A DEFENSE OF PRE‐CRITICAL POSTHUMANISM

download A DEFENSE OF PRE‐CRITICAL POSTHUMANISM

of 11

Transcript of A DEFENSE OF PRE‐CRITICAL POSTHUMANISM

  • 8/3/2019 A DEFENSE OF PRECRITICAL POSTHUMANISM

    1/11

    1

    A DEFENSE OF PRECRITICAL POSTHUMANISM

    David Roden, Open University

    Mankind's a dead issue now, cousin. There are no more souls. Only states of

    mind.1

    Since emerging in nineties critical theory, transhumanism and cyberpunk literature,

    the term 'posthuman' has been used to mark a historical juncture at which the

    status of the human is radically in doubt. Two main usages or, if you will, two

    distinctposthumanisms canbe discerned over this period.

    Transhumanists, futurists and science fiction authors regularly concatenate or

    hyphenate 'post' and 'human' when speculating about the longrun influence of

    advanced technologies on the future shape of life and mind.

    By contrast, for cultural theorists and philosophers in the 'continental' tradition the

    posthuman is a condition in which the foundational status of humanism has been

    undermined. The causes or symptoms of this supposed crisis of humanism are

    various as the bioengineered 'clades' ramifying through the postanthropoform

    solar system of Bruce Sterling's 1996 novel Schismatrix. Posthumanism, in this

    diagnostic or critical sense, is expressed in the postmodern incredulity towards

    enlightenment narratives of emancipation and material progress; the deconstruction

    of transcendental or liberal subjectivities; the end of patriarchy; the emergence of

    contrary humanisms in postColonial cultures; the reduction of living entities toresources for a burgeoning technoscience, or, if some theorists are to be believed, all

    of the above.2

    In this paper, I will argue that these two usages do not only reflect divergent

    understandings of the posthuman the speculative and the critical but also reflect

    a foreclosure of radical technogenetic change on the part of critical posthumanists.

    This gesture can be discerned in four arguments that occur in various forms within

    the extant literature of critical posthumanism:

    The antihumanist argument The technogenesis argument The materiality argument The antiessentialist argument

    All four, as I hope to show, are unsound.

    1Sterling (1996), p. 59.

    2

    This appears to be the position of Rosi Braidotti in her recent plenary address to the 2009 Society forEuropean Philosophy and Forum for European Philosophy Conference in Cardiff.

  • 8/3/2019 A DEFENSE OF PRECRITICAL POSTHUMANISM

    2/11

    2

    Analyzing why these arguments fail has the dual benefit of preventing us from being

    distracted by the antihumanist hyperbole accruing to theoretical frameworks

    employed within critical posthumanism such as deconstruction and cognitive

    science but, more importantly, contributes to the development of a rigorous,

    philosophically selfaware speculative posthumanism.

    * * *

    Contemporary transhumanists argue that human nature is an unsatisfactory 'work in

    progress' that should be modified through technological means where the

    instrumental benefits for individuals outweigh the technological risks. This ethic of

    improvement is premised on prospective developments in four areas:

    Nanotechnology, Biotechnology, Information Technology and Cognitive Science the

    'NBIC' suite of technologies. For example, improved bionic neural interfaces may

    allow the incorporation of a wide range of technical devices within an enhanced

    'cyborg' body or 'exoself' while genetic treatments may increase the efficiency or

    learning or memory (Bostrom and Sandberg 2006) or be used to increase the size ofthe cerebral cortex. The wired and genemodified denizens of the transhuman future

    could be sensitive to a wider range of stimuli, faster, more durable, more

    intellectually capable and morphologically varied than their unmodified forebears.

