warranty express or implied or make any representation that the contents will be complete or accurate or up to date. The accuracy of any instructions, formulae and drug doses should be independently verified with primary sources. The publisher shall not be liable for any loss, actions, claims, proceedings, demand or costs or damages whatsoever or howsoever caused arising directly or indirectly in connection with or arising out of the use of this material. © Taylor and Francis 2007

description

briston

Transcript of Bristow, William F - Self-Consciousness, Normativity and Abysmal Freedom

  • This article was downloaded by:[Alves, Marco Aurelio]On: 10 September 2007Access Details: Sample Issue Voucher: Inquiry [subscription number 781912732]Publisher: Taylor & FrancisInforma Ltd Registered in England and Wales Registered Number: 1072954Registered office: Mortimer House, 37-41 Mortimer Street, London W1T 3JH, UK

    InquiryAn Interdisciplinary Journal of PhilosophyPublication details, including instructions for authors and subscription information:http://www.informaworld.com/smpp/title~content=t713393858

    Self-Consciousness, Normativity and Abysmal FreedomWilliam F. Bristow aa University of California, Irvine, USA

    Online Publication Date: 01 December 2006To cite this Article: Bristow, William F. (2006) 'Self-Consciousness, Normativity andAbysmal Freedom', Inquiry, 49:6, 498 - 523To link to this article: DOI: 10.1080/00201740601016197URL: http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/00201740601016197

    PLEASE SCROLL DOWN FOR ARTICLE

    Full terms and conditions of use: http://www.informaworld.com/terms-and-conditions-of-access.pdf

    This article maybe used for research, teaching and private study purposes. Any substantial or systematic reproduction,re-distribution, re-selling, loan or sub-licensing, systematic supply or distribution in any form to anyone is expresslyforbidden.

    The publisher does not give any warranty express or implied or make any representation that the contents will becomplete or accurate or up to date. The accuracy of any instructions, formulae and drug doses should beindependently verified with primary sources. The publisher shall not be liable for any loss, actions, claims, proceedings,demand or costs or damages whatsoever or howsoever caused arising directly or indirectly in connection with orarising out of the use of this material.

    Taylor and Francis 2007

  • Dow

    nloa

    ded

    By:

    [Alv

    es, M

    arco

    Aur

    elio

    ] At:

    18:0

    5 10

    Sep

    tem

    ber 2

    007

    Self-Consciousness, Normativity andAbysmal Freedom

    WILLIAM F. BRISTOW

    University of California, Irvine, USA

    (Received 5 June 2006)

    ABSTRACT This article critically examines Christine Korsgaards claim in her TannerLectures to find in self-consciousness itself the norms that would answer our need forpractical reasons, insofar as that need is constituted through our capacity for reflection.It shows that the way in which Korsgaard sees the need for a reason as arising out ofself-consciousness implies a dilemma: on the one hand, we want as the ultimate sourceof our reasons an authority of which we cannot coherently demand legitimation in turn;on the other, our freedom demands that nothing count for us as a reason except insofaras it is in turn endorsed in reflection. Relying on resources drawn from the tradition ofreflection, this paper argues that Korsgaards attempt to resolve this tension isunsuccessful and appeals, in response to this failure, to faith in the authority of ourreasons in the absence of foundational justification of them.

    Kant writes in his essay Conjectures on the Beginnings of Human History

    that when in the history of humanity man became conscious of his power of

    choice, he suddenly found himself on the edge of an abyss.1 [W]hereas

    instinct had hitherto directed him towards individual objects of his desire,

    an infinite range of objects now opened up, and he did not yet know how to

    choose between them. I elaborate Kants thought as follows. The practical

    task this self-consciousness assigned us was perhaps initially limited to

    determining the best means available for the achievement of ends still set by

    nature. But, once having embarked on this path of reflection, we soon found

    ourselves burdened with the further task of setting our own ends as well.

    The ends nature set for us no longer had authority, since we now found our-

    selves with the capacity to call them into question in turn and to set them

    Correspondence Address: Bill Bristow, Department of Philosophy, University of California,

    Irvine, CA 92697-4555, USA. Email: [email protected]

    Inquiry,

    Vol. 49, No. 6, 498523, December 2006

    0020-174X Print/1502-3923 Online/06/06049826 # 2006 Taylor & Francis

    DOI: 10.1080/00201740601016197

  • Dow

    nloa

    ded

    By:

    [Alv

    es, M

    arco

    Aur

    elio

    ] At:

    18:0

    5 10

    Sep

    tem

    ber 2

    007

    aside in favor of others we set for ourselves. The abyss edged closer.

    Because, of course, we had to ask: what is the importance of these further

    ends? Reflection, once let loose, cannot be contained, and so we were

    eventually burdened with the ultimate practical question or with questions

    about the value of ultimate ends: what is the meaning of existence? Why

    ought we live at all? As literatures paradigm of reflectiveness puts it: to be

    or not to be, that is the question. Supposing we find ourselves with thequestion, but without the resources to answer it, where are we? If the

    beginning of reflection puts us at the edge of an abyss, as Kant writes, the

    end of reflection deposits us in the very pit of it, in despair.

    Or do we find in the capacity for reflection itself the answer to the

    practical problem that this capacity makes unavoidable for us? Do we find

    in reflection the resources to to choose our own way of life, as Kant puts

    itself-consciously choose itwithout thereby undermining our conviction

    in the values which guide our choice? Different philosophers have argued indifferent ways that we do. Indeed, one might see this taskthe task, namely,

    of showing that the answer to the practical question that reflection makes

    unavoidable for us is contained in reflection itselfas one of the central

    tasks of a tradition of philosophy extending from Rousseau (at least) to

    Hegel (at least). Hegel expresses the solution to the practical problem and

    its reflexivity in a slogan: the free will wills the free will.2 If the capacity to

    determine ones actions reflectively poses the practical problem of how to

    choose ones way of life, which amounts to being free in one sense, thenwilling in accord with the principles internal to the process of reflection itself

    is the solution to that problem, a solution which amounts to being free in

    another sense, in the sense of being autonomous. Self-determination is itself

    the solution to the problem of self-determination. So argue Rousseau, Kant,

    Fichte, and Hegel, each in his distinctive way. But the attempts of these

    philosophers to show the ground of practical choice in reflection itself,

    thereby bridging or averting the abyss, are shadowed by those of the

    skeptics. In both the philosophy and the literature of the period, the so-called age of reflection, the tasks of reflection are freighted with the risks

    of nihilism and despair.

    Recently, Christine Korsgaard has explicitly revived the project of this

    tradition. In her 1992 Tanner lectures, published as Sources of Normativity

    (abbreviated SN), Korsgaard argues that the human problems of choice and

    self-determination are set by our reflective nature.3 In accord with the

    ambition of the tradition, she claims further that: If the problem springs

    from reflection then the solution must do so as well (SN p. 93). She arguesthat the solution to the problem is autonomy, which consists, on her

    distinctive interpretation, in conforming to practical principles that express

    our practical identities. She argues, further, that this account of the source

    of practical norms implies a justification of distinctively moral obligations,

    practical obligations distinguished by their universality and necessity. Moral

    Self-Consciousness, Normativity and Abysmal Freedom 499

  • Dow

    nloa

    ded

    By:

    [Alv

    es, M

    arco

    Aur

    elio

    ] At:

    18:0

    5 10

    Sep

    tem

    ber 2

    007

    obligations bind us inescapably because they express our inescapable nature

    as self-conscious beings, as beings who must act for reasons.

    In this paper, I inscribe Korsgaards project more explicitly and fully into

    the tradition of reflection than she herself does and criticize her results in the

    light of that tradition. More specifically, employing distinctions drawn from

    the tradition, I object to her claim that practical principles expressing our

    practical identities are unconditionally authoritative for us (Section II). Iargue further that her justification of moral obligations either begs the

    question against her opponent or relies on a conception of how norms bind

    that is incompatible with her account (Section III). By the end, it should be

    clear that the way in which Korsgaard sees the need for a reason to arise

    out of our self-consciousness implies a dilemma: on the one hand, we want

    as the ultimate source of our reasons an authority of which we cannot

    coherently demand legitimation in turn; on the other, our freedom demands

    that nothing count for us as a reason except insofar as it withstand the testof reflection. Korsgaards attempt to find in self-consciousness principles

    that both express our freedom and yet have unconditional authority for us

    (i.e., meet our need for a reason) is unsuccessful. In the last section, I

    suggest a response to this failure, a response that also derives from the

    tradition, which opposes faith to the despair that may seem the failures

    inevitable consequence.

