1 Introduction to Computability Theory Lecture15: Reductions Prof. Amos Israeli.

37
1 Introduction to Computability Theory Lecture15: Reductions Prof. Amos Israeli
  • date post

    19-Dec-2015
  • Category

    Documents

  • view

    219
  • download

    4

Transcript of 1 Introduction to Computability Theory Lecture15: Reductions Prof. Amos Israeli.

1

Introduction to Computability Theory

Lecture15: ReductionsProf. Amos Israeli

The rest of the course deals with an important tool in Computability and Complexity theories, namely: Reductions.

The reduction technique enables us to use the undecidability of to prove many other languages undecidable.

Introduction

2

TMA

A reduction always involves two computational problems. Generally speaking, the idea is to show that a solution for some problem A induces a solution for problem B. If we know that B does not have a solution, we may deduce that A is also insolvable. In this case we say that B is reducible to A.

Introduction

3

In the context of undecidability: If we want to prove that a certain language L is undecidable. We assume by way of contradiction that L is decidable, and show that a decider for L, can be used to devise a decider for . Since is undecidable, so is the language L.

Introduction

4

TMATMA

Using a decider for L to construct a decider for , is called reducing L to .

Note: Once we prove that a certain language L is undecidable, we can prove that some other language, say L’ , is undecidable, by reducing L’ to L.

Introduction

5

TMA TMA

1. We know that A is undecidable.

2. We want to prove B is undecidable.

3. We assume that B is decidable and use this assumption to prove that A is decidable.

4. We conclude that B is undecidable.

Note: The reduction is from A to B.

Schematic of a Reduction

6

1. We know that A is undecidable. The only undecidable language we know, so far, is whose undecidability was proven directly. So we pick to play the role of A.

2. We want to prove B is undecidable.

Demonstration

7

TMA

TMA

2. We want to prove B is undecidable. We pick to play the role of B that is: We want to prove that is undecidable.

3. We assume that B is decidable and use this assumption to prove that A is decidable.

Demonstration

8

TMHALT

TMHALT

3. We assume that B is decidable and use this assumption to prove that A is decidable.In the following slides we assume (towards a contradiction) that is decidable and use this assumption to prove that is decidable.

4. We conclude that B is undecidable.

Demonstration

9

TMA

TMHALT

Consider

Theorem

is undecidable.

Proof

By reducing to .

The “Real” Halting Problem

10

wMwMHALTTM on haltsTM that a is ,

TMHALT

TMATMHALT

Assume by way of contradiction that is decidable.

Recall that a decidable set has a decider R: A TM that halts on every input and either accepts or rejects, but never loops!.

We will use the assumed decider of to devise a decider for .

Discussion

11

TMHALT

TMHALT

TMA

Recall the definition of :

Why is it impossible to decide ?

Because as long as M runs, we cannot determine whether it will eventually halt.

Well, now we can, using the decider R for .

Discussion

12

TMA

TMA

wMwMATM acceptsTM that a is ,

TMHALT

Assume by way of contradiction that is decidable and let R be a TM deciding it. In the next slide we present TM S that uses R as a subroutine and decides . Since is undecidable this constitutes a contradiction, so R does not exist.

Proof

13

TMHALT

TMA TMA

S=“On input where M is a TM:

1. Run R on input until it halts.

2. If R rejects, (i.e. M loops on w ) - reject.

(At this stage we know that R accepts, and we conclude that M halts on input w.)

3. Simulate M on w until it halts.

4. If M accepts - accept, otherwise - reject. “

Proof (cont.)

14

wM ,

wM ,

In the discussion, you saw how Diagonalization can be used to prove that is not decidable.

We can use this result to prove by reduction that is not decidable.

Another Example

15

TMA

TMHALT

Note: Since we already know that both and are undecidable, this new proof does not add any new information. We bring it here only for the the sake of demonstration.

Another Example

16

TMA

TMHALT

1. We know that A is undecidable. Now we pick to play the role of A.

2. We want to prove B is undecidable. We pick to play the role of B, that is: We want to prove that is undecidable.

3. We assume that B is decidable and use this assumption to prove that A is decidable.

Demonstration

17

TMHALT

TMA

TMA

3. We assume that B is decidable and use this assumption to prove that A is decidable.In the following slides we assume that is decidable and use this assumption to prove that is decidable.

