Against Measurement

download Against Measurement

of 10

Transcript of Against Measurement

  • 7/28/2019 Against Measurement

    1/10

    physicsworldarchive.iop.org

    Against measurementJohn Bell

    From

    Physics WorldAugust1990

    IOP Publishing Ltd 2009

    ISSN: 0953-8585

    Downloaded on Tue Mar 03 16:55:22 GMT 2009 [128.223.142.32]

    Institute of Physics Publishing

    Bristol and Philadelphia

  • 7/28/2019 Against Measurement

    2/10

    Physics World August 1990 3 3

    Uncertainty over terms such as 'apparatus'is still rife in serious discussions of quantum mechanics,over 60 years after its conception

    Against'measurement'S U R E L Y , after 62years, we should havean exact formulationof some serious part ofquantum mechanics?By 'exact' I do not ofcourse mean 'exactlyt rue ' . I mean only thatthe theory should befully formulated inmathematical terms, with nothing left to the discretion ofthe theoretical physicist . . . until workable approxim ationsare needed in applications. By 'serious' I mean that somesubstantial fragment of physics should be covered. No nrela-tivistic 'particle' quantum mechanics, perhaps with theinclusion of the electromagnetic field and a cut-off interac-tion, is serious enough. For it covers 'a large part of physicsand the whole of chemistry' (P A M Dirac 1929 Proc. R.Soc. A 123 714). I mean too, by 'serious', that 'apparatus'should not be separated off from the rest of the world intoblack boxes, as if it were not made of atoms and not ruledby quantum mechanics .Th e q uestion, ' . . . should w e not have an exactformulation . . . ? ' , is often answered by one or both of twoothers. I will try to reply to them: Why bother? Why not lookit up in a good book?Why bother?Perhaps the most distinguished of 'why bother?'ers hasbeen Dirac (1963 Sci. American 208 May 45). He dividedthe difficulties of quantum mechanics into two classes,those of the first class and those of the second. The second-class difficulties were essentially the infinities of relativisticquantum field theory. Dirac was very disturbed by these,and was not impressed by the 'renormalisation' proceduresby which they are circumvented. Dirac tried hard toeliminate these second-class difficulties, and urged others todo likewise. The first-class difficulties concerned the role ofthe 'observer', 'measurement', and so on. Dirac thoughtthat these problems were not ripe for solution, and shouldbe left for later. He expected developments in the theorywhich would m ake these problems look quite different. Itwould be a waste of effort to worry overmuch about themnow, especially since we get along very well in practicewithout solving them.Dirac gives at least this much comfort to those who aretroubled by these questions: he sees that they exist and aredifficult. Many other distinguished physicists do not. Itseems to me that it is among the most sure-footed ofquantum physicists, those who have it in their bones, thatone finds the greatest impatience with the idea that the'foundations of quantum mechanics' might need some

    JOHN BELL

    This article is published with the permission of PlenumPublishing, New York; it will appear in the proceedings of 62Years of Uncertainty (Erice, 514 August 1989).

    attention. Knowingwhat is right by in-stinct, they can be-come a little impatientwith nitpicking dis-tinctions betweentheorems and assump-t ions. When they doadmit some ambiguityin the usual formula-t ions, they are likely to insist that ordinary quantummechanics is just fine 'for all practical purposes'. I agreewith them about that : ORDINARY QUANTUMME CHA NICS (as far as I know) IS JUS T FIN E FO R AL LPR AC TIC AL PUR POSES.Even when I begin by insisting on this myself, and incapital letters, it is likely to be insisted on repeatedly in thecourse of the discussion. So it is convenient to have anabbreviation for the las t phrase: FOR ALL PRACTICALPUR POSES = FAPP.I can imagine a practical geome ter, say an architect, beingimpatient with Euclid's fifth postulate, or Playfair 's axiom:of course in a plane, through a given point, you can drawonly one straight line parallel to a given straight line, at leastFAPP. The reasoning of such a natural geometer might notaim at pedantic precision, and new assertions, known in thebones to be righ t, even if neither among th e originally statedassumptions nor derived from them as theorems, mightcome in at any stage. Perhaps these particular lines in theargument should, in a systematic presentation, be disting-uished by this label - FA PP - and the conclusionslikewise: QED FAPP.I expect that mathematicians have classified such fuzzylogics. Certainly they have been much used by physicists.But is there not something to be said for the approach ofEuclid? Even now that we know that Euclidean geometryis (in some sense) not quite true? Is it not good to knowwhat follows from what, even if it is not really necessaryFAPP? Suppose for example that quantum mechanics werefound to resist precise formulation. Suppose that whenformulation beyond FAPP is attempted, we find anunmovable finger obstinately pointing outside the subject,to the mind of the observer, to the Hindu scriptures, toGod, or even only Gravitation? Would not that b e very, veryinteresting?But I must say at once that it is not mathematicalprecision, but physical, with which I will be concernedhere . I am not squeamish about delta functions. From thepresent point of view, the approach of von Neu ma nn's bookis not preferable to that of Dirac's.Why not look it up in a good book?But which good book? In fact it is seldom that a 'noproblem' person is, on reflection, willing to endorse atreatment already in the literature. Usually the goodunproblematic formulation is still in the head of the person