    I. Self-consciousness and the normative question

    In her first lecture, Korsgaard defines what she calls the normative ques-

    tion. The normative question asks after the justification of the practical

    obligations we stand under. Korsgaard insists that we ask and answer the

    normative question from a particular standpoint, the standpoint, namely,

    from which the obligations make their demands upon us. Korsgaard insists

    upon this standpoint in order to distinguish the normative question from

    others with which it is sometimes confused. In particular, an account of thesource of norms that explains why creatures such as us possess normative

    concepts and act typically in accord with themfor instance, an evolution-

    ary accountwill typically fail even to address an agents demand for the

    justification of such obligations when they press upon her. Korsgaards

    normative question is the question, Why must I A?, where A is some action

    that is demanded of me; the answer must satisfy me in the standpoint from

    which I am deciding what to do.4

    There are two parts to Korsgaards response to the normative ques-tion. First, she offers an account of how practical obligations in general,

    whether moral or not, are grounded in a persons practical identities,

    whatever they are. Second, with the account of the source of the authority of

    obligations in general as a background, she offers a justification of moral

    obligations (obligations that are distinguished by their universality and

    500 W.F. Bristow

  • Dow

    nloa

    ded

    By:

    [Alv

    es, M

    arco

    Aur

    elio

    ] At:

    18:0

    5 10

    Sep

    tem

    ber 2

    007

    necessity), thus refuting the moral skeptic in at least one of his harassing

    appearances.

    Before examining Korsgaards response to the normative question, I

    examine in this section how the normative question is seen to arise out of

    our capacity for self-consciousness. Korsgaard claims that our capacity for

    self-reflection is the source of the need we humans have for norms or reasons

    in the first place, of which the demand for justification expressed in thenormative question is a special case. She writes, a lower animals attention

    is fixed on the world. Its perceptions are its beliefs and its desires are its will

    (SN pp. 9293). But human beings, by virtue of their capacity to reflect on

    their desires and perceptions, can distance themselves from them: our

    capacity to turn our attention on to our own mental activities is also a

    capacity to distance ourselves from them, and to call them into question.

    As Korsgaard explains in the following important passage, this reflective

    distance implies the need for a reason.

    I desire and find myself with a powerful impulse to act. But I back up

    and bring that impulse into view and then I have a certain distance.

    Now the impulse doesnt dominate me and now I have a problem.

    Shall I act? Is this desire really a reason to act? The reflective mind

    cannot settle for perception and desire, not just as such. It needs a

    reason. Otherwise, at least as long as it reflects, it cannot commit itself

    and go forward. (SN p. 93)

    The basic picture here is this: in becoming conscious of my psychological

    impulse to perform some action, I am simultaneously conscious of my

    freedom with respect to this action, which in turn implies my need for

    authoritative norms (reasons) on the basis of which to determine myself.

    Although Korsgaard does not call attention to the difference, the need for

    reasons implied by reflection on ones desire is different on the face of it

    from the need for a reason implied in the normative question above. There Iam faced in reflection with (apparent) obligation, with practical constraint,

    requiring sacrifice of my desires perhaps, and what I need is justification of

    the authority with which the obligatory action is demanded of me; here, in

    contrast, I am faced in reflection with freedom of choice, and so what I need

    is constraint or authority, something on the basis of which I can confidently

    determine myself one way rather than the other. Both acts of self-reflection

    imply needs for reasons, but there seem to be two distinct practical problems

    here that pull in opposite directions and are beset by different risks. If Ishould be unable to gain insight by reflection into the authority by which

    some action is demanded of me, then I have constraint without freedom;

    whereas, if I should fail to discover reasons in reflection on the basis of

    which to choose among the courses of action available to me, then I am

    faced with the abysmal freedom to which Kant refers in the passage quoted.

    Self-Consciousness, Normativity and Abysmal Freedom 501

  • Dow

    nloa

    ded

    By:

    [Alv

    es, M

    arco

    Aur

    elio

    ] At:

    18:0

    5 10

    Sep

    tem

    ber 2

    007

    Our need for reasons seems to reflect both a need for authority (or

    constraint), implied by consciousness of my freedom of choice, and a need

    for justification, implied by consciousness of alleged constraint or authority.

    This duality in the need for reasons suggests the dilemma: does not the

    satisfaction of one need simply imply the other? How is it possible for both

    needs to be fully and compatibly satisfied? Korsgaards account (following

    Kants) means to meet this challenge.Korsgaard does not call attention to this duality in the need for reasons

    because, I think, she operates with an underlying conception of free, rational

    agency according to which my need for a reason expressed in the normative

    question is the same as my need to have an authoritative norm by which to

    determine my capacity of free choice.5 According to the underlying con-

    ception, nothing determines my behaviorthat is, no values, principles,

    desires, goals, or obligationsexcept insofar as it has my endorsement in

    reflection. Behavior of mine counts as free action, of which I am regarded asthe author and for which I am responsible (subject to praise or blame), just

    in case the considerations to which one would appeal in describing the

    action as intentional (that is, the particular motivational desire or value or

    goal or principle, or set of such, that determines the behavior as the

    intentional action it is) do not determine the action immediately, but only as

    mediated by what we might call a moment of endorsement. The moment

    of endorsement consists in the agent counting or taking the practical

    considerations on which she acts as sufficient reason to act as she does. Inthe case of desires, Korsgaard is explicit on this point. A desire-based action

    only counts as free action insofar as the agent endorses the desire in

    reflection. But, given that it is the reflective distance that poses the practical

    problem (as she says in the passage above), the point is not unique to desire.

    If the capacity to back up and bring a desire into view implies that I have a

    certain distance, which implies in turn the need for a reason, then presum-

    ably my capacity to back up from my values, principles and obligations

    implies the same. I assume that Korsgaard does not note the duality in theneed for reasons remarked above because she takes the capacity to back

    up from some apparent obligation to imply the same question (namely, the

    question whether to endorse or not to endorse) that arises when one backs

    up from ones desire.

    With respect to this moment of endorsement, we must note another

    important ambiguity in Korsgaards account. Korsgaards characterization

    of the agents endorsement sometimes leaves open the possibility of inter-

    preting it as a dateable psychological act. We all know what it is to backup from a desire and to subject it to critical scrutiny and then consciously

    to affirm it before acting on it. Sometimes we do this, but most often we do

    not. Interpreted as a dateable, psychological act, the moment of endo-

    rsement does not have the normative significance Korsgaard would draw

    from it. So interpreted, the moment of endorsement is not necessary. One

    502 W.F. Bristow

  • Dow

    nloa

    ded

    By:

    [Alv

    es, M

    arco

    Aur

    elio

    ] At:

    18:0

    5 10

    Sep

    tem

    ber 2

    007

    may or may not endorse a desire in this sense, prior to acting on it.

    Moreover, whether or not the act of endorsement in this sense occurs makes

    no difference to the normative question.

    Accordingly, I interpret the moment of endorsement as logical, not

    psychological. I suggest that we interpret the moment of endorsement as a

    necessary component of the representation of a behavior as free, authored

    action. Then the claim is this: in representing a bit of behavior as authoredby the subject of the behavior, as that persons free action, for which she

    bears responsibility, we implicitly regard the considerations on which she

    acts as having her endorsement in reflection, in the sense that she takes the

    practical considerations to be sufficient reason to act as she does. This

    presupposition does not imply that, as a matter of the psychological facts,

    she has backed up from the practical considerations on which she acts

    and consciously endorsed them in reflection. Even if she is (as most of us are

    most of the time, I assume) unreflective with respect to her practical reasons,we are taking itin regarding her as the responsible author of the action

    that she is responding to reasons in the relevant stretch of behavior. This

    usually implicit assumption becomes explicit on those relatively rare occa-

    sions on which we call upon the person to justify her action. Whenever (and

    insofar as) we regard a person as the responsible author of her action, we

    implicitly take justification to be her task; we take justifying reasons to be

    hers to provide, even if we demand them only rarely and under particular

    circumstances. In taking the justification of an action to be the agents task,we take the considerations on which she acts to count for her as sufficient

    reason to do as she does. Thus the moment of endorsement is not a

    psychological act, the occurrence of which is contingent, but a necessary

    component of the representation of an action as authored.6

    In posing the normative question, the Korsgaardian practical agent

    arrogates to herself a kind of practical authority. She arrogates to herself the

    right to demand insight in reflection into the legitimacy (or rationality) of

    any practical demand made upon her, as a condition of granting thatdemand authority in her deliberation about what to do. 7 On the face of it,

    the authority she arrogates to herself conflicts with the authority by which

    an obligation is commanded, insofar as obligations as such bind us uncon-

    ditionally.8 But the authority the agent arrogates to herself is grounded in

    the underlying conception of free, rational agency. Though most of us

    accede to the obligations that daily constrain us without demanding insight

    into the rationality of the authority by which they are commanded, insofar

    as we are (regarded as) the responsible authors of our actions, endorsementis ours to give or to withhold. As such, each of us has the right to back up

    from a supposed obligation and demand justification as a condition of

    taking it as a sufficient reason to act. This authority is but the opposite face

    of our responsibility, of our being on the hook for the provision of justifying

    reasons, should they be demanded of us. To exercise this right, to press the

    Self-Consciousness, Normativity and Abysmal Freedom 503

  • Dow

    nloa

    ded

    By:

    [Alv

    es, M

    arco

    Aur

    elio

    ] At:

    18:0

    5 10

    Sep

    tem

    ber 2

    007

    demand for justification in reflection, just is to press Korsgaards normative

    question. However, the above-mentioned tension between the authority the

    agent arrogates to herself in pressing this question, as expressing her

    freedom as a rational agent, and the nature of obligations as commanding

    unconditionally, raises the disquieting possibility that nothing can satisfy us

    in pursuit of the normative question.

