A Theory of Strict Liability

download A Theory of Strict Liability

of 6

Transcript of A Theory of Strict Liability

  • 8/10/2019 A Theory of Strict Liability

    1/6

    hilosophical Review

    A Theory of Strict Liability by Richard A. EpsteinReview by: Jules L. ColemanThe Philosophical Review, Vol. 92, No. 4 (Oct., 1983), pp. 613-617Published by: Duke University Presson behalf of Philosophical ReviewStable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/2184887.

    Accessed: 04/12/2014 10:58

    Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at.http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

    .JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of

    content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms

    of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].

    .

    Duke University Pressand Philosophical Revieware collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend

    access to The Philosophical Review.

    http://www.jstor.org

    This content downloaded from 158.251.6.77 on Thu, 4 Dec 2014 10:58:57 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=dukehttp://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=philreviewhttp://www.jstor.org/stable/2184887?origin=JSTOR-pdfhttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/stable/2184887?origin=JSTOR-pdfhttp://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=philreviewhttp://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=duke
  • 8/10/2019 A Theory of Strict Liability

    2/6

    BOOK

    REVIEWS

    belief that those complexities are so

    much excess

    baggage which have

    nothing

    o

    do with he relationbetween

    fairness nd ustice

    and the search

    for basic and generallyacceptable premises.

    JOSHUA T.

    RABINOWITZ

    Universityf llinois-Urbana-Champaign

    The Philosophical eview,XCII, No.

    4

    (October

    1983)

    A THEORY OF STRICT LIABILITY. By

    RICHARD

    A.

    EPSTEIN.

    San Fran-

    cisco, The Cato Institute,1980. Pp. xv,

    141.

    The central question before each court trying case in

    torts s whether

    the costsof the harm sufferedby the plaintiffor victim)

    hould remain his

    responsibility-lie where theyhave fallen-or be shifted o

    the defendant

    (who is usually

    but

    not always the injurer). The rules that

    specify

    the

    conditionswhichmustbe satisfied n order for loss to be shifted rom he

    individualwho initially uffers t to someone else are called liability ules.

    Tort law consistsof a set of liability ules; tort heory onsists

    f efforts

    o

    explain and (if possible) ustify xisting iability ules.

    Liability ules are basically

    of

    two sorts: faultand strict. n strict iability

    the loss may be shifted o the defendant even if the loss is not his fault. n

    fault

    iability, loss may

    be

    shifted

    o the defendant

    only

    f

    it

    is his fault.

    Efforts o explain existing ort aw fall nto two general categories: those

    which

    purport

    to

    deduce

    the

    structure

    nd substance of tort aw from

    moral principles; and those which explain the law of tortsas rooted in

    economic theory.Richard Epstein's A Theory fStrict iabilitys

    the leading

    contemporary tatement f a moral account of the law of

    torts.

    Until

    recently, he dominant strategy

    or

    defending tort

    aw on moral

    grounds relied

    on

    the role

    of fault n

    determining iability.

    ecause

    strict

    liability mposes sanctions n the absence

    of

    culpability, he prevailingview

    was

    that

    t

    was not morallydefensible.

    n

    other words,

    a

    defendant

    could

    be

    liable under strict iability ven

    if

    he acted under what we would

    nor-

    mally hink f as exculpating onditions.Fault iability, owever, equiresa

    measure

    of

    wrongfulness n the defendant's behalf, and,

    in

    the received

    view, iability

    s

    ustly imposed upon the defendant to penalize his fault.

    The received view could not be sustained, however, since

    the standard

    of

    fault nvolved n tort aw

    does

    not

    coincide

    with

    he

    conditions f moral

    fault.