  • 7/28/2019 Against Measurement

    3/10

    3 4 Physics World August 1990

    'Perhaps the most distinguished of 'why bother?'ers has been PaulDirac1in question, who has been too busy with practical things topu t it on paper. I think that this reserve, as regards theformulations already in the good books, is well founded.For the good books known tome are not much concernedwith physical precision. This is clear already from theirvocabulary.Here are some words which, however legitimate andnecessary in application, have no place in a formulation withany pretension to physical precision: system, apparatus,environment, microscopic, macroscopic, reversible, irreversible,observable, information, measurem ent.The concepts 'system', 'apparatus ' , 'environment ' , im-mediately imply anartificial division of the world, and anintention to neglect, ortake only schematic account of, th einteraction across the split. The notions of 'microscopic'and 'macroscopic' defy precise definition. Soalso do thenotions of ' reversible' and 'irreversible'. Einstein said thatit is theory which decides what is 'observable ' . I think hewas right - 'observation' is acomplicated and theory-ladenbusiness. Then that notion should not appear in theformulation of fundamental theory. Information? Whoseinformation? Information about what?On this list of bad words from good books, the worst ofall is 'measurement ' . It must have a section toitself.Against 'measurement'When I say that the word 'measurement' is even worse thanthe others , I do not have in mind the use of the word inphrases like 'measure the mass and width of th e Z boson' .I dohave in mind its use in the fundamental interpretiverules of quantum mechanics. For example, here they are asgiven by Dirac (Quantum Mechanics Oxford UniversityPress 1930):

    '. . . any result of a measurement of a real dynamical variableis one of its eigenvalues . . . "'. . . if the measurement of the observable . . . is madea large number of times the average of all the results obtainedwill be . . .''. . . a measurement always causes the system to jump into aneigenstate of the dynamical variable that is being measured . . .'It would seem that the theory is exclusively concernedabout 'results of measurement ' , and has nothing to sayabout anything else. What exactly qualifies some physical

    systems toplay the role of 'measurer'? Was the wavefunc-tion of the world waiting to jump for thousands of millionsof years until a single-celled living creature appeared? Ordid it have towait a little long er, forsome better qualifiedsystem . . . with a P h D ? If the theory is to apply toanything but highly idealised laboratory operations, are wenot obliged to admit that more or less 'measurement-like'processes are going onmore or less all the t ime, more orless everywhere? Do w e not have jumping then all the time?The first charge against 'measurement', in the fundamen-tal axioms of quantum mechanics , is that it anchors therethe shifty split of the world into 'system' and 'apparatus ' .A second charge is that the word comes loaded withmeaning from everyday life, meaning which is entirelyinappropriate in the quantum context. When it is said thatsomething is 'measured' it is difficult not to think of th eresult as referring to some pre-existing property of theobject in question. This is to disregard Bohr's insistencethat in quantum phenomena the apparatus as well as thesystem is essentially involved. If it were not so, how couldwe unders tand , for example, that 'measurement ' of acomponent of ' angular momentum' in an arbitrarilychosen direction yields one of a discrete set of values?When one forgets the role of the apparatus , as the word'mea surem ent' makes all too likely, one despairs of ordinarylogic - hence 'quantum logic ' . When one remembers therole of the apparatus, ordinary logic is just fine.

    In other con texts, physicists have been able to take w ordsfrom everyday language and use them as technical termswith nogreat harm done. Take for example, the 'strange-ness', 'charm', and 'beauty' of elementary particle physics.No one is taken inby this 'baby talk', as Bruno Touschekcalled it. Would that it were so with 'me asureme nt ' . But infact the word has had such a damaging effect on thediscussion, that I think it should now be banned altogetherin quantum mechanics .The role of experimentEven in a low-brow practical account, I think it would begood to replace the word 'measurement ' , in the formula-tion, by the word 'experiment ' . For the latter word isaltogether less misleading. However, the idea that quantummechanics , our most fundamental physical theory, isexclusively even about the results of experiments wouldremain disappointing.In the beginning natural philosophers tried to understandthe world around them. Trying to do that they hit upon thegreat idea of contriving artificially simple situations inwhich the number of factors involved is reduced to aminimum. Divide and conquer. Experimental science wasborn . But experiment is a tool. The aim remains: tounderstand the world. To restr ict quantum mechanics to beexclusively about p iddling laboratory operations is to betraythe great enterprise. A serious formulation will not excludethe big world outside the laboratory.The quantum mechanics of Landau andLifshitzLet us have a look at the good book Quantum Mechanics byL DLandau and E M Lifshitz. I can offer three reasons forthis choice:

    (i) It is indeed a good book.(ii) It ha s a very good pedigree. Landau sat at the feet ofBohr. Bohr himself never wrote a systematic accountof the theory. Perhaps that of Landau and Lifshitz is thenearest to Bohr that we have.(iii) It is the only book on the subject in which I have

  • 7/28/2019 Against Measurement

    4/10

    Physics World August 1990 3 5

    read every word.This last came about because my friend John Sykesenlisted me as technical assistant when he did the Englishtranslation. My recommendation of this book has nothingto do with the fact that one per cent of what you pay for itcomes to me.LL emphasise, following Bohr, that quantum mechanicsrequires for its formulation 'classical concepts' - a classicalworld which intervenes on the quantum system, and inwhich experimental results occur (brackets after quotesrefer to page numbers):

    ' . . . It is in principle impossible . . . to formulate the basicconcepts of quantum mechanics without using classicalmechanics . ' (LL2)'. . . The possibility of a quantitative description of the motionof an electron requires the presence also of physical objectswhich obey classical mechanics to a sufficient degree ofaccuracy. ' (LL2)