    Though Korsgaard insists that the normative question must be pursuedby taking up the stance of the practical agents deliberative reflection about

    what to do, she perforce proposes her answers to the normative question

    from the slightly shifted perspective of philosophical reflection. Again, the

    answer she proposes to the normative question from this perspective has two

    main parts: she attempts to provide both the general sort of answer that can

    meet our need for justification with respect to practical obligations in

    general (as they vary in their particular content from person to person) and

    the particular answer that meets our demand for justification with respect tomoral obligations in particular, (which are distinguished as binding us

    universally). In the following two sections, I examine these two parts of

    Korsgaards response to the normative question in turn.

    II. Self-consciousness, autonomy and practical identity

    Korsgaard expresses the characteristic thought of the tradition of reflection

    when she writes: If the problem springs from reflection then the solutionmust do so as well (SN p. 93). The proposal is that we find in the very

    posing of the practical problem, insofar as that problem has its source in

    self-consciousness, a procedure of practical reflection the internal princi-

    ple(s) of which are the answer to the practical problem. In reflecting on ones

    desire, one is conscious of freedom of choice with respect to the desired

    action; as Ive interpreted it, the resulting need for a reason is a need for a

    norm or principle on the basis of which to determine ones faculty of free

    choice of which one is thereby conscious. Korsgaard suggests that reflectivescrutiny itself constitutes a kind of test or criterion on the basis of which one

    determines oneself: We need reasons because our impulses must be able to

    withstand reflective scrutiny. We have reasons if they do. The normative

    word reason refers to a kind of reflective success (SN p. 93).

    However, in the absence of a specification of the test of reflectionthat is,

    in the absence of a specification of the norms or standards brought to bear

    in reflective scrutiny, and of whence they in turn derive their authority for

    usappeal to the test of reflection does not answer the normative question.According to Korsgaards account, the procedure of backing up from

    practical considerations and subjecting them to critical scrutiny backs us up

    to authoritative, grounding practical principles. The questions remains, How ?

    As indicated above, if backing up from a desire implies the need for a

    reason, then presumably backing up from other practical content (practical

    504 W.F. Bristow

  • Dow

    nloa

    ded

    By:

    [Alv

    es, M

    arco

    Aur

    elio

    ] At:

    18:0

    5 10

    Sep

    tem

    ber 2

    007

    principles, values, goals, et cetera) implies the same need. For example,

    if consciousness of my desire to drop off to sleep during a colloquium

    implies the problem: shall I let myself? then consciousness of my practical

    precept not to drowse off during colloquia implies in turn the need for

    a justification or validation of this precept. Supposing the justification is

    that such behavior is disrespectful to the speaker, I can back up from the

    principle implied in this reason and ask for justification of its authorityfor me in turn. What then can the test of reflection consist in, if every

    principle applied in reflection is one that itself requires legitimation through

    a process of reflection, insofar as I can make it the object of a further

    reflection?

    What is needed, obviously, given the way the problem is posed, is a

    practical principle from which one cannot back up again in turn. Korsgaard

    conceives the problem in terms of what Kant called a search for the

    unconditionedin this case, for something which will bring the reiterationof but why must I do that? to an end. The unconditional answer must be

    one that makes it impossible, unnecessary, or incoherent to ask why again

    (SN p. 33). Korsgaard finds the unconditional answerthough one in need

    of modification, as we shall see belowin Kants derivation of the

    categorical imperative as the principle of the free will in the opening

    paragraphs of the Third Section of the Groundwork. A free will is as such,

    according to its concept, determined by nothing alien or external to it. In

    terms of the discussion above, whatever moves the free person to act isregarded as doing so only as mediated by the persons own endorsement of

    that practical content. But again, our question is: what determines for the

    person whether to endorse or not? The person needs a principle (or set of

    such) internal to the will in terms of which she can determine whether to

    endorse or identify with the particular practical consideration under

    examination; but given that whatever principles she employs need to be

    endorsed in turn, what can the test of reflection be, such that it constitutes a

    genuine criterion of self-determination?The answer attributed to Kant is that the demand that a candidate

    practical consideration be recognizable in reflection as a reason is itself

    the sole criterion of self-determination. The need to act for reasons is itself

    the single constraint internal to the will. Of course the difficulty is to see how

    the need to act for reasons, which from one point of view simply poses

    the problem, is supposed to be its solution, when looked at from another

    point of view. How can this need, which we see to be internal to the will,

    be understood itself to impose a constraint on, or a criterion for, choice?Our procedure makes clear that when searching for the ground of deter-

    mination of a free will, we must abstract away from particular contentful

    principles, because, as weve seen, such content can only be identified with

    the free will through its endorsement and so cannot serve as the principle of

    that endorsement. Abstracting from all particular, contentful principles

    Self-Consciousness, Normativity and Abysmal Freedom 505

  • Dow

    nloa

    ded

    By:

    [Alv

    es, M

    arco

    Aur

    elio

    ] At:

    18:0

    5 10

    Sep

    tem

    ber 2

    007

    leaves only the formal demand that one act on nothing that does not count

    as a reason. But is this a criterion? By what mark(s) are practical reasons

    recognized as such? For Kant, reasons or principles as such have the form

    of universality. Hence, the practical demand that one act only on what

    counts as a reason amounts to the demand expressed in the universal law

    formulation of the categorical imperative: act only according to that

    maxim that one can at the same time will as a universal law. Our pro-cedure reveals that this practical principle is internal to the process of

    deliberative reflection about how to determine oneself. One cannot back

    up from such a principle and subject it to critical scrutiny without

    presupposing it.9

    Korsgaard raises Hegels familiar objection that this formal constraint

    internal to reflection exerts no genuine constraint at allit is an empty

    formalism that can take any content whateverand modifies Kants posi-

    tion accordingly (SN p. 99). She distinguishes, as Kant does not, betweenthe categorical imperative, which is the demand that one act only according

    to principles that have the form of universality, and the moral law, which is

    the principle that one act only according to principles that every rational

    being could in principle consent to in a workable system of cooperation

    (Kants kingdom of ends). The former is short of the latter since, though

    every principle or law is as such universal, the domain of its legislation is

    not specified by this constraint. The lack of specification of the domain of

    legislation implies the emptiness of this constraint. If the law is the lawof acting on the desire of the moment, then the agent will treat each desire as

    a reason, and her conduct will be that of the wanton. If the law ranges over

    the agents whole life, then the agent will be some sort of egoist (SN p. 99).

    If the law ranges over every rational being, then the law is the moral law.

    How then does the constraint internal to practical deliberative reflection

    have content, according to Korsgaards account? This content is provided

    by the particular, contingent ways in which the individual conceives and

    values herself within the stance of practical deliberation. In order to makethis point, Korsgaard introduces a second respect in which the reflective

    structure of the mind is a source of self-consciousness as follows:10

    The reflective structure of the mind is a source of self-consciousness

    because it forces us to have a conception of ourselvesFrom a third-

    person point of view, outside of the deliberative standpoint, it may

    look as if what happens when someone makes a choice is that the

    strongest of his conflicting desires wins. But this isnt how it is for youwhen you deliberate. When you deliberate, it is as if there were

    something over and above all your desires, something which is you,

    and which chooses which desire to act on. This means that the

    principle or law by which you determine your actions is one that you

    regard as expressive of yourself. (SN p. 100)

    506 W.F. Bristow

  • Dow

    nloa

    ded

    By:

    [Alv

    es, M

    arco

    Aur

    elio

    ] At:

    18:0

    5 10

    Sep

    tem

    ber 2

    007

    This conception of yourselfor conceptions, since each of us typically has

    severalis what Korsgaard calls your practical identity: a practical

    identity is a description under which you find your life to be worth living

    and your actions to be worth undertaking (SN p. 101). The specific ways in

    which you conceive and value yourself (as teacher, mother, friend, et cetera)

    specify the domain of your legislation and thus provide specific content to

    your highest practical principles. When you back up from a practicalimpulse and ask whether it has practical authority for you, whether it

    constitutes a reason for you, you answer by seeing whether the maxim of

    acting on the desire could be willed as a law by you; the constraint here is

    provided by your practical identity, by who you take yourself to be, as it

    were (See SN p. 113).