    An individual

    s

    at fault n torts

    provided

    his conduct falls

    below

    that

    of

    a reasonable

    man

    of

    ordinary prudence. Generally,

    t

    does

    not matter

    whether

    the

    defendant could have done

    what

    a reasonable

    man would

    613

    This content downloaded from 158.251.6.77 on Thu, 4 Dec 2014 10:58:57 AMAll use subject toJSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/10/2019 A Theory of Strict Liability

    3/6

  • 8/10/2019 A Theory of Strict Liability

    4/6

    BOOK

    REVIEWS

    condition of the

    subsequent

    event's

    occurrence.

    One

    event s

    a

    proximate

    cause of

    another f,

    given

    the

    purposes of

    the

    nquiry, he

    antecedent vent

    is responsible for the subsequent one. But-forcausation is too weak to

    justify

    mposing

    iability. n

    the

    law, a

    judgment

    of

    proximate

    ausation s

    simply

    he

    assertion

    that

    responsibility

    r

    liability s

    warranted.

    Proximate

    causation is

    therefore

    oo

    strong

    to

    ustify

    mposing

    iability.

    Epstein's task

    is to

    develop

    an

    account of

    causation that s

    both

    strong

    and

    weak

    enough

    to

    ustify

    mposing

    liability

    n

    the basis

    of it.

    Epstein

    does not

    actually

    produce

    a theory

    of

    causation.

    Instead,

    he

    outlines

    and

    develops

    in

    some

    detail what

    he calls

    causal

    paradigms. In

    effect,

    hese

    are instances in which ordinaryindividuals experience no difficultyn

    employing

    ausal

    language both

    meaningfully nd

    as

    a basis of

    responsibil-

    ity.

    For

    example,

    sentences

    ike A

    frightened

    and

    A

    forcedB

    assert

    causal

    connection

    between

    A

    and

    B,

    and

    their

    truth

    may

    ustify

    mposing

    liability

    pon

    A

    for

    B's

    harms.

    The

    problem

    with

    Epstein's

    causal

    paradigms

    of fright

    nd

    compulsion,

    for

    example, is that

    they

    re not

    normatively

    eutral. t

    is not

    the fact hat

    A

    caused

    B

    harm

    that

    ustifies

    mposing

    iability

    pon A; it s

    the fact

    hat

    A frightened r compelled B thatustifies iability. he case for iabilitys

    built

    into

    the claim

    that one

    individual

    frightened

    nother or that

    one

    party

    compelled another. Both

    involve

    wrongful

    ways

    of

    causing

    harm

    either

    by

    violating he other's

    autonomy

    or

    by

    causing

    unwarranted

    pain

    and

    anguish.

    The

    real task

    then s to

    show that

    causation

    by tself s both

    necessary

    or

    liability

    nd

    sufficient

    o

    ustify t least

    a prima

    acie

    case.

    This

    requires a

    moral

    principle

    that

    imparts moral

    significance

    upon

    every instance in

    which A harmsB-innocently as well as wrongfully. or ifonlywrongful

    instancesof harm

    ustify

    iability, hen

    Epstein would have

    failed to

    pro-

    vide a

    defense

    of

    strict

    liability, that

    is,

    liability

    without

    regard

    to

    culpability.

    Epstein's basic

    argument

    s

    this: in order that

    iability

    or a

    loss be

    im-

    posed

    ustly,

    the

    ndividual

    must be

    responsible

    for

    the oss. An

    individual

    is

    responsiblefor

    an

    event

    f

    and

    only

    f

    he caused it. So if A

    harms

    B,

    A

    is

    responsiblefor

    B's

    loss, and ifA

    is

    responsible

    for

    B's

    loss,

    then

    iability

    or

    it s ustly mposed on him.Epsteinwrites: Indeed, formostpersons,the

    difficult

    uestion is often not

    whether these causal

    assertions

    create the

    presumption

    [of

    liability],

    ut

    whether there

    are

    in fact

    any

    means to

    distinguish

    etween

    causation and

    responsibility,

    o

    close

    is

    the connection

    between

    what

    a man

    does and what

    he

    is

    answerable for

    p.

    25).