    '. . . the 'classical object' is usually called apparatus and itsinteraction with the electron is spoken of as measurement.How ever, it must be emphasised that we are here not discussinga process . . . in which the physicist-observer takes part. Bymeasurement, in quantum mechanics, we understand anyprocess of interaction between classical and quantum objects,occurring apart from and independently of any observer. Theimportance of the concept of measurement in quantummechanics was elucidated by N Bohr. ' (LL2)

    And with B ohr they insist again on the inhum anity of it all:' . . . Once again we emphasise that, in speaking of 'performinga measu remen t' , we refer to the interaction of an electron witha classical 'apparatus ' , which in no way presupposes thepresence of an external observer. ' (LL3)' . . . Thus quantum mechanics occupies a very unusual placeamong physical theories: it contains classical mechanics as alimiting case, yet at the same time it requires this limiting casefor its own formulation . . . " (L L3)'. . . consider a system c onsisting of tw o pa rts: a classicalapparatus and an electron . . . The states of the apparatus aredescribed by quasiclassical wavefunctions where thesuffix n corresponds to the ' reading' gn of the apparatus, and denotes the set of its coordinates. The classical nature of theapparatus appears in the fact that, at any given instant, we cansay with certainty th at it is in one of the known states $ w ithsome definite value of the quantity g; for a quantum systemsuch an assertion would of course be unjustified .' (LL 21)'. . . Let %() be the wavefunction of the initial state of theapp aratus . . . an d W{q) of the electron . . . the initialwavefunction of the whole system is the pro du ct tf)After the measuring process we obtain a sum of the form

    where the A tt{q) are some functions of q. ' (LL22)'The classical nature of the apparatus, and the double role ofclassical mechanics as both the limiting case and the foundationof quantum mechanics, now make their appearance. As hasbeen said above, the classical nature of the apparatus means

    that, at any instant, the quantity g (the 'reading of theapparatu s ') has some definite value. T his enables us to say thatthe state of the system apparatus + electron after themeasurement will in actual fact be described, not by the entiresum, but by only the one term which corresponds to the' reading ' gn of the apparatus An(q)

  • 7/28/2019 Against Measurement

    5/10

    3 6 Physics World August 1990

    of the particular present enquiry - into the possibility ofprecision. More generally, KG's priorities are those of allr ight-thinking people.The book itself is above all pedagogical. The student istaken gently by the hand, and soon finds herself or himselfdoing quantu m mechanics , without pain - and almostwithout thought. The essential division of KG's world intosystem and apparatus, quantum and classical, a notion thatmight disturb the student, is gently implicit rather thanbrutally explicit. No explicit guidance is then given as tohow in practice this shifty division is to be made. Thestudent is simply left to pick up good habits by beingexposed to good examples.KG declares that the task of the theory is (KG 16) ' . . . t opredict the results of measurements on the system . . . ' Thebasic structure of KG's world is then W = S + R where 5is the quantum system, and R is the rest of the world from which measurements on 5 are made. When our onlyinterpretive axioms are about measurement results (orfindings (KG11)) we absolutely need such a base R fromwhich measurements can be made. There can be noquestion then of identifying the quantum system S with thewhole world W. The re can be no question - witho utchang ing th e axioms of getting rid of the shifty split.Sometimes some authors of 'quantum measurement 'theories seem to be trying to do just that. It is like a snaketrying to swallow itself by the tail. It can be done - up toa point. B ut it becomes embarrassing for the spectators evenbefore it becomes uncomfortable for the snake.

    But there is something which can and must be done toanalyse theoretically not removing the split, which cannot bedone with the usual axioms, but shifting it. This is taken upin KG 's chapter 4: 'Th e Measurement Process . . . " Surely'apparatus' can be seen as made of atoms? And it oftenhappens that we do not know, or not well enough, either apriori or by experience, the functioning of some system thatwe would regard as 'apparatus'. The theory can help us withthis only if we take this 'apparatus' A out of the rest of theworld R and treat it together with 5 as part of an enlargedquantum system S': R=A + R'; S + A = S'; W=S' + R'.The original axioms about 'measurement' (whatever theywere exactly) are then applied not at theS/A interface, but at the AIR' interface where for somereason it is regarded as more safe to do so. In real life itwould not be possible to find any such point of divisionwhich would be exactly safe. For example, strictly speakingit would not be exactly safe to take it between the coun ters,say, and the compute r - slicing neatly through some of theatoms of the wires. But with some idealisation, which mig ht'. . . be highly stylised and not do justice to the enormouscomplexity of an actual laboratory experiment . . . "(KG 165), it might be possible to find mo re than one not tooimplausible way of dividing the world up. Clearly it isnecessary to check that different choices give consistentresults (FAPP). A disclaimer towards the end of KG'schapter 4 suggests that that, and only that, is the modestaim of that chapter (KG189): ' . . . we emphasise that ourdiscussion has merely consisted of several demonstrationsof internal consistency . . . " But reading reveals otherambitions.Neglecting the interaction of A with R' , the joint systemS' = S + A is found to end, in virtue of the Schrodingerequation, after the 'measurement' on 5 by A, in a state

    where the states ty n are supposed each to have a definite

    apparatus pointer reading gn. The corresponding densitymatrix is4 Un m

    At this point KG insists very much on the fact that A, andso S' , is a macroscopic system. For macroscopic systems,he says, (KG186) ' . . . trAp = trAp for all observables Aknown to occur in nature . . . " where