    Putting the basic elements together, Korsgaards account of the source

    and nature of practical reasons and obligations is as follows. We begin from

    ones capacity to back up from ones desire and make it an object ofreflection. This is the capacity for self-consciousness in the first sense. It

    implies the agents consciousness of her freedom with respect to the desired

    action, and hence the need for norms on the basis of which to determine

    whether the desire constitutes sufficient reason to act as it impels her. But

    whence such norms and their authority? Typically a person appeals in

    reflection to other of her desires, her values, her practical principles, et

    cetera. However, she can back up from these in turn, and hence their

    authority is also conditional on endorsement. As Korsgaard puts it: afurther stretch of reflection requires a further stretch of endorsement (SN

    p. 119). The need for a reason is the need for norms on the basis of which to

    determine this endorsement. Because the original problem is posed by the

    reflective distance opened between what I am conscious of as me in the

    standpoint of deliberation and the grounds of choice on which I reflect (my

    desire), whatever I can take a reflective distance on is something for which I

    will in turn require a reason as mediating my endorsement of it as

    authoritative for my choice and action. So our need for reasons can onlybe met, finally, by principles from which we cannot coherently back up

    again in turn. The key claim is: the principles that express a persons

    practical identities satisfy this condition. In the standpoint of agency, I am

    conscious of myself not only in the sense of being conscious of my desire

    for something, but also in the sense of being conscious of being something

    over and above all my desires, something which is me and which chooses

    which desire to act on, as Korsgaard says. Insofar as a practical principle

    immediately expresses this self-conception, there is no reflective distancebetween what I am conscious of as me in the reflective stance and the

    principle. Since my practical identity is an identity under which I value

    myself and find my life to be worth living and my actions worth under-

    taking, to back up from this self-conception is by definition to lose my

    orientation in practical deliberation altogether. Thus I cannot intelligibly

    Self-Consciousness, Normativity and Abysmal Freedom 507

  • Dow

    nloa

    ded

    By:

    [Alv

    es, M

    arco

    Aur

    elio

    ] At:

    18:0

    5 10

    Sep

    tem

    ber 2

    007

    back up from such a self-conception and submit it to a further test of

    reflection. In having backed up to explicit articulation of my practical

    identity, Ive reached the normative foundation, the source of my reasons

    and obligations. Thus, on Korsgaards account: Your reasons express your

    identity, your nature; your obligations spring from what your identity

    forbids (SN p. 101).11

    In this way, then, Korsgaard finds in the capacity for self-reflectionitself the answer to the practical problem this capacity makes unavoidable

    for us. Korsgaards account means to be Kantian insofar as it finds the

    source of the authority of practical principles to be autonomy: the ulti-

    mately authoritative principles are the principles of ones own will. Hence

    Korsgaards account, like Kants, allegedly reconciles the tension between

    our freedom and our standing under unconditional practical obligations:

    since the unconditionally authoritative practical laws are self-legislated

    (i.e., principles that express ones identity, as Korsgaard puts it), theirauthority does not oppose ones freedom, but rather expresses it. However,

    Korsgaards departure from Kants position here is significant. For Kant

    the supreme principle of the free will is the single, formal principle of the

    categorical imperative, whereas for Korsgaard, the wills self-given princi-

    ples are those that express her practical identities, whatever (and however

    many) they are.

    Whatever the prospects of Kants own account, Korsgaards Kantian

    account does not succeed in reconciling our freedom and our standingunder unconditional obligations. Kants reasons for seeing the principle of

    the free will as a formal principle retain their force. Recall the point

    made above: behavior of mine counts as free action, of which I am the

    author and for which I am responsible, just in case the considerations

    on which I am acting, whatever they are, do not determine the action

    immediately, but only as mediated by my endorsement of them; that is, only

    insofar as I count them as sufficient reason to act as I do. This condition

    applies as much to the principles expressing my contingent practicalidentities as to my desires. If it were the case that I could not back up from

    a principle expressing my practical identity and subject it to rational

    scrutiny as a condition of endorsing it, then the behavior determined by

    that principle could not be seen as free, as authored by me, since this

    would mean that I am not responsive to reasons with respect to that

    behavior. To make this point vivid, suppose the case of someone who,

    because of the circumstances of his upbringing, deeply conceives and values

    himself as belonging to a pure race; suppose further that racist actionsfollow from this self-conception. Clearly, we would make the rational

    demand (implicitly, at least) that such a person subject his principles to

    rational scrutiny as a condition of acting on them; and in treating him as

    responsible for his racist actions, we would regard his principles as counting

    for him as sufficient reasons to act as he does. If we suppose that the person

    508 W.F. Bristow

  • Dow

    nloa

    ded

    By:

    [Alv

    es, M

    arco

    Aur

    elio

    ] At:

    18:0

    5 10

    Sep

    tem

    ber 2

    007

    cannot subject the practical principles implicit in his self-conception to

    rational scrutiny because the identity sticks too deep, then holding the

    person responsible for actions deriving from the principles is at least

    problematic, since, by that supposition, the principles amount to a kind of

    fixation from which the person is powerless to release himself. Again, it is as

    true of this practical content as of all other that it gives rise to action which

    we regard as free, authored action just in case it has the agents endorsementin reflection. But this just implies that it cannot serve as the ultimate

    normative basis of endorsement in reflection. As Kant argues, the principle

    that can alone serve as the principle of the self-determining will is the purely

    formal principle, the categorical imperative.12

    The point can be made by drawing out the implications of the distinction

    between the two sorts of self-consciousness indicated above. On the one

    hand, self-consciousness is consciousness of a mental state (e.g., a desire)

    as ones own: [W]e human animals [in contrast to other animals] turn ourattention on to our own perceptions and desires themselves, on to our

    mental activities, and we are conscious of them (SN p. 93). This is object-

    directed consciousness that has as its object some particular mental content

    of the subject of consciousness. On the other hand, practical self-

    consciousness is consciousness of that which is you, and which chooses

    which desire to act on (SN p. 100). It is essential that this second sort of

    self-consciousness not be understood on the model of the first, because,

    whereas the first exactly implies the practical problem (the problem ofwhether this psychological content on which I reflect is a sufficient practical

    reason), the second is supposed to provide the resources for solving the

    practical problem. The first sort of self-consciousness implies a reflective

    distance between the reflecting subject and the object of self-reflection (my

    desire, say). The practical problem implied by this self-consciousness,

    according to Korsgaard, is whether to identify oneself with the object of

    reflection or not. The second sort of self-consciousness can be the ground

    for self-determination, thus solving the problem, only if there is no reflectivedistance in this self-consciousness. Thus the self-consciousness the principle

    of which serves as the ultimate norm cannot have the same structure as

    other-directed consciousness; it cannot be consciousness of another, where

    the other is oneself. It must be immediate, unreflective self-consciousness.

    This implies that this self-consciousness must be pure or formal; whatever

    content it has can have authority for the person only insofar as the person

    takes it as authoritative for him, which just implies that it does not have that

    authority immediately, as the principle expressing the self-consciousnessdoes. Apperception (to use Kants term for self-consciousness) can only be a

    principle, normative for us in our activity, whether epistemic or practical, if

    it has no content on its own, but merely expresses a relation in which the self

    must stand to itself insofar as the self is the responsible agent of the norm-

    governed activity. The normative demand or constraint implied in the stance

    Self-Consciousness, Normativity and Abysmal Freedom 509

  • Dow

    nloa

    ded

    By:

    [Alv

    es, M

    arco

    Aur

    elio

    ] At:

    18:0

    5 10

    Sep

    tem

    ber 2

    007

    of agency is just the formal demand that one act for reasons, that is, on the

    basis of principles that have the form of universality. Either this can

    function as a principle, or, if not, if it is an empty formalism, then the self-

    consciousness that is internal to the stance of free, responsible agency

    contains no normative constraint at all.13

    Recall that Korsgaards aims are twofold in her Tanner lectures: 1) to

    argue that the source of practical normativity in general is autonomy and 2)to justify moral obligations in particular, which are distinguished by their

    universality and necessity. I will now go on to examine her argument for the

    claim that the necessary condition of a persons contingent values, whatever

    they are, is the value of her humanity. Does this argument do better in

    finding in reflection itself the principle that answers the practical question

    that our capacity for reflection makes inevitable for us?

