art_10.1007_s11245-007-9025-9

download art_10.1007_s11245-007-9025-9

of 8

Transcript of art_10.1007_s11245-007-9025-9

  • 7/23/2019 art_10.1007_s11245-007-9025-9

    1/8

    Jacques Derridas Writing and Difference

    Maurizio Ferraris

    Published online: 15 August 2007

    Springer Science+Business Media B.V. 2007

    1 Our Own Time Grasped in Thought

    Philosophy, Hegel used to say, is its own time grasped in

    thought. And, indeed, the book Im going to review would

    have been inconceivable without the technological explo-

    sion of writing (e-mail, SMS, the Internet) that has been the

    distinctive mark of the last twenty years. If this book had

    been published, let us say, in 1967 rather than in 2007, it

    would have looked like the work of an insane person, a

    visionary or an aesthete. Back in those years, there was the

    predominance of what McLuhan defined as the hot

    mediai.e. cinema, radio, television, letters were a

    disappearing species, and people made use of telephones

    only. The phenomenon of the return of illiteracy was quite

    a concrete prospect for the inhabitants of an advanced

    society. Moreover, it would have sounded absurd to say

    that there is a constitutive link between writing and

    thought, that we would have used our personal computers

    as writing machines rather than as devices for thinking, or

    that we were on the edge of an overflow of writing like the

    Babel library into which we enter every time we switch on

    our computers and phones. An illustration will suffice. In

    the 1968 movie 2001: A Space Odissey, in the spaceship

    the computer Hal is designed to think, whereas writing

    machineswhich nowadays are seen as modern artifacts

    are utilized for writing.

    Another aspect of this book that a reader of the past

    decades would have perceived as utterly out of time is the

    remarkable confidence in philosophy that comes out from

    its pages. It should be recalled, in fact, that for the large

    part of the twentieth century, the widespread opinion wasthat the end of philosophy would have come within years,

    and that something like post-philosophy was on the

    horizon. In this case, too, the expectations have been

    sharply disproved, since philosophy today seems to be

    quite in good health. It is worth considering that these

    two aspectsthe explosion of writing and philosophys

    survivalappear to have been closely intertwined with

    each other, thus disproving one of the most established and

    repeated philosophical dogmas from Plato to Gad-

    amer, according to which philosophy has to do in its

    essence with the spoken word, with dialogue, and that

    writing is therefore a potential adversary (or at least a

    degenerated form) both of the spoken word and of crea-

    tive thinking. But we live, of course, in 2007 and not in

    1967, and no one is surprised by the fact that philosophy

    has not dissolved itself into the natural or human sciences,

    or that it has not reduced itself to its own historyand

    most importantly that it is not something that belongs to

    the past.

    After all, we no longer live in the twentieth-century.

    However, it is precisely this negative circumstance that

    gives rise to one of the most objectionable traits of the

    bookalong with many other positive hintsnamely, the

    fact that the author, with the benefit of a hindsight that is

    available to any graduate student of our time, makes fun

    of some of the great authors of the twentieth century,

    whether their name is Foucault or Bataille, Levinas or

    Levi-Strauss, and simply refuses to consider them in their

    specific historical context; on the contrary, he insists on

    treating them as contemporaries. Let us be frank: as a

    thought experiment this is not funny at all inasmuch as its

    only result is to bring grist to the mill of the authors

    futile pride.

    M. Ferraris (&)

    University of Turin, Turin, Italy

    e-mail: [email protected]

    1 3

    Topoi (2007) 26:279286

    DOI 10.1007/s11245-007-9025-9

  • 7/23/2019 art_10.1007_s11245-007-9025-9

    2/8

    2 Hindsight

    Let us take the bull by the horns and deal with the first

    aspect of the book, which is not entirely pleasant. On the

    face of it, we are confronted with a survey of the mythical

    figures of French literature and thought of the last century:

    literary structuralism and the structuralism advocated by

    authors such as Levi-Strauss, Foucault, Jabes, Levinas,Artaud, Bataille The choice is undoubtedly appealing

    and definitely fascinating. Who were the ma tres a penser

    that seduced and enchanted the French and American

    cultures in the last century? What were their theories, their

    mistakes, their exaggerations, their more or less innocent

    obsessions and fixations? Every historian of culture could

    be interested in such a book. But Derridas approach is

    nonetheless morally deplorable, or at least is revealing of a

    complete lack of good taste, for he treats such authors like

    contemporaries, and criticizes them from the top of an

    experience accumulated in the successive half of the cen-

    tury. But having arrived later is not a plus, it is just a fact,just as having arrived before is not a fault in itself; to

    overlook this fact is the sign of the narrow-mindedness of

    ones historical sense, and amounts to treating disrespect-

    fully the giants, or at least the teachers, who have carried us

    on their shoulders.

