Anarchist Property - A Reconsilation of Socialist Equality and Libertarian Freedom

20
1 Anarchist Property: a Reconciliation of Socialist Equality and Libertarian Freedom Left-libertarians, in the analytic philosophy sense, believe that individuals ought to be full self- owners and that natural resources ought to be owned in some egalitarian manner. 1 The challenge for left-libertarians is to sketch out a theory of property rights that promotes both individual liberty and equality among individuals and does so in a manner that is not overly egalitarian at the cost of individual freedom or overly individualistic at the cost of equality. Left-libertarianism appears to be attractive to people who find themselves drawn to both libertarian and egalitarian conclusions. It is attractive to said individuals since it enables them to be libertarian without having to endorse either free market capitalism or the abolition of the welfare state and to be egalitarian without having to endorse authoritarian state socialism. Left-libertarianism strikes me as dissatisfying from both a libertarian and an egalitarian perspective. It is dissatisfying from both of these perspectives because it advocates social institutions and social structures that are both highly freedom restricting and based upon inegalitarian distributions of power and decision-making. Specifically, it advocates the nation state, capitalism and other such hierarchical centralised modes of social organisation in which a minority of individuals at the top of an organisation rule over the individuals below them. I take social anarchism, or as it is also known libertarian socialism, to be, from a libertarian- egalitarian perspective, a superior political philosophy than left-libertarianism. This is because it reconciles liberty and equality through the advocacy of forms of social organisation that place an emphasis on individuals being among equals, engaging in autonomous action, and having a say in decisions that affect them. Specifically, networks of voluntary associations that are organised at all levels of society, including workplaces and neighbourhoods, according to principles of nonhierarchical direct democracy. Within the literature, the closest philosopher to my position is Vrousalis. 2 Vrousalis shares my position that social anarchist views on liberty and equality provide a better reconciliation than left- libertarian alternatives. He attempts to show this by reconstructing social anarchist views on individual liberty and legitimate property rights into a commitment to a) effective self-ownership and b) joint ownership of the means of production. While I agree with Vrousalis’ s conclusion that the social anarchist view provides a better reconciliation than left-libertarian views, I do not think that Vrousalis’s characterisation of the social anarchist view on both individual sovereignty and property rights is sufficiently detailed to fully capture the social anarchist position. I shall attempt to 1 Vallentynre, Left-libertarianism: A Primer in (eds.) Vallentyne and Steiner 2000 2 Vrousalis 2011

description

An attempt to show that Anarchism is a superior libertarian-egalitarian political philosophy to Left-Libertarianism.

Transcript of Anarchist Property - A Reconsilation of Socialist Equality and Libertarian Freedom

  • 1

    Anarchist Property: a Reconciliation of Socialist Equality and Libertarian Freedom

    Left-libertarians, in the analytic philosophy sense, believe that individuals ought to be full self-

    owners and that natural resources ought to be owned in some egalitarian manner.1 The challenge for

    left-libertarians is to sketch out a theory of property rights that promotes both individual liberty and

    equality among individuals and does so in a manner that is not overly egalitarian at the cost of

    individual freedom or overly individualistic at the cost of equality.

    Left-libertarianism appears to be attractive to people who find themselves drawn to both libertarian

    and egalitarian conclusions. It is attractive to said individuals since it enables them to be libertarian

    without having to endorse either free market capitalism or the abolition of the welfare state and to

    be egalitarian without having to endorse authoritarian state socialism.

    Left-libertarianism strikes me as dissatisfying from both a libertarian and an egalitarian perspective.

    It is dissatisfying from both of these perspectives because it advocates social institutions and social

    structures that are both highly freedom restricting and based upon inegalitarian distributions of

    power and decision-making. Specifically, it advocates the nation state, capitalism and other such

    hierarchical centralised modes of social organisation in which a minority of individuals at the top of

    an organisation rule over the individuals below them.

    I take social anarchism, or as it is also known libertarian socialism, to be, from a libertarian-

    egalitarian perspective, a superior political philosophy than left-libertarianism. This is because it

    reconciles liberty and equality through the advocacy of forms of social organisation that place an

    emphasis on individuals being among equals, engaging in autonomous action, and having a say in

    decisions that affect them. Specifically, networks of voluntary associations that are organised at all

    levels of society, including workplaces and neighbourhoods, according to principles of

    nonhierarchical direct democracy.

    Within the literature, the closest philosopher to my position is Vrousalis.2 Vrousalis shares my

    position that social anarchist views on liberty and equality provide a better reconciliation than left-

    libertarian alternatives. He attempts to show this by reconstructing social anarchist views on

    individual liberty and legitimate property rights into a commitment to a) effective self-ownership

    and b) joint ownership of the means of production. While I agree with Vrousaliss conclusion that

    the social anarchist view provides a better reconciliation than left-libertarian views, I do not think

    that Vrousaliss characterisation of the social anarchist view on both individual sovereignty and

    property rights is sufficiently detailed to fully capture the social anarchist position. I shall attempt to

    1 Vallentynre, Left-libertarianism: A Primer in (eds.) Vallentyne and Steiner 2000 2 Vrousalis 2011

  • 2

    build upon Vrousaliss work and provide a fuller account of social anarchism by expanding the

    commitments to effective self-ownership and joint-ownership into commitments to self-mastery and

    full-communist ownership.

    The structure of this essay will be as follows. I shall first outline Vrousaliss conception of social

    anarchism and demonstrate that it is insufficient. I shall then outline full-communist ownership and

    demonstrate how it reconciles liberty and equality in a manner superior to left-libertarian

    alternatives. I shall end by defending full-communist ownership from a number of capitalist

    objections to socialist property.