    To harm

    an

    individual is to

    interferewith a

    legitimate

    nterest

    f

    his.

    Not

    every egitimate

    nterest s

    protected

    by

    a

    right.

    There are numerous

    ways

    n which

    an individual

    might

    harm

    another,

    for

    example,

    in

    business

    615

    This content downloaded from 158.251.6.77 on Thu, 4 Dec 2014 10:58:57 AMAll use subject toJSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/10/2019 A Theory of Strict Liability

    5/6

    BOOK

    REVIEWS

    and in love, without

    his so doing

    raising the question

    of

    liability.

    ecause

    there is no general

    right not to be harmed, there

    is no general right

    to

    compensationwhenever one suffersharm, and no reason thereforeto

    suppose

    that causing harm is sufficient

    o

    establish

    ven

    a

    prima acie

    case

    for liability.

    The argumentfromresponsibility

    lso failsbecause

    it relies on the claim

    that because

    causation is necessary

    for responsibility

    t

    is necessary

    for

    liability. hat Epstein holds such

    a view s evidenced

    by his solutionto the

    good Samaritan

    problem. The problem

    s whether

    n individualwho fails

    to come to the aid of another

    can

    be liable

    in

    damages

    to that

    person

    for

    harms the good Samaritan could have prevented. n general, thecom-

    mon law fails to recognize the duty

    to be

    a

    good

    Samaritan. Epstein be-

    lieves thatwhereas

    the economic theory

    annot explain the court'sposture

    towardthe good

    Samaritan,the theory

    f

    strict

    iability an. The reason:

    to

    failto come to another's aid is

    to

    fail

    to

    perform

    n

    act.

    Failure

    to act s not

    itself

    n

    action,

    nor therefore

    s it an event. Only

    events can cause other

    events.

    By

    failing

    o come

    to

    the aid

    of

    others

    the

    good

    Samaritan

    does

    not

    cause

    harm: he

    simply

    does not

    prevent

    t. Since he does not cause harm,

    he fails to satisfy he causal requirement, nd cannot be held liable.

    There are

    two things wrong

    with this argument. First,

    f

    Epstein

    is

    correct

    that causation is

    necessary

    for

    liability

    ecause

    it

    is

    necessary

    for

    responsibility,

    hen the theory

    f

    strict iability

    willbe unable

    to

    account for

    a wide

    range

    of

    cases in which liability

    s

    normally

    mposed. Suppose

    it

    snows and

    I

    fail to

    clear

    the snow

    from

    he steps eading

    to

    my

    house.

    The

    mailman delivers

    the mail to my house and upon leaving

    slips

    and

    injures

    himself.Normally,

    would be held

    liable

    for

    the

    mailman's

    njury.

    am

    liable, however,not because I harmed the mailman,but because I could

    have and should have prevented

    his njury.My

    failure o shovel s not tself

    an action.

    Because

    it

    s

    not an action

    t cannot cause

    anything.

    f

    the

    theory

    of strict

    iability

    elies

    on

    causation

    as a necessary

    ondition

    of both

    respon-

    sibility

    nd

    ust liability,

    t will

    fail

    to account

    formuch

    of

    negligence

    aw in

    which

    iability s imposed

    for

    omissions.

    The lesson

    of this xample, however, s

    that

    he

    theory

    f

    strictiability

    s

    wrong

    to

    insist upon causation

    as a condition

    of

    responsibility.

    ven if

    liability equired responsibility,t would not require causation. An indi-

    vidual

    may

    be responsible

    and thus iable

    for what he failsto

    do as well as

    forwhat he

    does. The range

    of individual

    responsibility

    s

    not restricted

    o

    the

    events

    that an individual causes,

    and

    though

    the

    events

    an individual

    causes are

    always

    n

    the sense

    of

    individual

    authorship

    his

    responsibility,

    they may

    or

    may

    not be

    things

    he

    is

    morallyresponsible

    for.