    Let me consider Derridas approach to structuralism in

    the opening and in the penultimate essay, the one devoted

    to Levi-Strauss. Its easy for Derrida to argue that the

    dream of a structure completely detached from history is

    not so different in and by itself from a critique of pure

    reason. But, again, its easy to make such considerations

    half a century later. This is even truer in the case of

    Cogito and the History of Madness. From a contempo-

    rary standpoint, it is too easy a win to criticize Foucault, to

    proclaim untenable the views advocated in a 1961 book

    such as Histoire de la folie a lage classiqueFolie et

    de raison in the light of the successive, and well-known,

    failures of anti-psychiatry. But the most objectionable

    feature of Derridas critique lies in the fact that he doesnt

    appeal to empirical evidence (e.g. anti-psychiatry has

    failed) but rather simply offers captious arguments against

    Foucaults theoretical assumptions. Foucault, as the reader

    might recall, insisted on the socially constructed features of

    madness, and, at the same time, wanted to see in madness a

    radical alterity in relation to the rationality that left it out.

    Its easy for Derrida to point out that, as long as we con-

    sider madness as socially constructed, it is difficult to

    maintain that there is something in madness that is radi-

    cally at variance with the dominant rationality.

    Derrida analyzes the subject of an impossible alterity

    in detail, and, indeed, such a theme plays a fundamental

    role in his argument against Levinas, in what perhaps is the

    most dense and longest essay in the collection. As

    historians of the philosophy of the last century know well,

    Levinas philosophical activity was entirely devoted to the

    search for radical alternatives to the tradition in which we

    all grew up. Levinas saw metaphysics, as the thought of the

    person, in sharp opposition to ontology, as the thought of

    being; and, analogously, he saw Judaism in opposition

    to Hellenism, the Greek philosophical tradition. Derrida

    insists on the fact that this search is nothing other than amere illusion, just like the empiricist dreams of a pure

    experience. The alternative to traditionDerrida writ-

    esis nullified in the precise moment in which it becomes

    word; in the same way that in the essay on Foucault,

    madness is neutralized in the precise instant in which it

    becomes the subject of reason. Derrida sums up his own

    view by quoting Joyce, at the end of the essay: Jewgreek

    is greekjew: Extremes meet. In other words, alterity looks

    more like a dream than a reality. Now, its easy to reach

    such a conclusion today in the aftermath of the failure of

    revolutionary movements, or even of the critiques

    addressed by Western alternatives to the system at atime when globalization has prevailed all over the world.

    However, how can we blame someone like Levinas who

    certainly didnt have a crystal ball and lived in another

    century?

    One may ask what is the fundamental core of Derridas

    critique; as I said earlier, it is not founded on a number of

    historical evidences, but rather originates from theoretical

    considerations, not without an unforgivable vanity and a

    deleterious passion for complexity. In a more general

    sense, what we have here is a reiteration of Hegelian dia-

    lectics, made more spicy and existential by the use,

    between the lines, of Kojeves Hegelian comments. Con-

    sidered in this light, Derridas passion for modern artifacts

    never contradicts itself; however, in this respect too, Der-

    rida does not stand out for his originality. Fifty years ago,

    to talk about Hegel required some courage, all things

    considered; but nowadays, when even analytic philoso-

    phers show a renewed interest in Hegels philosophy,

    Derridas gesture is not original at all. In his essay on

    Bataille, Derrida confines himself to a number of triviali-

    ties. For he strives to show us the intrinsic virtues of

    dialectics, its being insurmountable as long as alterity can

    always be absorbed into identity and the negative always

    recovered by the positive.

    3 The Materialism of the Incorporeal

    I shall leave it to the reader to evaluate this proposal. The

    argument Derrida offers in the essays devoted to Artaud is

    somehow subtler. He praises Artauds combination of

    metaphysics and corporeality. These, however, are not

    viewed as incompatible ingredients, but rather are

    280 M. Ferraris

    1 3

  • 7/23/2019 art_10.1007_s11245-007-9025-9

    3/8

    construed as two faces of the same coin, in agreement with

    Artauds project of a materialism of the incorporeal that

    inspired his experimental theatre. (The younger readers

    may know nothing about the experimental theatre, and this

    is surely a deficiency; but Derrida feels no need to spend a

    single word to explain this phenomenon of the last century

    to the younger people.) In this case too, by underscoring

    the metaphysical theatre and the materialism of theincorporeal, Derrida runs the risk of explaining what is

    obvious at a time when metaphysics has taken, once again,

    its own place within the philosophical constellation, after

    an ostracism that lasted for the entire twentieth century; in

    fact, in the last twenty years, the debate over the mind

    body problem has become a philosophical routine. How-

    ever, there is a point that deserves attention, which

    discloses Derridas sensibility for current philosophy, a

    receptivity that I have already signaled at the outset of this

    critical review. Derridas sensibility is so strong that even

    the harshest criticas I think I amis somehow con-

    vinced to turn a blind eye to his pontificating about thegreat authors of the past. Such a sensibility reveals itself in