    Before I proceed, I just wish to make four clarifications. First, when I speak of rights I mean rights

    in a Hohfeldian3 sense. Second, when I speak of anarchism I am referring to socialist political

    anarchism. I am not referring to philosophical anarchism or anarcho-capitalism. Third, when I speak

    of communism I mean a stateless, classless and moneyless society in which the means of production

    are collectively owned and controlled by the communities in which they are located, and in which

    economic activity is organised according to the principle from each according to their ability, to

    each according to their need.4 I am not referring to the totalitarian societies that were commonly

    labelled as communist in the twentieth century.5 In order to help differentiate my sense of

    communism from the Stalinist or Maoist sense of communism I will use the phrase full-

    communism to pick out communism in my sense. Fourth, in this essay I am concerned with

    abstract theoretical questions regarding principles and the manner in which these principles promote

    freedom and equality. I am not concerned with the practical question of how one would effectively

    implement the sort of society advocated by said principles.

    Vrousalis's Account of Social Anarchism

    Vrousalis characterises self-ownership by quoting Otsukas statement that self-ownership consists in

    the belief that individuals possess,

    (1) a very stringent right of control over the use of ones mind and body that bars others

    from intentionally using one as a means by forcing one to sacrifice life, limb or labour,

    where such force operates by means of incursions or threats of incursions upon ones mind

    and body. . . [and] (2) a very stringent right to all of the income that one can gain from ones

    mind and body (including ones labour) either on ones own or through unregulated

    3 Hohfeld 1913 4 Marx 1875 5 See Kropotkin 1901 for an outline of anarcho-communism and Chomsky 1986 for an anarchist perspective

    on the Soviet Union.

  • 3

    voluntary exchanges with other individuals.6

    Vrousalis goes beyond mere self-ownership and endorses effective self-ownership.7 This is the view

    that in addition to not being intentionally forced to sacrifice life, limb or labour by others,

    individuals ought not to be forced by circumstances to sacrifice life, limb, or labour for others.

    Effective self-ownership is therefore secured by, and thus requires that, every individual have, or be

    provided with, adequate living space, access to food, shelter, and other basic necessities. An

    individuals subsistence shell refers to exactly those resources that guarantee an individuals

    effective self-ownership.

    Vrousalis characterises the social anarchist conception of property as consisting in the advocacy of

    joint-ownership, which is the position that all the members of a community have a claim-right to

    an equal say in the disposal and distribution of natural and produced worldly resource.8 This

    advocacy of joint-ownership applies to those resources that are not part of an individuals

    subsistence shell. Thus, to use Vrousaliss example, if Able and Infirm are on an island with three

    coconut trees and ownership of one coconut tree is for arguments sake sufficient to guarantee

    effective self-ownership, then Able and Infirm should possess one coconut tree each in order to be

    effective self-owners and jointly own the third coconut tree.

    The exercise of this claim right to an equal say in the disposal and distribution of worldly resources

    is to be mediated through forms of direct democratic organisation within the community, such as

    workers councils and people's assemblies.9

    The Inadequacy of Vrousaliss Account of Social Anarchism

    While social anarchists should endorse effective self-ownership, doing so is insufficient for a full

    characterisation of the social anarchist view on individual liberty. This is because a core component

    of the social anarchist view is that to be free individuals ought to be autonomous.10

    By autonomy,

    social anarchists have in mind people engaging in self-directed activity where this broadly speaking

    means that a person consciously determines the nature of the actions that they themselves engage in

    and the conditions under which they engage in such actions.11

    This notion of autonomy can be seen

    as an extension of effective self-ownership such that to be a full self-owner is not merely to possess

    certain rights or to have a subsistence shell but is to be a self-master.

    6 Otsuka 2005, p.15 7 Such a move may be justified by the sort of argument provided by Mack 1995. 8 Vrousalis 2011, p.3 9 For concrete examples of such forms of organisation see Ness and Azzellimi (eds.) 2011 10 For example, see Bakunin, Man, Society, and Freedom in (ed) Dolgoff 1980, pp.234-242 11 I lack the space in which to develop a systematic anarchist theory of autonomy but such a theory would be similar, although not identical with, republican notions of liberty as outlined by Pettit 2001.

  • 4

    Vrousaliss position on joint-ownership can be understood in either a strong or a weak sense. Strong

    joint-ownership holds that all resources beyond each individuals subsistence shell ought to be

    jointly-owned such that an individual does not have the right to own resources beyond their

    subsistence shell unless they jointly own these resources with the other members of their

    community. Weak joint-ownership holds that individuals have the right to own resources beyond

    their subsistence shell in any manner that is consistent with social anarchist principles but that joint-

    ownership is the most morally desirable form of ownership.

    Strong joint-ownership is flawed because it fails as an accurate reading of social anarchism. This is

    because it entails that certain forms of property, which major social anarchist thinkers thought were

    allowable within an anarchist society, are not in fact allowable within an anarchist society.

    The main form of property in question is that advocated by individualist anarchists, such as Tucker.

    Tucker thought that individuals ought to be free to own a resource unless they were not the user or

    occupier of the thing owned. Tucker writes, "in the case of land, or of any other material the supply

    of which is so limited that all cannot hold it in unlimited quantities, Anarchism undertakes to protect

    no titles except such as are based on actual occupancy and use."12

    Put more systematically, individualist anarchists held that whether or not a given individual has a

    right to own a scarce resource or not is contingent upon what they are doing with the resource in

    question. It is specifically contingent upon whether or not the individual who owns (in the

    descriptive sense) the property is identical with the individual who uses or occupies it. If there is a

    unity of possessor and owner then it is legitimate and an instance of personal property. If there is a

    separation between possessor and owner then it is illegitimate and an instance of private property.

