Bader Ethics

31
Constellations Volume 12, No 3, 2005. © Blackwell Publishing Ltd., 9600 Garsington Road, Oxford OX4 2DQ, UK and 350 Main Street, Malden, MA 02148, USA. The Ethics of Immigration Veit Bader Migration, Immigration, and Practical Philosophy Migration, the geographical movement of people in order to settle in other places for longer periods of time, has extensively been analyzed by historians and social scientists, but philosophers have thought little – and said even less – about it. This gap is quite astonishing if one considers the fact that migration policies involve highly contested normative judgments in all phases. Yet historically, moral and political philosophers and political theorists have rarely discussed migration; none developed a coherent ethics of migration. Only in the past thirty years have theorists begun to think about the issue, but still we do not have any comprehen- sive and systematic treatment. Two main reasons may help explain this astonishing gap. First, predominant political thought after World War II has been preoccupied with finding general principles of justice under ideal conditions. Hence it has almost completely neglected the separateness of (nation-) states, the normative relevance of state membership, and broader issues of international justice. 1 Second, any ethics of migration is particularly broad and complex. Migration involves many phases: emigration (root and intermediate causes), immigration or actual first admis- sion, and the different stages of incorporation. Seen from the perspective of affluent state-societies with liberal-democratic constitutions, the normative issues can be grouped accordingly: Do their governments and (organizations of) citizens have duties to fight the root causes of migration in order to make it possible for people to stay where they have been born and raised? Do people not only have a right to emigrate but do governments also have an obligation to let the different categories of migrants – refugees, asylum seekers, family mem- bers of current residents, economic and cultural migrants – in? Do the broadly recognized principles of state-sovereignty and non-interference imply that states are free to exclude all or to select freely to admit some and exclude others? What, if any, would be morally legitimate and what are morally impermissible criteria of selection in first-admission policies? If people have passed this first gate of entry, 2 ought the rights and duties of permanent residents (denizenship, the second gate of entry) resemble, or might they legitimately differ from, those of citizens? Do states have an obligation to naturalize all permanent residents (third gate of entry into full citizenship), or may they refuse some? If so, what are morally legitimate criteria of exclusion? Finally, what are minimal moral

Transcript of Bader Ethics

Page 1: Bader Ethics

Constellations Volume 12, No 3, 2005. © Blackwell Publishing Ltd., 9600 Garsington Road, Oxford OX4 2DQ, UK and 350 Main Street, Malden, MA 02148, USA.

The Ethics of Immigration

Veit Bader

Migration, Immigration, and Practical Philosophy

Migration, the geographical movement of people in order to settle in other placesfor longer periods of time, has extensively been analyzed by historians and socialscientists, but philosophers have thought little – and said even less – about it. Thisgap is quite astonishing if one considers the fact that migration policies involvehighly contested normative judgments in all phases. Yet historically, moral andpolitical philosophers and political theorists have rarely discussed migration;none developed a coherent ethics of migration. Only in the past thirty years havetheorists begun to think about the issue, but still we do not have any comprehen-sive and systematic treatment.

Two main reasons may help explain this astonishing gap. First, predominantpolitical thought after World War II has been preoccupied with finding generalprinciples of justice under ideal conditions. Hence it has almost completelyneglected the separateness of (nation-) states, the normative relevance of statemembership, and broader issues of international justice.1 Second, any ethics ofmigration is particularly broad and complex. Migration involves many phases:emigration (root and intermediate causes), immigration or actual first admis-sion, and the different stages of incorporation. Seen from the perspective ofaffluent state-societies with liberal-democratic constitutions, the normativeissues can be grouped accordingly: Do their governments and (organizationsof) citizens have duties to fight the root causes of migration in order to make itpossible for people to stay where they have been born and raised? Do peoplenot only have a right to emigrate but do governments also have an obligation tolet the different categories of migrants – refugees, asylum seekers, family mem-bers of current residents, economic and cultural migrants – in? Do the broadlyrecognized principles of state-sovereignty and non-interference imply that statesare free to exclude all or to select freely to admit some and exclude others?What, if any, would be morally legitimate and what are morally impermissiblecriteria of selection in first-admission policies? If people have passed this firstgate of entry,2 ought the rights and duties of permanent residents (denizenship,the second gate of entry) resemble, or might they legitimately differ from, thoseof citizens? Do states have an obligation to naturalize all permanent residents(third gate of entry into full citizenship), or may they refuse some? If so, whatare morally legitimate criteria of exclusion? Finally, what are minimal moral

Page 2: Bader Ethics

332 Constellations Volume 12, Number 3, 2005

© 2005 Blackwell Publishing Ltd.

requirements with regard not only to legal incorporation of permanent residentsand naturalized citizens but to a broad range of economic, social, and culturalpolicies of incorporation? All these interrelated questions are hotly contested.3

Even a short overview of all these debates is, obviously, beyond the scope ofan article. For two reasons, I focus on immigration, i.e., migration across stateborders and corresponding first-admission policies. First, immigration and firstadmission are, in my view, even more contested in politics and in practical philo-sophy than incorporation. Incorporation policies compatible with minimal moralrequirements of liberal-democratic constitutions include a common core increas-ingly recognized by competing traditions in practical philosophy but stronglycontested recently in practical politics: permanent residents increasingly have thesame civil and social rights as citizens and, in the EU, they even have some polit-ical rights;4 long-term residents, particularly second-generation immigrants, areincreasingly being naturalized even in states like Germany, and naturalizationrequirements are becoming more moderate;5 even dual or multiple nationalityseems less objectionable. Defensible incorporation policies require not only legaland political equality, but also some minimal economic and social equality, andcultural minorities are less likely to be expected to assimilate or to be segregated.These sea-changes in the moral landscape are at least partly also affirmed bydefenders of moderate particularism in practical philosophy. The hard core ofmore exclusivist policies is therefore first admission, and it is here that opinionsof universalists and particularists in politics and practical philosophy mostobviously clash. Second, first-admission policies are not only the most contestedissue of migration policy, they are also the least developed aspect of an ethics ofmigration.

The aim of the article is thus to present and critically discuss the relevantarguments favoring opening or closing of borders. I will employ a problem-driven rather than a theory-driven approach for two reasons. First, most theoret-ical paradigms are neither systematic nor consistent. This results, especiallygiven the general problem of indeterminacy of general principles, in quite diver-gent views on whether borders should be (more) open or (more) closed. Second,arguments in favor of open or closed borders are often shared by, and developedwithin the same, e.g., egalitarian liberal, theoretical approach. Consequently,I have chosen to contrast universalist arguments in favor of (more) open borders(II) with particularist arguments in favor of (more) closed borders (III).6 In myconclusion, I discuss the main reasons why it is so difficult to balance thesearguments, why practical philosophy is in so much trouble, and what should bedone to overcome this. And I present my own view of what a contextualizedpractical philosophy requires, why I think we should reject the conventionalrestrictive view, based on principles of fairly unlimited state sovereignty, self-determination, and non-intervention, and why we should opt for “fairly openborders.”7

Page 3: Bader Ethics

Ethics of Immigration: Veit Bader 333

© 2005 Blackwell Publishing Ltd.

I. First Admission and Traditions of Practical Philosophy

Practical philosophy has always been deeply embedded in contexts. Membershipregimes in the city-states of classical Greece were severely restrictive and thiswas declared legitimate by Aristotle in his Politics, initiating a long tradition ofrepublican exclusionism. The subsequent decline of the city-states and the rise ofthe Roman Empire saw unprecedented freedom of movement and multiple citi-zenship.8 The first waves of cosmopolitanism in the western world were advo-cated by a diverse group of thinkers, including Democritus, Antiphon, Diogenes,the Cyrenaics, Epicureans, and Stoics like Cicero, Seneca, and Marcus Aurelius,which started a long tradition of moral inclusiveness. Modern state-formation andmodern capitalism have been facilitated by the new notions of absolute sover-eignty and property, and principles of sovereignty and non-intervention werefirmly established in international law after the Treaty of Westphalia (1648).Modern political philosophy has focused on the constitutional limitation anddemocratization of government. Matters of state membership, of exit and entry,were merely taken for granted. But not completely so. Liberal consent theoriesseem to require not only that government be based on consent, but also member-ship in the polity. John Locke best exemplifies the transition from ascriptivesubjectship to consensual citizenship: every adult man is “at liberty whatGovernment he will put himself under; what Body Politick he will unite himselfto.” This seems to base the right to leave and even the right to enter a polity com-pletely on express and ongoing consent. Locke, however, severely restricts theimplications of voluntary membership by mixing choice with ascriptive criteria,allowing for tacit consent, restricting the right to leave, and neglecting issues ofentry.9 The same unresolved tensions are also characteristic of the great inter-national legal theorists of the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries (Grotius,Pufendorf, Wolff, and particularly Burlamaqui and Vattel), who allowed ascriptivebirthright citizenship alongside consensual citizenship and restricted the “naturalright” to leave, though Emmerich de Vattel defended an “absolute right torenounce his country” in cases in which it is impossible to attain subsistencethere, in which a country fails to discharge its obligations towards its citizens, orif a majority changes the terms of the national contract without his consent.10

Even Vattel “held that no other nation had an absolute duty to admit those whohad left their homelands due to exile, banishment, or some other pressingcause.”11 The “imperfect” natural right to seek residence elsewhere is counter-vened by the sovereignty of each nation “to judge, whether it is, or is not in aproper situation to receive this stranger.” This sovereign right of nations to decideon admission has been defended explicitly and with less reluctance by all modernrepublican democratic consent theorists, from Rousseau onwards.

The unresolved tension between individual and collective rights,12 betweena universalist, inclusionary, liberal tradition stressing the natural rights of allhuman beings irrespective of ascriptive criteria, including nationality, and a more

Page 4: Bader Ethics

334 Constellations Volume 12, Number 3, 2005

© 2005 Blackwell Publishing Ltd.

particularist, exclusionary, republican tradition, also lies at the bottom of theAmerican Revolution and American law.13 The “right which nature has given toall men of departing from the country in which chance, not choice has placedthem”14 has only rarely and inconsistently been accompanied by the recognition“that openness of borders to aliens and ease of immigration and naturalization arethe logical corollaries of a fundamental right to leave one’s country and settleelsewhere.”15 Immanuel Kant’s essays “with a cosmopolitan intent” restrict“Weltbürgerrecht (ius cosmopoliticum)” to the “conditions of general hospital-ity.”16 His “Recht der Wirtbarkeit” should not be misconceived as a “Gastrecht,”let alone as a right to stay; it is a right to visit that can be refused when itcan occur without his demise (“wenn es ohne seinen [des Fremden, V.B.] Unter-gang geschehen kann”).

Despite the rise of nationalism, the nineteenth century (1815–1914) has beencharacterized as the century of free movement and fairly unlimited migration.Classical political economists had criticized mercantilist restrictions andcelebrated free competition and free movement of commodities, capital, andlabor; only a minority criticized the inherent power asymmetries of British FreeTrade Imperialism (List) and of exit of capital compared to exit of labor (Marx).Apart from utilitarianism, practical philosophy did not reflect upon issues ofmembership and migration. Henry Sidgwick published the first systematictreatment of issues of membership, exit, and entry.17 The right to leave is,compared with earlier consent theories, more restricted by arguments of expediency(225, 213, 247) and emigration is governed by the military and population pol-icies of empires (213ff, 247). Sidgwick rejects an individual right to entry and allattempts to impose upon states “as an absolute international duty, the free admis-sion of immigrants” (309f, 248): “a state must obviously have the right to admitaliens on its own terms, imposing any conditions on entrance or any tolls ontransit, and subjecting them to any legal restrictions or disabilities that it maydeem expedient . . . it may legitimately exclude them altogether” (248). However,the right “to exclude them altogether” confronts us with “the general conflictbetween the cosmopolitan and the national ideals” (309). The rigor of exclusionmight be limited by distributive justice (255) and be mitigated by “the practicalallowance of free immigration” (255): “the free admission of aliens will generallybe advantageous to the country admitting them” (310, 306f).