    III. Moral obligations and the universal identity as human

    Given her view that the source of obligations in general is ones practical

    identities, Korsgaards argument that we are all bound by moral obliga-

    tions, whatever particular ways in which we happen to conceive and value

    ourselves, takes the form of arguing that there is one practical identity that

    each of us must have, namely, the practical identity simply as human being.

    Korsgaard means by human being not a natural or biological category of

    course, but rather what Kant means in some texts by humanity, namelythe capacity to set ends for ourselves, or, as Korsgaard construes it, the

    capacity (or, indeed, the need) to act for reasons.14 Since she takes herself

    already to have shown by this point in her lectures that acting for reasons is

    acting from some self-conception or other, she defines human being as

    an animal who needs a practical conception of her own identity, a con-

    ception of who she is which is normative for her (SN p. 123). Korsgaard

    argues that this meta-identity must stand behind ones other contingent,

    practical identities, in the sense that valuing ones humanity is a condition ofones other contingent values. In a second part of her argument reserved for

    the fourth lecture, Korsgaard argues that, in being committed to the value of

    ones own humanity, one is bound by a principle requiring one to respect

    always the humanity of each person. Thus, the authority of the moral

    principle, as expressed in Kants Formula of Humanity, is implied in valuing

    ourselves merely as human. I restrict my attention to Korsgaards argument

    for the claim that we are committed to conceiving and valuing ourselves

    simply as human. In evaluating Korsgaards argument, I press a questionconcerning the normative status of human identity. It is only if we endorse

    the identity (that is, conceive and value ourselves under this description) that

    it serves as a source of norms for us. But the argument that a person must

    take this identity as normative for herself (as a matter of normative

    requirement) begs the question at issue.

    510 W.F. Bristow

  • Dow

    nloa

    ded

    By:

    [Alv

    es, M

    arco

    Aur

    elio

    ] At:

    18:0

    5 10

    Sep

    tem

    ber 2

    007

    Korsgaards argument proceeds according to the following steps.15

    (1) The nature of the normative force of ones practical reasons andobligations in general is that ones practical identity is at stake in

    conformity to them.

    (2) Hence the following description holds of you, whoever you are (that is,

    whatever your contingent practical identities): as a reflective being,

    you have some practical conception(s) or other, from which you derive

    reasons and obligations.

    (3) It follows that you (again and throughout: whatever your contingent

    practical identities) have a reason to have some practical identity orother, from which to derive reasons and obligations.

    (4) This reason cannot derive from any of the identities you happen to

    have, given the way your life has fallen out, since it is a reason you

    have independent of these contingent identities and since its a reason

    you have regardless of the contents of your particular identifications.

    (5) Therefore, this reason derives from the universal self-description, from

    the description that holds of you whoever you are.

    Conclusion: This universal self-description (i.e., your humanity) must be

    normative for you. Korsgaard puts the conclusion as follows: You must

    value your own humanity if you are to act at all (SN p. 123). Or: all value

    depends on the value of humanity; other forms of practical identity matter

    in part because humanity requires them (SN p. 121). If valuing your ownhumanity commits you to respecting the humanity of each person, as

    Korsgaard argues in the fourth lecture, then moral obligations follow, on

    one recognizable characterization of them.

    Korsgaard regards the first claim, that practical norms are expressions of

    ones practical identities, as having been established already. The second

    claim derives from this point a universal self-description, a description that

    applies to each of us, whatever particular ways we happen as individuals to

    conceive and value ourselves, given the way our lives have fallen out. Thetrick, however, is to see how this universal self-description is itself for each

    of us a normative identity. A true self-description is not a source of norms for

    a person unless the person conceives and values herself under that

    description. The fact that Im a Hatfield, as a matter of blood relationship,

    gives me no duties or reasons in the matter of the feud with the McCoys on

    its own; this identity is a source of reasons and obligations only if the

    conception of myself as a Hatfield is one under which I value myself and

    find my life to be worth living and my actions worth undertaking. Hence,the rest of the argument aims to show that the universal self-description is

    normative for you. The key to showing this is the third claim: it follows,

    given (1), that without some practical identity or other, you will lose your

    grip on yourself as having any reason to do one thing rather than another

    and with it, your grip on yourself as having any reason to live and act at all

    Self-Consciousness, Normativity and Abysmal Freedom 511

  • Dow

    nloa

    ded

    By:

    [Alv

    es, M

    arco

    Aur

    elio

    ] At:

    18:0

    5 10

    Sep

    tem

    ber 2

    007

    (SN p. 121). So the force of the reason to have some practical identity or

    other is what the force of a reason always is, according to the general

    account of normativity: your practical identity is at stake in it. But which

    practical identity is at stake here in particular? It could only be the universal

    identity. Hence the conclusion: the addressee of the argument must

    acknowledge the value of herself simply qua human.

    On the most natural and immediate interpretation of the argument, itssuccess depends on getting its addressee to endorse her identity as human, to

    value herself under that description.16 The argument depends on this,

    because the human identity is a source of norms for a person only if that

    person conceives and values herself under that description. But, so inter-

    preted, the argument runs in a short circle. Obviously, unless I already have

    reasons and obligations, independently of my endorsement of my identity as

    human, I cannot be shown a reason why I must endorse this identity; and yet

    the reason urged upon me by the argument for endorsing this identity isthat, if I do not, I lack any reasons and obligations at all. The role that the

    argument itself assigns to this meta-identity, as standing behind my other

    contingent practical identities (that is, as the highest source of reasons and

    obligations), implies that no reason can be given for why I ought to endorse

    it that does not presuppose that I already do. If the proponent of the

    argument maintains that my actually valuing my humanityas opposed to

    the value of humanity, whether or not I recognize itis the ultimate source

    of my reasons and obligations, then the proponent of the argument can-not give me a reason to value humanity that does not presuppose that I

    already do.

    Accordingly, the argument must be interpreted differently. A different

    interpretation seems required anyway by the aim of the argument. If the

    argument aims to show the universality and necessity of moral obligations,

    and if it is a contingent matter whether a given person conceives and values

    himself under the universal self-description, then the proponent of the

    argument cannot concede that its addressee has moral obligations only if hecomes to conceive and value himself under the universal self-description

    through the argument itself.

    In order to avoid the circle, we need an interpretation of the argument

    according to which the force of the reason it gives us to recognize the value

    of humanity does not depend on getting its addressee to endorse her identity

    as human through the argument itself. This seems to point to a construal of

    the argument according to which its work is to show that the value of

    humanity is rationally implied by (presupposed by) the addressees affirma-tion of the particular values she holds, independently of the addressees

    actual recognition of the value of humanity or of this rational implica-

    tion. But on any such construal the argument faces the following problem:

    the reason it would offer to compel recognition of the value of humanity

    would have force independently of a threat to ones practical identities,

    512 W.F. Bristow

  • Dow

    nloa

    ded

    By:

    [Alv

    es, M

    arco

    Aur

    elio

    ] At:

    18:0

    5 10

    Sep

    tem

    ber 2

    007

    contradicting the first premise of the argument. The first premise claims that

    the normative force of reasons and obligations in general consists in ones

    identity being at stake in conformity to them. This premise can rationally

    imply the value of humanity only if the force of the reason implied by it also

    consists in your identity, under some description, being at stake. But,

    according to the argument itself, given that the argument means to regress

    or ascend to the highest source of practical reasons and obligations, the onlyidentity that could be at stake in this reason is your identity as human. Thus

    the force of the reason the argument provides for recognizing the value of

    humanity must presuppose that you already value humanity, on pain of

    contradicting its first premise. The force of the reason the argument

    provides for you to recognize the value of humanity must either derive from

    your valuing humanity already or compel recognition independently of your

    identifications or endorsements.

    The basic dilemma faced by the proponent of the argument is this: unlessthe reason the argument gives us to recognize the value of humanity compels

    this recognition independently of our prior recognition of the value of

    humanity, the argument is circular; but if it does, then, in this case at least,

    our reasons have some other source than the value of humanity.