    Just how unrestricted and capable transhuman minds and bodies can become is

    contested since the scope for enhancement depends both on hypothetical

    technologies and upon hotly contested metaphysical claims. Among the prospective

    technologies which excite radical transhumanists like Ray Kurzweil are the use of

    microelectric neuroprostheses which might noninvasively stimulate or probe the

    brains native neural networks, allowing it to jack directly into immersive cognitivetechnologies or map its state vector prior to uploading an entire personality

    (Kurzweil 2005, 317);3

    the elusive goal of artificial general intelligence the

    creation of robots or software systems which approximate or exceed the flexibility of

    human belieffixation and comportment; or, perhaps less speculatively,

    improvements in processor technology sufficient to emulate the computational

    capacity of human and other mammalian brains (Ibid. 124125).

    Among the metaphysical issues that trouble all but the most facile of transhumanist

    itineraries is the scope of functionalist accounts of mental states and processes.

    Functionalist philosophers of mind claim that the mental states types such as beliefsor pains are constituted by the causal role of token states within a containing

    system rather than by the stuff that the system is constituted from. The causal role

    of a token state is defined by the set of states that can bring it about (its inputs) and

    set of the states that it causes in turn (its outputs). The substrate on which that state

    is realized is irrelevant to its functional role.4

    Some philosophers of mind David

    3For a rather less sanguine commentary on the state of the art in noninvasive scanning see Jones

    2009.

    4

    By analogy, any system could count as being in the state White Wash Cycle if inputting dirty whitesat some earlier time resulted in it outputting clean whites at some later time.

  • 8/3/2019 A DEFENSE OF PRECRITICAL POSTHUMANISM

    3/11

  • 8/3/2019 A DEFENSE OF PRECRITICAL POSTHUMANISM

    4/11

    4

    Speculative posthumanism is logically independent of the normative thesis of

    transhumanism: one can be consistently transhumanist while denying the

    ontological possibility of posthuman transcendence. Similarly, speculative

    posthumanism is consistent with the rejection of transhumanism. One could hold

    that a posthuman divergence is a significant ontological possibility but not a

    desirable one.

    Critical posthumanists such as Katherine Hayles, Andy Clark, Don Ihde and Neil

    Badmington do not contest the potential of NBIC technologies or advance principled

    arguments against enhancement (Clark is a warmblooded, moderate transhumanist

    according to my taxonomy) but argue that speculative or precritical posthumanism

    reflects a philosophically nave conception of the human such that the posthuman

    would constitute a radical break with it. This position is clearly implied in the title of

    Katherine Hayles' seminal work of cultural history How We Became Posthuman. For

    Hayles, the posthuman is not a hypothetical state which could follow someprospective singularity event, say, but a work in progress: a complex and contested

    reconception of the human subject in terms drawn from the modern 'sciences of

    the artificial': information theory, cybernetics, Artificial Intelligence and Artificial Life

    (Hayles 199, 286).

    One example of the intellectual tendencies that inform this new cultural moment is

    socalled 'Nouvelle AI' (NAI). Where the manipulation of syntactically structured

    representations is the paradigm of intelligence traditional AI, NAI draws inspiration

    from computational prowess exhibited in biological phenomena involving no

    symbolization, such as swarm intelligence, insect locomotion or cortical featuremaps. The guiding insight of NAI is that the preconditions of intelligence such as

    errorreduction strategies, pattern recognition or categorization can emerge in

    biological systems from local interactions between dumb specialized agents (like

    ants or termites) without a central planner to choreograph their activities.

    If human mentation 'emerges' likewise from millions of asynchronous, parallel

    interactions between dumb components, Hayles argues, there is no classically self

    present 'human' subjectivity for the posthuman to transcend. Mental powers of

    deliberation, inference, consciousness, etc. are already distributed between

    biological neural networks, actively sensing bodies and artefacts (Hayles 1999, 239).