    P =i.e. p is obtained from p by dropp ing interference termsinvolving pairs of macroscopically different states. Then(KG 188) ' . . . we are free to replace p by p after themeasurement, safe in the knowledge that the error willnever be found . . . "Now, while quite uncomfortable with the concept 'allknown observables', I am fully convinced of the practicalelusiveness, even the absence FAPP, of interference be-tween macroscopically different states (J S Bell and MNauenbe rg 1966 'The moral aspects of quantum mechanics 'in Preludes in Theoretical Physics North-Holland). So let usgo along with KG on this and see where it leads: ' . . . If wetake advantage of the indistinguishability of p and p tosay that p is the state of the system sub sequent tomeasurement, the intuitive interpretation of cm as a proba-bility amplitude emerges without further ado. This isbecause cm enters p only via | c j 2 , and the latter quantityappears in p in precisely the same m anne r as probabilitiesdo in classical statistical physics . . .'I am quite puzzled by this. If one were not actually onthe lookout for probabilities, I think the obvious interpreta-tion of even p wou ld be th at th e system is in a state inwhich the various ^ s somehow coexist: ^ P ^ * and ^ 2 ^ 2and . . .This is not at all a probability inte rpretatio n, in which thedifferent terms are seen not as coexisting, but as alterna-t ives: ^P ,^ * or ^2^2* or . . .The idea that elimination of coherence, in one way oranother, implies the replacement of 'and' by 'or' , is a verycommon one among solvers of the 'measurement problem'.It has always puzzled me.It would be difficult to exaggerate the importanceattached by KG to the replacement of p by p: ' . . . Tothe extent tha t nonclassical interference terms (such as cmc%)are present in the mathematical expression for p . . . thenumbers cm are intuitively uninterpretable, and the theoryis an emp ty mathem atical formalism . . . ' (K G 187)But this suggests that the original theory, 'an emptymathematical formalism', is not just being approximated but discarded and replaced. And yet elsewhere KG seemsclear that it is in the business of approximation that he isengaged, approximation of the sort that introduces irrever-sibility in the passage from classical mechanics to thermo-dynamics: ' . . . In this connection one should note that inapproxima ting p by p one introduces irreversibility,because the time-reversed Schrodinger equation cannotretrieve p from p.' (KG188)New light is thrown on K G's ideas by a recent recapitula-tion, referred to in the following as KGR (K Gottfried 'Doesquantum mechanics describe the collapse of the wavefunc-tion?' Presented at 62 Years of Uncertainty, Erice, 5-14August 1989). This is dedicated to the proposition that(KG R1) ' . . . the laws of qua ntum mechanics yield th e

  • 7/28/2019 Against Measurement

    6/10

    Physics World August 1990 3 7

    results of measurements . . . "These laws are taken to be(KGR1): '(1) a pure state isdescribed by some vector inHilbert space from which ex-pectation values of observ-ables are computed in thestandard way; and (2) thetime evolution is a unitarytransformation on that vector'(KGR1). Not included in thelaws is (KGR1) vonNe um ann 's ' . . . infamouspostulate: the measurementact 'collapses' the state intoone in which there are nointerference terms betweendifferent states of the mea-surement apparatus . . ." In-deed, (KGR1) 'the reductionpostulate is an ugly scar onwhat would be a beautifultheory if it could be removed

    Perhaps it is useful to recallhere just how the infamouspostulate is formulated byvon Neumann (J vonNeumann 1955 MathematicalFoundations of QuantumMechanics Princeton University Press). If we look back wefind that what vN actually postulates (vN347, 418) is that'measure men t' an external intervention by R on 5 causes the state$ = X cn < l > n

    to jump, with various probabilities into fy1 or 2 or . . .From the 'or' here, replacing the 'and', as a result ofexternal intervention, vN infers that the resulting densitymatrix, averaged over the several possibilities, has nointerference terms between states of the system whichcorrespond to different measurement results (vN347). Iwould emphasise several points here.(i) von Neum ann presents the disappearance of coherencein the density matrix, not as a postulate, but as aconsequence of a postulate. The postulate is made at thewavefunction level, and is just that already made by Diracfor example.(ii) I cannot imagine von Neumann arguing in theopposite direction, that lack of interference in the densitymatrix implies, without further ado, 'or' replacing 'and' atthe wavefunction level. A special postulate to that effectwould be required.(iii) von Neumann is concerned here with what happensto the state of the system that has suffered the measurement an external intervention. In application to the extendedsystem S'(= S + A) von Neumann's collapse would notoccur before external intervention from R'. It would besurprising if this consequence of external intervention on S'could be inferred from the purely internal Schrodingerequation for S'. Now KG's collapse, although justified byreference to 'all known observables' at the S'/R' interface,

    occurs after 'measurement' by A on S, but before interac-tion across S'/R'. Thus the collapse which KG discusses isnot that which von Neumann infamously postulates. It is

    John von Neumann - ' . . . infamous postulate: the measurement act'collapses' the state into one in which there are no interference termsbetween different states of the measurement apparatus

    the LL collapse rather thanthat of von Neumann andDirac.The explicit assumptionthat expectation values are tobe calculated in the usual waythrows light on the subse-quent falling out of the usualprobability interpretation'without further ado'. For therules for calculating expecta-tion values, applied to projec-tion operators for example,yield the Born probabilitiesfor eigenvalues. The mysteryis then: what has the authoractually derived rather thanassumed? And why does heinsist that probabilitiesappear only after the butcher-ing of p into p, the theoryremaining an 'empty mathe-matical formalism' so long asp is retained? Dirac, vonNeumann, and the others ,nonchalantly assumed theusual rules for expectationvalues, and so probabilities,in the context of the unbutch-ered theory. Reference to theusual rules for expectation values also makes clear whatKG's probabilities are probabilities of. They are probabilitiesof 'measurement' results, of external results of externalinterventions, from R' on S' in the application. We mustnot drift into thinking of them as probabilities of intrinsicproperties of S' independent of, or before, 'measurement'.Concepts like that have no place in the orthodox theory.