    There may seem to be a third way of taking the argument, a way which

    avoids the whirlpools of circularity on the one side and the shoals of

    reversion to normative realism on the other. Clearly, from the perspective

    of the proponent of the argument, what Ive pointed to and criticized as itscircularity is something like the crucial point of the argument. The crucial

    point is: in acting at all, on whatever values we happen to have, we pre-

    suppose the value of humanity. Perhaps, then, the proponent of the argu-

    ment means to get us to see that we are, in all that we do, in fact, perforce,

    already recognizing (or endorsing) the value of humanity. Perhaps the

    argument is meant to show that ones actual valuing of oneself merely as

    human is implicit in ones explicit, but contingent, values. Only on this

    construal, it would seem, could the proponent both consistently maintainthat humanity is a source of norms for a person only if that person endo-

    rses herself under that description (as required by the arguments starting

    point) and still mean to conclude to the universality and necessity of moral

    obligations.

    The proponent of the argument, so taken, relies crucially on an obscure

    distinction between valuing humanity implicitly (or endorsing oneself under

    this description implicitly) and valuing humanity explicitly. Most of us some

    of the time and some of us most of the time pursue deeply immoral projects,in more or less conscious defiance of universal values. In such pursuits, we

    fail to recognize the value of humanity in some sense. The proponent of the

    argument does not deny this undeniable empirical fact, presumably, but

    accommodates it by insisting that, in such a pursuit, while one fails to

    recognize (or even denies) the value of humanity explicitly, one nevertheless

    Self-Consciousness, Normativity and Abysmal Freedom 513

  • Dow

    nloa

    ded

    By:

    [Alv

    es, M

    arco

    Aur

    elio

    ] At:

    18:0

    5 10

    Sep

    tem

    ber 2

    007

    cannot fail to implicitly recognize the value of humanity. In order to do the

    work that the proponent wants of it, implicitly valuing must be a form of

    actually valuing, because it is only if one actually endorses the value of

    humanity that one has the reasons and obligations that stem from such an

    identity.

    Whether the argument on this construal works depends on what content

    can be given to the claim that someone implicitly values humanity, eventhough she may not know that she does and even though her actual actions

    and statements would lead us to say of her that she does not. Though it is

    not clear in advance that such a content cannot be specified, in the absence

    of this specification, the argument itself is not specified. I suspect that we

    cannot specify this content without generating a more complicated concep-

    tion of the source and nature of norms than is available to us so far. Take

    the most obvious beginning for specifying this content. The meaning of the

    claim that a person implicitly values humanity, even in his deeply immoralaction and even while explicitly disavowing that value, is cashed out in a

    conditional: if the person were to reflect, fully and correctly, on the con-

    ditions of his explicitly recognized values, then he would recognize (expli-

    citly) the value of humanity. But this conditional analysis just raises again

    the original problem regarding the force of the reason that would compel

    this explicit recognition in reflection. How is this conditional itself to be

    spelled out? Presumably the conditional is not stating a prediction of what

    will in fact happen if the person reflects. Rather the conditional rests on thefact that a reason to recognize the value of humanity is either revealed or

    generated through reflection on ones values. The original problem is: what

    is the source or nature of that reason? If we want to say at this juncture that

    the persons reason to explicitly recognize the value of humanity in reflec-

    tion is that he already does, then clearly we do not manage to explicate the

    meaning of implicit recognition by appeal to this conditional, since, in

    explaining the meaning of the conditional, we appeal again to implicit

    recognition. We have not gotten any closer to understanding the necessity ofrecognizing this value.17

    We find it difficult to hold to the conception of the force of norms as

    consisting entirely in the strength of our actual commitments. Ordinarily, of

    course, we take ourselves in our practical reasoning to be answerable to an

    objective order of values, independent of our endorsements and self-

    conceptions. Korsgaards argument begins from the denial of this assump-

    tion; it begins from the claim that, as reflective beings, we project value onto

    the world (SN p. 116). Ive argued in this section that the argument cannotgive us a reason to recognize the value of humanity compatibly with the

    conception of the force of a reason with which it begins. The apparent force

    of the argument relies, I believe, on the fact that we so easily lose our grip on

    this conception of normativity and slide insensibly back into the ordinary,

    realist point of view.18

    514 W.F. Bristow

  • Dow

    nloa

    ded

    By:

    [Alv

    es, M

    arco

    Aur

    elio

    ] At:

    18:0

    5 10

    Sep

    tem

    ber 2

    007

    IV. Self-consciousness, the need for a reason and abysmal freedom

    I conclude that Korsgaard does not succeed in showing us the answer in

    reflection itself to the practical question constituted by our capacity for

    practical reflection. In this last section, I want to question the moral of our

    criticism.19 What follows? Prominent options are: skepticism (regarding the

    justification of practical norms in general or only of moral norms in

    particular); despair or nihilism (if that differs from skepticism); or con-

    cluding that this way of posing the practical problem is misguided from the

    beginning.

    I want to suggest a moral different from these. In order to address this

    question, we need to re-visit the need for a reason raised by reflection on

    ones practical impulses and demands. What would meet this need? On the

    one hand, the need seems very difficult to satisfy, since, insofar as it arises

    through the capacity to back up from a practical impulse and subject it to

    critical scrutiny before granting it authority, the reason needed must be one

    in principle exempt from further reflective scrutiny. We need, not just a

    practical reason, but a regress-stopping, foundational reason, a reason that

    makes it impossible, unnecessary or incoherent to ask why again (SN

    p. 33). Such reasons are notoriously hard to come by.

    However, on the other hand, when Korsgaard gives her argument against

    the moral skeptic, the demand for a reason (or on reason) seems to slacken.

    Korsgaard admits that the reason she finds for endorsing the moral

    principle is at best conditional: if you acknowledge the existence of any

    practical reasons, then you must value your humanity as an end in itself.20

    The reason Korsgaard offers for conforming to moral requirements pre-

    supposes our commitment to the force of the non-moral practical reasons

    that we recognize. If the skeptic calls these into question at the same time,

    then, according to Korsgaards own admission, we are at a loss to answer

    his challenges. Presumably Korsgaard is willing to make this concession

    because it seems minimal: having pushed the skeptic to the extremity of

    denying wholesale the force of all practical reasons, the skeptical hysteria is

    revealed as such. The cost of following the skeptic in his all-consuming

    doubt proves too high to pay. According to Korsgaards argument,

    supposing that we are unwilling to pay that cost, we are constrained to

    recognize the normativity of the moral principle.

    However, this response misses the point, if the question is whether we find

    in reflection the materials to satisfy the need for a reason constituted

    through this reflection. The answer to the question of what satisfies this need

    ought not depend on what the given reflecting individual, as a matter of

    contingent, psychological fact, is or is not able to accept. Rather, the

    standards of satisfaction of the need ought to be determined internally by

    what motivates the reflection in the first place. Korsgaards justification

    does not satisfy, according to those internal standards. The need for a

    Self-Consciousness, Normativity and Abysmal Freedom 515

  • Dow

    nloa

    ded

    By:

    [Alv

    es, M

    arco

    Aur

    elio

    ] At:

    18:0

    5 10

    Sep

    tem

    ber 2

    007

    reason arises from the fact that, when one reflects on ones practical

    impulses, their authority for one is suspended, pending the provision of a

    justification. The suspension of the authority of the practical reasons that

    ordinarily move one in reflection is what motivates the need for a reason

    in reflection, hence the search for the practical unconditioned, in the first

    place. Clearly then, one cant rely on the authority of those practical reasons

    in justifying the authority of the unconditional principle in reflection. The

    consideration that, unless one recognizes the authority of the moral

    principle, no practical reasons at all have authority may move a given

    individual to endorse the moral principle, but the consideration does not

    satisfy the need for a reason, insofar as that need is constituted through

    practical reflection.

    Our examination of Korsgaards arguments has suggested that nothing

    satisfies the need for a reason insofar as that need is determined by the

    distance opened in reflection between oneself as deliberator and the practical

    grounds on which one chooses.21 One finds reasons in reflection, but not

    foundational or unconditional reasons, not reasons that make it impossible

    or incoherent or unnecessary to question in turn. Hence, the investigation

    here suggests what I would like to call the truth of practical skepticism:

    that we do not find internal to the stance of reflective scrutiny on the

    grounds of our choices a reason that satisfies the demand for an uncon-

    ditioned that is internal to such an inquiry.22

    Humes discussion of epistemological skepticism in his Treatise, of which

    we may be reminded by these considerations, teaches that such skepticism

    has an ambiguous moral. Hume shows that, when we take what he calls the

    intense view in reflection on the rational grounds of our beliefs, we end in

    skepticism. Humes application of the standards internal to the intensely

    critical standpoint of rational reflection undermines his natural convictions

    and threatens to cast him into doubt and despair. But, as Hume goes on

    famously to attest, when he leaves his study to dine or play, as he inevitably

    does, the natural force of his ordinary beliefs overwhelms and conquers his

    skeptical doubts.23 This calls into question the authority of the standards

    internal to the standpoint of intense rational reflection, when it comes to the

    daily business of forming and modifying beliefs in response to empirical

    evidence. Humes response to skepticism in the epistemological context

    poses the following question for our discussion: granted that nothing meets

    the standards internal to the standpoint of critical reflection on our practical

    impulses, is the appropriate response, perhaps, not despair or nihilism, but

    the rejection of the authority of such standards when it comes to the

    business of deciding how to act? Or, more generally: having come to doubt

    that anything can satisfy our need for an unconditional reason, we may be

    motivated to question the exact relation between the standards of satisfac-

    tion that hold sway within the standpoint of critical scrutiny (in which

    516 W.F. Bristow

  • Dow

    nloa

    ded

    By:

    [Alv

    es, M

    arco

    Aur

    elio

    ] At:

    18:0

    5 10

    Sep

    tem

    ber 2

    007

    nothing less than the unconditioned satisfies us) and the more relaxed

    standards we employ in our practical reasoning outside the study.