    I have christened this 'the antihumanist objection to posthumanism' given its

    striking similarities to the deconstruction of subjectivist philosophy and

    phenomenology undertaken in postwar French antihumanisms Derridas in

    particular (Ibid. 146). Hayles proximate target, here, is the putatively autonomous

    subject of modern liberal theory. The autonomous liberal subject, she argues, is

    unproblematically present to itself and distinct from the conceptually ordered world

    in which it works out its plans for the good (Ibid. 286). The posthuman subject, by

    contrast, is problematically individuated, because its agency is constituted by an

    increasingly 'smart' extrabodily environment on which its cognitive functioningdepends and because of the open, ungrounded materiality or iterability of

  • 8/3/2019 A DEFENSE OF PRECRITICAL POSTHUMANISM

    5/11

    5

    language which is both arrested by the context of embodied action and infected by

    its opacity (Derrida 1988 152; Hayles 1999, 2645). The decentered or distributed

    posthuman subject is no longer sufficiently distinct from the world to order it

    autonomously as the subject of liberal theory is required to do.

    But is this right?

    Lets suppose, along with Hayles and other proponents of embodied and distributed

    cognition, that the skinbag is an ontologically permeable boundary between self

    and nonself (or exoself). Proponents of the extended mind thesis like Andy Clark

    and David Chalmers argue from a principle of 'parity' between processes that go on

    in the head and any functionally equivalent process in the world beyond.6

    The parity

    principle implies that mental processes need not occur only in biological nervous

    systems but in the environments and tools of embodied thinkers. If I have to make

    marks on paper to keep in mind the steps of a lengthy logical proof, the PP states

    that my mental activity is constituted by these inscriptional events as well as by theknowledge and habits reposing in my acculturated neural networks.

    However, given the parity between bodily and extrabodily processes, this cannot

    make the activity less evaluable in terms of the rationality standards we apply to

    deliberative acts. Even if the humanist subject emerges from the summed activities

    of biological and nonbiological agents, this metaphysical dependence (or

    supervenience) need not impair its capacity to subtend the powers of deliberation or

    reasoning liberal theory requires of it.7

    Derridas more systematic deconstruction of the semantically constitutive subjectnuances this picture by entailing limits on the scope of practical reason in the face of

    the outside or exception which infects any rulegoverned system (Derrida 1988,

    p.152). The rule or desire is always precipitate, in this way. But there is a difference

    between being ahead of oneself and being beheaded. The posthuman, in Hayles

    critical sense of the term, is not less human for confronting the fragile, constitutively

    precipitate character of cognition and desire.

    This is not to say, of course, that there is no merit in the model of the hybrid self that

    Hayles presents as 'posthuman' or that it has no implications for precritical or

    6Parity Principle. If, as we confront some task, a part of the world functions as a process which, were

    it to go on in the head, we would have no hesitation in accepting as part of the cognitive process,

    then that part of the world is (for that time) part of the cognitive process.(from Clark and Chalmers

    (1998) p.XX)

    7The notion of supervenience is frequently used by nonreductive materialists to express the

    dependence of mental properties on physical properties without entailing their reducibility to the

    latter. Informally: M properties supervene on P properties if a things P properties determine its M

    properties. If aesthetic properties supervene on physical properties, if x is physically identical to y and

    x is beautiful, y must be beautiful. Supervenience accounts vary with the modal force of the

    entailments involved. Natural or nomological supervenience holds in worlds whose physical laws

    are like our own. Metaphysical supervenience, on the other hand, is often claimed to hold withlogical or conceptual necessity.

  • 8/3/2019 A DEFENSE OF PRECRITICAL POSTHUMANISM

    6/11

    6

    speculative posthumanism. On the contrary, a 'deconstruction' of the classically

    constitutive subject of postCartesian thought is, I have argued, a useful prophylactic

    against immaterialist fancies or transcendentally inspired objections to the

    naturalizing project of cognitive science (Roden 2006). However, the naturalization

    of subjectivity and mind is at best a conceptual precondition for envisaging certain

    transcendent posthumanist itineraries involving the emergence of artificial minds

    from new technological configurations of matter. It does not represent their

    culmination.