    Derridas construalwhich is nothing original, but is

    perfectly in accord with our timesof writing (precisely

    what is overflowing into our computers and cell phones) as

    a good instantiation of Artauds idea of a materialism of

    the incorporeal. Indeed, in this case, Derridas intuition

    appears to be well grounded. The Materialism of the

    incorporeal sounds more or less like an oxymoron;

    however, as long as writingwhich is materialcan be a

    vehicle of intelligible contents, we cannot dismiss Derri-

    das view as simply untenable, since he points to a truth

    that anyone can see. For once, let us acknowledge it,

    Derrida does not put forth a mere triviality. In his sensi-

    bility for what is actual, in fact, there are no concessions to

    the postmodern idea according to which information sci-

    ence has placed us in a dematerialized world. If it suffices

    to pull out the plug of our computers to turn them off, then,

    one can easily understand how important a form of

    materialism is even in the realm of the incorporeal (recall

    that here we are dealing with Derridas intuitions, which

    today sound much less original than they could have

    sounded twenty years ago when postmodernism was

    flourishing).

    I am quite aware that I have offered a rather critical

    analysis of Derridas views, as they are put forward in these

    essays. Nonetheless, it is difficult not to feel uncomfortable

    when confronted with such a bizarre mixture of archaisms

    and resolutely modern considerations with which virtually

    anyone can agree. Incidentally: why has Derrida left this

    book unfinished and why does he not revise his files in

    order to finish it? Why did he only write a short intro-

    ductory note in which he talks about sketches that must

    be preserved? In the age of computers, to publish

    unfinished essays is really a form of laziness. Enough with

    the cahier des dole ances. It is time to explain the reason

    why this book deserves to be published, and why there are

    reasons to believe that, in spite of everything, it will be

    quite a successful book.

    4 A Psychoanalysis of Philosophy

    The mixture of the old and the new, which is typical of

    Derrida, becomes very visible in the essay on Freud, which

    in this respect is exemplary. On the one hand, we face a

    colossal archaism, namely, the philosophical concern with

    psychoanalysis. Its been ages since this topic was dropped

    from the philosophical agenda and now we perceive it

    clearly as something belonging to the past. Derrida himself

    must be aware of this, since, at the beginning of the essay,

    he makes clear that appearances notwithstanding what

    hes proposing is not a psychoanalysis of philosophy. But

    then, for Gods sake, why should we deal with psycho-analysis? On the other hand, the caveat just mentioned has

    to be reckoned as a denegation, a Verneinung, an

    instance of that admitting by denying and denying by

    admitting which was so popular in those days when

    psychoanalysis was the latest craze in salons and

    conferences.

    But this is not the only archaism. Whos the patient to be

    psychoanalyzed here? Nothing less than metaphysics, just

    as if we were in Nietzsches time or, in the best case, in

    Heideggers. This seems to lead to the following conclu-

    sion: Derrida has spent a lot of time mocking past thinkers,

    treating them like junk store items, and then it turns out that

    his own tools of the trade are outdated as well. Like

    Nietzsches Twilight of the Idols (a 1888s work!) or He-

    ideggers writings from the 1940s. Hence, the best Derrida

    can do is the following: we have to psychoanalyze meta-

    physics, which suffers from so many tics and neuroses. He

    claims then that metaphysics, a two-thousand-years-old

    tradition which thinks of itself as being unselfishly in love

    with the truth, needs a session with the psychoanalyst. And

    the questions to be raised are: what are the grounds of such

    a love? Is it really a feeling that has nothing to do with any

    sensible motivation or technical implication? Is it true that

    theres no hidden purpose behind it? With its back against

    the wall, philosophy will try to defend herself, but Freudian

    slips hidden between the lines of its texts will uncover the

    resistances and truth will come to light.

    We have the feeling of finding ourselves in the past

    century in the middle of the 1960s, possibly in Paris, in an

    apartment in Rue Saint-Andre des Arts, where men of

    letters, philosophers and psychoanalysts (slightly Maoist,

    as was in fashion at that time) meet. Now the reply is

    foregone: this psychoanalysis of philosophy, which Derrida

    Jacques DerridasWriting and Difference 281

    1 3

  • 7/23/2019 art_10.1007_s11245-007-9025-9

    4/8

    (following Heidegger, once again) calls deconstruction,

    is pursuing truth too, and in so doing it is not immune from

    the flaws and hypocrisies of metaphysics. Nevertheless,

    Derrida seems to be more interested in the right/wrong

    dichotomy rather than in the true/false one (and here we

    can perceive the lesson of Levinas, despite the distance

    with which hes treated in the essay devoted to him): if we

    are wrong and unfair, selfish, racist, sexist, etc., thatsbecause we tend to repress too many things, caught as we

    are in a dream of presence, integrity, and identity at the

    level of morality, sociality, and sexuality. Thus, the history

    of metaphysics turns out to be dominated by a struggle

    between Good and Evil, whose presuppositions have to be

    unmasked. In this context, the philosopher will appear like

    the scholarly kinsman of the revolutionary.