    What an individual is the actual occupier or user of is not identical with what is within their

    subsistence shell and can in fact go beyond it. For example, a person may own twenty 3D printers

    with which they alone produce a variety of commodities that they sell for profit. They only need,

    say, five 3D printers to guarantee their effective self-ownership but despite this, for Tucker, they

    ought to have exclusive property rights over the other 3D printers since they are the sole users of the

    3D printers. Such exclusive property rights rule out the rest of the community having a claim right

    to an equal say in the disposal and distribution of the 3D printers. Individualist anarchists thus

    believe that people have the right to own individually resources beyond their subsistence shell.

    The major social anarchist theorist Malatesta, whom Vrousalis cites13

    to support his reconstruction,

    did advocate joint-ownership, but he also thought, as the weak version holds, that joint-ownership

    12Tucker 1969, p.61 13 Vrousalis 2011, p.2 and p.3

  • 5

    was one, among many, type of property rights compatible with anarchist principles. As Malatesta

    writes, we remain communist in our sentiment and aspiration, but we want to leave freedom of

    action to the experimentation of all ways of life that can be imagined and desired14 providing that

    these ways of life do not violate anarchist principles. After all, free and voluntary communism is

    ironical if one has not the right and the possibility to live in a different regime, collectivist,

    mutualist, individualist15

    -- as one wishes, always on condition that there is no oppression or

    exploitation of others".16

    Malatesta further holds that individualist anarchist property ought to be abolished by the force of

    circumstances, by the demonstrable advantages of communistic management, and by the growing

    spirit of brotherhood. This is in contrast to capitalist property, which is the fact that a few control

    the natural wealth and the instruments of production and can thus oblige others to work for them

    and which ought to be destroyed at once, even with violence if necessary. Thus under anarchism

    Free . . . is the peasant to cultivate his piece of land, alone if he wishes; free is the shoe maker to

    remain at his last, or the blacksmith in his small forge.17 Social anarchists thus believe that

    individualist anarchist property is allowable within an anarchist society, even though it grants

    individuals the right to own resources beyond their subsistence shell. Strong joint-ownership is

    therefore inconsistent with the social anarchist view on individualist anarchist property and so ought

    to be rejected if we are concerned with an accurate reconstruction of social anarchism.

    The failure of strong joint-ownership may tempt one to endorse weak joint-ownership as the social

    anarchist view on property. Recall that weak joint-ownership holds that joint-ownership is the most

    morally desirable form of property but that individuals ought to be free to own resources providing

    that this ownership is consistent with social anarchist principles. Weak joint-ownership as it stands

    is however inadequate as a theory of social anarchist property. This is because it does not specify

    what exactly these social anarchist principles that govern what can and cannot be legitimately

    owned are and so raises a variety of unanswered questions. The rest of this essay shall be concerned

    with outlining these social anarchist principles and so rendering the weak version of Vrousaliss

    account of social anarchist property more fully developed.

    Social Anarchist Principles

    On this view so far, social anarchists advocate a bundle of property rights the exercise of which is

    14 Malatesta 1924 15 To those unfamiliar with Anarchist jargon a collectivist is a proponent of Bakunins economic system, a mutualist is a proponent of Proudhons economic system and an individualist is a proponent of Tuckers or Spooners economic system. 16 Malatesta in Richards (ed) 1965, p.103 17 Malatesta in Richards (ed) 1965, pp.97-98

  • 6

    consistent with all the types of resource ownership advocated by the different schools of

    anarchism.18

    Joint-ownership is merely the best exercise of this distinct bundle of property rights.

    An idea of what this bundle of property rights is can be gained by considering what social

    anarchists wish to prohibit. Social anarchists are opposed to any form of property that denies self-

    mastery in some significant respect. As Malatesta writes, anarchists respect freedom for everybody

    . . . with the only limit of the equal freedom for others; which does not mean . . . that we recognise,

    and wish to respect, the freedom to exploit, to oppress, to command, which is oppression and

    certainly not freedom.19

    Social anarchists are specifically opposed to two main types of situation. The first situation is when

    an individuals ownership of resources enables them to use their resources in order to exercise

    power over other individuals and in so doing deny the autonomy of said individuals in some

    significant respect. For example, a Feudal lord who owns land and uses this land ownership to

    exercise power over peasants in an autonomy denying manner. The second situation is one in which

    an individual owns resources and excludes other individuals from access to these resources and in

    so doing prevents said individuals from being effective self-owners. For example, an individual

    who owns the only local source of water, say a reservoir, decides to exclude every other local from

    access to the reservoir. The owner thereby prevents every other local from being effective self-

    owners, as they lack access to water.

    I think that social anarchists should rule out situations of these types by holding that individuals

    have property rights but that these property rights may be trumped in situations where doing so is

    required to protect individual autonomy and secure effective self-ownership. Social anarchists can

    thus demarcate between legitimate personal property and illegitimate private property via holding

    that individuals ought not to continue to own resources if they a) exercise their rights over a

    resource and in so doing establish relations of domination and oppression and b) own resources

    beyond their subsistence shell and as a result of this ownership prevent others from having their

    effective self-ownership secured. Before I outline this conception of property rights in detail, I must

    first sketch an analysis of rights.

    An Analysis of Rights

    18 One may wish to consider the occupancy and use theory of the individualist anarchists as the bundle of rights shared by all anarchists. I do not have the space in which to critique such a view but briefly put I hold that occupancy and use if reconstructed to deal with a number of problem cases ends up being theoretically unnecessary and so should be abandoned. 19 Malatesta in Richards (ed) 1965, p.53

  • 7

    Following Christman,20

    I view a property right as a triadic relation between a person and all other

    persons in regard to some particular thing. For the specifics of conceptualising property rights I take

    Attass21 analysis of property rights to be highly useful and shall largely stick to the core

    components of his account, although I shall differ from him in a few key respects. Attas

    distinguishes between the content and the form of a right. The content of a right is those features of

    it that have the thing owned as their subject, for instance the right to use a pen. The form of a right

    is those features of it that have the right itself as their subject, for example, the right to transfer to

    another person the right to use a particular pen.