    Having tried hard to understand what KG has written, Iwill finally permit myself some guesses about what he mayhave in mind. I think that from the beginning KG tacitlyassumes the Dirac rules at S'/R' - including the Dirac -vonNeumann jump, required to get the correlations betweenresults of successive (moral) measurements. Then, for 'allknown observables', he sees that the 'measurement' resultsat S'/R' are AS IF (FAPP) the LL jump had occurred inS'. This is important, for it shows how, FAPP, we can getaway with attributing definite classical properties to 'appar-a tus ' while believing it to be governed by quantummechanics. But a jump assumption remains. LL derived theDirac jump from the assumed LL jump. KG derives,FAPP, the LL jump from assumptions at the shifted splitR'/S' which include the Dirac jump there.It seems to me that th ere is then some conceptual drift inthe argument. The qualification 'as if (FAPP)' is dropped,and it is supposed that the LL jump really takes place. Thedrift is away from the 'me asu rem ent ' ( . . . e xternalintervention . . .) orientation of orthodox quantum mecha-nics towards the idea that systems, such as S' above, haveintrinsic properties - independ ently of and before observa-tion. In particular the readings of experimental apparatusare supposed to be really there before they are read. Thiswould explain KG's reluctance to interpret the unbutchereddensity matrix p, for the interference terms there couldseem to imply the simultaneous existence of differentreadings. It would explain his need to collapse p into p,in contrast with von Neumann and the others , withoutexternal intervention across the last split S'/R'. It wouldexplain why he is anxious to obtain this reduction from the

  • 7/28/2019 Against Measurement

    7/10

    3 8 Physics World August 1990

    internal Schrodinger equation of S' . (It would not explainthe reference to 'all know n observables' - at the S'/R'split.) The resulting theory would be one in which some'macroscopic' 'physical attributes' have values at all times,with a dynamics that is related somehow to the butcheringof p into p which is seen as somehow not incompatiblewith the internal Schrodinger equation of the system. Sucha theory, assuming intrinsic properties, would not needexternal intervention, would not need the shifty split. Butthe retention of the vague word 'macroscopic' would reveallimited ambition as regards precision. To avoid the vague'microscopic' 'macroscopic' distinction again a shifty split I think one would b e led to introduce variables whichhave values even on the smallest scale. If the exactness ofthe Schrodinger equation is maintained, I see this leadingtowards the picture of de Broglie and Bohm.The quantum mechanics of N G van KampenLet us look at one more good book, namely Physica A 153(1988), and more specifically at the contribution: 'Tentheorems about quantum mechanical measurements ' , by NG van Kampen. This paper is distinguished especially byits robust common sense. The author has no patience with'. . . such m ind-boggling fantasies as the many worldinterpretation . . . " (vK98). He dismisses out of hand thenotion of von Neumann, Pauli , Wigner that 'measure-ment' might be complete only in the mind of the observer:' . . . I find it hard to understand that someone who arrivesat such a conclusion does not seek the error in his argu me nt'(vK lO l). For vK '. . . the min d of the observer is irrelevant. . . the quantum mechanical measurement is terminatedwhen the outcome has been macroscopically recorded . . . "(vKlOl). Moreover, for vK, no special dynamics comes intoplay at 'meas urem ent': ' . . . The measuring act is fullydescribed by the Schrodinger equation for object systemand appara tus together. Th e collapse of the wavefunction isa consequence rather than an additional postulate . . . "(vK97).After the measurement the measuring instrument,according to the Schrodinger equation, will admittedly bein a superposition of different readings. For example,Schrodinger's cat will be in a superposition \cat> = a\life>+ b\death>. And it might seem that we do have to deal with'and' rather than 'or' here, because of interference: ' . . . forinstance the temperature of the cat . . . the expectationvalue of such a quantity G . . . is not a statistical averageof the values G and Gdd with probabilities \a \2 and \b \2, butcontains cross term s between life and death . . . " (vK10 3).But vK is not impressed: 'The answer to this paradox isagain that the cat is macroscopic. Life and death aremacrostates containing an enormous number of eigenstates|/> and \d> . . .

    \ c a t > = X a , \ l >

    . . . the cross terms in the expression for . . . as thereis such a wealth of terms, all with different phases andmagnitudes, they mutually cancel and their sum practicallyvanishes. This is the way in which the typical quantummechanical interference becomes inoperative betweenmacrostates . . . ' (vK103).This argument for no interference is not, it seems to me,by itself immediately convincing. Surely it would bepossible to find a sum of very many terms, with different

    amplitudes and phases, which is not zero? However, I amconvinced anyway that interference between macro-scopically different states is very, very elusive. Grantingthis, let me try to say what I think the argument to be, forthe collapse as a 'consequence' rather than an additionalpostulate.The world is again divided into 'system', 'apparatus', andthe rest: W = S + A + R' = S' + R'. At first, the usualrules for quantum 'measurements' are assumed at the S'/R'interface - including the collapse postulate , which dictatescorrelations between results of 'measurements' made atdifferent times. But the 'measurements' at S'/R' which canactually be done, FAPP, do not show interference betweenmacroscopically different states of S' . It is ax t/ th e 'and ' inthe superposition had already, before any such measure-ments, been replaced by 'or' . So the 'and' ha s already beenreplaced by 'or' . It is as if i t were so . . . so i t is so.