    So it was no mirage, after all. We really are in Paris,

    between the Odeon and the Rue dUlm! Dien Ben Phus

    defeat happened just yesterday and the battle of Algiers

    stands out on front pages of newspapers. Philosophers,

    people who are sensitive to Marxism and who are thepsychoanalysts of their own society, think they have

    something important to say about the process of decolo-

    nization: Western rationality is not the only one; on the

    contrary, it is something historically determined and geo-

    graphically localized. Whats important in this work of

    disassembling is to question not only the purity of philos-

    ophys intentions, but also its identity, that is to say, the

    alleged existence of something like a pure philosophy,

    separated from history, sciences, myths and, of course,

    human events. This purity must be taken for what it really

    is: a myth. It has to be shown that the centre of philo-

    sophical discourse can never set its own margins (rhetoric,

    technique) aside, and that in some cases it is intertwined

    with its opposite (literature, fiction).

    That was the Zeitgeistof those days. But, again, taking

    (irritatingly) advantage of hindsight, Derrida seems to have

    fun in playing the role of an older, wiser and more

    responsible brother, when in actuality hes just a small

    grandson who writes his verdict forty or fifty years later.

    Philosophy, he explains (as if we didnt know that), is not

    merely history or geography, although it has much to do

    with (and in some respect it depends from) them. But the

    exit from philosophy isnt really so smooth and easy as

    those guys in Rue dUlm were supposing. Now that

    libraries, websites and professors desks are overflowing

    with post-colonial studies, it is worth wondering whether

    dismantling a whole tradition is really such a simple

    enterprise. Moreover, we know now that the revolution

    didnt succeed, at least not the one which had been planned

    between Rue dUlm and the Odeon. Here, again, Derrida

    indulges in belated balances and retrospective looks. But

    today its just too easy to see how things are going, whereas

    we could accept lessons from him only if we knew that he

    had really declared his intuitions in 1968s Paris, similarly

    to what Heidegger did in 1933s Germany.

    5 The Scene of Writing

    Nonetheless, in this crowd of confused and illogical claims,

    there is a truly shining gem, an idea which provides us witha useful insight not only into the spirit of 1968, but into the

    challenges awaiting us today, almost half a century later.

    Psychoanalysis is not only a way of uncovering complexes

    and repressions. It can be examined with respect to the

    concept of writing. This move may appear trifling, and

    even obsessive, if we consider how compulsively Derrida

    seems to find the theme of writingor, more precisely, of

    its repressionin all his interpretations of philosophers

    from Plato to Heidegger. Could we find in Freud, too, the

    repression of writing? The question has to be answered

    negatively. FreudDerrida points outneither represses

    nor resists writing. Indeed, he represents the mind as awriting apparatus, in agreement with the classical images

    of the mind as a tabula rasa or as an empty room from

    Plato and Aristotle to Locke; but in so doing, Freud, unlike

    many philosophers, doesnt slide toward the spirit, the

    voice, the incorporeal. On the contrary, the metaphor of

    writing, constantly emphasized, turns out to be more than a

    metaphor; it constitutes a realization of that materialism

    of the incorporeal which Derrida finds also in Artaud.

    Here we have to acknowledge an aspect of concreteness

    that characterizes Derridas perspective, which allows him

    to resist the temptations of postmodern immaterialism. And

    this is why it is ultimately correct to think of Derrida as

    belonging to the realist turn, which is typical of our

    century.

    But let me proceed in order. The main theme of the essay

    devoted to Freud is the comparison between the 1895s

    Project of a Psychology, written by a still positivist Freud,

    and a much later text, the 1925s Note upon the Mystic

    Writing-Pad.The two essays deal with the same theme. If

    experience is traditionally construed in terms of an

    inscription, how is it possible that the writing pad is not

    saturated very quickly? And how can a single space account

    for the recording as well as the forgetting and novelty of

    experience? In 1895, the physician Freud answers with a

    physiological hypothesis: there are two types of neurons;

    the first ones, impermeable, serve to record perceived

    events; the others, permeable, do not retain the impressions

    and thus ensure the novelty of experience. In 1925, the

    philosopher Freud introduces a metaphor that involves

    straightforwardly the notion of writing. The mind is like a

    mystic writing-pad, one of those old small boards where

    writing was obtained by means of a contact between a

    celluloid sheet and a base of resin.