    The content incidents specify the kinds of action on, with or deriving from the thing owned that are

    permitted by the right. There are two types of content incidents, control incidents and income

    incidents. Control incidents are rights to possess, use, and manage property. Rights of possession

    consist in the right to physically hold onto the thing owned. Rights of use consist in the right to

    engage in consumption, modification or other such employment or handling of the thing owned.

    Rights of management consist in the right to decide how a thing shall be used and by whom.

    Income incidents are rights to own the products of the exercise of one's control rights over a given

    thing. I take these to be the right to the fruits of ones property and the right to revenue from the

    trade of ones property.22 The right to the fruit of ones property consists in the right to own those

    things that the property yields either naturally or as a result of its modification by a person. For

    example, the right to own the apples that grow on ones apple tree or the right to own a chair that

    one produced given that one created the chair through the exercise of ones control rights over raw

    materials that one owned. The right to the revenue from the trade of ones property consists in the

    right to own goods derived from the sale of ones property.

    The form incidents are rights of continuity and rights of transferability with respect to ones control

    rights and income rights. Rights of continuity consist in the rights of immunity, indefinite duration,

    and reverting to owner when lesser rights lapse. These are specifically, the right to not have ones

    rights taken away by force; there being no predetermined term when ones rights lapse; and one

    retaining rights when one transfers them for a limited term such that one, say, retains ownership of

    ones pen when one lets a friend use it for a day. Rights of transferability are the right to transfer a

    given right to another person.

    Full-Communist Ownership

    Given this framework, I can now specify what property rights social anarchists think individuals

    20 Christman 1994, p.16 21 Attas 2006, pp.23-30 22 This differs from Attas, according to whom income rights consist in the right to fruits, profit and rent.

  • 8

    should have. This view is labelled full-communist ownership since it consists in those rights that

    social anarchists believe ought to be enforced in a full-communist society.

    Full-communist ownership holds that individuals possess rights of control, income, continuity and

    transferability over resources; that individuals ought to be effective self-owners; and that the most

    morally desirable manner in which to exercise these property rights is to voluntarily establish joint-

    ownership over resources, in particular over land, housing and means of production, with members

    of ones community.

    Full-communist ownership further holds that there are two limitations on these property rights.

    These are a) the on-going ownership of the resources outside ones subsistence shell is contingent

    upon whether or not one is dominating others through the exercise of ones rights over these

    resources and b) the strength of one's right to ownership of land or housing beyond one's

    subsistence shell is that it can be trumped if other individuals must necessarily gain ownership of

    the land or housing in order to secure their effective self-ownership. Let us call a) the domination

    principle and b) the redistribution principle. I shall discuss each of these in turn.

    The domination principle in general holds that individuals have rights of continuity over a given

    property right to own a particular resource(s) outside their subsistence shell unless they exercise

    their rights over said resource(s) in such a manner as to establish a relation of domination over

    another. A relation of domination is established if one denies a persons autonomy in some

    significant respect.

    When an individual exercises their property rights in such a dominating manner, they thereby forfeit

    their rights and their property may be legitimately expropriated. Those whom they were dominating

    gain a right to own those resources that were being used to dominate them and so gain a right to

    expropriate those resources from the dominator.

    There may be cases in which large-scale expropriation occurs but an individual chooses not to

    exercise their right to expropriate or in which an individual is unable to exercise their right to

    expropriate. In both cases, individuals ought to have those resources that they had a right to

    expropriate distributed to them after expropriation. This is important since anarchists do not wish

    people to lose out on owning what is rightfully theirs because they made a decision to not

    expropriate because they were, say, too afraid or uncertain or because they had a very bad cold on

    the day of expropriation and so spent the day in bed.

    The domination principle does not apply to those resources within one's subsistence shell because

    even if one uses these resources to establish relations of domination over another, one nonetheless

    still ought to have one's effective self-ownership guaranteed. In such instances, the relation of

  • 9

    domination ought to be abolished but the individual ought to retain ownership of the resource(s) in

    question. Thus if a person uses a sewing machine to establish a relation of domination over another

    and said sewing machine is for arguments sake part of their subsistence shell, then the relation of

    domination ought to be abolished but they ought to retain their right to own the sewing machine.

    We can now turn to the redistribution principle. The redistribution principle holds that since

    individuals ought to have their effective self-ownership guaranteed it follows that they have a prima

    facie claim right to gain ownership of another individuals land or housing beyond said individual's

    subsistence shell if doing so is necessary for securing their effective self-ownership. It is not the

    claim that ones first course of action when faced with a person who lacks effective self-ownership

    due to lack of ownership of housing or land is to expropriate. After all, their effective self-

    ownership could be more easily and peacefully secured by an anarchist federation allotting them

    some land and housing that is currently owned in common. But were one in, for whatever reason, a

    situation in which the only realistic course of action to secure an individuals effective self-

    ownership is to expropriate another's property then doing so is prima facie the morally right course

    of action.

    Having outlined the details of full-communist ownership in the abstract I shall now illustrate it

    concretely by applying it to capitalism and sketching out what full-communism would look like.

    Applying Full-Communist Ownership to Capitalism

    Capitalism is characterised by the private ownership of the means of production, land and housing

    and by, in particular, two types of social relations. These are wage labour and landlordism. I shall

    discuss each in term.