    There are two other objections that may potentially survive this analysis. Firstly, it

    could be objected that the critical posthumanism like the extended mind thesis

    shows that the human is always already technically constituted. In her contribution

    to a recent Templeton Research Seminar on transhumanism Hayles argues that

    transhumanists are wedded to a technogenetic anthropologyfor which humans and

    technologies have existed and coevolved in symbiotic partnership. Not only would

    future transhuman enhancement be a technogenetic process; but so, according tothis story, are comparable transformations in the deep past. Human technical

    activity has, for example, equipped some with lactose tolerance or differential

    calculus without monstering the beneficiaries into posthumans. One of the

    proponents of the extended mind thesis, Andy Clark, has framed the technogenesis

    argument against posthumanism particularly clearly in his book Natural Born

    Cyborgs:

    The promise, or perhaps threatened, transition to a world of wired humans

    and semiintelligent gadgets is just one more move in an ancient game. . . We

    are already masters at incorporating nonbiological stuff and structure deepinto our physical and cognitive routines. To appreciate this is to cease to

    believe in any posthuman future and to resist the temptation to define

    ourselves in brutal opposition to the very worlds in which so many of us now

    live, love and work (Clark 2003, p. 142).

    Natural born cyborgs, as suggested, are already dealers in hybrid mental

    representations which exploit both a linguistically mapped environment and the

    pattern detecting talents of our multifariously talented brains. This is significant

    because our capacity to ascribe structured propositional attitudes to others arguably

    presupposes the capacity to use language to represent their contents. Representingthe contents of beliefs is necessary for evaluating them and it is independently

    plausible to suppose that, as Donald Davidson argues in his essay Thought and Talk,

    having the capacity to evaluate beliefs is part of what is required in a believer

    (Davidson 1984).

    Clearly, if we restrict the evidence base for the technogenesis argument to cases

    where augmentation has not resulted in a species divergence or something very like

    it, then we will induce that this is not liable to happen in the future. However, some

    prehuman divergence had to have happened in our evolutionary past and it is at

    least plausible given the natural born cyborgs thesis that technologies such aspublic symbol systems were a factor in the hominization process. Given a prehuman

  • 8/3/2019 A DEFENSE OF PRECRITICAL POSTHUMANISM

    7/11

    7

    divergence has occurred in the past, perhaps due to evolutionary pressures brought

    about the development of simpler symbolization techniques, why preclude the

    possibility that convergent NBIC technologies might prompt a similar step change in

    the future?

    I have argued elsewhere that a cognitive augmentation that replaced public

    language with a nonsymbolic vehicle of cognition and communication might

    assuming Clark's account of hybrid representations lead to the instrumental

    elimination of propositional attitude psychology through the elimination of its public

    vehicles of content. Postfolk folk might, arguably, be opaque to the practices of

    intentional interpretation we bring to bear in our i.e. human social intercourse

    and thus might well form initially discrete social and reproductive enclaves that

    might later seed entirely posthuman republics.

    Another of Hayles objections to standard posthumanists visions of transcendence is

    their supposed elision of the materiality of human embodiment and cognition: themateriality argument. The fact that computer simulations can help us understand

    the selforganizing capacities of biological systems does not entail that these can be

    fully replicated by some system by virtue of implementing a sufficiently finegrained

    software representation of their functional structure.

    It is true that some posthumanist scenarios presuppose that minds or organisms can

    be fully replicated on speculative nonbiological substrates like the computronium or

    'smart matter' imagined in Ken MacLeod's Fall Revolution novels. However, this

    objection applies to a fairly restricted class of posthuman itineraries: namely those

    involving the replication of existing minds and organisms in computational form.Although Hayles provides no arguments against pancomputationalism or global

    functionalism, it might well be the case that syntheticlife forms or robots,

    being differently embodied, will be differently mindedas well (who knows?).

    Thus the materiality of embodiment argument works in favour of the precritical

    posthumanist account, not against it.8

    On the other hand, she may be wrong and the

    pancomputationalists right. Mental properties of things may, for all we know,

    supervene on their computational properties because every other property

    supervenes on them as well.

    I turn, finally, to an objection that is perhaps implicit rather than explicit in the

    arguments of Critical Posthumanists to date but is worth considering on its own, if

    only for its speculative payoff. I refer to this as the antiessentialist argument.