    282 M. Ferraris

    1 3

  • 7/23/2019 art_10.1007_s11245-007-9025-9

    5/8

    Why all this emphasis on writing? And why should we

    care about the magic pad? Here the answer is rather

    obvious: because today, in 2007, we are in the age of

    writing, and a magic pad, characterized by an infinite

    possibility of inscription and deletion, can be found on

    everybodys desk; there is surely one on the desk of the one

    who is writing this review (i.e. my desk), and probably one

    on the desk of the one who is reading it. Thus, what Derridaseeks out in Freud is an insight on the present. And this

    insight has nothing to do with obsolete notions like the

    unconscious, but rather with actual and still relevant issues

    like consciousness or the mindbody relation. Here the

    main thread of Derridas discourse is, again, the materi-

    alism of the incorporeal, which, for him, is realized

    precisely in writing. If we consider how usual it is to think

    of the mind in analogy with computers, and how increas-

    ingly consciousness and knowledge turn out to be a library

    (a powerful apparatus for writing and recording) we have

    to admit that Derridas bet seems to be a winning one, and

    that his approach to Freud, despite the very unpromisingpremises, proves to be original and stimulating.

    6 From Phenomenology to Grammatology

    It should be acknowledged that the reference to writing is

    neither a mere affectation nor a concession to the over-

    whelming topicality of the theme. On the contrary, it

    reflects a rigour in approach and a solid academic back-

    ground, which do honour to the author, who proves to be

    well-grounded in his readings on phenomenology, as is

    testified to by the central (robustly academic) essay of this

    book on Genesis and Structure (a contribution to a

    conference, which is probably the original motive of all the

    essays collected here). Indeed, phenomenology is Derridas

    academic specialty, and the theme of writing, far from

    being a sociological whimsicality, is rooted in an inter-

    pretation of Husserl which tries to draw a correlation

    between his thought and dialectical materialism. In this

    context, once again, we find (but this is no longer a sur-

    prise) apasticheof the old and the new. And the old here is

    even decrepit: phenomenology and dialectical materialism!

    We plunge right into the Fifties of the past century, face to

    face with the Vietnamese philosopher Tran-Duc-Thao and

    his book Phenomenology and Dialectical Materialism

    (1951). This is a very remote world, even older than the

    one in which we tried the cocktail of Freud and philosophy,

    since the barmen serving the cocktail of phenomenology

    and dialectical materialism are not the older brothers, but

    rather the academic fathers of those who liked to mix

    Freudianism with Maoism.

    This archaism leads Derrida to an entirely original

    reworking of phenomenology, just as he did in the case of

    Freud. Actually, phenomenology is an old obsession, and

    in this connection a digression on the overall production of

    Derrida may be useful. Fifteen years before Writing and

    Difference, in his dissertation entitled The Problem of

    Genesis in the Philosophy of Husserl, Derrida used phe-

    nomenology as a tool to overcome the alternative between

    structuralism (basically idealistic) and historicism (basi-

    cally materialistic). This is very old stuff indeed,souvenirsfrom the 1950s, things whose origin can be traced back to

    the days when Claude Levi-Strauss and Raymond Aron

    debated each other. Here, though, with a youthful and

    lively impudence, Derrida pretends that the debate is even

    older than that. Thus, by introducing in this context a ref-

    erence to Husserl (who had to deal with similar problems at

    the end of the XIX century), Derrida, not only cunningly

    predates the debate, but is able to point to its upshot: his-

    tory and structure are complementary rather than opposed.

    The one involves the other; since the ideal structures didnt

    fall from heaven, they have origins to which they cannot be

    reduced (in the same sense in which logic cant be reducedto psychology).

    Ten years later, in his introduction to the French trans-

    lation of Husserls The Origin of Geometry, Derrida faced

    up to the alternative between history and structure, exam-

    ining the special case of the history of a pure science. In

    geometry idealism seems unavoidable: would we be will-

    ing to accept that Every equilateral triangle is equiangular

    is a truth of the same type as Caesar crossed the Rubi-

    con? Geometrical truth seems to be completely

    independent from any empirical fact whatsoever: Pytha-

    goras theorem would still be true even if Pythagoras had

    never existed and nobody had discovered it. And yet, as

    Derrida remarks, an idealist philosopher like Husserl has

    deeply revised this conception. Of course, Pythagoras

    theorem cant be identified with its discoverer. But the fact

    that an ideal (and, thus, not contingent) entity like Pytha-

    goras theorem exists depends on the existence of a real and

    contingent entity like Pythagoras; and if Pythagoras had

    immediately forgotten his own discovery, the whole thing,

    so to say, would have fallen into oblivion; and if he had not

    communicated to someone else his discovery, using lan-

    guage, it would have disappeared with him. Finally, if that

    discovery did reach beyond the borders of his original

    community, it was only because it was written down.

    Thus, paradoxically (but not too much), the condition of

    the ideal is to be found in something material like writing.

    InVoice and Phenomenon, just published like Writing and

    Difference, Derridas departure from phenomenology

    becomes visible and the intuition just mentioned is gener-

    alized along these lines: without writing, traces, memories,

    signs and marks in general, not only would there be no

    history; there would be no structure and idea, either. And

    this is so because what has been called structure, or, in a

    Jacques DerridasWriting and Difference 283

    1 3

  • 7/23/2019 art_10.1007_s11245-007-9025-9

    6/8

    more Kantian vein, transcendental, the condition of the

    possibility of knowledge is ultimately a form of writing.