    Wage labour, in the strict socialist sense of the term, is a relation between a worker and a capitalist

    employer23

    in which the worker sells their labour to the capitalist employer. A worker is any

    individual who a) sells their labour to a capitalist employer in exchange for a wage, b) does not own

    the means of production that they use at work and c) produces commodities for the individual(s)

    who do own the means of production that they use at work, namely, capitalist employers. A

    capitalist employer is any individual who a) owns means of production and b) hires people to

    produce commodities for them, some of whom must be workers.24

    Workers ought to be distinguished from independent contractors, who despite also selling their

    labour for a wage, nonetheless own the means of production that they use at work and do not

    23 A capitalist employer is a type of capitalist, a capitalist being any individual who owns capital and invests it in firms. 24 The general category of 'people' is required since capitalist employers may hire people other than workers to produce commodities for them, such as independent contractors.

  • 10

    necessarily sell their labour to capitalist employers.25

    For example, a casting agent who owns their

    own means of production, say a laptop, and who sells their labour to actors, who are of course not

    necessarily capitalists.

    Landlordism is a relation between a landlord and a tenant in which a landlord owns housing and the

    tenant pays rent to the landlord in order to live in the housing such that the housing becomes the

    home of the tenant. Landlordism is thus distinct from those relations that characterise hotels since

    when one pays a hotel owner to live in a room one does not thereby possess this room as one's

    home.

    Let us apply full-communist ownership to these social relations. Anarchists take wage labour and

    landlordism to be autonomy denying. A sketch of an anarchist argument for this is as follows.

    Under capitalism, capitalist employers, in virtue of their private ownership of the means of

    production, possess the right to determine what their employees will produce and how their

    employees will produce it. It is because of this that decision-making power within capitalist

    workplaces is concentrated into the hands of CEOs and boards of directors. Power within capitalist

    institutions flows from the top to the bottom such that workers lack decision-making power and

    must do as capitalists instruct them. Workers thus lack autonomy.

    Workers remain nonautonomous even in capitalist workplaces where the capitalist chooses not to

    actively exercise their power to determine the nature of the productive process and grants this

    power to the workers while themselves retaining ultimate ownership of the workplace. This is

    because the relative autonomy that such privileged workers have is a product of the capitalists will.

    The capitalist decides that the worker can determine their work and so the workers are autonomous

    to the extent that the capitalist thinks it is fitting. They may lose this autonomy if and when the

    capitalist decides and so are not properly autonomous, as their freedom is granted to them by a

    master who retains the right to take such freedom away. Under capitalism even if workers have the

    autonomy to determine the nature of their work, they do not have the power to determine the

    conditions under which their work is done, namely one in which their freedom is not granted to

    them from above by a benevolent autocrat. They lack this power because they do not own the place

    in which they work and so must, if they are to be truly autonomous, own their workplace.

    Landlordism is likewise autonomy denying. Landlords require that tenants must pay rent and adhere

    to the rules stipulated by the landlord if they are to continue to have a home. The vast majority of

    25 This distinction has a basis in law. Mr Justice Cooke ruled in the high court case Market Investigations Ltd v Minister for Social Security 1969 that one factor for distinguishing between employees and independent contractors is that independent contractors own their own equipment.

  • 11

    tenants are not in a position to not pay rent or to not adhere to the landlords rules since doing so

    renders them homeless. As a result, peoples decisions to pay rent or adhere to the landlords rules

    are not autonomous decisions.

    Even if tenants were in a position to freely decide to pay rent or adhere to the landlords rules they

    would still not be autonomous. Such tenants would be in a position to decide where they lived and

    so to select the rules that they will have to adhere to from a limited pre-existing set of rules

    determined for them by an external authority figure, namely a landlord. Such tenants would not be

    in a position to determine the nature of the rules themselves. But if people are to be autonomous

    they must have direct control over the conditions in which they live and so must have the power to

    themselves determine the specific nature of those rules that they follow within their home. A

    landlord that one chooses to live under is still a lord, just as a king that one votes for is still a

    monarch. In both instances one is choosing a ruler and so is still being ruled, as opposed to

    governing ones life oneself. Such self-governance thus requires that one owns ones own home.

    From the domination principle and the anarchist view that relations of wage labour and landlordism

    are autonomy denying, it follows that anarchists believe that workers and tenants possess the right

    to expropriate their employer capitalist or landlord.

    The nature of this expropriation is as follows. In workplaces, individual workers have the right to

    expropriate, and so individually own, those resources that they alone used in the workplace, such as

    their office computer. This does not apply to resources that are a crucial component of collective

    production. Thus, an individual worker does not possess the right to individually expropriate a blast

    furnace even if they were the only worker to use it. This is because the blast furnace is crucial for

    the wider activities of production within, say, the steel mill. Those resources that are used either

    collectively or individually but which are necessarily required for acts of collective production,

    ought to be expropriated by the entire workplace and owned in common among the workers, for

    example, an assembly line or the building the assembly line is in.

    Individuals can if they so choose decide that the resources that they individually used ought to be

    owned in common by either the whole workplace or by a group of workers within the workplace. A

    cleaner for example may decide that their mop and bucket ought to be owned by all the cleaners,

    but not be owned by the IT staff.

    With respect to rented land or housing, tenants possess the right to expropriate the housing that they

    rented. If the housing is within a distinct building, such as inside a tower block of flats, then

    individuals possess the right to collectively expropriate the building with their fellow tenants.

    Given the proviso that the domination principle does not apply to resources within a persons

  • 12

    subsistence shell, we can infer that anarchists believe that workers have a right to expropriate a

    factory from a capitalist but do not possess the right to expropriate a capitalists toothbrush or those

    means of production that they do not use to deny the autonomy of anybody, such as their sewing

    machine at home.