    This may be good FAPP logic. If we are more pedantic,it seems to me that we do not have here the proof of atheorem, but a change of the theory at a strategically wellchosen point. The change is from a theory which speaksonly of the results of external interventions on the quantumsystem, S' in this discussion, to one in which that systemis attributed intrinsic properties deadness or aliveness inthe case of cats. The point is strategically well chosen in thatthe predictions for results of 'measurements' across S'/R'will still be the same . . . FAPP.Whether by theorem or by assumption, we end up witha theory like that of LL, in which superpositions ofmacroscopically different states decay somehow into one ofthe mem bers. W e can ask as before just how and how oftenit happens. If we really had a theorem, the answers to thesequestions would be calculable. But the only possibility ofcalculation in schemes like those of KG and vK involvesshifting further th e shifty split - and the ques tions with it.For most of the paper, vK's world seems to be the pettyworld of the laboratory, even one that is not treated veryrealistically: ' . . . in this connection the m easurem ent isalways taken to be instantaneous . . .' (vKlOO)But almost at the last moment a startling new vista opensup - an altogether more vast one:'Theorem IX: The total system is described throughout by thewave vector W and has therefore zero entropy at all times . . .

    This ought to put an end to speculations about measure-ments being responsible for increasing the entropy of theuniverse. (I t won' t of course.) ' (vKlll)So vK , unlike many o ther very practical physicists, seemswilling to consider the universe as a whole. His universe,or at any rate some 'total system', has a wavefunction, and

    that wavefunction satisfies a linear Schrodinger equation. Itis clear, however, that this wavefunction cannot be thewhole story of vK's totality. For it is clear that he expectsthe experiments in his laboratories to give definite results,and his cats to be dead or alive. He believes then in variablesX which identify the realities, in a way which thewavefunction, without collapse, can not. His completekinematics is then of the de Broglie-Bohm 'hidden variable'dual type: ((t,r), X(t)).For the dynamics, he has exactly the Schrodingerequation for ^ , but I do not know exactly what he has inmind for the X, which for him would be restricted to some'macroscopic' level. Perhaps indeed he would prefer toremain somewhat vague about this, for

    'Theorem IV: Whoever endows W w ith m ore meaning than isneeded for computing observable phenomena is responsible forthe consequences . . .' (vK99)

  • 7/28/2019 Against Measurement

    8/10

    Physics World August 1990 3 9

    Towards a precise quantum mechanicsIn the beginning, Schrodinger tried to interpret his wave-function as giving somehow the density of the stuff of whichthe world is made. He tried to think of an electron asrepre sente d by a wavep acket - a wavefunction appreciab lydifferent from zero only over a small region in space. Theextension of that region he thought of as the actual size ofthe electron - his electron was a bit fuzzy. At first hethought that small wavepackets, evolving according to theSchrodinger equation, would remain small. But that waswrong. Wavepackets diffuse, and with the passage of timebecome indefinitely extended, according to the Schrodingerequation. But however far the wavefunction has extended,the reaction of a detector to an electron remains spotty. SoSchrodinger's 'realistic' interpretation of his wavefunctiondid not survive.

    Then came the Born interpretation. The wavefunctiongives not the density of stuff, but gives rather (on squaringits modulus) the density of probability. P robability of what,exactly? Not of the electron being there, but of the electronbeing found there, if its position is 'measured'.Why this aversion to 'being' and insistence on 'finding'?The founding fathers were unable to form a clear picture ofthings on the remote atomic scale. They became very awareof the intervening apparatus, and of the need for a 'classical'base from which to intervene on the quantum system. Andso the shifty split.The kinematics of the world, in this orthodox picture, isgiven by a wavefunction (maybe more than one?) for thequa ntu m p art , and classical variables variables whichhave values - for the classical par t: ($?(t,q . . .), X(t)). T he Xs are somehowmacroscopic. This is not spelled outvery explicitly. The dynamics is notvery precisely formulated either. It in-

    cludes a Schrodinger equation for thequantum part, and some sort of classicalmechanics for the classical part, and'collapse' recipes for their interaction.It seems to me that the only hope ofprecision with the dual (^, x) kinema-tics is to omit completely the shiftyspl it, and let bot h M*1 and x refer to theworld as a whole. Then the xs must notbe confined to some vague macroscopicscale, but must extend to all scales. Inthe picture of de Broglie and Bohm,every particle is attributed a positionx(t). Then instrument pointers assemblies of particles have positions,and experiments have results . Thedynamics is given by the worldSchrodinger equation plus precise'guiding' equations prescribing how thex(t)s move under the influence of ^ .Particles are not attributed angularmomenta, energies, etc, but only posi-tions as functions of time. Peculiar'measurement' results for angularmomenta, energies, and so on, emergeas pointer positions in appropriate ex-perimental setups. Considerations ofthe KG and vK type, on the absence(FAPP) of macroscopic interference,take their place here, and an importantone , in showing how usually we do nothave (FAPP) to pay attention to the