    Rather than attempting to tackle this large question that the inquiry has

    led us to, I will end by merely pointing to a positive (and to me: attractive)

    response to these skeptical considerations that one finds in the tradition. It is

    easy to suspect at the root of the need for a reason a felt need to divest

    oneself of ones abysmal freedom and responsibility. The critical reflectionon ones practical impulsesas both Korsgaard and Kant describe it

    makes one aware of that freedom and responsibility. Simultaneously it

    makes one aware of the need for a reason. The reason that answers the

    need, could it be provided, would have the effect of divesting one of that

    freedom and responsibility. The reason that would answer the need, again,

    would be such that no reflective distance between oneself in the standpoint

    of reflection and it could be opened again in turn. Hence the reason would

    be such as to command independently of ones endorsement, that is,independently of ones taking it as authoritative in the stance of reflection.

    This feature is what would mark it out as the desired unconditioned. So

    what we want in wanting such a reason, it would seem, is a reason that

    cancels our discretionary role in taking reasons as authoritative for us. We

    want a reason in reflection recognition of the authority of which is literally

    compelled. Our criticism of Korsgaards arguments suggests that no reasons

    have that sort of authority.

    If this diagnosis is correct, if at the bottom of the need for a reason asconstituted through critical reflection on the grounds of ones choice is a felt

    need to be divested of ones role in freely accepting the practical reasons one

    takes to be authoritative in ones practical reasoning, then the answer to the

    threat of despair and nihilism contained in the procedure of intense

    reflective scrutiny is not the vainly sought foundational reason, but faith in

    the authority of ones reasons, in the absence of foundational justification of

    them.

    In the writings of Soren Kierkegaard, which are a late and ambiguousfruit of the tradition of reflection, one finds repeated an image that can be

    read as an answer to Kants image for the beginning of practical reflection,

    namely, that it places us on the edge of an abyss. Kierkegaard employs

    frequently the image of the existing individual as suspended in his activity

    over 70,000 fathoms deep.24 Kierkegaard can be taken to express by this

    recurrent image that the human individual, who is as such wholly

    accountable for how he conducts his life, cannot appeal in reflection to a

    foundational justification of the norms which he takes to be authoritative inthought and action. What must suspend him over the abyss in the face of

    this recognition, what must prevent his plunging into despair, is the strength

    of his faith in the authority of the norms he recognizes, whatever they are. I

    suggest that the skeptical considerations raised here imply, not that practical

    reasons have no justified authority in our deliberations, but that practical

    Self-Consciousness, Normativity and Abysmal Freedom 517

  • Dow

    nloa

    ded

    By:

    [Alv

    es, M

    arco

    Aur

    elio

    ] At:

    18:0

    5 10

    Sep

    tem

    ber 2

    007

    reasoning never proceeds to an unconditioned in the sense that we feel in

    need of it in that standpoint; that is, our practical reasoning in reflection

    never makes unnecessary the leap of faith we are always making in taking

    the reasons we recognize to be sufficient and authoritative. Accordingly, I

    suggest that full reflection on the conditions of our agency need neither leave

    us at the edge of an abyss nor deposit us in the pit of it, but rather may find

    us suspended over it by faith in the authority of the reasons we recognize.25

    Notes

    1. Kant: Political Writings. Edited by Hans Reiss (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,

    1970) p. 224.

    2. See G. W. F. Hegel Elements of the Philosophy of Right. Edited by Allen W. Wood

    (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991) Introduction pp. 2564, especially 127,

    p. 57.

    3. Christine M. Korsgaard (1996) The Sources of Normativity. Edited by Onora ONeill

    (New York: Cambridge University Press). The volume contains, besides Korsgaards

    Tanner Lectures, an introduction by ONeill, responses to the lectures by G. A. Cohen,

    Raymond Geuss, Thomas Nagel, and Bernard Williams, and a set of replies by

    Korsgaard. I will indicate page references to this volume (abbreviated SN) in the body of

    the text.

    4. Korsgaard claims that the normative question must be posed from the first-person

    standpoint at SN pp. 1516.

    5. I ascribe the following conception of rational agency to Korsgaard partly on the strength

    of her discussion in a more recent article: Christine M. Korsgaard (1999) Self-

    constitution in the ethics of Plato and Kant Journal of Ethics Vol. 3, pp. 129.

    6. I proceed on the assumption of this interpretation of the moment of endorsement despite

    passages that suggest the psychological construal, because endorsement construed

    psychologically seems to me a non-starter for any account of the source or nature of

    practical normativity. Given that the psychological act of endorsement is contingent,

    how does the normative demand enter the account on the psychological construal?

    Suppose the answer is: when (or if) one reflects, then one needs a reason, i.e., there must

    be the dateable act of endorsement in order for action to occur, as a matter of the way

    our reflective minds actually, contingently work. But this construal of Korsgaards point

    implies too drastic a restriction on the norm-governed domain of human actions-for-

    reasons and, what comes with this, an unacceptably revisionist account of that domain.

    Speaking for myself, I do not very often back up from motives and endorse them in

    reflection before proceeding to act on them. Moreover, it is clear that whether I do or

    not makes no difference to whether I am the responsible author of the resulting action

    nor to whether I am on the hook for the provision of justifying reasons, should their

    provision be called for. Whereas the haphazard fact of psychological endorsement has

    no promise or attraction as the beginning point of an account of practical normativity,

    the moment of endorsement construed as an internal component of the representation

    of an action as authored, as an action on the basis of reasons, is a promising beginning

    for an account of the normative domain with significant antecedents in the tradition of

    reflection. For a discussion of the relation of Korsgaards moment of endorsement

    not so calledto Kants necessity of a possibility of attaching the I think to any

    representation that counts as mine, see Mark Okrent (1999) Heidegger and Korsgaard

    on human reflection Philosophical Topics Vol.27, pp. 4854. (I thank an anonymous

    referee of the paper for prompting me to expand my discussion on this point. Also, I am

    518 W.F. Bristow

  • Dow

    nloa

    ded

    By:

    [Alv

    es, M

    arco

    Aur

    elio

    ] At:

    18:0

    5 10

    Sep

    tem

    ber 2

    007

    indebted to Barbara Herman for a very thought-provoking discussion of an earlier

    version of the paper that helped me in particular to improve this part of it.)

    7. Hegel describes this as the right of the subjective will: The right of the subjective will

    is that whatever it is to recognize as valid should be perceived by it as good, and that it

    should be held responsible for an action as right or wrong, good or evil, legal or

    illegal, according to its cognizance [Kenntnis] of the value which that action has in this

    objectivity (Hegel Elements of the Philosophy of Right 1132, p. 158). Further, in the

    Anmerkung: The right to recognize nothing that I do not perceive as rational is the

    highest right of the subject

    8. Korsgaard expresses the view that obligations are, as such, always unconditional at

    SN p. 103.

    9. Kant does not argue in this way from the idea of the free will to the categorical

    imperative as its principle in the opening of the Third Section of his Groundwork of the

    Metaphysics of Morals. Kant makes the transition from the negative definition of the

    free will (the will not determined by anything external) to the positive (the will governed

    by its own law, which is the categorical imperative) on the basis of the concept of

    causality, which brings with it, he claims, that of laws. (See Immanuel Kant Groundwork

    of the Metaphysics of Morals. Edited by Mary Gregor (Cambridge: Cambridge

    University Press, 1998) pp. 5253, (Akademie edition of Kants works, Volume 4,

    pp. 446447).) Korsgaard does not suggest that Kants argument is that represented in

    the paragraph above. However, I think it is helpful to see how Kant could arrive at his

    unconditioned practical principle from within the standpoint of practical reflection on

    grounds of choice that Korsgaard insists on, and which is, according to her, the

    standpoint from within which the practical problem is discovered in the first place.