    This view on expropriation is neither new nor innovative as it can be found in the work of

    Kropotkin. He writes that the anarchist revolution aims at abolishing the exploitation of man by

    man via the complete expropriation of all those who have the means of exploiting human

    beings.26 That is to say everything that enables any man be he financier, mill-owner, or

    landlord to appropriate the product of others toil.27 More concretely, when we see a Sheffield

    cutler, or a Leeds clothier working with their own tools or handloom, we see no use in taking the

    tools or the handloom to give to another worker. The clothier or cutler exploit nobody. But when we

    see a factory whose owners claim to keep to themselves the instruments of labour used by 1,400

    girls, and consequently exact from the labour of these girls . . . profit . . . we consider that the people

    are fully entitled to take possession of that factory and to let the girls produce . . . for themselves

    and the rest of the community.28 All I have done is thus expand upon Kropotkin's views.

    Envisioning Full-Communism

    Under full-communism, individual autonomy is achieved through voluntary association into

    egalitarian social relations. That is to say, joint ownership of resources would emerge from people

    voluntarily deciding to own certain resources in common with other people. This association is

    voluntary since each individual would be an effective self-owner as their subsistence shell would be

    secured for them by resource distribution, and if it is warranted, resource redistribution. Individuals

    would further possess the right to decide if they lived in a market economy or a moneyless planned

    economy or any other alternative economic form that is not ruled illegitimate by the domination

    principle. They would thus also possess the right to engage in economic activity as an individual

    producer, such as an artisan, or as an independent contractor, such as a plumber, or as a member of a

    jointly owned workplace.

    Joint-ownership promotes individual autonomy by ensuring that individuals determine the use of

    those resources that they jointly own with others. This is done through collective decision making.

    Specifically, the owners of the resource(s) have meetings in which individuals make proposals on

    courses of action regarding the resource and the group agrees to implement or not implement said

    proposals. To this end, the group would utilise particular forms of democratic decision making, such

    26 Kropotkin 1992, pp.206-207 27 Kropotkin 2007, p.61 28 Kropotkin in Walter and Becker (ed.) 1998, p.105

  • 13

    as majority rule, in which each member has a vote and a proposal is passed if the majority of the

    group vote for it, or forms of consensus, in which a proposal is only passed if everybody agrees to

    it.

    In order to organise at a large scale, particular associations of individuals who jointly owned

    resources would enter into free agreement with other associations in order to create a confederation

    of associations. A confederation is thus just a group of several associations with each association

    retaining the right to leave the confederation at any point. A confederation does not have power over

    its constituent associations but instead performs the role of institutionalising communication

    between associations and decision making involving multiple associations. If necessary, multiple

    confederations of associations can federate with one another to form confederations of

    confederations of associations.

    Crucially, power remains at the bottom in the hands of each constituent association. All those who

    perform a set role within a confederation do so because they have been mandated this task by the

    members of the association that they are a member of. They can be instantly recalled and replaced

    by their association if they are thought to not be doing their job correctly or not serving the interests

    of the associations members. This decentralised and federal mode of organisation thus ensures that

    individuals will not easily be able to establish themselves in positions of power over others and so

    ensures that individuals are in a position to exercise their property rights autonomously.

    In situations in which holding a democratic assembly is highly counterproductive, such as during a

    battle, individuals may decide to delegate the responsibility of decision making over certain

    activities to a person of their choosing. Such delegates are of course instantly recallable and

    replaceable by those delegating to them.29

    Reconciling Liberty and Equality

    Full-communist ownership reconciles liberty and equality since it advocates the voluntary

    establishment of forms of egalitarian resource ownership that have built into them egalitarian forms

    of decision making and organisation that serve to protect an individuals autonomy within a group

    of people.

    Full-communist ownership reconciles liberty and equality in a manner superior to left-libertarian

    alternatives for three main reasons. First, full-communist ownership is far more egalitarian than left-

    libertarianism. This is because left-libertarianism limits its egalitarianism to the egalitarian

    ownership of natural resources, where this usually consists only in egalitarian constraints on the

    29 This was in fact done by anarchists during the Spanish Civil War of 1936-39. See Bolloten 1991, p261-2

  • 14

    individual appropriation of natural resources30

    , and in most cases, a particular form of egalitarian

    taxation on those who individually own or gain income from the use of natural resources or

    egalitarian redistribution of the value produced by said natural resources.31

    Full-communist

    ownership in contrast advocates the far more egalitarian positions that a) natural and produced

    resources ought to be jointly owned by the communities in which they are located, such as workers

    owning their own workplaces, b) joint-ownership ought to be organised via egalitarian,

    decentralised, nonhierarchical and democratic modes of organisation, and c) inegalitarian forms of

    ownership that produce significant autonomy denial, such as capitalism, ought to be forcefully

    abolished by collective acts of expropriation by those being dominated. Thus from a purely

    egalitarian point of view, full-communist ownership is favourable to left-libertarianism.

    Second, full-communist ownership is far more libertarian than left-libertarianism. This is for two

    reasons. The first reason is that, unlike left-libertarianism, it allows individuals to own natural

    resources such as land without having to pay a tax for doing so and without having to meet stringent

    requirements on appropriation, such as having to gain the permission of wider society in order to be

    free to appropriate a natural resource. The second reason is that the left-libertarian characterisation

    of freedom has its adherents supporting highly un-libertarian social relations, such as wage labour

    or landlordism, since such social relations do not violate full self-ownership or their egalitarian

    notions of ownership. Full-communist ownership in contrast prohibits such un-libertarian social

    relations and advocates forms of organisation and decision making that are conducive towards

    individual self-mastery, as opposed to merely not violating full self-ownership. As a result,

    individuals in a full-communist society would be far freer than in a left-libertarian society.