    whole world, but only to some subsystem and can simplifythe wavefunction . . . FAPP.The Born-type kinematics (% X) has a duality that theoriginal 'density of stuff picture of Schrodinger did not.The position of the particle there was just a feature of thewavepacket, not something in addition. The Landau-Lifshitz approach can be seen as maintaining this simplenondual kinematics, but with the wavefunction compact ona macroscopic rather than microscopic scale. We know,they seem to say, that macroscopic pointers have definitepositions. An d we think there is nothing but the wavefunc-tion. So the wavefunction must be narrow as regardsmacroscopic variables. The Schrodinger equation does notpreserve such narrowness (as Schrodinger himself drama-tised with his cat). So there must be some kind of 'collapse'going on in addition, to enforce macroscopic narrowness.In the same way, if we had modified Schroding er'sevolution somehow we might have prevented the spreadingof his wavepacket electrons. But actually the idea that anelectron in a ground-state hydrogen atom is as big as theatom (which is then perfectly spherical) is perfectly toler-able - and maybe even attractive. The idea that amacroscopic pointer can point simultaneously in differentdirections, or that a cat can have several of its nine lives atthe same tim e, is harder to swallow. And if we have no extravariables X to express macroscopic definiteness, the wave-function itself must be narrow in macroscopic directions inthe configuration space. This the Landau-Lifshitz collapsebrings about. It does so in a rather vague way, at rathervaguely specified times.In the Ghiradi-Rimini-Weber scheme (see the box andthe contributions of Ghiradi, Rimini, We ber, Pe arle, Gisin

    The Ghiradi-Rimini-Weber schemeThe GRW scheme represents a proposalaimed to overcome the difficulties ofquantum mechanics discussed by JohnBell in this article. The GRW model isbased on the acceptance of the fact thatthe Schrodinger dynamics, governing theevolution of the wavefunction, has to bemodified by the inclusion of stochasticand nonlinear effects. Obviously thesemodifications must leave practically un-altered all standard quantum predictionsabout microsystems.

    To be more specific, the GRW theoryadmits that the wavefunction, besidesevolving through the standard Hamil-tonian dynam ics, is subjected, at randomtimes, to spontaneous processes cor-responding to localisations in space ofthe microconstituents of any physicalsystem. The mean frequency of thelocalisations is extremely small, and thelocalisation width is large on an atomicscale. As a consequence no prediction ofstandard quantum formalism for micro-systems is changed in any appreciableway.The merit of the model is in the factthat the localisation mechanism is suchthat its frequency increases as the num-ber of constituents of a composite system

    increases. In the case of a macroscopicobject (containing an Avogadro numberof constituents) linear superpositions ofstates describing pointers 'pointingsimultaneously in different directions'are dynamically suppressed in extremelyshort times. As stated by John Bell, inGRW 'Schrodinger 's cat is not both deadand alive for more than a split second'.# Th e original and technically detailedpresentation of GRW can be found in1986 Phys. Rev D 34 470; a brilliant andsimple presentation has been given byJohn Bell in Schrodinger: CentenaryCelebration of a Polymath C W Kilmister(ed) 1987 Cambridge University Pressp4 1# A general discussion of the con ceptualimplications of the scheme can be foundin 1988 Foundation of Physics 81 1# Th e GRW model has been the objectof many recent papers and a lively debateon its implications is going on. Recentlythe model has been generalised to coverthe case of systems of identical particlesand to meet the requirements of relativis-tic invariance.G C Ghiradi , A Rimini and T Weber

  • 7/28/2019 Against Measurement

    9/10

    0 Physics World August 1990

    and Diosi presented at 62 Years of Uncertainty, Erice, 5-14August 1989) this vagueness is replaced by mathematicalprecision. The Schrodinger wavefunction even for a singleparticle, is supposed to be unstable, with a prescribed meanlife per particle, against spontaneous collapse of a pre-scribed form. The lifetime and collapsed extension are suchthat departures of the Schrodinger equation show up veryrarely and very weakly in few-particle systems. But inm a c r o s c o p i c s y s t e m s , axa consequence of the prescribedequations, pointers very rapidly point, and cats are veryquickly killed or spared.

    The orthodox approaches, whether the authors thinkthey have made derivations or assumptions, are just fineFAPP when used with the good taste and discretionpicked up from exposure to good examples. At least tworoads are open from there towards a precise theory , it seemsto me. Both eliminate the shifty split. The de Broglie-Bohm-type theories retain, exactly, the linear wave equa-tion, and so necessarily add complementary variables toexpress the non-waviness of the world on the macroscopicscale. The GRW-type theories have nothing in theirkinematics but the wavefunction. It gives the density (in amultidimensional configuration space!) of stuff. To accountfor th e narrowness of that stuff in m acroscopic dimensions,the linear Schrodinger equation has to be modified, in theGRW picture by a mathematically prescribed spontaneouscollapse mechanism.The big question, in my opinion, is which, if either, ofthese two precise pictures can be redeveloped in a Lorentzinvariant way.