    The antiessentialist objection to posthumanism starts from a particular

    interpretation of the disjointness of the human and the posthuman. This is that the

    only thing that could distinguish the set of posthumans and the set of humans is

    that all posthumans would lack some essential property of humanness by virtue of

    their augmentation history. It follows that if there is no human essence no

    8It may militate against transhumanist dreams of virtual immortality, but, as many have pointed out,

    this is a humanist or hyperhumanist scenario, not a posthumanist one.

  • 8/3/2019 A DEFENSE OF PRECRITICAL POSTHUMANISM

    8/11

    8

    properties that humans possess in all possible worlds there can be no posthuman

    divergence or transcendence.

    This is a potentially serious objection to speculative posthumanism because there

    seem to be plausible grounds for rejecting essentialism in the sciences of complexity

    or selforganization that underwrite many posthumanist prognostications. Some

    philosophers of biology hold that the interpretation of biological taxa most

    consonant with Darwinian evolution is that they are not kinds (i.e. properties) but

    individuals. Evolution by natural selection is a form of selforganization involving

    feedback relationships between the distribution of genetic traits across populations

    and their phenotypic consequences in particular environments. An individual or

    protoindividual can undergo a selforganizing process, but an abstract kind or

    universal cannot. Thus, the argument goes, evolution happens to species qua

    individuals (or protoindividuals) not species qua kinds. To be biologically 'human'

    on this view is notto exemplify some set of necessary and sufficient properties, but

    to be genealogically related to earlier members of the population of humans (Hull1988).

    Clearly, if biological categories are not kinds and posthuman transcendence requires

    the technically mediated loss of properties essential to membership of some

    biological kind, then posthuman transcendence envisaged by precritical

    posthumanism is metaphysically impossible.9

    Underlying the antiessentialist objection is the assumption that the only significant

    differences are differences in the essential properties demarcating natural kinds. But

    why adhere to this philosophy of difference?10

    The view that nature is articulated bydifferences in the instantiation of abstract universals sits poorly with the idea of an

    actively selforganizing nature underlying the leading edge cognitive and life

    sciences. A view of difference consistent with selforganization would locate the

    engines of differentiation in those micro components and structural properties

    whose cumulative activity generates the emergent regularities of complex systems.

    For example, we might adopt an immanent ontology of difference for which

    individuating boundaries are generated by local states of matter: such as differences

    in pressure, temperature, miscibility or chemical concentration (Delanda 2004). For

    immanent ontologies of difference that of Gilles Deleuze, say the conceptualdifferences articulated in the natural language kind lexicons are asymmetrically

    9This objection is overdetermined because the possibility of successfully implementing radical

    transhumanist policies seems incompatible with a stable human nature. If there are few cognitive or

    body invariants that could not in principle be modified with the help of some hypothetical NBIC

    technology then transhumanism arguably presupposes that there are no such essential properties

    for humanness.

    10David Hull points out that the genealogical boundaries between species can be considerably

    sharper than boundaries in 'character space' (Hull 1988, 4). The fact that nectarfeeding hummingbird

    hawk moths and nectarfeeding hummingbirds look and behave in similar ways does not invalidatethe claim that they have utterly distinct lines of evolutionary descent (Laporte 2004, 44).

  • 8/3/2019 A DEFENSE OF PRECRITICAL POSTHUMANISM

    9/11

    9

    dependent upon active individuating differences (Ibid. 10). Deleuzean ontology is

    obviously not the only option here: any ontology which reconciles the existence of

    real or radical differences with the lack of transcendent or transcendental organizing

    principles would do.

    In short: we can be antiessentialists and antiPlatonists while holding that the world

    is profoundly differentiated in a way that owes nothing to the transcendental

    causality of abstract universals, subjectivity or language.