    This is the topic of Derridas third book, published in 2007,

    whose title is Of Grammatology. Incidentally, is there

    anyone who wants to deny that a Spirit of the Time exists?

    Derrida is a true iPod philosopher, to the point that his

    philosophy would be inconceivable without it; the annus

    mirabilis of Derrida (which Gerard Granel mysteriouslylinks to mystical and Heideggerian notions like the

    withdrawal of the origin, upon reviewing the three books

    from the pages ofCritique) is actually suspended between

    Googles leap into cell phones and the release of the

    iPhone. And we should notice that all this, far from chal-

    lenging the validity of grammatological hypotheses, fully

    confirms them.

    Going back to pure philosophy: the categories, which

    according to Kant mediate our relation to the world, are

    transposed by Derrida into the notion of arche-writing,

    which sums up the function of the inscription illustrated so

    far. But Derrida doesnt show much concern for systema-ticity. Unlike the general semiotics developed by Umberto

    Eco more than thirty years ago, grammatology is less

    interested in describing the role of signs in the construction

    of social reality, than it is in emphasizing how this role is

    subject to a systematic repression both in the philosophical

    tradition as well as in daily life. Logocentrism is the

    name Derrida gives to this repression, which seems to

    embody and to coincide with the fate of metaphysics from

    Plato to Nietzsche: it is the fact that matter, signs, means

    for transmitting and conserving disappear in the face of the

    triad of Idea, Meaning and Spirit.

    7 Deconstruction and Difference

    Repression, logocentrism I can imagine what the reader is

    going to ask: are we not talking once more about past fads,

    like the philosopher that is a critic and physician of culture

    (as Nietzsche has it), a figure that is two centuries old? Yes

    and no. Or, better, this time we would rather not be driven by

    an instinctive repulsion. Such an instinct was unavoidable

    when we caught Derrida showing off with Levinas or Levi-

    Strauss. Through his analysis, Derrida comes to what one

    might call the Critique of Impure Reason: philosophers

    and philosophy must awake from a dream of integrity and

    purity, which turns out to be limited and totalitarian. In this

    picture, it is not surprising that the fundamental notion of

    Derridas philosophy is, as anticipated,deconstruction. The

    termwhich is introduced in Of Grammatology, but

    underlies Writing and Difference, and more generally the

    whole work of Derridais borrowed from Heidegger (De-

    struktionorAbbau), who introduced the notion eighty years

    ago. Heidegger was concerned with the history of

    metaphysics. His insight was that of de-sedimenting, or

    reviving, inherited concepts, which have become inert, in

    order to give a living meaning back to them. Derrida, how-

    ever, wants to stress the constructive aspect of

    deconstruction. In other words, deconstruction amounts to

    the immediate construction of something different.

    This is possible because Derrida is concerned with the

    practical rather than with the theoretical sphere. One candemonstrate that a theory is false without thereby propos-

    ing a true one, but it is impossible to criticize a form of life,

    without thereby proposingat least implicitlyan alter-

    native one. Still, the very idea of deconstruction is more

    than a simple substitution of values. The underlying view is

    that values are always relational: there is no white without

    black, no center without outskirt, no figure without back-

    ground, and thus no right without wrong (which is usually

    identified with the different, the other, the stranger). Now,

    deconstruction must first of all uncover this relationality,

    the fact that the terms cannot exist apart from one another.

    Just as in Hegels dialectic, the master does not existwithout the slave, identity does not exist without differ-

    enceeventually, the one depends on the other. Therefore,

    difference is implication, hidden complicity. This is the

    intuition that grounds Hegels Logic: we just need to

    introduce time, and the oppositions (between life and

    death, day and night, nature, culture, technique, etc.) turn

    into complementarities.

    This is why Derridain the text of a talk he kindly put

    at my disposal, and which will be delivered at the Institut

    Philosophique on January 2008re-christens difference as

    differance, with an a. In French, differencethe fact

    that two things differis spelled diffe rence, with a e,

    even if the two words are homophonic. The neologism,

    which looks like a grammatical mistake (notice, for

    instance, that Derrida has not entitled the book I am

    reviewing Le criture et la diffe rance), transforms the

    difference in a gerund, thereby stressing the reference to an

    act of differing or postponing. The orthographical alter-

    ation expresses in an economic way Derridas thought: the

    couples of opposites that are part of our life do not exist

    autonomously; rather, one exists with respect to the other,

    and time shows the complicity underlying their opposition.

    Should we come to the conclusion that everything is rela-

    tive? Not at all. The right conclusion is that nothing is

    definitive, and thatdifferently from Hegelian dialectic

    we will never come to an absolute knowledge, or to a last

    word.

