Aesthetic Adjectives and Context Aaron Meskin (Philosophy, Leeds) Experimental Aesthetics Workshop.

14
Aesthetic Adjectives and Context Aaron Meskin (Philosophy, Leeds) Experimental Aesthetics Workshop

Transcript of Aesthetic Adjectives and Context Aaron Meskin (Philosophy, Leeds) Experimental Aesthetics Workshop.

Page 1: Aesthetic Adjectives and Context Aaron Meskin (Philosophy, Leeds) Experimental Aesthetics Workshop.

Aesthetic Adjectives and Context

Aaron Meskin(Philosophy, Leeds)

Experimental Aesthetics Workshop

Page 2: Aesthetic Adjectives and Context Aaron Meskin (Philosophy, Leeds) Experimental Aesthetics Workshop.

My hypothesis

Aesthetic terms are like ordinary relative gradable adjectives in that they exhibit context sensitivity.

Page 3: Aesthetic Adjectives and Context Aaron Meskin (Philosophy, Leeds) Experimental Aesthetics Workshop.

Aesthetic gradability

Aesthetic (and artistic and expressive) adjectives are gradable.

Allow for degree modifiers.The flower is very beautiful.The novel is extremely original.The song is very sad.

Allow for comparative constructions.That painting is more elegant than this painting.He is less creative than my aunt.Durham Cathedral is more serene than York Minster.

Page 4: Aesthetic Adjectives and Context Aaron Meskin (Philosophy, Leeds) Experimental Aesthetics Workshop.

Context-sensitivity in gradable adjectives

(1) John is tall.“What proposition is expressed by a sentence like [1] is context dependent, depending on what standard of tallness is given by the context. It might express a true proposition if the standard is set to a value appropriate for talking about jockeys, but a false one if set to a value appropriate for talking about the tallness of basketball players” (Glanzbeg, ‘Context, Content, and Relativism’, 9; see also Stanley “On the Linguistic Basis for Contextualism, 123)

Page 5: Aesthetic Adjectives and Context Aaron Meskin (Philosophy, Leeds) Experimental Aesthetics Workshop.

But not all gradable adjectives are context-sensitive

“Some expressions are gradable, yet not context-sensitive” (Stanley, “The Linguistic Basis for Contextualism”, 132).

Examples: “taller than six feet”, “regret”, “justified”

In fact, some linguists argue that one distinctive and large class of gradable adjectives do not exhibit context-sensitive. Do aesthetic terms belong to that class?

Page 6: Aesthetic Adjectives and Context Aaron Meskin (Philosophy, Leeds) Experimental Aesthetics Workshop.

What kind of gradable adjectives are aesthetic adjectives?

Kennedy: “There is a well-defined set of adjectives that are demonstrably gradable but do not have context dependent interpretations...” (“Vagueness and Grammar”, 22).

minimum standard absolute gradable adjectives: impure, damp, wet, open, bent...

application requires some minimal degree of property

maximum standard absolute gradable adjectives: pure, dry, closed, straight...

application requires a maximal degree of property

Page 7: Aesthetic Adjectives and Context Aaron Meskin (Philosophy, Leeds) Experimental Aesthetics Workshop.

Aesthetic terms are not absolute gradable

NO ENTAILMENT TO AN ANTONYM

It is not closed.=>It is open.

It is not wet. => It is dry.

It is not beautiful. ≠> It is ugly.

It is not ugly. ≠> It is beautiful.

Page 8: Aesthetic Adjectives and Context Aaron Meskin (Philosophy, Leeds) Experimental Aesthetics Workshop.

Aesthetic terms are not absolute gradable

NOT MAXIMUM STANDARD

??It is CLOSED but it could be more closed.It is BEAUTIFUL but it could be more beautiful.He is CREATIVE but he could be more creative.

My door is more closed than Robbie’s door. => Robbie’s door is not closed.

John is more beautiful than Jim. ≠> Jim is not beautiful.Jane is more creative than Bob. ≠> Bob is not creative.

Page 9: Aesthetic Adjectives and Context Aaron Meskin (Philosophy, Leeds) Experimental Aesthetics Workshop.

Aesthetic terms are not absolute gradable

NOT MINIMUM STANDARD

??It is not damp but it has some moisture in it.She is not beautiful, but she displays a bit of beauty.He is not creative but he possesses a bit of creativity.

The table is more damp than the towel. => The table is damp.

John is more beautiful than Jim. ≠> John is beautiful. (“John is not beautiful but he is more beautiful than Jim.”)

Mary is more creative than Maisie. ≠> Mary is creative.

Page 10: Aesthetic Adjectives and Context Aaron Meskin (Philosophy, Leeds) Experimental Aesthetics Workshop.

The Presupposition Assessment Task (Syrett et al 2005)

Pairs of objects (e.g., 2 cubes, 2 rods, 2 disks) were presented. Experimenter made request using definite description: “Please give me the X one” (X= target adjective) Pairs designed so that neither, both or one of the objects could be modified by the adjective.

Page 11: Aesthetic Adjectives and Context Aaron Meskin (Philosophy, Leeds) Experimental Aesthetics Workshop.

Prediction

In relative gradable adjective case, participant can always shift context to satisfy presupposition of unique existence. So subjects should always conform to request and give the object that possesses property to the greater degree. In absolute gradable adjective case, subjects won’t be able to shift context. So in cases where presupposition is not met, subjects will reject request.

Page 12: Aesthetic Adjectives and Context Aaron Meskin (Philosophy, Leeds) Experimental Aesthetics Workshop.

Relative gradable

“Please give me the big one.”

“Please give me the long one.”

Result: Compliance at or near ceiling.

Page 13: Aesthetic Adjectives and Context Aaron Meskin (Philosophy, Leeds) Experimental Aesthetics Workshop.

Absolute gradable

“Please give me the spotted one.”

“Please give me the full one.”

Result: Much more rejection of requests.

Page 14: Aesthetic Adjectives and Context Aaron Meskin (Philosophy, Leeds) Experimental Aesthetics Workshop.

Aesthetic adjectives and the presupposition assessment test

“Please give me the beautiful one.”