After World War I, most states clearly judged that free movement was‘disadvantageous’ and consequently severely restricted the admission of immi-grants, political refugees, and asylum seekers. After the experiences of genocideand World War II, the legal duty and procedure for determining refugee statusand the legal duty of non-refoulment have been generally accepted (Geneva Con-vention 1951, 1967 Protocol) and continuous efforts have been made to guaranteea legal right to leave.18 A more general discussion of membership and legaland illegal migration only emerged – with the usual time lag – after the changesin American immigration law in 1965 and after western European states grudgingly

Page 5: Bader Ethics

Ethics of Immigration: Veit Bader 335

© 2005 Blackwell Publishing Ltd.

came to realize that postcolonial and guest-worker immigration had turned theminto immigration countries.

Michael Walzer was the first to break the deafening silence in contemporarypractical philosophy,19 and from then on we find an increasing stream of publica-tions on an emerging ethics of immigration. Many attempts have been made todistinguish different theoretical traditions or paradigms.20 I think it is helpfulto distinguish roughly between universalist (or moral cosmopolitan, globalist,impartialist) and particularist approaches.21 Universalist approaches can bedivided into (i) utilitarianism focusing on happiness, utility, or, more recently andpromisingly, welfare or basic needs.22 In the attempt to derive moral rights andduties from prudential obligations, its consequentialism differs from realistapproaches23 and from rational choice or mutual advantage contractarianism. (ii)More deontological approaches, stressing different varieties of equal rights of allhuman beings, like libertarian property or natural rights or the different varietiesof egalitarian liberalism or basic rights.24 (iii) More duty- and virtue-orientedapproaches like O’Neill’s.25

Particularist approaches are also highly diversified and range from liberal-democratic or moderate patriotism (Nathanson, Fletcher) and liberal nationalism(Whelan, Miller, Tamir, Kymlicka) to defenders of social-democratic welfare-states (Walzer, Føllesdal, Offe, Streeck) to tougher communitarianism and moreexclusive patriotism (MacIntyre), neo-Hegelianism (Frost), and extreme or“nasty” nationalism.26

These theoretical approaches are also internally divided: the indeterminacy ofprinciples and practical judgment explains why practical philosophers in the sametradition have argued for or against fairly open borders or international redistri-bution.27 This is the reason I have chosen a problem- or argument-drivenpresentation instead of a theory-driven presentation. On the other hand, however,it is obvious that universalist approaches favor freedom of movement and inter-national redistribution while more particularist approaches clearly oppose thesepolicies.

Even for my limited aims, difficult questions have to be answered, and noimpartial, consensual answers are available: (i) Do universalist and particularistapproaches have to be combined and, if so – as most practical philosophers think –how? Where to start, and what does this imply for the contested issue of priorityof competing obligations? (ii) Practical judgment is complex and practical reasoninvolves moral, ethico-political, prudential, and realist arguments.28 The moralought requires to treat all human beings as free and equal irrespective of allascriptive criteria. The ethico-political ought requires to further our particularnotions of the good life, in our case the specific ethos, ways of life, or culture ofthe ethno-political community of the ‘nation-state.’ The prudential ought requiresus to do what is in our well-informed, rational, long-term interest. Realist argu-ments do not, of themselves, point in any specific direction: whatever one oughtto do for moral or ethico-political reasons, one should always take into account

Page 6: Bader Ethics

336 Constellations Volume 12, Number 3, 2005

© 2005 Blackwell Publishing Ltd.

that ‘ought implies can.’ Realist arguments imply specifically negative normativestatements directed against moral oughts: ‘one should not’ do what moralityrequires. In the case of first admission, realism seems, at present, completelylinked with the particularist perspective of (nation-) states and is nearly indistin-guishable from prudential or ethno-political arguments for closed borders.29 In animaginable ideal world these four components of practical judgment may comple-ment each other harmoniously, but in the real world of first-admission policiestheir tensions are sharp and visible. Should all these different ‘oughts’ count,count equally, or should there be priority rules? How can they be compared andweighed?

I belief that all productive practical philosophy has to deal with the tensionbetween the universalizing trend of moral principles and the particularizing trendof institutions, cultures, and practices in order to avoid two dangers. First, thedanger of abstract, merely stipulated universalism, of an imaginary moral viewfrom nowhere; and second, the danger of unreflective particularism, of anuncritical acceptance of ‘our’ particular institutions and practices as “falsenecessities” or as morally right or at least as defensible “first approximations.”30

In our case, the institutional international status quo and the existing first-admission policies may turn out to be not first or second best, but “fifteenth bestor worse.”31 Obviously, there has to be some critical, reflexive disequilibrium,some back and forth connecting our moral intuitions – always intuitions of ahistorically and socially situated moral community – to more universally sharedmoral principles. If institutional settings and policies are seriously wrong from amoral point of view, one needs to gain critical distance and widen the gapbetween principles and practices, between an ideal world and the real world,before trying to bridge it.32

However difficult it may be to compare the four types of ought, at least incases of serious moral wrongs moral arguments have to trump competing ethico-political, prudential, and realist ones (the common conviction of all egalitarianliberals); otherwise morality would be practically toothless. We should thereforestart our inquiry with universalist moral arguments.

A plea to start with moral arguments does not resolve two other problems: theproblem of moral pluralism (that we live in a world of competing moral princi-ples and rights and that we have good reasons not to fix them in context-independent hierarchies) and the problem of the underdetermination of ourpractical judgments (e.g., what would Rawlsian justice require regarding freemovement and redistribution?). In such conditions it may not only be a virtue that“citizens should seek the rationale that minimizes rejection of the position theyoppose”; economizing moral disagreement may also be advisable for practicalphilosophers.33 My theoretical strategy in favor of fairly open borders will thusbe, in section II, morally and strategically minimalist; I do not claim that moral,ethico-political, prudential, and realist arguments favoring closure (III) are point-less or lack normative significance and power.

Page 7: Bader Ethics

Ethics of Immigration: Veit Bader 337

© 2005 Blackwell Publishing Ltd.

II. Arguments in Favor of Open Borders

Moral theories compatible with the constitutions of liberal democratic welfarestates and international treaties on human rights share a common core of univer-salist egalitarianism.34 The egalitarian principle of equal liberties criticizes allascriptive privileges. It is incompatible with the strong exclusionary effects ofcitizenship in a world of several (nation-)states. Citizenship laws combine criteriaof descent (jus sanguinis) and territory (jus solis), which are prima facie morallyno more defensible than sex, age, language, religion, or social class. Theuniversalism of the moral point of view, even in its considered and weak versions,does not allow prima facie moral privileges for the members of particular (nation-)states and criticizes restrictive “membership approaches” of equality.35 Broadly,two different, analytically distinct universalist arguments in favor of open borderscan be distinguished. First, free mobility is an important moral principle in itselfand should be recognized not only as a basic moral, but also as a legal humanright independent from issues of poverty or distributive justice (II.1). The secondargument tries to show that states have a moral and legal obligation to let peoplein as long as and to the degree that they do not live up to their minimal moral obli-gations to guarantee basic human rights to safety and subsistence for all humanbeings irrespective of nationality (II.2). The two approaches are often not clearlydistinguished,36 and they can be seen as mutually reinforcing: free movement canbe seen as a “reduction of political, social, and economic inequalities” and openborders are morally required to the degree that severe international inequalitiespersist.37 Yet others object that they are bound to conflict as soon as one asks“whether affluent countries should give . . . priority to those who are poorest andmost in need, if all who wish to enter cannot be admitted.”38

II.1. Free Movement

Free movement has played an important role in economic utopias of completelyfree markets (free exit and entry of all commodities, capital, and labor) and corres-ponding free trade policies by many classical political economists and in standardneo-classical theory of free trade. They are said to guarantee the optimal alloca-tion of all factors of production and, consequently, to benefit all, at least in thelong run.39 Chang provides excellent prudential arguments for liberalizedimmigration based on an equilibrium theory from three different perspectives:particularist national economic welfare, the welfare of immigrants, and globaleconomic welfare.40 In addition, recent demographic developments and projecteddifficulties to finance pension-schemes contribute to a remarkable shift in theprudential balance sheet. On the basis of such arguments a strong case can bemade against the remarkable and persisting inconsistency in neoliberal regimesand policies which stimulate free exit and entry of capital but restrict free entry ofworkers.41 Two inherent flaws of standard theories, however, have been pointed

Page 8: Bader Ethics

338 Constellations Volume 12, Number 3, 2005

© 2005 Blackwell Publishing Ltd.

out by institutionalist critics. First, capital, particularly financial capital, is moreflexible, mobile, and ‘footloose’ than labor: workers are relationally and cultur-ally more rooted and less mobile.42 Second, free exit of capital, combined withfree entry of workers, structurally weakens the organizations and power-positionsof labor and tends to undermine the thicker legal regulations and institutions ofwelfare states (see below III.4). Defenders of free movement of labor againstexclusionary politics of Big Labor like Roberto Unger have to address these prob-lems in order to avoid the double counterproductive effects of weakening laborwithin affluent states without strengthening it globally (thus making all workersworse off).43 If institutionalist critics are right regarding this highly contestedprudential and realist issues, if defending the “weak” would require particularistclosure, then the need for a moral defense of free movement of people would bemore obvious.

Freedom of movement is presented as a basic moral right of natural persons,unlike commodities or capital, mainly for two reasons. First, from Hobbes on, itis seen as an important liberty in itself, sometimes even as “the first and most fun-damental of man’s liberties.”44 Second, it is (more instrumentally) seen as (i) avital prerequisite for other freedoms, like autonomy, personal self-determination –from which it gains its fundamental importance in comprehensive liberal theoriesof morality – or human rights to marriage and family life; (ii) as a condition ofmeaningful equality of opportunity; and (iii) as a condition of more substantive ormaterial equality or an instrument of distributive justice.45

Freedom of movement across state borders implies both a right to leave a statetemporarily or permanently (right to exit) and a right to enter another state (rightto entry). The exit right is based in liberal and democratic theories of consent (seeabove). As a right to escape from oppressive or otherwise unresponsive states, itis an important mechanism for making governments more democratic and res-ponsive: “exit, voice, and loyalty.”46 Increasingly, it is legally recognized that theright to emigration and voluntary “expatriation” includes the right to stay(proscription of expulsion and involuntary expatriation) and the right to return(distinguishing emigration from banishment).47 The freedom to leave imposesthree correlative, demanding duties on states: not to hinder emigration (byrefusing papers, unfair impositions etc.), to make return possible, and to furtheradmission elsewhere, because a right to leave without being able to entersomewhere is actually ineffective.48 A general legal right to entry, however, does notexist and even in the case of the right to refuge, asylum, and family re-unification,the corresponding duties of states are imperfectly and badly allocated. Beforediscussing and evaluating the arguments for such a general moral right to entry,however, we should take into account the limitations of a moral right to freedomof movement recognized by its defenders.

There are no ‘absolute’ rights and the presumption of free movement, likeother basic individual rights, can be overridden. “The above mentioned rightsshall not be subjected to any restrictions except those which are provided by law,

Page 9: Bader Ethics

Ethics of Immigration: Veit Bader 339

© 2005 Blackwell Publishing Ltd.

are necessary to protect national security, public order, public health or morals orthe rights and freedoms of others, and are consistent with the other rights recog-nized in the present covenant.”49 Most defenders of the moral and legal right toexit accept that it can be overridden not only by other basic rights, but also byother special moral and legal obligations. The right to exit does not legitimizeevading punishment for serious crimes, payment of debts, compulsory universalmilitary or civil service and, as some argue, even paying back public costs forhigher education. Obviously, these limitations can be interpreted very restric-tively or very extensively, and the margins of discretion get even wider when itcomes to “national security, public order, public health or morals.” Even defend-ers of as liberal as possible a right to exit do not, in principle, deny the morallegitimacy of some of these limitations.50 Equally, the right to internal free move-ment and settlement is seen to be legitimately limited by other basic individualrights, and also by indigenous peoples’ collective land and autonomy rights, andby prudential and realist arguments – avoiding congestion, necessary regulationsof space (traffic, building, city- and regional planning, and so on) – and otherimportant values (e.g., protection of wildlife, nature), which can be interpreted insuch an extensive way that little actual freedom is left.

At present, state laws and international law do not guarantee a universal humanright to international free movement and residence. These liberties are explicitlyrestricted to “everyone lawfully within the territory of a State,” excluding illegalimmigrants, and hold only “within that territory,” excluding a general right toentry.51 Why should there be such a general moral right to free entry, strongenough to generally outweigh competing moral rights, particularly democraticself-determination?52 To be plausible, such a view should explicitly reject theideas that each right is a trump in itself (unrestricted freedom of movement as themost basic human right), that all rights (the long list of – often competing – civil,political, social, and cultural human rights) are equally compossible, and thatrights cannot be limited by other normative arguments. The main issue, then, isthe weight of a moral right in balancing all relevant normative arguments.

The weight of freedom of movement alone – without referring to other basicrights or to principles of equal opportunity or distributive justice – is contested. Inbalancing rights, reference to basic human needs seems particularly convincing,and many practical philosophers agree that ‘security’ and ‘subsistence’ are theparamount basic needs. Even among liberal universalist rights theorists, only afew seem to defend the claim that free movement has the same weight or status.Indicative is the ambiguity of John Rawls in this regard. At one point, he lists(presumably internal) free movement as among the basic liberties of citizens, butin his Theory of Justice it is not explicitly included.53

The argument by analogy – that international free movement should be treatedexactly like internal free movement54 – is not convincing: it either neglects moralprinciples of democratic self-determination completely, or it neglects the import-ance of democratic states among other units in emerging democratic multi-level

Page 10: Bader Ethics

340 Constellations Volume 12, Number 3, 2005

© 2005 Blackwell Publishing Ltd.

polities (see below III.1 and III.3). If it is accepted that states still are importantloci of democratic self-determination, it cannot show why limited ‘sovereignty’should be regularly overruled: the prudential and realist reasons limiting internalfreedom of movement may be much stronger in the case of free entry.55 Sociolo-gical and historical arguments that try to show that the development of capitalism,the modern state, and modern society require internal free movement and nowa-days – referring to ‘globalization’ – global free movement, are empirically highlycontested and lack normative force.56

The argument pointing to the asymmetry of exit and entry opens up a morepromising avenue. The recognition of the right to refuge and asylum presupposesthat state sovereignty and self-determination have to yield in cases of “well-founded fear of being persecuted” or, in another language, that the basic right orneed to security is strong enough to outweigh other rights and competing ethico-political, prudential, and realist arguments. Evidently, the refugee definition inthe Convention is today very inappropriate: it is highly individualistic (focused on‘activists’ and ‘targets’ rather than on ‘victims,’57 it does not cope with theprotection needs of women, children, those fleeing civil war or generalizedviolence58), and it does not recognize ecological catastrophes, famine, and otherreasons for flight and forced migration. Morally motivated proposals for reformof the Refugee Convention start from the insight that threats to security cannot beneatly and easily separated from threats to subsistence, but even then not allreasons for leaving a state count equally and are serious enough to outweigh allarguments to restrict entry (in Zolberg’s proposal it is still “well founded fear ofviolence” and flight, not all other reasons people may have to leave a state59).Most people feel that “freedom from want and fear” are more basic than manyother rights and freedoms. Freedom from fear, however, is not only recognized inthe set of civil rights protecting basic security but also in corresponding duties,whereas freedom from want or basic rights to subsistence and the declaration ofthe respective economic and social human rights is not accompanied by anadequate allocation of the corresponding duties. This points to a serious gapbetween broadly recognized moral requirements and recent international law.

Prudent defenders of a free right to entry recognize the weakness of argumentsbased on free movement alone. They recur to other arguments – either more basicrights to security and subsistence, or more demanding principles of internationalequality of opportunity or distributive justice – to add urgency to the moral claimsfor open borders. A considered right to free entry, then, has to be part of a morecomplex normative argument.

II.2. Poverty and/or Global Inequality

Compared with arguments from free movement, arguments in favor of openborders based on moral requirements of basic subsistence or international distri-butive justice seem to have obvious disadvantages. They are not direct and

Page 11: Bader Ethics

Ethics of Immigration: Veit Bader 341

© 2005 Blackwell Publishing Ltd.

straightforward, they do not imply a strong individual right to immigration, andthey do not hold even in an ideally just world. Still, critics of closed borders havelinked the moral permissibility of closure to issues of poverty and distributivejustice.60 The analogy to threats of basic security is striking: a basic right isviolated, challenging the moral standing of the system of states; direct policies toprevent violations are preferable (in this case to fight poverty or gross inter-national inequality), but if they are not feasible or effective, ‘we’ have an indirectmoral obligation to help the victims.61 The nature of the link between poverty orglobal inequality and open borders, though, is rarely clarified: it may be remedial,causal, or moral.

Free immigration is not an effective remedy for poverty because the proportionof the world’s poor that might be helped in this way would be very small. Therelief provided by open borders would be imperfectly distributed because thosewho can afford to migrate are usually not among the worst-off. Moreover, freemigration could lead to a brain drain, leaving the worst-off even worse off.Finally, such an approach could weaken pressures on governments to addressproblems of poverty where they emerge.62 As an anti-poverty strategy, “immigra-tion is at best one strategy among several”; it may not even be a “second-best”stopgap.63 Poverty is only one of the many motivational causes of migration. Itcannot by itself explain why people migrate, let alone when and where theymove. Nevertheless, poverty is – along with and increasingly interrelated withviolence – the most important structural cause of forced migration.

The perceived threat of hundreds of millions refugees and migrants serves asthe main argument to close borders. The counterargument, which stresses thestate’s obligation to maintain open borders, is intended, firstly, to show thatclosure is impermissible as long as poverty or gross inequality exists and,secondly, to undermine standard arguments in political rhetoric and practicalphilosophy favoring closed borders. The link is specifically a negative, indirect,and moral one. “The aim is to argue that, if arguments for international distribu-tive justice are valid and if rich countries do not want to give generously of theirmoney to meet the demands that those arguments impose, then they are morallyobliged to pay instead in a currency that they hold even dearer . . . to admit sub-stantial numbers of immigrants from the poorest countries.”64

The argument puts the finger on the festering sore of poverty or seriousinequality and urgently asks for effective remedies: Open your wallets or openyour borders! Whatever their inherent value may be, closed borders can only bemorally permissible if, and to the degree to which, states fulfill their minimalmoral obligations following from humanitarianism or distributive justice. Underconditions of rough, complex international equality, normative arguments infavor of closure (be they ethico-political, prudential, or realist) would gain inpractical legitimacy because closure would lose its sting. If citizenship in rich andsafe states ceased to be a privilege, exclusion would be less a prima facie moralwrong. This if has two aspects. The first is temporal: as long as measures to fight

Page 12: Bader Ethics

342 Constellations Volume 12, Number 3, 2005

© 2005 Blackwell Publishing Ltd.

poverty are not taken or as long as they are not really effective, ‘we’ (individuals,organizations, states in affluent societies) have no moral right to close borders.The second is gradational: to the degree that affluent states do not live up to theirinternational moral obligations, they have no moral right to close borders. Thisdouble if makes all other arguments conditional upon the prior fulfillment of ourmoral obligations with regard to safety and subsistence. For sake of brevity, I callthis the Global Moral Obligation (GMO) proviso.

Two theoretical strategies should be distinguished. First, moral obligations tofight poverty and the corresponding allocation of duties and policies (II.2.1).These arguments are more minimalist, and are shared by all theorists defendinguniversalism even in its thin, most moderate varieties.65 The required moral limi-tations of sovereignty and self-determination thus have to be accepted by alldefenders of ‘moderate’ patriotism. The required ‘sacrifices’ and policies (aid)are also less demanding. Second, moral obligations to fight global inequality andthe corresponding allocation of duties and policies (II.2.2). These arguments aremore demanding, require a stronger universalist – though not an extreme univer-salist – foundation and may seem less convincing to moderate patriots. Theyrequire stronger limitations on sovereignty and self-determination, more sacri-fices and more demanding policies (redistribution) and are, expectably, morecontested, although they can be grounded in a morally minimalist argumentationshared by all varieties of egalitarian liberal theories of distributive justice.

II.2.1. Poverty and Aid

The basic argument includes three steps. First, some hardly ever contested rock-bottom ‘facts.’ About one billion people live under conditions of severe poverty,whichever standards one uses.66 Extreme poverty is all-encompassing: it con-cerns all aspects of life in mutually reinforcing vicious circles. It is permanent,not simply momentous, and the prospects of the poor of changing their predica-ment on their own are utterly bleak. And finally, relative poverty, the huge gapbetween affluence and poverty, is growing globally as well as inside some afflu-ent states, notably the US. Secondly, almost all approaches to moral theory acceptthat those who are able to help, without ‘supererogatory’ sacrifices (‘cut-off forheroism’), have a moral duty – and in some countries also a legal duty – to help.67

Help is not an act of charity or generosity but a moral obligation.68 Thirdly, thismoral duty is indiscriminately addressed to all those who are able to help: richindividuals, organizations, states. Tackling the problems of this imperfect alloca-tion of duties requires, minimally, adding institutionalist or collectivist policies(Shue, Goodin, Elfstrom, Jones) to an overly individualist approach (Singer,P. Unger).69

Postponing contested answers to urgent questions like: how much aid is minim-ally required? what would be adequate institutions and policies for fightingpoverty effectively?, this strategy has the obvious advantage of not asking ‘too

Page 13: Bader Ethics

Ethics of Immigration: Veit Bader 343

© 2005 Blackwell Publishing Ltd.

much.’ It does not require ‘maximizing’ utility or welfare, but focuses on “basicwants,” “basic needs,” or “basic rights” fighting “malfare.”70

II.2.2. Global Inequality and Redistribution

Extreme poverty is not an unalterable state of nature or the human condition. Atleast in our times, it can and should be prevented. However, poverty is notdescribed or explained in relational terms and is therefore not seen as a severeinjustice. The second strategy tries to make plausible that the worse-off are worseoff because the better-off are better off. Such a causal connection between pov-erty and affluence constitutes more demanding moral duties to avoid and preventgross inequalities. The second strategy is thus more demanding and more con-tested both in a descriptive and explanatory regard and from a moral perspective.

It starts from a richer interpretation of the egalitarian universalism of the moralpoint of view, connecting equal liberties with issues of distributive justice: (i)Citizenship and exclusion: state membership is, in the present situation of grossinequalities among states, one of the crucial mechanisms that guarantee andsanction these inequalities.71 “Citizenship in Western liberal democracies is themodern equivalent of feudal privilege – an inherited status that greatly enhancesone’s life chances. Like feudal birthright privileges, restrictive citizenship is hardto justify when one thinks about it closely.”72 (ii) One of the basic assumptions ofrecent moral theories is that people should not benefit or suffer from morallyarbitrary natural and social contingencies like natural talents or handicaps or thegood or bad luck to be born of rich or poor parents. A radical “membershipapproach” to equality73 restricts the scope of the argument to contingencies insidestates and neglects natural and social contingencies among states, whereasmoderate patriots, moderate and extreme universalists recognize that (a) nobodydeserves to be born into a rich or poor country, (b) the distribution of naturalresources among states is a “natural lottery”, and (c) the moral legitimacy of theinheritance of all other advantages of “national economies” must also be verylimited.74 Depending upon the degree of radicality, these arguments should beable to overrule sovereignty, national self-determination, and priority for compa-triots under circumstances of serious global inequality (see below III.1).

Theories of distributive justice are particularly contested if they try to picturemodels of ideally just societies, but the degree of dissent can be considerablydiminished if one starts from the opposite end of severe injustice, gross inequal-ity.75 Three argumentative strategies try to link poverty to gross inequalities.Their descriptive and explanatory claims are fairly minimalist and it is possible tofind much “overlapping consensus” among rival traditions in order to reinforceand strengthen the resulting moral duties of redistribution.76 (i) The rich andthe poor live in a global economic and political order with one system ofcommon institutions for which we are morally responsible. The structure of thissystem reproduces gross inequalities and there are better and practically feasible

Page 14: Bader Ethics

344 Constellations Volume 12, Number 3, 2005

© 2005 Blackwell Publishing Ltd.

alternatives. (ii) Even if states were completely self-contained entities, as thoserejecting (i) try to show, there is a strong case for GMOs in situations where thedistribution of natural resources among states is radically unequal. The better-off have a moral obligation to compensate the worse-off because the naturalresources should be the joint possession of humankind. (iii) The starting positionsof the better- and the worse-off are a result of massive crime, force, and fraud,and the history of conquest, colonialism, and imperialism implies for all –particularly for retrospective – theories of justice strong moral claims forrestitution.

Each of these three lines of argument is in itself sufficient to show that grossglobal inequalities constitute severe injustice and each invites us to allocate ourmoral duties. These approaches need not be mutually exclusive. Often, but not inall cases, they reinforce each other. This is not the place to discuss feasible –moderate or more radical – alternative policies and institutions better able to fightpoverty and injustice.77 Thomas Pogge is correct when he asserts that our firstmoral priority ought to be projects that address poverty and global injusticedirectly, instead of fully opening our borders. However, policies to eradicatepoverty directly and policies of fairly open borders are not mutually exclusivealternatives.78 The problem is that affluent states do not succeed and will notsucceed in the near future in “alleviating the terrible conditions that make themwant to come here in the first place.”79 As long as this is the case, our moral andpolitical projects still have to include moral criticism of policies of closedborders. We cannot, counterfactually, presume that policies to address povertyand global injustice will be successful in the long run and close our eyes in themeantime.

III. Why Closed Borders?

Borders should be closed, so it is said, (i) because moral priority should be givento compatriots, and because states have an important role in the allocation ofduties; (ii) because fundamental civil and (iii) political rights (including demo-cratic political culture and virtues) can only be guaranteed in this way; (iv)because social rights and welfare arrangements have to be defended; and (v)because ethno-national cultures have to be protected. These moral, ethico-political, and realist arguments are often mixed. They are presented in strong or inweak forms.80 They need not be thinly veiled welfare chauvinism and should not,in my view, be dismissed per se, but they have to be balanced in practical judg-ment against moral and prudential arguments for open borders.

III.1. Priority for Compatriots and the Moral Standing of States

Two conflicting perspectives, the universalist view and the bounded view, seemto tear any coherent view of moral philosophy apart. The extreme universalist

Page 15: Bader Ethics

Ethics of Immigration: Veit Bader 345

© 2005 Blackwell Publishing Ltd.

view, defended by Godwin and Tolstoy, declares all particular, special relationsmorally irrelevant and consequently does not recognize any special obligations,particularly no moral obligations for compatriots. The extreme particularist view,implicit in all forms of extreme nationalism, does not recognize any transnationaland global moral obligations. Both views operate with a flat world of socialrelations and enforce dichotomous choices between either global or particularlistobligations, making extreme universalism not only extremely demanding but alsocounterintuitive and extreme nationalism morally repulsive. Actually, specialrelations are multiple and overlapping: they range from intimate relations amongpartners or spouses, parents and children, or friends to relations among serviceproviders (teachers, physicians, therapists, etc.) and clients to relations amongpractitioners of specific cultures, among members of cities, provinces, or statesto specific transnational relations.81 Most moral philosophers acknowledge thatspecial moral obligations can arise from these relations apart from those moralobligations we owe to all human beings. Three questions, however, are particu-larly contested.

First, does the character or quality of the relations matter or do special obligationsarise independently from the value of relations, communities, or states, as defend-ers of priority for compatriots often hold?82 A critical scrutiny of their argumentsdemonstrates that the value-independent approach is morally indefensible.83

Second, most philosophers agree that intimate relations, compatible with min-imal moral requirements, create special obligations justifiable in universalistterms,84 but utilitarians like Singer or Goodin, libertarians, and extreme liberals,feminists, and socialists tend towards abstract cosmopolitanism and are reluctantto accept special national obligations. Is the “argument by analogy” in the defenseof priority for compatriots sound?85 Three objections are valid: (i) the imagery ofa “morality of concentric circles” suggests a ready-made answer to questions ofpriority of moral obligations: there is just one throw of one pebble, and thestrongest obligations are the closest, getting weaker and weaker the farther awayfrom this centre and unduly discounting trans-national and global obligationsa limine.86 (ii) Modern nations are “imagined communities” and compatriots arestrangers in the sense that we do not directly or personally interact with them. Therelevant moral sentiments could thus not be love and care, like in misleadingblood and family analogies, or at least not the same kinds of love and care. Theadequate public morality is a morality of strangers.87 (iii) Defenders of a priorityfor compatriots often use a textbook model of ideally democratic and “genuinenation-states.”88 Actual states, however, are neither ethno-nationally or culturallyhomogeneous communities nor unqualified democratic communities; they arecold, hierarchical organizations based on the threat of physical violence.

These are strong arguments against unqualified communitarian defenses ofpriority for compatriots. Do they also convincingly show that nations and demo-cratic polities are “morally irrelevant”?89 Is a co-national exactly in the same waya stranger as members of foreign states, as Shue claims?90 Four arguments refute

Page 16: Bader Ethics

346 Constellations Volume 12, Number 3, 2005

© 2005 Blackwell Publishing Ltd.

this claim: (i) special relations do not only result from intimacy or direct inter-actions. (ii) It neglects that not only thick, shared values or cultures may createspecial ties and obligations, but also a common political history, commonpractices of contestation, and even bitter conflicts.91 (iii) If and to the degree thatthere exists a common ethno-national culture compatible with minimal moralrequirements, this may create special obligations among those sharing thesepractices. This argument gains in strength if these cultures are intrinsically inter-mingled with the huge and morally legitimate variety of practices of liberaldemocracy.92 (iv) Even if states could and should be strictly neutral and anti-perfectionist, as many liberal political philosophers claim, their civic relationswould generate special political obligations for compatriots neglected by abstractcosmopolitans (and democratic patriotism rightly has pointed out its democraticweakness).93

Third, as a result, many liberal philosophers like Rawls and Dworkin accept evenfairly unqualified versions of a priority for compatriots;94 others (like Ackerman,Carens, and Whelan) do so in a much more considered and circumscribed way.There is clearly more room between intimates and complete strangers and in thisspace divergent philosophical positions – from moderate cosmopolitanism andmoderate patriotism to liberal and democratic communitarianism and liberalnationalism – can meet and find a minimalist common ground: considered priorityfor compatriots can play a legitimate role in a multi-layered model of moralobligations. It has, though, to be constrained by two arguments:

(i) States, whether nation-states or not, have to fulfill their GMOs. This rules outany unconditional priority for compatriots (‘my country right or wrong’). Allreasonable defenders of moderate patriotism, liberal nationalism or commu-nitarianism acknowledge this limitation (Walzer, Miller, Tamir, Nathanson,Scheffler). Under conditions of scarcity of resources, global and special obli-gations do not “peacefully coexist” but may imply “serious conflict.”95 Thenglobal obligations must be strong enough to overrule national obligations.This poses unresolved questions: how can these conflicting obligations bemeasured and compared? How much is needed to fulfill the GMOs? Howlarge a gap between the standards imposed by national and global obligationscan be considered morally acceptable?

(ii) The relevant historical and social ties are not confined to state-members.States would have to “recognize special obligations . . . towards specific pop-ulations that may result from active involvement in the affairs of anothercountry, from geographical proximity, or from historic ties.”96 The domesticobligations of states extend beyond their citizens and include all residents.97

Their transnational obligations include family members of citizens, immi-grants, and refugees. Their colonial history has created moral obligationstowards immigrants from former colonies. Their involvement in the affairs ofother states creates special responsibilities with regard to refugees fleeing

Page 17: Bader Ethics

Ethics of Immigration: Veit Bader 347

© 2005 Blackwell Publishing Ltd.

from those countries, etc. Their international obligations towards otherstates, resulting from treaties or from historical injustice, create specificobligations like restitutions, special ‘aid’ programs towards ex-colonies.Supranational and global obligations create specific responsibilities forredistribution (e.g., within the EU) and for refugees and asylum seekers(e.g. minimum quotas, burden sharing, etc.).

The recognition of such transnational obligations sheds new light on thecontested moral standing of states and their role in allocating duties.98 ‘Liberalstatist,’99 democratic, and particularly communitarian theorists accord intrinsicvalue to liberal democratic states (see III.3). For utilitarians, states can only bejustified in a strictly “instrumental” (Goodin) and “derivative” (Elfstrom) way asmeans to maximize utility or basic needs, and for libertarians like Nozick asmeans to guarantee absolute rights of individuals.100 But even the latter have toacknowledge that states may help to address the problem of imperfectly allocatedduties, which perpetuates poverty and forced migration.101 Declaring universalbasic rights to security and subsistence without adequately allocating the corre-sponding duties is “hypocrisy and fraud.”102 “We can clearly identify the rightand its bearers, but not who has to comply with the corresponding obliga-tions.”103 States have the duty to resolve this problem within their borders byfighting poverty and preempting the reasons for forced emigration. The clearrecognition and fulfillment of their trans-domestic special obligations could helpalleviate the problem by reducing the number of unallocated duties, particularlyif one could convincingly translate unspecified and unrelational ‘deprivation’ or‘poverty’ into more specific contexts of international exploitation and oppres-sion.104 The deserving poor out there would then be seen as people and countrieswhose basic rights have been violated, with known bearers of the correspondingduties to help. Yet this would not resolve the problem because the basic needs ofthose who cannot claim special relations or who are not covered by globalschemes would still not be satisfied.

It is very hard to compel states, particularly weak states and (for differentreasons) the sole remaining superpower, to fulfill their domestic, transnational, andglobal obligations. The existing international institutions are “primitive andclumsy.”105 Recent humanitarian and peace-keeping or -enforcing interventionshave tragically weakened international law, as in Kosovo, and increased thetension between geopolitical governance and humane governance.106 The war ofthe US-UK coalition against Iraq has tragically and decisively weakened alreadyweak UN institutions. Concerted global efforts to fight poverty are lacking (see thedisasters of the conferences in Monterrey and Cancún). The design of suprana-tional and global ‘mediating’ institutions, and the crafting of policies to remedy themisallocation of duties and to coordinate the required state activities, remains anurgent task. As long as no considerable progress is achieved, the moral standing ofthe system of several states is seriously defective and moral pressures to override

Page 18: Bader Ethics

348 Constellations Volume 12, Number 3, 2005

© 2005 Blackwell Publishing Ltd.

national obligations and state sovereignty seem legitimate, especially if one criti-cizes the false choice between the exclusive alternatives of either a world govern-ment or ‘sovereign’ states by designing democratic multilevel polities.

Obviously, the moral standing of states also depends upon the degree to whichthey actually fulfill their duties internally: “The primary reason which can legiti-mate restrictions on immigration is the maintenance of a comprehensive systemof civil, democratic and social rights of citizenship.”107

III.2. Public Security and Civil Rights Need Closure

The state owes the guarantee of civil rights not only to state members, but to allresidents and foreigners on its territory because civil rights are not citizenshiprights strictly speaking, but human rights allowing for a further specification ofrights for tourists, residents, and citizens.108 Reasons for exclusion referring tothis dimension of citizenship can only be realist reasons. One of the preferredlegitimations for closing borders is that the overwhelming number of migrantswould pose a threat to public order and social stability. This realist argument, ifcorrect, would have serious moral implications because the maintenance of publicorder belongs to the well-allocated duties of states to guarantee basic civil rightsof citizens and residents recognized even by advocates of more open borders.There are levels of immigration that cannot be exceeded without serious negativeconsequences for the receiving state, but these levels are highly contested andcannot be discussed without intimate knowledge and information of the demo-graphic, economic, and socio-political conditions of each state. The ‘blackscenarios’ (B. Barry) of defenders of restrictive policies are clearly examples ofirresponsible rhetoric – especially when the presumed ‘propensity to crime’ ofimmigrants are culturalized or racialized – but it would be naïve to dismiss alldangers in this regard. The potential tension between fair admission and fairincorporation policies grows as more people enter because it is irresponsible toadmit people without minimally adequate employment, education, healthcare,and housing opportunities. Incorporation policies involve costs, and prudentialistshave to balance them with the expected and actual benefits of immigration.109 Ifthe threats to public security and the huge costs are not simply alarmist rhetoric,the argument would only add weight to the duty to guarantee minimal safety andsubsistence for the excluded. At present, we see exactly the opposite: in moststates, the ‘overwhelming numbers’ of immigrants are far below any reasonablethreshold and the same states that apply ever more restrictive policies do notfulfill their GMOs.

III.3. Democracy Needs Closure

Democratic decision-making in all polities (from cities to transnational unions likethe EU) presupposes, first, well-defined and relatively stable rules of membership,

Page 19: Bader Ethics

Ethics of Immigration: Veit Bader 349

© 2005 Blackwell Publishing Ltd.

and, second, democratic culture and trust. The fact that democracy needsmembership and some form of closure, however, does not determine the design ofinstitutions.110 It is compatible with a world of many ‘sovereign’ democraticstates and with a world of multi-layered and overlapping democratic polities inwhich conceptions and practices of sovereignty and self-determination arelimited, divided, and delegated.111 It also does not determine the character ofmembership rules. The need for closure is compatible with the traditional mix ofjus sanguinis and jus solis rules as well with rules that require short residencyperiods and allow easy naturalization and dual citizenship. The fact thatdemocratic decision-making requires closure cannot, by itself, justify highlyexclusionist first admission policies without appealing to democratic culture andtrust.

The necessity of trust and democratic culture is seen to favor closed borders intwo different, interconnected ways. First, majority decisions are acceptable onlyunder conditions of trust, meaning that citizens are sufficiently benign and rea-sonable as not to exploit minorities. Trust is historically linked to “nation-stateforms of political integration.”112 This argument is mainly directed againstproposals to delegate powers to supranational or global units, but it is alsomobilized against immigrants who cannot be trusted owing to their lack of acommon history of special relations. Second, the entry of many immigrants whosupposedly lack a tradition of, or are even hostile to, civic and democratic culture –like the ‘Catholic Irish’ in the nineteenth century or the ‘fundamentalist Muslims’nowadays – will inevitably threaten the maintenance and flourishing of democracy.The maintenance of democracy or the protection of “the ongoing process ofliberal conversation itself”113 is a value recognized by ‘thin’ liberal democrats114

and by all stronger democrats (Barber, Unger), democratic communitarians likeWalzer, and republicans like David Hollinger or Michael Lind. Three remarks areminimally in order:

(i) The following arguments are valid: civic/political and ethno-national culturecannot be, and need not be, completely disentangled; democratic practicesare inevitably embedded in ethno-national cultures and traditions; and ittakes time to learn the different – morally permissible – ways of doingdemocracy. However, ethno-political cultures vary on a scale from a fairly‘thin’ (in Canada) to a very ‘thick’ ethnic core (in the French republican orthe German ethnocentric model). Liberal democracy clearly favors ‘thinner’cultures, but even these may necessitate some ceiling to the admission ofculturally unaccustomed newcomers, as the accommodative capacity ofpolitical societies is limited (Ackerman) and it takes time to accommodate.

(ii) The legitimacy and height of these ceilings cannot be evaluated withoutlooking at the predominant model of democracy and the specific culturesof immigrants. Yet it is unfair to confront a textbook model of a sharedand vivid democratic culture among compatriots with a chaotic band of

Page 20: Bader Ethics

350 Constellations Volume 12, Number 3, 2005

© 2005 Blackwell Publishing Ltd.

anti-democratic foreigners looking to invade the democratic paradise.Different groups of immigrants may have practiced different degrees orforms of democracy in their countries of origin. Moreover, outrightfundamentalist opposition to liberal democracy is, to a large extent, areaction by immigrants to illiberal and anti-democratic practices of dis-crimination, exclusion, and marginalization, and especially to miserablestate policies of assimilation. And states that cultivate the myth of ethno-national homogeneity and lack deeply-rooted democratic cultures, such asGermany or Japan, also use these arguments to legitimize illiberal, exclu-sionist admission and incorporation policies.

(iii) Under conditions of rough, complex equality among states, the collectiveright to democratic self-determination prioritized by democratic particular-ists would not guarantee unjust distributions and, consequently, need not beoverruled. Even morally permissible thicker ethno-political models of state-societies defended to protect welfare (III.4) or ethnic culture (III.5) wouldlose their distributive exclusionary sting.

III.4. Welfare, Solidarity, and Closure

Maintaining adequate welfare and social rights inside states is one of the strongestreasons in favor of closure against environments in which no similar systemexists. In general, three lines of arguments support this point of view.

(i) Higher standards may be directly derived from the previously discussedpriority for compatriots.

(ii) Higher standards may derive from self-determination of democratic‘nation-states.’ Democratic self-governance may lead to a diversity ofequally just social arrangements and may “conflict with trans-borderclaims to equality.”115 The claim that different standards and welfareregimes must be accepted as a consequence of the indeterminacy ofprinciples of social justice116 and as an expression of democracy can belegitimate if it is qualified in two ways. First, no matter how high theirdomestic standards may be, democratic states would have to fulfill theirGMOs. Second, the flourishing of political democracy requires a min-imum of socio-economic equality, denied only by libertarians. It holds forall democratic states, irrespective of differences in social standards andwelfare regimes. The “egalitarian thrust of nationality” is laudable butempirically contested.117 One should avoid widespread fallacies in con-clusions from what democratic nation states should do – reduce domesticinequalities – to what they actually do. At present, domestic and inter-national inequalities are growing simultaneously.118 These states cannotlegitimize restrictive immigration policies by referring to their domesticduties.

Page 21: Bader Ethics

Ethics of Immigration: Veit Bader 351

© 2005 Blackwell Publishing Ltd.

(iii) Free mobility of labor under conditions of neoliberal market integration isseen – by neo-institutionalist critics of standard economic theory – to under-mine domestic systems of collective agreements, co-determination, neo-corporatist governance, and social services in the receiving countries.119

Supranational and global institutions of governance cannot be made demo-cratically legitimate because there exist no corresponding ‘people,’ ‘publicsphere,’ or ‘trust.’120 If they can develop common policies of social securityand services at all, then this would necessarily mean a ‘race to the bottom.’The most fundamental reason for this is a supposedly inevitable trade-offbetween inclusiveness and trust, solidarity, and motivation: the more inclusiveand culturally heterogeneous polities become, the less trust, solidarity, andmotivation can be expected, so we are told.121 Democratic welfare states areonly possible as culturally fairly homogenous ‘nation-states.’ This claimis empirically implausible, as demonstrated by the examples of Australia andNew Zealand.122 It is theoretically contested.123 It may be possible to trans-form the one ‘big trade-off’ into many smaller ones.124 The argument is alsosomewhat unbalanced because the same authors recognize that the mainthreat to viable democratic welfare states comes not from immigration butfrom “free exit of capital.”125 Still, it is evident that under present conditionsof neoliberal globalization and triadic supranational institutions likeNAFTA, ASEAN, and the EU, free migration of labor undermines higherdomestic standards without helping to raise global standards. If this is a validtheoretical and empirical claim (see section II), then it provides strong rea-sons why some ceilings to first admission are required. Completely openborders would make the poor and less resourceful worse off, both domesti-cally and globally.

In sum, double or multiple standards in social security and services can belegitimate. This leaves tricky questions concerning definitions, measurement, andcomparison, in particular: How big a difference between the global minimum andthe domestic standards is legitimate and tolerable?126 How can global justice anddifferences in democratically agreed-upon domestic standards be balanced? Onlycontextualized judgment can give plausible answers. As long as states do notfulfill their GMOs and the demands of domestic equality, all three lines of argu-ment are morally pointless. If states actually complied with these requirements,the exclusionary arguments would become more plausible, thus lending statesmore democratic and social legitimacy.

III.5. Ethno-national Culture Demands Closure

Arguments for closure based on security, democracy, and welfare are inextricablyinterwoven with protection and maintenance of “thick” ethnic or nationalcultures. Civil, political, and social rights constitute the core moral and legal

Page 22: Bader Ethics

352 Constellations Volume 12, Number 3, 2005

© 2005 Blackwell Publishing Ltd.

principles of modern social-democratic constitutions, and mainstream liberalismteaches us that they are ethnically blind. Even if political cultures cannot becompletely disentangled from ethno-national ones,127 a liberal-democratic stateshould be as neutral as possible with regard to economic and social opportunitiesand as even-handed as possible with regard to competing majority and minoritycultures.128

Ethnocentric and nationalistic arguments for closure are incompatible withliberal-democratic principles.129 The same is true for strong communitarian orperfectionist calls for closed borders, assuming that the central purpose of thestate is to protect and develop a supposedly homogeneous culture. However, notall arguments favoring fairly closed borders for broadly cultural reasons stipu-late some pure, homogeneous, static, uncontested ‘national culture.’130 Recog-nizing important differences between liberal communitarians, liberal nationalists,and moderate cosmopolitans, it is still possible to detect a common moral andrealist core in their arguments. The moral argument is based on a distinctionbetween relatively free cultural change (including retention, accommodation,assimilation) on one hand, and enforced cultural change on the other. Insidestates, ethnic and national minorities should be protected against state policies ofenforced assimilation and against the unfair outcomes of the working of ‘strictlyneutral’ or ‘difference-blind’ mechanisms, such as markets or elections. Someform of collective autonomy seems required in all cases of longstanding struc-tural inequalities among majorities and minorities.131 On the international level,state sovereignty may legitimately protect against policies of cultural assimila-tion by other states. In both cases, ceilings for immigration and settlement maybe morally permissible. The realist argument explains why. Cultural continuityis perfectly compatible with cultural pluralism and cultural stability includescultural change. The core issue is not the preservation of an existing culture or anexisting ‘plurality of nomoi,’ but the rate of cultural change or, more precisely,the avoidance of externally enforced, excessive cultural disruption.132 Therealist proviso reminds us that – highly contested – ceilings to immigration andsettlement are required in order to avoid enforced disruption and ensuresufficiently gradual change. Again, this is a terribly open-ended formula inurgent need of context-specific delineation.133

If closure to maintain a “national” culture took place under conditions of roughinternational equality, it would clearly conflict with recent globalization, but itwould cease to be a pressing distributive moral problem. In practice, restrictionson first admission that are intended to preserve cultural stability and continuityare morally legitimate only if states fulfill their minimal global obligations. Themore states close their borders, the higher the moral pressure should be for themto fulfill their GMOs. That they do not recognize such a trade-off between higherdegrees of “cultural closure” and more pressing GMOs is demonstrated by thefact that Germany devotes a mere 0.3 percent of its GDP to external developmentaid.

Page 23: Bader Ethics

Ethics of Immigration: Veit Bader 353

© 2005 Blackwell Publishing Ltd.

Contextualized Morality and Fairly Open Borders

For all their drawbacks, these five arguments for closure, combined with otherrealist and prudential reasons, explain why completely open borders are neitherfeasible nor desirable. Some degree of closure is morally permissible and ethico-politically required. Do not, however, these same arguments add up to a convincingplea for closed borders? Does not ‘fairly open’ actually mean exactly the same as‘fairly closed’? The crucial question for practical philosophers and policymakersalike, then, is the degree of openness or closure.

Practical philosophy has to take into account the complexity of practical judg-ment and, at the same time, to admit that it does not possess a method to exactlycompare, let alone calculate, the diverging moral, ethico-political, prudential, andrealist reasons. Universalist moral reasons prescribe that the right to free move-ment has to be balanced and that GMOs have to be fulfilled, but practical philo-sophy cannot tell us at exactly what points states fall below the minimallyrequired threshold. Particularist arguments favoring a ‘qualified’ priority forcompatriots or a ‘limited veto’ suffer from the same indeterminacy and vaguenessas realist provisos of necessary ‘ceilings’ not to be surpassed in order to guaranteepublic security, democratic or ethno-national culture, and welfare. These ques-tions can only be productively addressed in specific contexts making use of allrelevant information and practical knowledge. No generally valid answers canbe expected, but this does not mean that contextualized morality would becompletely opportunistic, that all judgments would be purely ‘subjective,’ that‘anything goes,’ and that we would only be able to repeat that ‘it depends.’GMOs and the right to free movement should have the power to overrule otherreasons in particular contexts, and the advantage of strategies of moral minimal-ism consists exactly in mobilizing as much overlapping consensus as possible inthis regard. Contextualized approaches in practical philosophy also have to recog-nize that information, descriptions, and explanations by sober and critical socialscientists – which it urgently has to use – are contested, but there are clearly betterand worse ones. In both cases, good cognitive and normative judgment and‘educated guesses’ are more than simply the continuation of the battle of interestsor the warfare of political ideologies in practical philosophy. The development ofsuch a gradualist, empirically informed, and institutionally rich practical philoso-phy is, in my view, the most urgent task on the recent research agenda.

It may be deplored that practical philosophy is unable to prescribe exactly whatwe have to do, or this fact may be welcomed as a condition of freedom for publicdeliberation and democratic decision-making informed by context-specific moralarguments and by the critical social sciences.134 I am convinced that at present theaffluent states, given all important differences of degree among them, by far donot meet their GMOs. As long as and to the degree that they do not, their moralstanding is deplorable. Discussion of special obligations, security, democracy,domestic welfare, and culture then only serve to hide welfare-chauvinism and to

Page 24: Bader Ethics

354 Constellations Volume 12, Number 3, 2005

© 2005 Blackwell Publishing Ltd.

avoid that ‘ought implies costs.’ Substantive policy changes are urgently neededto win the fight against global poverty and insecurity. The prospects for thesechanges are bleak, but they are not precluded by institutional impossibilities.Democratic and humane forms of supranational and global governance, includingpolicies of fairly open borders, may be much harder to achieve than some of theirproponents assume.135 But they are feasible and urgently required for the sake ofhumanity. Looking back from a possible future, the philosophical defenders ofstate-sovereignty, non-intervention, and restrictive admission in our day mightlook to those happier people like the philosophical defenders of slavery look to us.

NOTES

1. Charles Beitz, Political Theory and International Relations (Princeton: Princeton Uni-versity Press, 1979); Will Kymlicka, Multicultural Citizenship (Oxford: Clarendon, 1995), ch. 1.

2. Tomas Hammar, Democracy and the Nation State: Aliens, Denizens and Citizens in aWorld of International Migration (Aldershot: Avebury, 1990).

3. Joseph Carens, “Migration, Membership, and Morality,” unpublished project proposal(2000).

4. Veit Bader, “Citizenship of the European Union,” Ratio Juris 12, no. 2 (1999): 155–181.5. Dilek Çinar, “From Aliens to Citizens,” in Rainer Bauböck, ed., From Aliens to Citizens:

Redefining the Status of Immigrants in Europe (Aldershot: Avebury, 1994).6. See for similar strategies: Frederick Whelan, “Citizenship and the Right to Leave,”

American Political Science Review 75, no. 3 (1981), 636–53; Frederick Whelan, “Citizenship andFreedom of Movement,” in M. Gibney, ed., Open Borders? Closed Societies? (New York: Green-wood, 1988), 3–39; Carens, “Migration and Morality: A Liberal Egalitarian Perspective,” in BrianBarry and Robert Goodin, eds., Free Movement: Ethical Issues in the Transnational Migration ofPeople and of Money (University Park: Pennsylvania State University Press, 1992), 25–47; RainerBauböck, “Notwendige Öffnung und legitime Schliessung liberaler Demokratien,” Arch. Europ. deSociologie XXXVIII (1997): 71–103; Gerard Elfstrom, Ethics for a Shrinking World (Houndsmill& London: Macmillan, 1990); John Isbister, “Are Immigration Controls Ethical?,” Social Justice23, no. 3 (1996): 54–67; and Charles Jones, Global Justice: Defending Cosmopolitanism (Oxford:Oxford University Press, 1999).

7. See my earlier articles: “Citizenship and Exclusion,” Political Theory 23, no. 2 (1995):211–46; “Fairly Open Borders,” in Veit Bader, ed., Citizenship and Exclusion (Houndsmill &London: Macmillan, 1997), 28–60; and “Practical Philosophy and First Admission,” SAIS Review20, no. 1 (2000) 39–60.

8. Frederick Whelan, “Citizenship and the Right to Leave,” American Political ScienceReview 75, no. 3 (1981): 643f.

9. See sharp criticism by William Godwin, Enquiry Concerning Political Justice and itsInfluence on Modern Morals and Happiness (Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1976).

10. Whelan, “Citizenship and the Right to Leave,” 649; James Nafziger, “The GeneralAdmission of Aliens under International Law,” The American Journal of International Law 77, no. 4(1983): 807–47.

11. Peter Schuck and Rogers Smith, Citizenship without Consent: The Illegal Alien inAmerican Polity (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1985), 48.

12. Michael Teitelbaum, “Right versus Right,” Foreign Affairs 50, no.1, 21–59.13. Schuck and Smith, Citizenship Without Consent.14. Thomas Jefferson, “A Summary View of the Rights of British America,” in Merrill

Peterson, ed., The Portable Jefferson (Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1974), 3–21.15. Whelan, “Citizenship and the Right to Leave,” 650.

Page 25: Bader Ethics

Ethics of Immigration: Veit Bader 355

© 2005 Blackwell Publishing Ltd.

16. Immanuel Kant, “Über den Gemeinspruch” (1793) and “Zum ewigen Frieden,” (1795),Kleine Schriften zur Geschichtsphilosophie, Ethik und Politik (Leipzig: Meiner, 1913), 135.

17. Henry Sidgwick, The Elements of Politics, 3e (London: MacMillan, 1908); in the follow-ing cited parenthetically.

18. See José Inglés, “Study of Discrimination in Respect of the Right of Everyone to LeaveAny Country,” United Nations, E/CN. 4/Sub. 2/229/Rev. 1 (New York, 1963); Antonio Cassese,“On the Universal Level,” in K. Vasak and S. Liskofsky, eds., The Right to Leave and to Return(New York: American Jewish Committee, 1976), 516; Frederick Whelan, “Citizenship and theRight to Leave”; Hurst Hannum, The Right to Leave and Return in International Law and Practice(Washington, DC: The Procedural Aspects of International Law Institute, 1985); Alan Dowty,Closed Borders: The Contemporary Assault on Freedom of Movement (New Haven: YaleUniversity Press, 1987).

19. Michael Walzer, Spheres of Justice (New York: Basic Books, 1983).20. Brian Barry, Democracy, Power, and Justice (Oxford: Clarendon, 1989); Onora O’Neil,

“Transnational Justice,” in David Held, ed., Political Theory Today (Stanford: Stanford UniversityPress, 1991), 276–304; Terry Nardin and David Mapel, “Convergence and Divergence in Inter-national Ethics,” in Terry Nardin and David Mapel, eds., Traditions of International Ethics(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1992), 297–322; Nardin, “Alternative Ethical Perspect-ives on Transnational Migration,” in Barry and Goodin, eds., Free Movement, 267–278; Barry andGoodin, “The Quest for Consistency: A Sceptical View,” in Barry and Goodin, eds., FreeMovement, 279–87; Stephen Perry, “Immigration, Justice, and Culture,” in Warren Schwartz, ed.,Justice in Immigration (Cambridge, MA: Cambridge University Press, 1995), 94–135; and Jones,Global Justice.

21. See already Sidgwick, The Elements of Politics; see also Alasdair MacIntyre, “Is Patriot-ism a Virtue?,” Lindley Lecture, University of Kansas, 1994: 5f; Stephen Nathanson, “In Defenseof ‘Moderate Patriotism’,” Ethics 99 (1989): 539; Donald Galloway, “Liberalism, Globalism, andImmigration,” Queens Law Journal 18 (1993): 274f; Sissela Bok, “From Part to Whole,” in MarthaNussbaum and Joshua Cohen, eds., For Love of Country (Boston: Beacon, 1996), 40; David Miller,On Nationality (Oxford: Clarendon, 1995): 49f, 78; Simon Caney, “Individuals, Nations, andObligations,” in Simon Caney, David George, and Peter Jones, eds., National Rights, InternationalObligations (Boulder: Westview, 1996), 7; Jones, Global Justice, 15f; and M. Freeman, “Obliga-tions, Institutions and International Justice,” ECPR paper, Mannheim, 26–31 March 1999: 2ff.

22. Sidgwick, The Elements of Politics; Peter Singer, “Famine, Affluence, and Morality,”Philosophy and Public Affairs 1, no. 3 (1972): 229–243; Robert Goodin, Protecting the Vulnerable(Chicago: University of Chicago University, 1985); idem., “What is so Special about Our FellowCountrymen?,” Ethics 98 (1988): 663–686; idem., “If People Were Money,” in Barry and Goodin,eds., Free Movement, 6–21; and Elfstrom, Ethics for a Shrinking World.

23. David Hendrickson, “Migration in Law and Ethics: A Realist Perspective,” in Barry andGoodin, eds., Free Movement, 213–232; and Hans Morgenthau, In Defence of the National Interest(New York: Albert Knopf, 1951).

24. Libertarian property (Hillel Steiner, “Libertarianism and the Transnational Migration ofPeople,” in Barry and Goodin, eds., Free Movement, 87–94; Cecile Fabre, “Justice, Fairness andWorld Ownership,” unpublished manuscript, 1999) or natural rights (Anne Dummett, “The Trans-national Migration of People Seen from within a Natural Law Tradition,” in Barry and Goodin, eds.,Free Movement, 169–180) or the different varieties of egalitarian liberalism (Rawls, Beitz, Pogge,Barry; Ronald Dworkin, Law’s Empire (London: Fontana, 1986); Carens, “Aliens and Citizens: TheCase for Open Borders,” Review of Politics 49, no. 2 (1987): 251–273; idem., “Migration andMorality: A Liberal Egalitarian Perspective,” 25–47; idem., “Immigration, Welfare, and Justice,” inSchwartz, ed., Justice in Immigration, 1–17; Dowty, Closed Borders; Rainer Bauböck, Transna-tional Citizenship (Aldershot: Edward Elgar, 1994); Simon Caney, “Human Rights and the Rightsof States,” International Political Science Review 18, no. 1 (1997): 27–37; idem., “Review Article:International Distributive Justice,” ECPR paper, Mannheim, 26–31 March 1999; M. Freeman,“Obligations, Institutions and International Justice”) or basic rights (Henry Shue, Basic Rights(Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1980); Jones, Global Justice).

Page 26: Bader Ethics

356 Constellations Volume 12, Number 3, 2005

© 2005 Blackwell Publishing Ltd.

25. Onora O’Neill, “Lifeboat Earth,” in Charles Beitz, Marshall Cohen, Thomas Scanlon,and John Simmons, eds., International Ethics (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1985); Facesof Hunger: An Essay on Poverty, Justice, and Development (London: Allen and Unwin, 1986);“Transnational Justice,” in Held (ed.), Political Theory Today; “Justice and Boundaries,” inChristopher Brown, ed., Political Restructuring in Europe: Ethical Perspectives (London:Routledge, 1994), 69–88; and Towards Justice and Virtue (Cambridge: Cambridge UniversityPress, 1996).

26. Moderate patriotism like Nathanson (“In Defense of ‘Moderate Patriotism’,” and Patriot-ism, Morality, and Peace (Lanham: Rowman and Littlefield, 1993) or George Fletcher (Loyalty: AnEssay on the Morality of Relationships (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1993)), liberal national-ism (Whelan, “Citizenship and Freedom of Movement”; Miller, On Nationality; Yael Tamir,Liberal Nationalism (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1993); Will Kymlicka, ContemporaryPolitical Philosophy, 2e (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2002)) to defenders of social-democratic welfare-states (Michael Walzer, “Response to Veit Bader,” Political Theory 23, no. 2(1995), 247–49; Andreas Føllesdal, “Do welfare obligations end at the boundaries of the NationState?,” in Koslowski and Føllesdal, eds., Restructuring the Welfare State (Berlin: Springer, 1997),145–63; Claus Offe, “Demokratie und Wahlfahrtsstaat” and Wolfgang Streeck, “Einleitung: Inter-nationale Wirtschaft, nationale Demokratie?,” in Streeck, ed., Internationale Wirtschaft – NationaleDemokratie (Frankfurt & New York: Campus, 1998), 99–136 and 11–58) to tougher communitarian-ism and more exclusive patriotism (MacIntyre, “Is Patriotism a Virtue?”), neo-Hegelianism(Mervyn Frost, Ethics in International Relations (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996)).

27. Singer versus Sidgwick (see O’Neill, “Transnational Justice,” 282f, for the indetermi-nacy of utilitarianism) or the Rawlsian Pogge (Thomas Pogge, Realizing Rawls (Ithaca & London:Cornell University Press, 1989); “An Egalitarian Law of Peoples,” Philosophy and Public Affairs23 (2001), 195–224); Global Justice (Oxford: Blackwell, 2001)) versus Rawls (see JamesWoodward, “Commentary: Liberalism and Migration,” in Barry and Goodin, eds., Free Movement;Nardin, “Alternative Ethical Perspectives on Transnational Migration,” 268f, 274ff), for egalitarianliberalism.

28. Joseph Raz, Practical Reason and Norms (London: Hutchinson, 1975); Jürgen Haber-mas, Justification and Application (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1993); Veit Bader, “Citizenshipand Exclusion,” Political Theory 23, no. 2 (1995): 215f.

29. Goodin, “Commentary: The Political Realism of Free Movement,” in Barry and Goodin,eds., Free Movement.

30. Roberto Unger, Politics (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1987); Jules Colemanand Sandra Harding, “Citizenship, the Demands of Justice, and the Moral Relevance of PoliticalBorders,” in Schwartz, ed., Justice in Immigration, 38.

31. Mark Tushnet, “Immigration Policy in Liberal Political Theory,” in Schwartz, ed.,Justice in Immigration, 149.

32. Charles Beitz, “Justice and International Relations,” in Beitz et al., International Ethics,306; Joseph Carens, “Aliens and Citizens: The Case for Open Borders,” 262, and extensively“Realistic and Idealistic Approaches to the Ethics of Migration,” International Migration Review30, no. 1 (Spring 1996): 156–70, and “Open Borders and Liberal Limits: A Response to Isbister,”International Migration Review 34 (Summer 2000); Goodin, “What is so Special about Our FellowCountrymen?,” 686; Barry, Democracy, Power, and Justice, 447; Pogge, Realizing Rawls, 259ff;Bauböck, Transnational Citizenship, 327ff; Bader, “Fairly Open Borders,” 51f. 33. Amy Gut-mann and Dennis Thompson, Democracy and Disagreement (Cambridge, MA: Belknap Harvard,1995), 84f.

34. Will Kymlicka, Contemporary Political Philosophy, 4; Robert Goodin, “If People WereMoney,” in Barry and Goodin, eds., Free Movement, 7.

35. Donald Galloway, “Liberalism, Globalism, and Immigration,” 165ff; see below III.1.36. Carens, “Migration and Morality: A Liberal Egalitarian Perspective,” and “Reconsider-

ing Open Borders,” International Migration Review 33 (Winter 1999).37. Carens, “Migration and Morality: A Liberal Egalitarian Perspective”; Goodin, “If People

Were Money.”

Page 27: Bader Ethics

Ethics of Immigration: Veit Bader 357

© 2005 Blackwell Publishing Ltd.

38. Woodward, “Commentary: Liberalism and Migration,” 61; Thomas Pogge, “Poverty andMigration: Normative Issues,” in Veit Bader, ed., Citizenship and Exclusion.

39. See Paul Krugman and Maurice Obstfield, International Economics (New York: HarperCollins, 1991).

40. Howard Chang, “Liberalized Immigration as Free Trade: Economic Welfare and theOptimal Immigration Policy,” University of Pennsylvania Law Review 145 (1997): 1147–1244.

41. Robert Goodin, “If People Were Money.”42. Barry, “The Quest for Consistency: A Sceptical View.”43. Roberto Unger, Democracy Realized (London: Verso, 1988), 175–87.44. Maurice Cranston, What are Human Rights? (New York: Taplinger, 1973), 31; see also

Dowty, Closed Borders, 12; Carens, “Migration and Morality: A Liberal Egalitarian Perspective,”26ff; Bauböck, “Notwendige Öffnung und legitime Schliessung liberaler Demokratien.”

45. Carens, “Aliens and Citizens: The Case for Open Borders,” 255ff; Whelan, “Citizenshipand Freedom of Movement,” 8ff for Rawlsian perspectives

46. Albert Hirschman, “Exit, Voice, and the State,” World Politics 31, no.1 (Winter 1976): 92.47. Universal Declaration of Human Rights (UDHR), 13.2, 14, 15; European Convention of

Human Rights (ECHR), 4th Prot. 1963, 2.2; ICCP 12.2.48. Bauböck, “Notwendige Öffnung und legitime Schliessung liberaler Demokratien,” 75;

Aristide Zolberg, Astri Suhrke, and Sergio Aguayo, Escape from Violence (Oxford: OxfordUniversity Press, 1987), 270.

49. International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights (ICCP), 12.3.50. Dowty, Closed Borders; Bauböck “Notwendige Öffnung und legitime Schliessung

liberaler Demokratien.”51. ICCP 12.1, ECHR (European Covenant on Human Rights) 4th Prot. 2.152. See James Nafziger, “The General Admission of Aliens under International Law,” The

American Journal of International Law 77, no. 4 (1983).53. John Rawls, “Constitutional Liberty and the Concept of Justice,” in NOMOS VI (New

York: Atherton, 1963); Whelan, “Citizenship and Freedom of Movement,” 35.54. Carens, “Migration and Morality: A Liberal Egalitarian Perspective,” 27, 32; Goodin, “If

People Were Money,” 12; Dummett, “The Transnational Migration of People Seen from Within aNatural Law Tradition,” 173.

55. Democratic self-determination may also provide an important moral argument againstfree movement within federal states where federal units have substantial autonomy, though in thiscase it is fairly generally accepted that it cannot provide sufficient justification for restrictingfreedom of movement. As long as democratic self-determination even in multi-level polities (likeSwitzerland, Canada, or the EU) is still concentrated on the level of the ‘nation-state,’ state bordersare, in my view, also morally more important than borders between cantons or provinces and theanalogy-argument is weakened. Hence, my criticism is a contextual, conditional one because thingsmay change (e.g., in the EU). It does, hopefully, not conflict with my criticism of the conventionalview of the moral legitimacy of the existing state system presented below. Critical comments by ananonymous referee induced me to clarify this issue.

56. Bauböck, “Notwendige Öffnung und legitime Schliessung liberaler Demokratien,” 93f.57. Zolberg etal., Escape from Violence, 30ff.58. Guy Goodwin-Gill, “Asylum: The Law and Politics of Change,” lecture, Amsterdam, 19

October 1994: 7; J.C. Hathaway, “Fundamental Justice, International Comity, and the Deflection ofRefugees from Canada,” conference paper, ‘Organizing Diversity,’ Berg en Dal, November 1995;Dowty, Closed Borders, 183; Galloway, “Liberalism, Globalism, and Immigration,” 171f; RegWhitaker, “Refugees: The Security Dimension,” in Citizenship Studies 2, no. 3 (November 1998):413–434.

59. Zolberg et al., Escape from Violence, 33.60. Sidgwick, The Elements of Politics, 255; Carens, “Aliens and Citizens: The Case for

Open Borders,” 270; idem., “Migration and Morality: A Liberal Egalitarian Perspective,” 34ff;idem., “Reconsidering Open Borders”; idem., “Open Borders and Liberal Limits: A Response toIsbister,” in International Migration Review 34 (Summer 2000); Robert Goodin, “If People Were

Page 28: Bader Ethics

358 Constellations Volume 12, Number 3, 2005

© 2005 Blackwell Publishing Ltd.

Money”; Stephen Perry, “Immigration, Justice, and Culture,” in Warren Schwartz, ed., Justice inImmigration; Mark Tushnet, “Immigration Policy in Liberal Political Theory,” in ibid., 148ff;Michael Treblicock, “The Case for a Liberal Immigration Policy,” in ibid., 243.

61. Shue, Basic Rights.62. Whelan, “Citizenship and Freedom of Movement,” 11ff; Carens, “Migration and Moral-

ity: A Liberal Egalitarian Perspective,” 35ff; Barry, “The Quest for Consistency: A ScepticalView,” 282; Isbister, “Are Immigration Controls Ethical?,” 60; Pogge, “Poverty and Migration:Normative Issues,”; but see the ‘migration versus aid’ arguments: Whelan, “Citizenship and Free-dom of Movement,” 12ff; Stephen Perry, “Immigration, Justice, and Culture,” 103.

63. Woodward, “Commentary: Liberalism and Migration,” 67.64. Goodin, “If People Were Money,” 8f.65. Michael Walzer, Thick and Thin (Notre Dame and London: University of Notre Dame

Press, 1994).66. Shue, Basic Rights; Elfstrom, Ethics for a Shrinking World; Peter Unger, Living High &

Letting Die (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1996); Pogge, “Poverty and Migration: NormativeIssues”; Pogge, Global Justice.

67. Peter Singer, “Famine, Affluence, and Morality,” Shue, Basic Rights; Elfstrom, Ethicsfor a Shrinking World; O’Neill, “Faces of Hunger.”

68. Michael Walzer, “Response,” in David Miller and Michael Walzer, eds., Pluralism,Justice, and Equality (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1995), 293.

69. Institutionalist or collectivist: Shue, Goodin, Elfstrom, Jones; overly individualist:Singer, P. Unger.

70. Elfstrom, Ethics for a Shrinking World, 14ff, 27; see Jones, Global Justice, 41–49;Casiano Hacker-Cordón, Global Justice and Human Malfare, unpublished PhD manuscript,ch. 1: 19.

71. Charles Beitz, “Sovereignty and Morality in International Affairs,” in David Held, ed.,Political Theory Today, 243.

72. Carens, “Aliens and Citizens: The Case for Open Borders,” 252. See also Beitz, PoliticalTheory and International Relations; idem., “Justice and International Relations,” in Charles Beitz,et al., eds., International Ethics; idem., “Sovereignty and Morality in International Affairs”; BruceAckerman, Social Justice in the Liberal State (New Haven: Yale University Press), 93; Walzer,Spheres of Justice, 55; Schuck and Smith, Citizenship without Consent, 2; Whelan, “Citizenship andFreedom of Movement,” 10; Pogge, Realizing Rawls, 247; Elfstrom, Ethics for a Shrinking World,136; Dummet, “The Transnational Migration of People Seen from within a Natural Law Tradition,”171; Stephen Nathanson, Patriotism, Morality, and Peace (Lanham: Rowman and Littlefield,1993), 169; Donald Galloway, “Strangers and Members,” Canadian Journal of Law andJurisprudence VII (1): 152f; Martha Nussbaum, “Reply,” in For Love of Country?, 133; Bauböck,“Notwendige Öffnung und legitime Schliessung liberaler Demokratien,” 90.

73. Galloway, “Strangers and Members,” 165ff.74. Barry, Democracy, Power, and Justice, 452.75. Minimalist theories of equality are more convincing because (i) they accept an irreduci-

ble plurality of distribuenda (Amartya Sen, “Equality of What?”; Walzer, Spheres of Justice), (ii)they are more immune against challenges of cultural imperialism because they can easily take intoaccount that distribuenda are not only culturally interpreted but also weighed differentially, and (iii)they are more robust concerning inherent problems of comparing and aggregating differentresources and rewards.

76. See Thomas Pogge, “Eine globale Rohstoffdividende,” Analyse und Kritik 17 (December1995): 200; Bader, ed., Citizenship and Exclusion for extensive references.

77. See ibid., 36ff.78. Isbister, “Are Immigration Controls Ethical?,” 60.79. Pogge, “Poverty and Migration: Normative Issues,” 22.80. Jones, Global Justice, 112.81. Veit Bader, “Institutions, Culture and Identity of Trans-National Citizenship,” in Colin

Crouch, Klau Eder, and Damian Tambini, eds., Citizenship, Markets, and the State (Oxford: Oxford

Page 29: Bader Ethics

Ethics of Immigration: Veit Bader 359

© 2005 Blackwell Publishing Ltd.

University Press, 2001); Samuel Scheffler, “Individual Responsibility in a Global Age,” in SocialPhilosophy and Policy 12, no. 1 (1995): 219–36.

82. David Miller, Market, State, and Community (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1989),41; idem., On Nationality, ch. 3; George Fletcher, Loyalty; Alasdair MacIntyre, “Is Patriotism aVirtue?”

83. Caney, “Individuals, Nations, and Obligations,” 121ff; see also Stephen Nathanson,Patriotism, Morality, and Peace, pt. II; Samuel Scheffler, Boundaries and Allegiances (Oxford:Oxford University Press, 2001).

84. Nussbaum, “Patriotism and Cosmopolitanism,” 13; Nathanson, Patriotism, Morality, andPeace; Lawrence Blum, Friendship, Altruism, and Morality (Boston: Routledge & Kegan Paul,1988).

85. Caney, “Individuals, Nations, and Obligations,” 126f.86. Henry Shue, “Mediating Duties,” Ethics 98 (1998): 687–704.87. Goodin, “What is so Special about Our Fellow Countrymen?,” 665.88. David Miller, On Nationality, 59, 70, 73.89. Nussbaum, “Patriotism and Cosmopolitanism,” 5.90. Shue, “Mediating Duties,” 693.91. Miller, On Nationality; Michael Walzer, “The Rights of Political Communities,” in Beitz

et al., eds., International Ethics; Michael Walzer, “The Moral Standing of States: A Response toFour Critics,” in ibid.; Galloway, “Liberalism, Globalism, and Immigration,” 286f; Scheffler,“Individual Responsibility in a Global Age”; Stephen Perry, “Immigration, Justice, and Culture,”99f; Veit Bader, “Reasonable Partiality and Priority for Compatriots?,” Ethical Theory and MoralPractice 8 (2005): 83–103.

92. Veit Bader, “The Cultural Conditions of Transnational Citizenship,” Political Theory 25,no. 6 (1997): 783ff.

93. Nathanson, Patriotism, Morality, and Peace; Veit Bader, “For Love of Country,” PoliticalTheory 27, no. 3 (1999): 379–97.

94. John Rawls, The Law of Peoples (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1999);Ronald Dworkin, Law’s Empire, 206.

95. Perry, “Immigration, Justice, and Culture,” 109; MacIntyre, “Is Patriotism a Virtue?,” 6.96. Bauböck, Transnational Citizenship, 315.97. Whelan, “Citizenship and Freedom of Movement”; Galloway, “Strangers and Members”;

Andrew Mason, “Special Obligations to Compatriots,” Ethics 107 (1997): 427–47.98. Beitz et. Al, eds., International Ethics.99. Whelan, “Citizenship and Freedom of Movement,” 24f.

100. Goodin, “What is so Special about Our Fellow Countrymen?,” 685; Elfstrom, Ethics fora Shrinking World, 171; Steiner, “Libertarianism and the Transnational Migration of People,” 93.

101. Shue, Basic Rights; O’Neill, “Transnational Justice.”102. Shue, “Mediating Duties,” 695.103. Bauböck, Transnational Citizenship, 308.104. Miller’s account (On Nationality, 76) is particularly disappointing in this regard.105. Shue, “Mediating Duties,” 702.106. Richard Falk, On Humane Governance (Cambridge: Polity, 1995).107. Bauböck, Transnational Citizenship, 320.108. Luigi Ferrajoli, “Dai diritti de cittadino al diritti della persona,” in Danilo Zolo, ed.,

La Cittadinanza (Roma and Bari: Laterza, 1994); Bader, “Citizenship of the European Union,”159–67.

109. Michael Teitelbaum, “Right versus Right”; more sophisticated: Howard Chang, “Liberal-ized Immigration as Free Trade: Economic Welfare and the Optimal Immigration Policy.”

110. Bauböck, Transnational Citizenship, 178ff.111. Bader, “Citizenship and Exclusion,” 211f.112. Claus Offe, “Demokratie und Wahlfahrtsstaat,” 105; Miller, On Nationality, 96.113. Ackerman, Social Justice in the Liberal State, 95.114. See Whelan, “Citizenship and Freedom of Movement,” 17ff, 29ff.

Page 30: Bader Ethics

360 Constellations Volume 12, Number 3, 2005

© 2005 Blackwell Publishing Ltd.

115. Føllesdal, “Do welfare obligations end at the boundaries of the Nation State?,” 157.116. Jones, Global Justice, 165f.117. Michael Walzer, “Response,” in Miller and Walzer, eds., Pluralism, Justice, and Equality;

Isbister, “Are Immigration Controls Ethical?”;118. Nathanson, Patriotism, Morality, and Peace, 178; Philippe van Parijs, “Commentary:

Citizenship Exploitation, Unequal Exchange and the Breakdown of Popular Sovereignty,” in BrianBarry and Robert Goodin, eds., Free Movement, 164; Isbister, “Are Immigration ControlsEthical?,” 64; Bauböck, “Notwendige Öffnung und legitime Schliessung liberaler Demokratien,”100; Jones, Global Justice, 169.

119. Wolfgang Streeck, “Einleitung: Internationale Wirtschaft, nationale Demokratie?”; FritzScharpf, “Demokratie in der transnationalen Politik,” in ibid., 151–74; Paul Hirst and GrahamThompson, Globalization in Question? (Cambridge: Polity, 1998); Fritz Scharpf and VivienSchmidt, eds., Welfare and Work in the Open Economy, 2 vols. (Oxford: Oxford University Press,2000).

120. Streeck, “Einleitung: Internationale Wirtschaft, nationale Demokratie?,” 18–25; Offe,“Demokratie und Wohlfahrtsstaat,” 106f, 111f.

121. Ibid.; Streeck, “Einleitung: Internationale Wirtschaft, nationale Demokratie?”; Miller,On Nationality.

122. See vs. Walzer: Veit Bader, “Reply to Michael Walzer,” Political Theory 23, no. 2(1995): 251.

123. See A. Benz, “Politkverflechtung ohne Politkverflechtungsfalle,” PVS 3 (1998): 558–89;David Vogel, “Trading Up and Governing Across,” Journal of European Public Policy 4 (1997):556–71; Fritz Scharpf, Governing in Europe (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1999); idem.,“Problem-Solving Effectiveness and Democratic Accountability in the EU,” MPIfG working paperno. 1, 2003.

124. Veit Bader, “Building European Institutions. Beyond Strong Ties and Weak Commit-ments,” in Seyla Benhabib, Ian Shapiro, and Danilo Petranovich, eds., Identities, Affiliations, andAllegiances (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2006).

125. Streeck, “Einleitung: Internationale Wirtschaft, nationale Demokratie?,” 33ff.126. Note that this implies a decisive turn away from traditional conceptions of egalitarianism

requiring uniform application of the same standards for all both inside states and globally. Here,differential standards in different contexts are seen as morally permissible within states (providedthey guarantee to satisfy historically defined basic needs (e.g. by way of an individualized, income-independent GMI for all residents)), within the EU (Philippe Schmitter, How to democratize theEuropean Union . . . and Why Bother? (Boulder: Rowman and Littlefield, 2000)) and globally (BillJordan and Franck Düvell, The Boundaries of Equality and Justice (Cambridge: Polity, 2003). Notealso, that morally permissible is not the same as politically desirable: all radical democrats andsocialists like myself have excellent reasons to strive for less inegalitarian internal and globalrelations.

127. Joseph Carens, Culture, Citizenship, and Community (Oxford: Oxford University Press,2000); Bhikhu Parekh, Rethinking Multiculturalism (London: Macmillan, 2000).

128. Bader, “Dilemmas of Ethnic Affirmative Action,” Citizenship Studies 2, no. 3 (1998):435–73; idem., “The Cultural Conditions of Transnational Citizenship” and “Religious Pluralism:Secularism or Priority for Democracy?,” Political Theory 25, no. 6 (1997) and 27, no. 5 (1999).

129. Nathanson, Patriotism, Morality, and Peace.130. Veit Bader, “Culture and Identity. Contesting Constructivism,” Ethnicities 1, no. 2

(2001): 277–99.131. Hurst Hannum, Autonomy, Sovereignty, and Self-determination (Philadelphia: University

of Pennsylvania Press, 1990); Maurice Rickard, “Liberalism, Multiculturalism, and MinorityProtection,” Social Theory and Practice 20, no. 2 (1994): 143–170; Will Kymlicka, MulticulturalCitizenship; idem., Contemporary Political Philosophy; Rainer Bauböck, “Why Stay Together?,” inWill Kymlicka and Wayne Norman, eds., Citizenship in Diverse Societies (Oxford: Oxford UniversityPress, 2000), 366–94; Graham Smith, “Sustainable Federalism, Democratization, and DistributiveJustice,” in ibid., 345–65.

Page 31: Bader Ethics

Ethics of Immigration: Veit Bader 361

© 2005 Blackwell Publishing Ltd.

132. Perry, “Immigration, Justice, and Culture,” 113ff.133. Whelan, “Citizenship and Freedom of Movement “, 22f; Elfstrom, Ethics for a Shrinking

World, 154.134. Veit Bader, “The Arts of Forecasting and Policymaking,” in Bader, ed., Citizenship and

Exclusion, 155–74.135. Richard Falk, On Humane Governance; David Held, Cosmopolitan Democracy

(Cambridge: Polity, 1995).

Veit Bader is Professor of Sociology and Philosophy at the University ofAmsterdam, and a member of the Institute for Migration and Ethnic Studies. Heis the author of numerous articles on religious diversity, cultural identity, andassociative democracy, and editor of Religious Pluralism, Politics, and the State,a special volume of Ethical Theory and Moral Practice (2003), Citizenship andExclusion (1997), and co-editor of Associative Democracy: The Real Third Way?, aspecial volume of Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy(2001).