    8 Archive-ache

    However, the objection that I have put forth and propelled

    myself still stands, I suppose. Talking about regret and

    284 M. Ferraris

    1 3

  • 7/23/2019 art_10.1007_s11245-007-9025-9

    7/8

    censorship, or aiming at deconstructions in the trans-

    parent society of the Internet is definitively vieux jeu: it

    leads us, if not to Nietzsches world, to Adornos world (at

    best). Such a world is dumb dead, and the Critique of

    culture along with it. If it is not dead, it is at least decre-

    pitand, again, this aspect shows us a peculiar mix of

    archaism and actuality. However, the reviewer cannot

    elude a question: what if Derridas archaism and naivetewere not a fiction? What if in the society of the Internet,

    which is so transparent, the repressions were not a daily

    business, and the deconstructions more urgent than ever?

    Let me make a suggestion to illustrate how hot and

    topical the theme of writing is to-day. Theut, the Egyptian

    semi-god, the inventor of writing, takes note of the merits

    and faults of each soul till her or his judgment. The

    archivist, or the secretary, has never performed a futile

    activity. The archivist is the tutor of documentality, the

    keeper of crimes and punishments, and, more generally, of

    social objects. What if the final solution were not recorded?

    What if it, as the Nazis planned, there really were a his-torical decision nobody would ever know about?

    Eventually, everybody came to know it, and there are still

    the notes of the meeting of January 20th 1942 when the

    decision was taken, readily available on the Internet

    without the aid of papers. Here we see the point: sans

    papier is not just the clandestine in a Manu Chaos song

    (perdido en el corazon/de la grande babylon/me dicen el

    clandestino/por no llevar papel), but the world of the

    archive, too, which is increasingly devoid of papers.

    The current world of the archivist is infinitely more

    fragile than the world of the paper-archives. It is so because

    of the obsolescence of the supports (after all, in forty years

    our hard disks may share the same destiny of vinyl records,

    which are unreadable without record-players), and it is

    even more so because of its power, which leads to the

    inflation of the archive (the infinite versions of the same file

    on our PC, the abnormal redundancy of e-mail). Therefore,

    we can legitimately speak, in a sense, and following Der-

    ridas suggestion, of a archive-achean ache that the

    archive suffers in the transition from paper to sans papier.

    But, indeed, the problem arising from the fragility of

    supports is not as big as that arising from the excess of

    means. The latter does not consist exclusively in the

    inflation of data, but also and foremost in the impressive

    transformation of the capacity and speed of the archive,

    both omnipresent and polymorphic.

    Let me take an example from the latest news. Once

    more, in Iraq, images and words recorded by a cell phone

    have embarrassed the American administration. I am

    talking about Saddam Husseins execution. At the outset

    Bush said that he was satisfied. Then he objected to the

    manner of the execution. Besides, note that in the USA it is

    forbidden to record executions, a very convenient provision

    indeed, since it is doubtful that there can be flawless

    executions.

    The moral of the story, for me, is the following: Pro-

    vided that even a cell phone can be an archive, anyone will

    have (actually, we already have) an archive at hand: the

    space of the archive is massively contracted, and the

    consequences are easily foreseeable. Moreover, the timeof

    the archive is massively contracted too. At a glance, we cancome to know, thanks to Googlenow available on cell

    phones tooa huge amount of information about the per-

    son standing right in front of us. A little space and a little

    time, and the archive will be everywhere. This is the worst

    of the archive-aches. We have invented systems and prin-

    ciples for the safeguard of privacy, for the treatment of

    sensitive data in short, for making sure that nobody

    can mind our own business, if we dont decide to disclose

    it. But the data emerging from the Internet, on Google, are

    completely open; they are the public data concerning our

    work, our affiliations, the public documents we have

    written or subscribed to. Once upon a time, those data weredifficult to retrieve, you needed time and commitment;

    those inertial difficulties constituted a form of spontaneous

    privacy. Now that everything is accessible just in few

    seconds, everything changes.

    This is a strange and perverse realization of absolute

    knowledge, and it would not be surprising if Derrida,

    prompted by the reality he is diagnosing, were to write a

    book on Hegel out of his interests in the link between

    writing and societywhy not? He could title or subtitle it

    What is left of Absolute Knowledge. We imagine the text,

    written on many columns, as it is on the web, with

    windows, annotations, footnotes and comments of all sort,

    a blog having Hegel as respondent. What a satisfaction,

    so to speak. Maybe, he could title it Glas in honor of his

    computers screen. We will see. Surely it is a long work,

    and it will take time to write such a book whose grounds

    though lie here in the essays collected in Writing and

    Difference.

    References

    Adorno TW (1966) Negative Dialektik. Suhrkamp, Fankfurt a.M.English Version: Adorno TW (1973) Negative dialectics.

    Routledge, London

    Aron R (1955) LOpium des intellectuals. Calmann-Levy, Paris.

    English Version: Aron R (1957) The Opium of the intellectuals.