4. We conclude that B is undecidable.

Demonstration

18

TMA

TMHALT

Let R be a decider for . Given an input for , R can be run with this input :If R accepts, it means that .This means that M accepts on input w. In particular, M stops on input w. Therefore, a decider for must accept too.wM ,

Discussion

19

wM ,

TMHALT

TMA

TMAwM ,

If however R rejects on input , a decider for cannot safely reject: M may be halting on w to reject it. So if M rejects w, a decider for must accept .

Discussion

20

TMHALT

wM ,

wM ,

TMHALT

How can we use our decider for ?The answer here is more difficult. The new decider should first modify the input TM, M, so the modified TM, , accepts, whenever TM M halts.

Since M is a part of the input, the modification must be a part of the computation.

Discussion

21

TMA

1M

Faithful to our principal “ If it ain’t broken don’t

fix it”, the modified TM keeps M as a subroutine, and the idea is quite simple:Let and be the accepting and rejecting states of TM M, respectively. In the modified TM, , and are kept as ordinary states.

Discussion

22

acceptq

1M

rejectq

acceptq rejectq

We continue the modification of M by adding a new accepting sate . Then we add two new transitions: A transition from to , and another transition from to .

This completes the description of . It is not hard to verify that accepts iff M halts.

acceptnq

Discussion

23

acceptq

rejectq

acceptnq

acceptnq

1M

1M

Discussion

24

acceptnq

1M

acceptq

rejectq

M

The final description of a decider S for is:

S=“On input where M is a TM:

1. Modify M as described to get .

2. Run R, the decider of with input .

3. If R accepts - accept, otherwise - reject. ”

Discussion

25

TMHALT

TMA

1M

wM ,1

wM ,

It should be noted that modifying TM M to get , is part of TM S, the new decider for , and can be carried out by it.

It is not hard to see that S decides . Since

is undecidable, we conclude that is undecidable too.

Discussion

26

1M

TMHALT

TMHALT

TMHALTTMA

We continue to demonstrate reductions by showing that the language , defined by

is undecidable.

Theorem

is undecidable.

The TM Emptiness Problem

27

M AndTM a is LMMETM

TME

TME

The proof is by reduction from :

1. We know that is undecidable.

2. We want to prove is undecidable.

3. We assume toward a contradiction that is decidable and devise a decider for .

4. We conclude that is undecidable.

Proof Outline

28

TME

TMA

TMA

TMATME

TME

Assume by way of contradiction that is decidable and let R be a TM deciding it. In the next slides we devise TM S that uses R as a subroutine and decides .

Proof

29

TME

TMA

Given an instance for , , we may try to run R on this instance. If R accepts, we know that . In particular, M does not accept w so a decider for must reject .

Proof

30

TMA

ML

wM ,

wM ,

TMA

What happens if R rejects? The only conclusion we can draw is that . What we need to know though is whether .

In order to use our decider R for , we once again modify the input machine M to obtain TM :

Proof

31

ML

MLw

TME

1M

We start with a TM satisfying .

Description of___

32

1M

MLML 1

1Macceptq

rejectq

M

startq

acceptnq

rejectnq

startnq

wM

wMwML

rejects if

accepts if 1

Now we add a filter to divert all inputs but w.

Description of___

33

1M

wx

wx

1Macceptq

rejectq

M

startq

acceptnq

rejectnq

startnq

wx filter

no

yes

TM has a filter that rejects all inputs excepts w, so the only input reaching M, is w.

Therefore, satisfies:

wM

wMwML

rejects if

accepts if 1

Proof

34

1M

1M

Here is a formal description of :

“On input x :

1. If - reject . 2. If - run M on w and accept if M accepts. ”

Note: M accepts w if and only if .

Proof

35

wx 1M

wx

1ML

1M

S=“On input where M is a TM:

1. Compute an encoding of TM . 2. Run R on input .

3. If R rejects - accept, otherwise - reject.

Proof

37

wM ,

1M 1M

1M

Recall that R is a decider for . If R rejects the modified machine , , hence by the specification of , , and a decider for must accept .If however R accepts, it means that , hence , and S must reject . QED

Proof

38

1M

TME

1ML

MLw1M

TMA

1ML

wM ,

MLw wM ,