    One may worry that the libertarian view on owning and appropriating natural resources will come at

    the cost of the inegalitarian conclusion that any instance of unequal resources ownership after the

    initial act of appropriation is allowable. But this is not a problem for full-communist ownership

    since inegalitarian property distributions almost always coincide with unequal power relations and

    so certain individuals denying the autonomy of others. Were this to happen then expropriation

    would be justified due to the domination principle. If inegalitarian property distribution does not

    result in an unequal power distribution that results in autonomy denial then I cannot see what there

    is to worry about.

    Third, full-communist ownership places a great emphasis on voluntary association among equals

    and so advocates social structures that foster both a sense of individuality and a sense of

    community. Democratic assemblies in particular do this since in order to participate effectively in a

    30 Otsuka ,Steiner and Vallentyne 2005, pp.2-3 31 Vallentyne in (eds.) Vallentyne and Steiner 2000, pp.8-11

  • 15

    democratic assembly one must learn to make decisions for oneself and by making decisions with

    ones equals one develops social bonds with those individuals. These social structures in turn ensure

    that individuals are in a social environment that is both a space in which individuals are free to

    develop their own capacities, since they are autonomous within them and stand in social relations to

    individuals that they have social bonds with; and in which individuals actively do develop their own

    capacities, since merely by participating in said social structures they will inevitably engage in

    capacity developing activities such as determining the nature of their own work. Left-libertarianism

    in contrast does not place theoretical emphasis on the development of individuality and community

    and advocates social structures that are arguably actively detrimental to such development, such as

    wage labour.

    Capitalist Objections to Full-Communist Ownership

    I shall consider a variety of standard arguments for capitalist property rights that attempt to show

    that an important value or valuable state of affairs is realised by capitalist property rights, but not by

    socialist property rights. I shall argue that such arguments do not apply to full-communist

    ownership and in fact can be used as arguments for full-communist ownership. I shall be focusing

    on the arguments of Hayek and Brennan specifically.

    Hayek argues that capitalist private property is superior to socialist property because it, unlike

    socialist property, decentralises power. He writes,

    private property is the most important guaranty of freedom, not only for those who own

    property, but scarcely less for those who do not. It is only because the control of the means

    of production is divided among many people acting independently that nobody has complete

    power over us, that we as individuals can decide what to do with ourselves. If all the means

    of production were vested in a single hand, whether it be nominally that of society as a

    whole or that of a dictator, whoever exercises this control has complete power over us 32

    Full-communism would be a socialist society and yet still meet Hayeks requirement that power be

    decentralised via the decentralised ownership of the means of production. In full-communism the

    ownership of the means of production would be decentralised among individuals who own means of

    production both within and beyond their subsistence shell and among members of a specific

    community who jointly own means of production, such as an individual workplace or a federation

    of workplaces.

    Such an anarchist society not only meets Hayeks requirement that power be decentralised but also

    meets this requirement to a greater extent than capitalism does. Firstly, in a full-communist society,

    32 Hayek 2001, p.108

  • 16

    unlike a capitalist society, all individuals own means of production since doing so is a requirement

    for them being effective self-owners. Secondly, in a capitalist society, power is centralised both

    within workplaces, as the capitalist or their appointed managers wield power over wage labourers,

    and within housing, as the landlord or their appointed managers wield power over tenants. In a full-

    communist society, by contrast, power is decentralised as each individual either works as an

    individual producer or jointly owns a workplace with their fellow workers and participates

    democratically in workplace decisions that affect them; while each individual owns their own home

    and can if they so choose jointly own whole areas of housing with others. Thus favouring the

    decentralisation of power via the decentralisation of ownership is a reason to support full-

    communist ownership over capitalist property.

    In Why Not Capitalism? Brennan argues for capitalist property, and against socialist property, by

    holding that capitalist property rights ensure that individuals are able to implement their ideas and

    visions, pursue projects over time and express and develop themselves. This is because such actions

    often requires that we have sustained and exclusive control of objects over time. For example, a

    person needs sustained and exclusive control over a piece of farmland in order to pursue their

    project of creating just the kind of farm that they want. Or a person may gain meaning and self-

    confidence from the fact that other people want to buy the things that they produce and so need to

    have sustained and exclusive ownership of those items required for such production and trade.

    Socialist property rights allegedly do not enable people to pursue their projects. Brennan states,

    In an imaginary ideal socialist economy, the nice socialists would no doubt let Willie plow

    the collectively owned fields with the collectively owned plow. But thats not good enough.

    Willie wants a farm that he can shape according to his vision. He wants the farm to be his,

    not because hes selfish and mean, but because he wants to realise his own personal plans

    and ideas of how farming should go. For that to happen, he needs to have property that he

    can use at will and that others will refrain from using33

    Brennans argument, however, applies only to socialist conceptions of property rights that at the

    very least hold that all means of production ought to be owned in common and that no individual

    ought to be free to own means of production by themselves. It does not apply to full-communist

    ownership, according to which an individual is free to not only individually own means of

    production but to also produce commodities with said means of production and engage in trade with

    others. Such an individual would be free to pursue their own projects with their own property. Thus,

    in full-communism Willie would be free to individually own a farm and shape it according to their

    33 Brennan 2014, p.93

  • 17

    own vision. Furthermore, since under full-communism a far greater number of people would own

    resources than under capitalism it follows that more people would be able to pursue their projects

    than under capitalism. Thus, if Brennans argument is a reason to favour capitalist property rights, it

    is also a reason to favour full-communist ownership over capitalist property rights.

    Brennan might object that his argument does not justify full-communist ownership because in such

    a society, individuals would not be free to hire wage labourers or to rent out land or housing and so

    would not be free to pursue their own projects. However, not all projects ought to be allowed.