    '. . . All historical experience confirms that m en m ight notachieve the possible if they had not, time and time again,reached out for the impossible.' Max Weber'. . . we do not know where we are stupid until we stick ournecks out.' R P Feynman

    Further readingJ S Bell and M Nauenberg 1966 The moral aspect of quantummechanics inPrelitdes intheoretical physics ( in honour of V FWeisskopf) (North-Holland) 278-286P A M Dirac 1929 Proc. R. Soc. A 123 71 4P A MDirac 1948 Quantum mechanics third edn (OxfordUniversity Press)P A M Dirac 1963 Sci. American 208 May 45K Gottfried 1966 Quantum mechanics (Benjamin)K Gottfried Does qua ntum mechanics describe the collapse of thewavefunction? Presented at 62 Years ofUncertainty, Erice, 5-14August 1989L D Landau and E M Lifshitz 1977 Quantum mechanics third edn(Pergamon)N G van Kampen 1988 Ten theorems about quantum mechanicalmeasurements Physica A 153 97-113J von Neumann 1955 Mathematical foundations of quantum mecha-nics (Princeton University Press)

    John Bell is in the theory division, CERN , CH-1211, Geneva,Switzerland i

    IOP MEMBERSEXCLUSIVEMOTOR

    INSURANCEFROM ENDSLEIGH

    Within thenext fewminutes you canalmostcertainly start saving a tidy sum on motorinsurance. Just phone us or call into yourlocal centre.

    clients over thepast two decades toprovidean insurance service to every sector ofthe community.

    This isprobably whywere unshockableand consequently very competitive in thosemore extreme cases that most insurersturn away-young drivers with fast cars,for example.

    WE'RE LOCAL.We have over 130 centres nation-wide,so youcan phone or call inforaquote.

    Whenwe have your details,our computer willhunt down thecheapest quote and thebestpolicy from our exclusive schemes.

    Exclusive because theyare all designedand negotiatedby uswitha wde variety ofinsurers which means theyare not availableanywhereelse.

    HIGH RISK.

    Although Endsleigh's roots are with thestudent movement,we have grown withourWITHYOURCOMPETITIVE MOTOR QUOTECOMESANEQUALLY COMPETITIVE

    HOMESTYLE' QUOTE WTHOUT ANSWERINGANY EXTRA QUESTIONS.

    Circle 16 on reply card

  • 7/28/2019 Against Measurement

    10/10

    Physics World August 1990 4 1

    C a m b r i d g eR e l a t i v i t y o n C u r v e d M a n i f o l d sF. DE FELICE a n d C. J. S. CLARKEGeneral relativity is now essential to the understanding ofmodern physics, but the po wer of the theory cannot befully explained witho ut a detailed know ledge of itsmathematical structure. This is a self-contained expositionwith emphasis given to tetrad and spinor structures andphysical measurements on curved manifolds.45.00 net Hardback 0 521 26639 4 464 pp. 1990Cambridge Monographs on Mathematical PhysicsNow in paperbackH a m i l t o n i a n S y s t e m s :C h a o s a n d Q u a n t i z a t i o nALFREDO M. OZORIO DE ALMEIDAThe study of nonlinear dynamics, and in particular ofchaotic systems, is one of the fastest growing andprodu ctive areas in physics and applied m athem atics. Thisintroduction to the theory of Ham iltonian chaos outlinesthe main results in the field, and goes on to consider theimplications for q uantu m mechanics.15.00 net Paperback 0 52138 670 5 247 pp. 1990Cambridge Monographs on Mathematical Physics

    G e n e r a l R e l a t i v i t yAn Introduction to the Theory of GravitationSecond EditionHANS STEPHANIThe revised and corrected edition of an excellentintroduction to the subjects of gravitation and space-timestructure. It presumes a good background in specialrelativity, electrodynam ics, and classical mechanics.40.00 net Hardback 0 521 37066 3 315 pp. 199017.50 net Paperback 0 521 37941 5

    I n t r o d u c t i o n t o M i l l i k e l v i nT e c h n o l o g yD. S. BETTSA concise introduction to the experimental technicalitiesof low and ultralow temperature physics research. Allaspects of low tem perature techn ology are covered,beginning with an introduction to the thermodynamicprinciples of refrigeration and therm ome try.22.50 net Hardback 0 521 3445 6 5 110 pp. 1989Cambridge Studies in Low Tem perature Physics 1

    T h e P h i l o s o p h y o f Q u a n t u mM e c h a n i c sRICHA RD A. HEALEYThis is one of the most imp ortant books on qua ntummechanics to have appeared in recent years. It offersa dramatically new interpretation of quantum mechanicswhich resolves puzzles and paradoxes associated with themeasurement problem and the behaviour of coupledsystems.22.50 net Hardback 0 521 37105 8 112 pp. 1990

    D i g i t a l D e s i g n f o r C o m p u t e rD a t a A c q u i s i t i o nCHARLES D. SPENCERA digital electronics text focussing on 'how to ' design,build, operate and adapt data acquisition systems. Thefundam ental idea of the book is that parallel I/O portsoffer a superior balance of simplicity, low cost, speed,flexibility and adaptability.22.50net Hardback 0521371996 368pp. 1990

    S y m p l e c t ic T e c h n i q u e s i n P h y s i c sV. G U I LLEMI N a n d S. STERNBERCAn un cluttered, coordinate-free approach to symplecticgoemetry which is useful for clearly and conciselyformulating problems in classical physics and also forunderstanding the link between classical problems andtheir quantum counterparts.15.00 net Paperback 0 52138 990 9 468 pp. 1990

    H i g h R e s o l u t i o n X - r a y S p e c t r o s c o p yo f C o s m i c P l a s m a sPAUL CORENSTEIN an d MARTIN ZOMBECKA comprehensive description of the current status ofX-ray astronomy w ith emphasis upon high resolutionspectroscopy. The papers discuss all aspects of X-rayspectroscopy ranging fro m theo retical models, toobservational results, to new missions andinstrumentation.35.00 net Hardback 0 521 3701 8 3 400 pp. 1990

    For further information please contact Susan Chadwick at the address below

    CambridgeU niversity PressThe Edinburgh B uilding, Cambridge CB2 2 RU , UK.