    Conclusion:

    I have argued that critical posthumanists provide few convincing reasons for

    abandoning precritical or speculative posthumanism. The antiessentialist argument

    presupposes a model of difference that is ill adapted to the sciences that critical

    posthumanists cite in favour of their naturalized deconstruction of the human

    subject. The deconstruction of the humanist subject implied in the antihumanistobjection may itself be a useful prolegomenon to a posthumanengendering

    cognitive science; but it complicates rather than corrodes the philosophical

    humanism that critical posthumanism problematizes while leaving open the

    possibility of a radical differentiation of the human and the posthuman. The

    technogenesis objection is weak, if conceptually productive. The elision of

    materiality argument is based on problematic assumptions and, even if sound, would

    preclude only some scenarios for posthuman divergence.

    Of these, the antiessentialist objection seems the strongest and most wide ranging

    in its implication. Our response to it suggested that it might be circumvented with animmanent ontology of emergent differences such as Deleuze's ontology of the

    virtual. However, a consequence of embracing locally emergent differences in this

    way is that there can be no adequate concept of posthuman difference without

    posthumans. For it is surely a consequence of any such account that a science of the

    different cannot precede its historical emergence or morphogenesis, even if only in

    simulated form. This implies that the posthuman is at best a placeholder signifying a

    possibility that we cannot adequately conceptualize ahead of its actualization.

    However, this does not preclude a theoretical development of the implications of

    the posthuman insofar as we can conceptualize it.

    Moreover, the emptiness of the signifier 'posthuman' has an ethical or, perhaps,

    'antiethical' consequence that arguably should be considered more fully in the light

    of Derrida's remarks about the precipitate character of thought.11

    If the speculative

    idea of the posthuman is a placeholder for differences that are determinable only via

    some synthetic process such as the creation of actual posthumans, modified

    11In her address to the Cardiff, SEPFEP conference, 'The Ethics of Extinction' Claire Colebrook argued

    that while ethos implies habit, place and environment, situations of catastrophic change (e.g. climate

    change) imply the need to overcome these rooted modes of action and affect. Hence the prospect of

    humanity being superseded by nonhumans requires an antiethics which imagines or simulates theradically nonhuman.

  • 8/3/2019 A DEFENSE OF PRECRITICAL POSTHUMANISM

    10/11

    10

    transhumans, or a range of simulations or aesthetic models (as in cybernetic art)

    these differences can be determined only by progressive actualization. Thus

    posthumanist philosophy is locked into a dialectically unstable preterition falling

    between speculative and synthetic activity. To understand what it as yet

    undetermined, it must attempt however incrementally to bring it into being and

    to give it shape.

    BIBLIOGRAPHY:

    Bostrom, Nick (2005), A History of Transhumanist Thought,Journal of Evolution and

    Technology, 14 (1).

    ____(2008), Why I Want to Be Posthuman When I Grow Up, B. Gordijn, R

    Bostrom N, Sandberg A (2006), 'Converging Cognitive Enhancements', Ann. N.Y.

    Acad. Sci. 1093: 201227.

    Chadwick (eds.), Medical Enhancement and Posthumanity, Springer.

    ____ (2005b), In Defence of Posthuman Dignity, Bioethics 19(3), pp. 203214.Clark, Andy (2003), Natural Born Cyborgs, (Oxford OUP).

    ___Language, Embodiment and the Cognitive Niche, Trends in Cognitive Science

    10(8), pp. 370374)

    ___(1993)Associative Engines, (MIT Bradford).

    ___(2006) Material Symbols, Philosophical Psychology Vol. 19, No. 3, June 2006, pp.

    291307.

    Clark Andy, Chalmers David (1998), The Extended Mind, Analysis 1998 58(1), pp. 7

    19.

    Churchland, Paul (1998), Conceptual Similarity Across Sensory and Neural Diversity:

    The Fodor/LePore Challenge Answered, Journal of Philosophy, XCV, No.1,pp. 532.

    _____(1995). The Engine of Reason, The Seat of the Soul(Cambridge Mass.:

    MIT Press.

    _____(1989)Folk Psychology and the Explanation of Human

    Behaviour, Philosophical Perspectives 3, pp. 225241.