    10. Korsgaard does not note that this is a distinct form of self-consciousness from that

    discussed earlier. I comment on the distinction directly and draw out its implications

    below.

    11. According to my interpretation of Korsgaards position, the principles expressing a

    persons practical identities have unconditional authority for that person just in virtue of

    the fact that there is no reflective distance for that person between the I of which he is

    conscious in the reflective stance and those principles. And that the principles express

    practical identity implies this lack of reflective distance. However, others interpret

    Korsgaard differently, and there are resources in her text for doing so. Her justification

    of moral obligations implies that, if a persons practical identity is in and of itself

    contradictory to the value of humanity, then its claims are not normative for him (SN

    p. 126). Taking his cue both from Korsgaards recognition of a condition on the

    normativity of the demands of a practical identity and from passages that suggest that in

    deciding how to live we must choose between the conflicting practical identities that are

    available to us, Christopher Gowans takes Korsgaards position to be that an act of will

    is necessary in order to make a practical identity strongly normative for the person,

    where a strongly normative practical identity is distinguished as a source of those

    obligations the respect for which gives real worth to our lives. (See Christopher

    Gowans (2002) Practical identities and autonomy: Korsgaards reformation of Kants

    moral philosophy Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Vol.64, p.551).

    According to Gowans, in order to answer her over-arching question, Korsgaard needs

    to tell us how a contingent practical identity can be strongly normative for the person

    whose identity it is (p. 551). But, supposing this challenge is motivated, the prospects

    that Korsgaard will be able successfully to meet it are dim. Having backed up in

    practical reflection to the articulation of practical identity, weve backed up to the edge

    of the existential precipice, as it were. The only higher principle is the moral principle,

    and it is useless as a criterion if our choice is between morally permissible, but

    conflicting, practical identities. Also, the claim that we ought to prioritize that identity

    Self-Consciousness, Normativity and Abysmal Freedom 519

  • Dow

    nloa

    ded

    By:

    [Alv

    es, M

    arco

    Aur

    elio

    ] At:

    18:0

    5 10

    Sep

    tem

    ber 2

    007

    which in fact matters most to us obviously begs the question Gowans presses, which is

    why one practical identity ought to matter more to us than another, granted that those

    we choose among are all morally permissible.

    On my reading, Korsgaards account does not have this problem, since, as I read her,

    principles expressing a persons practical identity are unconditionally binding on the

    person just by virtue of the fact that they express the persons practical identity. Gowans

    reading ignores the normative significance of the fact that what is at stake in conforming

    to obligations for Korsgaard is ones identity. How a person came to have the particular,

    contingent practical identities she in fact has is not relevant to the normativity of their

    demands; that the demands express the persons identity constitutes their special

    normativity.

    Of course, my interpretation of Korsgaards view avoids Gowans challenge only by

    opening the view to other challenges. In particular, if principles expressing a persons

    practical identities are simply as such unconditionally authoritative for her, then how can

    we understand those demands as being conditioned by their conformity to moral

    principles? In fact, Korsgaard maintains that, since obligations are always uncondi-

    tional, moral obligations do not always trump other obligations: Conflicting

    obligations can both be unconditional; thats just one of the ways in which human life

    is hard (SN p. 126). Nevertheless, some of Korsgaards statements clearly conflict with

    the view that the demands of a persons practical identity are simply as such

    unconditionally binding on the person. Again, the conclusion of her argument justifying

    moral obligations is that practical conceptions of your identity which are fundamen-

    tally inconsistent with the value of humanity must be given up (SN p. 130). Further, she

    claims: obligation is always unconditional, but it is only when it concerns really

    important matters that it is deep (SN p. 103). An obligation is unconditional as

    expressing ones identity. But Korsgaard also writes: some parts of our identity are

    easily shed, and when they come into conflict with more fundamental parts of our

    identity, they should be shed (SN p. 102, my emphasis). This certainly seems to express

    the following condition on the authority of any principle that expresses ones practical

    identity: the condition that there be no principle with which the given principle conflicts

    which expresses a more fundamental part of ones identity.

    In short, Korsgaards position in her Tanner lectures with respect to the question of

    whether the demands of a practical identity are simply as such obligatory seems not to be

    completely fixed. I pursue the reading I do here because of my interest in examining

    Korsgaards view as re-animating a project of the tradition of reflection.

    12. Korsgaard herself argues in the more recent publication referred to above (Self-

    Constitution in the Ethics of Plato and Kant) that the principle that expresses the self-

    consciousness of the free or self-determining agent is solely the categorical imperative.

    She expresses the conclusion of her argument as follows: To put the point in familiar

    Kantian terms, we can only attach I will to our choices if we will our maxims as

    universal laws. The categorical imperative is an internal standard for actions, because

    conformity to it is constitutive of an exercise of the will, of an action of the person, as

    opposed to an action of something within him (p. 27). According to Korsgaards

    position in the Tanner Lectures, in contrast, the authority of a principle that expresses

    some particular practical identity of yours is as such (that is, as expressing your practical

    self-conception, whatever it is) beyond question. Further, you are autonomous in acting

    from such a principle by virtue of the fact that it expresses your practical self-conception.

    The argument Korsgaard runs in the Self-Constitution paper implies that no contingent

    practical content is suited to express practical self-consciousness immediately, because

    all such content is subject to the condition of being able to have the I will attached to

    it (that is, of being willed as a universal law). If this constraint is an empty formalism,

    then practical self-consciousness imposes no constraint. The principle that expresses

    520 W.F. Bristow

  • Dow

    nloa

    ded

    By:

    [Alv

    es, M

    arco

    Aur

    elio

    ] At:

    18:0

    5 10

    Sep

    tem

    ber 2

    007

    practical self-consciousness must be a pure, or formal, principle; it cannot be infected

    with contingent content.

    13. The distinction between the two sorts of self-consciousness is roughly that which Sartre

    famously draws between what he calls thetic (reflective) and what he calls non-thetic

    (unreflective) self-consciousness. (See Being and Nothingness. Translated by Hazel

    Barnes [New York: Washington Square Press, 1956] pp. 917.) But Sartre does not

    claim, unlike others in the tradition, that a principle expressing non-thetic self-

    consciousness is a highest principle for either theory or practice. The original source of

    the distinction, presumably, is Kants discussion in his transcendental deduction of the

    categories, where, in the context of arguing that a principle expressing self-consciousness

    is the highest principle in the whole sphere of human knowledge, he distinguishes

    between empirical self-consciousness and pure or original or transcendental self-

    consciousness, which latter is alone suited to serve as a governing principle (see Critique

    of Pure Reason. Translated and Edited by Paul Guyer and Allen W. Wood [Cambridge:

    Cambridge University Press, 1998] B131-140).

    14. See Korsgaards discussion in her essay Kants Formula of Humanity in Christine M.

    Korsgaard (1996) Creating the Kingdom of Ends (Cambridge: Cambridge University

    Press) pp. 110114.

    15. See SN pp. 120125.

    16. Thus Korsgaard writes, in the midst of the argument: It is because we are such animals

    [that is, animals who need practical conceptions of their own identity, conceptions which

    are normative for them] that our practical identities are normative for us, and, once you

    see this, you must take this more fundamental identity, being such an animal, to be

    normative as well (SN p. 123, my emphasis).

    17. In addition to bringing with it the original problem, this conditional analysis suggests

    another. The conditional suggests that the pressure on my identities will be felt only

    insofar as I engage in the activity of reflection. This fact accounts for the much

    chronicled human tendency to evade Socratic questioning of our values. The call to

    justify our values in reflection rouses in us anxiety and resistance, even if we consider

    ourselves relatively good persons, because we fear that the failure to justify will put

    pressure upon us to change or will deprive us of the practical guidance and orientation in

    our lives that we derive from reliance on our uncriticized values. Granted that the

    activity of reflection itself threatens our identity, if we adopt Korsgaards claim that an

    obligation consists in a threat to ones identity, must we not acknowledge, not merely a

    temptation, but an obligation, to refrain from this activity?

    18. We see Korsgaard trying to keep a firm grasp on this conception of normativity in her

    response to one of Cohens objections at the end of her Repliesand failing, I think.

    Gerald Cohen objects in his response to Korsgaards lectures that, if the force of a

    practical obligation just consists in ones identity being at stake in the demanded action,

    then a Mafioso who is motivated by his Mafioso identity to do some hideous thing

    required by the Mafia code of hono