    Sadistic individuals who mainly gain self-expression, self-value and meaning from owning slaves

    ought not to be free to pursue their project of being a slave owner. Likewise, individuals ought not

    to be free to pursue their project of being a capitalist since doing so results in the oppression of

    others. This move is not particularly radical given that Brennan himself would wish to prohibit

    projects that involve, say, murder or theft. All the anarchist is doing is prohibiting a greater number

    of projects than Brennan does and doing so for the same kind of reason that Brennan would prohibit

    murder, namely that it violates certain fundamental rights or illegitimately infringes upon individual

    autonomy.

    Furthermore, while the removal of the option to be a capitalist limits the freedom of those

    individuals whose projects involve being capitalists, it is the case that doing so results in greater

    overall freedom. This is because prohibiting capitalist property removes an autonomy denying

    social relation and replaces it with social relations conducive towards the protection and expansion

    of autonomous action.

    Conclusion

    This essay has drawn two main conclusions. The first conclusion is that if an individual is from a

    theoretical point of view drawn towards left-libertarianism due to its reconciliation of liberty and

    equality, then said individual should be drawn more strongly to social anarchism due to full-

    communist ownership providing a far more libertarian and egalitarian reconciliation of liberty and

    equality. The second conclusion is that, contrary to defenders of capitalism, a) the advocacy of

    socialism is not inconsistent with the advocacy of freedom and individual property rights and b) the

    advocacy of capitalism is inconsistent with the advocacy of freedom due to the autonomy denying

    nature of wage labour and landlordism. As the founder of anarchism Bakunin writes, we are

    convinced that liberty without socialism is privilege, injustice; and that socialism without liberty is

    slavery and brutality.34

    Libertarian-egalitarian minded individuals may still prefer left-libertarianism to social anarchism

    34 Bakunin 1867

  • 18

    due to practical concerns, such as doubts about the practical feasibility of a communist economy.

    Such practical considerations are however beyond the scope of this essay and so I shall merely

    conclude that from a purely theoretical point of view, social anarchism provides a rival and superior

    account of the reconciliation of liberty and equality than left-libertarianism does.

  • 19

    Bibliography

    Books & Articles

    Attas, Daniel., 'Fragmenting Property', Law and Philosophy, 25:1, pp.119-149 (2006). Bakunin,

    Mikhail., Federalism, Socialism, Anti-Theologism. (1867). Available online at:

    [accessed on 26 April 2015].

    Bolloten, Burnett., The Spanish Civil War: Revolution and Counterrevolution, (University of North

    Carolina Press 1991).

    Brennan, Jason., Why Not Capitalism, (Routledge, 2014). Epub file.

    Chomsky, Noam., 'The Soviet Union Versus Socialism', Our Generation, 17(2), (Spring/Summer

    1986). Available online at: [accessed on 26 April

    2015].

    Christman, John., The Myth of Property: Toward an Egalitarian Theory of Ownership, (Oxford

    University Press, 1994).

    Dolgoff, Sam., (ed.), Bakunin on Anarchy, (Montreal: Black Rose Books, 2nd

    edition, 1980).

    Hayek, Friedrich., Road to Serfdom, (Routledge Classics, 2nd

    Edition, 2001).

    Hohfeld, Wesley., 'Some Fundamental Legal Conceptions As Applied In Judicial Reasoning' , Yale

    Law Journal, 23:1 pp.16-59 (November 1913).

    Kropotkin, Peter., The Conquest of Bread, (Oakland, California: AK Press, 2006)

    Kropotkin, Peter., Words of A Rebel, (Montreal: Black Rose Books, 1993)

    Kropotkin, Peter., 'Communism and the Wage System' in Walter, Nicholas., and Becker, Heiner.,

    (eds.), Act For Yourselves: Articles from Freedom, 1886-1907 (Freedom Press, 1998)

    Kropotkin, Peter, 'Communism and Anarchy', Freedom (July/August 1901) Available online at:

    [accessed on

    26 April 2015].

    Mack, Eric., The Self-Ownership Proviso: A New and Improved Lockean Proviso, Social Philosophy and Policy, 12:1, pp.186-218 (1995).

    Malatesta, Errico., 'Note to the article 'individualism and anarchism' by adamas' Pensiero e

    Volont, 15, (1924). Available online at:

    [accessed on 26 April 2015].

    Marx, Karl., Critique of The Gotha Program (1875). Available online at:

    [accessed on 26 April 2015].

    Ness, Immanuel., and Azzellimi, Dario., (eds.), Ours to Master and to Own: Workers Control from the Commune to the Present, (Haymarket Books, 2011).

  • 20

    Otsuka, Michael., Libertarianism without Inequality, (Oxford University Press, New Ed., 2005)

    Pettit, Philip., A Theory of Freedom: From the Psychology to The Politics of Agency, (Polity Press,

    2001).

    Richards, Vernon., (ed.), Errico Malatesta: His Life and Ideas, (London: Freedom Press, 1965).

    Available online at:

    [accessed on 26 April 2015].

    Tucker, Benjamin., Instead of A Book, By A Man Too Busy To Write One, (Haskell House Publishers

    1969)

    Vallentyne, Peter., 'Left-Libertarianism: A Primer', in Vallentyne, Peter., and Steiner, Hillel., (eds.),

    Left-Libertarianism and Its Critics: The Contemporary Debate (Palgrave Macmillan, 2000).

    Vallentyne, Peter., Steiner, Hillel., and Otsuka, Michael., 'Why Left-Libertarianism Isnt Incoherent, Indeterminate, or Irrelevant: A Reply to Fried', Philosophy and Public Affairs, 33, pp.201-15

    (2005). Available online at: [accessed on 26 April 2015].

    Vrousalis, Nicholas., 'Libertarian Socialism: A Better Reconciliation between Self-Ownership and

    Equality', Social Theory and Practice, 37:2 pp.211-226 (2011). Available online at:

    [accessed

    on 26 April 2015].

    Cases

    Market Investigations v Minister of Social Security [1969] 2 QB 173 at page 185