    ____(1981), Eliminative Materialism and the Propositional Attitudes,Journal of

    Philosophy78(2), 6790.

    Cilliers, Paul (1998). Complexity and Postmodernism. London: Routlege.

    Davidson, Donald (1984) Thought and Talk, in Inquiries into Truth and

    Interpretation (Oxford, Clarendon Press), pp. 155170.Deacon,Terrence (1997), The Symbolic Species: The Coevolution of Language and

    the Human Brain (London: Penguin).

    DeLanda, Manuel (1997), Immanence and Transcendence in the Genesis of

    Form, South Atlantic Quarterly96:3, Summer 1997, pp. 499514.

    _____(2004), Intensive Science & Virtual Philosophy, London: Continuum.

    Deleuze, Gilles and Guattari, Felix (1992),A Thousand Plateaus, Brian Massumi

    (trans.). London: Athlone.

    Derrida, Jacques (1986), Margins of Philosophy, Alan Bass (trans.). Brighton:

    Harvester Press), pp. 209271.

    ___(1988), Limited Inc. Samuel Weber (trans.). Northwestern University Press.___(2002),Acts of Religion, Gil Anidjar (ed.). New York: Routledge.

  • 8/3/2019 A DEFENSE OF PRECRITICAL POSTHUMANISM

    11/11

    11

    Daniel,Dennett (1991). Consciousness Explained. London: Penguin.

    Fukuyama, Francis (2002), Our Posthuman Future: Consequences of the

    Biotechnology Revolution (London: Profile Books).

    Hayles, N Katharine (1999), How We Became Posthuman: Virtual bodies in

    Cybernetics, Literature and Informatics (Chicago: University of Chicago Press).

    Hull, David (1988), On Human Nature, in PSA 1986, vol. 2, A. Fine and P. Machamer

    (eds.), East Lansing, MI: Philosophy of Science Association, pp. 313; reprinted in Hull

    (1989) and Hull and Ruse (eds.), Philosophy of Biology(1998).

    Jones, Richard (2009), Brain Interfacing with Kurzweil,

    http://www.softmachines.org/wordpress/?p=450, Accessed08.09.2009.

    Kurzweil, Ray (2005), The Singularity is Near(New York Viking).

    LaPorte, Joseph (2004), Natural Kinds and Conceptual Change (Cambridge CUP).

    Lisewski, Andreas Martin (2006), The concept of strong and weak virtual

    reality, Minds and Machines 16, 201219.

    Lycan, William G. (1999), The Continuity of Levels of Nature, in William Lycan

    (ed.) Mind and Cognition(Oxford Blackwell), pp. 4963.MacLennan, B.J. (2002), Transcending Turing Computability, Minds and Machines 13:

    322.

    Marx, Karl and Engels, Frederick (1994), The German Ideology, C.J. Arthur (Ed.).

    London: Lawrence and Wishart.

    Mackenzie, Adrian (2002), Transductions: bodies and machines at speed(London:

    Continuum).

    Patton, Paul (2007), Utopian Political Philosophy: Deleuze and Rawls, Deleuze

    Studies 1, pp. 4159.

    Rawls, John (1999),A Theory of Justice (Harvard University Press).

    Roden, David. 2010. Deconstruction and excision in philosophicalposthumanism.Journal of Evolution and Technology21(1) (June): 2736.

    Simondon, Gilbert (1989), Du mode dexistence des objets techniques (Editions

    Aubier).

    Shragrir, Oron (2006), Why we View the Brain as a Computer, Synthese (153), pp

    393416.

    Soper, Kate (1986), Humanism and Antihumanism. London: HarperCollins.

    Sterling, Bruce (1996), Schismatrix Plus, (Berkley, New York).

    Vinge, Vernor (1993) [online] The Coming Technological Singularity: How to Survive

    in the PostHuman

    Era,http://www.rohan.sdsu.edu/faculty/vinge/misc/singularity.htmlAccessed2008.24.04.