    Secker and Warburg, London

    Artaud A (1938) Le theatre et son double. Gallimard, Paris. English

    Version: Artaud A (1958). The theatre and its double. Grove

    Press, New York

    Bataille G (1970) uvres completes. Gallimard, Paris

    Derrida J (1967) Lecriture et la difference. Seuil, Paris. English

    Version: Derrida J (1978) Writing and difference. University of

    Chicago Press, Chicago

    Jacques DerridasWriting and Difference 285

    1 3

  • 7/23/2019 art_10.1007_s11245-007-9025-9

    8/8

    Derrida J (1967) De la grammatologie. Minuit, Paris. English

    Version: Derrida (1976) Of grammatology. Johns Hopkins

    University Press, Baltimore & London

    Derrida J (1967) La voix et le phenomene. Introduction au probleme

    du signe dans la phenomenologie de Husserl. P.U.F., Paris.

    English Version: Derrida J (1973) Speech and phenomena and

    other essays on Husserls theory of signs. Northwestern Univer-

    sity Press, Evanston

    Derrida J (1974) Glas. Galilee, Paris. English Version: Derrida J

    (1986) Glas. University of Nebraska Press, Lincoln & London

    Foucault M (1961) Histoire de la folie a lage classiqueFolie et

    deraison. Plon, Paris. English Version: Foucault M (1965)

    madness and civilization: A history of insanity in the age of

    reason. Tavistock, London

    Freud S (1895) Entwurf einer Psychologie. In: Bonaparte M, Freud A,

    Kris E (eds) Aus den anfangen der psychoanalyse. Briefe an

    Wilhelm Fliess, abhandlungen und notizen aus de jahren 1887

    1902. Imago, London, pp 387477. English Version: Freud

    (1950) A project for a scientific psychology. In: Bonaparte M,

    Freud A, Kris E (eds) The origins of psychoanalysis: Letters to

    Wilhelm Fliess, drafts and notes, 18871902. Imago, London. pp

    347445

    Freud S (1925) Notiz uber den Wunderblock. International

    Zeitschrift fur Psychoanalysis 11:15. English Version: Freud S

    (1961) A note upon the mystic writing-pad In: Freud S, The

    standard edition of the complete psychological works of

    Sigmund Freud, Volume XIX (19231925): The ego and the

    id and other works. Hogarth, London, pp 225232

    Gadamer GH (1960) Wahrheit und Methode. Grundzuge einer

    philosophischen Hermeneutik. J.C.B. Mohr, Tubingen. English

    Version: Gadamer GH (1989) Truth and method. Crossroad,

    New York

    Heidegger M (1927) Sein und Zeit. English Version: Heidegger M

    (1962) Being and time SCM Press, London

    Hegel GWF (1808) System der Wissenschaft. Erster Theil, die

    Phanomenologie des Geistes. Verlag Joseph Anton Goebhardt,

    Bamberg/Wurzburg. English Version: Hegel GWF (1977) Phe-

    nomenology of spirit. Clarendon Press, Oxford

    Hegel GWF (1813/16) Wissenschaft der Logik. Erster Band. Die

    objektive Logik. Zweites Buch. Die Lehre vom Wesen (1813).

    Hrsg. v. Hans-Jurgen Gawoll, 2. Aufl. Meiner: Hamburg 1999.

    Wissenschaft der Logik. Zweiter Band. Die subjektive Logik.

    Die Lehre vom Begriff (1816). Hrsg. v. Hans-Jurgen Gawoll.

    Meiner, Hamburg 2003. English Version: A.V. Miller, Science

    of logic, George Allen & Unwin, Ltd.: London, 1969

    Jabes E (1963) Le livre des questions. Gallimard, Paris. English

    Version: Jabes E (19761984) The book of questions. Wesleyan

    University Press,

    Joyce J (1922) Ulysses, The 1922 text, with an introduction and notes

    by Jeri Johnson. Oxford University Press, 1993

    Levinas E (1961) Totalite et infini. Essai sur lexteriorite, Martinus

    Nijhoff, Leiden. English Version: Levinas E (1969) Totality and

    infinity. Duquesne University Press, Pittsburgh

    Levi-Strauss C (1958) Anthropologie structurale. Plon, Paris. English

    Version: Levi-Strauss (1963) Structural anthropology. Basic

    Books, New York

    McLuhan M (1964) Understanding media: the extension of man.

    Routledge, London

    Nietzsche F (1888) Gotzen-Dammerung: oder Wie man mit dem

    Hammer philosophiert. Naumann, Leipzig. English Version:

    Nietzsche F (1977) The twilight of the idols and The Anti-Christ.

    Penguin Books, New York

    Nietzsche F (1975) Kritische Gesamtausgabe Briefwechsel. In: Colli

    G, Montinari M (eds) 24 vols. in 4 parts. Walter de Gruyter,

    Berlin

    Plato (1997) In: John M (ed) Complete works. Hackett, Cooper

    Tran-Duc-Thao (1951) Phenomenologie et materialisme dialectique,

    Editions Minh-Tan: Paris. English Version: Tran-Duc-Thao

    (1986) Phenomenology and dialectical materialism, Kluwer:

    Dordrecht

    286 M. Ferraris

    1 3