    One can

    construct nother

    argument

    for the

    theory

    of strict

    iability

    based

    on

    Epstein's

    conception

    of

    the principle

    of

    correctivejustice. pstein

    616

    This content downloaded from 158.251.6.77 on Thu, 4 Dec 2014 10:58:57 AMAll use subject toJSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/10/2019 A Theory of Strict Liability

    6/6

    BOOK

    REVIEWS

    does

    not explicitly

    make

    this

    argument

    in the book. Still there

    is

    some

    textual upport

    for t and

    in his

    most recentessays

    he has taken

    to empha-

    sizing the role of corrective ustice in the theoryof strict iability.The

    argument

    ppears

    to be

    this: fA harms

    B,

    there

    s

    an

    imbalance,

    disequi-

    librium,between

    them.

    Following

    Aristotle,

    his

    s an occasion

    to rectify

    the imbalance,

    to

    reestablish

    he

    equilibrium.

    The

    basis

    of

    liability,

    n

    this

    view, s not

    the injurer's

    responsibility

    or causing

    harm as

    much

    as it

    s the

    correlative

    f the victim's

    ight

    to have

    his

    losses rectified.

    Not

    every

    oss,

    however,

    s a departure

    from

    distribution

    hat

    ought

    to

    be preserved;

    and not

    every

    way

    of departing

    from distribution

    s

    wrong-

    ful. Therefore,not every oss is an unjustifiable ne. Contrary o Epstein,

    only

    wrongful

    r unjustifiable

    ains

    and

    losses n

    Aristotle's

    heory

    must s

    a matter

    of justice

    be

    annulled.

    Ironically,

    the appeal

    to

    principles

    of

    correctiveustice

    appears

    to

    provide

    a

    moral account

    of the

    fault

    principle,

    not

    f the principle

    of

    strict

    iability.

    loss

    caused by

    the

    fault f another

    s,

    in a suitably

    narrow

    sense,

    a

    wrongful

    one.

    Those

    losses

    are

    distortions

    which,

    according

    to the

    principle

    of corrective

    ustice,

    ought

    to be

    rec-

    tified.The

    obligation

    correlative

    to

    the right

    to have

    one's

    unjustifiable

    losses rectified allson the injurerwho is at fault.Thus, the principleof

    correctiveustice

    provides

    the

    beginnings

    of

    a

    moral defense

    of fault,

    not

    of strict iability.

    A

    Theory

    f Strict

    iability

    s the

    only systematic

    ttempt

    to deduce

    the

    basic

    structure

    f tort aw

    and the

    content

    of tortrules

    from

    principles

    f

    morality.

    t is

    a well-written

    nd carefully

    rgued

    essay

    that focuses

    on

    important

    uestions

    in the

    theories

    of

    responsibility

    nd justice.

    It is es-

    pecially

    recommended

    for legal philosophers

    who have

    devoted

    far

    too

    much attention o the criminal aw almostto the exclusionof tort aw.A

    Theory

    f

    Strict

    iability

    ill

    give

    the reader

    an idea

    of

    ust

    how

    philosophi-

    cally

    fertile

    he private

    aw

    can be.

    JULES

    L. COLEMAN

    University

    f

    Wisconsin-Milwaukee

    ThePhilosophical eview,XCII, No. 4 (October 1983)

    UTILITARIANISM

    AND

    CO-OPERATION.

    By

    DONALD

    H.

    REGAN.

    New

    York,

    The

    Clarendon

    Press,

    Oxford

    University

    Press,

    1980. Pp.

    xvi,

    279.

    Anyone interested

    n the

    battle

    among

    utilitarianisms

    ill

    want to

    study

    this book.

    Regan

    presents

    a tightly

    woven

    argument

    for the

    position

    that

    617

    This content downloaded from 158.251.6.77 on Thu, 4 Dec 2014 10:58:57 AMAll bj t t JSTOR T d C diti

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp